Can Human Actions Be Explained
Can Human Actions Be Explained
Can Human Actions Be Explained
only to the extent that it is recognized by the present. We recognize the authority
of a text (or a work of art) by engaging with it in textual explication and
interpretation, by entering into a dialogical relationship with the past. It is this
movement of understanding that Gadamer refers to as the fusion of horizons. As
we come, through the work of interpretation, to understand what at first appears
alien, we participate in the production of a richer, more encompassing context of
meaningwe gain a better and more profound understanding not only of the
text but also of ourselves. In the fusion of horizons, the initial appearance of
distance and alienness does itself emerge as a function of the limitations of our
own initial point of departure.
Obtaining a fusion of horizons requires us to engage with the text in a
productive way. This, however, is not something we can learn by coming to
master a certain doctrine, method, or theory. It is more like a tacit capacity,
which we acquire by following the example of others. The knowledge at stake is
like a practical know-how; it resembles the Aristotelian phronesis. It is a
knowledge that can neither be deduced theoretically, nor be fully articulated, but
that rests on a kind of tact or sensitivity that is only exhibited in the form of
exemplary judgments and interpretations.
This co-determination of text and reader is Gadamer's version of the
hermeneutic circle. As important as the interplay between the parts and the
whole of a text is the way in which our reading contributes to its effective history,
adding to the complexity and depth of its meaning. The meaning of the text is
not something we can grasp once and for all. It is something that exists in the
complex dialogical interplay between past and present. Just as we can never
master the texts of the past, so do we failnecessarily and constitutivelyto
obtain conclusive self-knowledge. Gaining knowledge of tradition and knowing
ourselves are both interminable processes; they are tasks without determinate
end-points. This is the philosophical gist of Gadamer's humanistic ontology: that
our being, historically conditioned as it is, is always more being (Sein) than
conscious being (Bewusstsein).
4)
Understanding is a process continuously changing over time. There is no final
state resulting in divine insight to all knowledge. Recall the example of baking a
blueberry cake. Early in the learning process of baking a cake, understanding
involves the ability to follow a recipe. At a later point, understanding consists in
profound knowledge of how adding a certain ingredient will enhance the taste of
the blueberry cake. Understanding requires the ability to identify a relevant
relation in a domain, which provides the possibility to understand more complex
aspects of the domain.
Gaining new knowledge requires going back and forth between hypotheses and
the material until a fit is achieved (Fllesdal, 2001). The fit between the
hypothesis and the investigated material must be suitable both for the whole and
for the parts of the investigated material. The interpretation of the material is
always affected every time a new viewpoint is considered. This is called the
process of the hermeneutic circle. The fluctuation between the whole and the
part is one part in the hermeneutic circle. According to Fllesdal (2001) there is a
question-answer circle and a subject object circle as well. He describes these
circles in relation to the interpretation of texts. However, I claim that these
circles can be applied and used for describing what happens when understanding
occurs. The question-answer circle can be applied to understanding a knowledge
domain, like the French revolution, and changes occurring as we gain more
understanding of the material. In the same way as an interpretation changes
when a text is studied, the same occurs with understanding.
5)
Given his extension of the domain of hermeneutics from texts to all
manifestations of the human spirit, the hermeneutic circle affects also the
understanding of what humans do: their action. Here we can perhaps
reformulate the problem in out terminology as follows.
To understand an action we have to understand the intention with which persons
do what they do. This intention can be said to unify the various bits of behaviour
which realise the action. Now in order to understand this intention we have to
also understand the beliefs and desires that prompt the individual parts of the
action. But in order to understand what the beliefs and desires are that prompt
the individual parts of the action, we must also understand the overall intention
which makes the whole behaviour into an action.
The hermeneutical circle also poses a problem to the sciences that use
interpretation: can we ever test an interpretation?
To convince another of our preferred interpretation, we must bring him/her to
understand the language of the original text/the mental states behind the
behaviour as we do. To achieve this, we must show how our interpretation
coheres with already accepted interpretations and renders darker
passages/behaviours clearer etc. But we can never offer evidence that is not an
interpretation itself: to establish reading for the whole, we appeal to readings of
specific parts, yet meanings of parts also depend on meaning of whole.
Accordingly, interpretive social science is sharply distinguished from natural
science by having no obvious decision procedure. Rather we need "insight" (and
one persons insight is anothers flight of fancy).