Art and Aesthetics After Adorno
Art and Aesthetics After Adorno
Art and Aesthetics After Adorno
Claudia, Princeton University Cascardi, Anthony J, University of California, Berkeley de Duve, Thierry, Universit Lille 3 Erjavec, Ale, Slovenian Academy of Sciences and Arts Kaufman, Robert, University of California, Berkeley Rush, Fred, University of Notre Dame Publication Date: 10-01-2010 Series: Townsend Papers in the Humanities Publication Info: Townsend Papers in the Humanities, Townsend Center for the Humanities, UC Berkeley Permalink: http://www.escholarship.org/uc/item/86b2b3jr Abstract: Theodor Adornos Aesthetic Theory (1970) offers one of the most powerful and comprehensive critiques of art and of the discipline of aesthetics ever written. The work offers a deeply critical engagement with the history and philosophy of aesthetics and with the traditions of European art through the middle of the 20th century. It is coupled with ambitious claims about what aesthetic theory ought to be. But the cultural horizon of Adornos Aesthetic Theory was the world of high modernism, and much has happened since then both in theory and in practice. Adornos powerful vision of aesthetics calls for reconsideration in this light. Must his work be defended, updated, resisted, or simply left behind? This volume gathers new essays by leading philosophers, critics, and theorists writing in the wake of Adorno in order to address these questions. They hold in common a deep respect for the power of Adornos aesthetic critique and a concern for the future of aesthetic theory in response to recent developments in aesthetics and its contexts. Copyright Information:
eScholarship provides open access, scholarly publishing services to the University of California and delivers a dynamic research platform to scholars worldwide.
T h e T o w n s e n d Pa p e r s i n t h e H u m a n i t i e s No. 3
T h e T o w n s e n d Pa p e r s i n t h e H u m a n i t i e s No. 3
Published by
The Townsend Center for the Humanities University of California | Berkeley
Distributed by
University of California Press Berkeley, Los Angeles, London | 2010
Copyright 2010 The Regents of the University of California ISBN 978-0-9823294-2-9 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Art and aesthetics after Adorno / J. M. Bernstein...[et al]. p. cm. (The Townsend papers in the humanities ; no. 3) ISBN 978-0-9823294-2-9 1. Aesthetics, Modern20th century 2. Aesthetics, Modern21st century 3. Adorno, Theodor W., 19031969. sthetische Theorie. I. Bernstein, J. M. BH201.A78 2010 111.850904dc22 2010018448
Inquiries concerning proposals for the Townsend Papers in the Humanities from Berkeley faculty and Townsend Center affiliates should be addressed to The Townsend Papers, 220 Stephens Hall, UC Berkeley, Berkeley, CA 947202340, or by email to [email protected]. Design and typesetting: Kajun Graphics Manufactured in the United States of America Credits and acknowledgements for quoted material appear on page 18081.
Table of Contents
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
Anthony J. Cascardi
41
69
116
182
210
249
Anthony J. Cascardi
Whether Adornos ideas can be followed in the contemporary moment, and if so how, are not questions that admit of a simple answer. Indeed, there are questions to be raised about whether our present historical moment, in society as in art, is continuous with the world that Adorno knew. The collaborators in this volume take vastly different approaches to these issues, some by turning their attention to how Adorno helps us rethink the ways in which the art of the past must be reinterpreted in the light of subsequent history, others by reconsidering Adornos project within the larger field of aesthetic theory, and still others by reasserting the transhistorical claims of art as a way of resisting the conceptual force-field that has made Adornos work so influential. They hold in common a recognition of the power of Adornos aesthetic critique, and they share a commitment to the place of aesthetic theory in response to historical developments that Adorno could not possibly have foreseen. In spite of its detail and the density of its intellectual arguments, Aesthetic Theory can be read as presaging an aesthetics that Adorno did not live to write. The work was left unfinished, just as modernism itself. And yet what he did produce seems both to offer a trenchant critique of the field of aesthetics and to advance a set of ideas to which any future aesthetics would have to respond. These take as their point of orientation a set of remarks about the difficulty of art in the present timeits identity, its right to existcoupled with a diagnosis of the perpetual instability of aesthetic theory. The Draft Introduction to the work cites a telling passage from the work of Moritz Geiger (18801937) that speaks to the ongoing identity crisis of aesthetics. Aesthetics, he says, is blown about by every philosophical, cultural, and scientific gust; at one moment it is metaphysical and in the next empirical; now normative, then descriptive; now defined by artists, then by connoisseurs; one day art is supposedly the center of aesthetics and natural beauty merely preliminary, the next day art beauty is merely second-hand natural beauty.2 While the history of
8
Anthony J. Cascardi
aesthetics may be somewhat less random than this description suggests, aesthetics has nonetheless labored under ongoing uncertainties about itself. Hegel expressed the concern that art may not be a suitable subject for systematic and scientific treatment (hence for theory) at all. Before Hegel, in Kant, there are worries about whether aesthetic reflective judgments mark out a distinct field. And, before Kant, Hume asked whether questions of taste would require something other than the resources of epistemology in order to be resolved. This is hardly all. In the course of attempts to grasp central questions about beauty and art, aesthetic theory has often found itself in a centrifugal relation to its objects, attempting to transform itself into psychology, sociology, moral philosophy, and political analysis, among other things. Indeed, almost all the models on which modern aesthetic theory has been based have been drawn from extra-aesthetic domains. Aesthetic theory has attempted to imagine itself as a version of the theory of knowledge, as a philosophy of judgment, as a vehicle for morality, as a stand-in for political theory, and as substituting for a theory of community. It has looked to phenomenology, psychoanalysis, cognitive science, semiotics, ontology, pragmatics, communication theory, cultural studies, and ideology-critique for guidance. The peculiar lability of aesthetic theory has no doubt been a consequence of the fact that the social practice of art was itself in flux during the period when aesthetic theory began to take shape. Aesthetic theory developed in tandem with it. Such instability appears all the more striking now that the domain of art includes a much wider range of practices than ever before. If aesthetic theory is thought of as tied to the existence of art as a specific class of objects set apart from the rest of experience, then what becomes of aesthetics in an age when art seems intent on refusing that separation? Adornos writing suggests that these questions need to be addressed along two axes, one directed toward issues of history and practice, the other directed toward more conceptual concerns. As
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
for history, aesthetics must reckon with shifts in the practice of art in relation to new technologies for communication and circulation. These, no doubt, are driven by the borderless extension of global capitalism even in the face of is various crises and collapses, by the inescapable allure of what Guy Debord presciently called the society of the spectacle, and by a deep longing for meaningful social relations in a world of isolated individuals. For better or for worse, the practices of art have become entirely porous and open to new technologies of production and circulation, many of which represent themselves as immaterial, as happily divorced from the embodied world. Are these new practices continuous with modern modes of production as Adorno understands them, often implicitly, through Marx? Or are they something indeed radically different, representing a historical break that in turn obviates making distinctions between art and other kinds of material making? The more theoretical questions involve asking, first and foremost, whether thinking about art in relation to new modes of production within the framework of globalized capitalism remains a relevant concern and, concomitantly, whether attempts to align art with truth can help restore the value of art as a domain of meaningful sensuous particulars in a world that otherwise continues to believe that rationality is something radically other than, indeed higher than, whatever meaning is carried by art. Far from being outdated, the suggestion that art can stand as an example of what may be called embodied meaning seems all the more important in the world of global media capitalism.
abstract concepts. Artworks speak concretely, addressing themselves to the senses. They are meaningful but they are, in Hegels terms, forms of embodied meaning. The difficulty with aesthetic theory is that it has sought to assimilate the truth-content of art to the truth of concepts in their more or less conventional forms, which are disembodied and abstract. This would seem to suggest that aesthetic theory is bound to miss the very thing it hopes most to explain. Indeed, it could well seem that if art is forced to submit its truth-content to the demands of a discourse built around abstract concepts, the results might well resemble what Walter Benjamin described as the burning up of the husk as it enters the realm of ideas (The Origin of German Tragic Drama, p. 31). Benjamins remark signaled two fears: first, that in discounting arts sensuous surface and grain, aesthetic theory would leave us with little more than a periphrastic reduction of the thematic content of the works in question; and second, that the transposition of art into the realm of ideas would blind us to the ways in which artworks help reveal what is incomplete in any form of knowledge that limits itself to concepts alone. Art is, or strives to be, a sensuous way of knowing that seems ever to be at odds with the theories designed to explain it. But in its wish to carry a form of knowledge that is concrete, art can nonetheless help articulate a critique of the ways in which the very notion of a concept, hence of what counts as rationality, has been split off from the world of sense.3 And insofar as it is also conscious of the fact that the wish to reconcile sense and concept is bound to remain unfulfilled, art may be able to frame that critique in a way that is grounded in something other than the naive ideal of a return to a fullness of sense. Modern and contemporary art are as conscious of the illusions bound up in the notion of an immediacy of sense as they are resistant to the abstractions of pure concepts. What Adorno calls the truth content of art lies in the work itself but also in its historical formation, its cultural location, and in the sensory and affective responses it calls into being.
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
11
Of course, any encounter with art may well require some involvement with concepts in their more or less conventional forms: as sources of knowledge, or expressions of opinions, or statements of beliefs. One can hardly attempt to exclude from aesthetics the knowledge that a particular painting by Caravaggio is of the head of the Medusa; or the belief that Kenneth Branagh, the director of a film based on Shakespeares Hamlet, is also, as an actor in the film, the prince of Denmark; or the informed opinion that the author of Don Quixote was in all likelihood born of converso ancestors. But such things are a matter of our cognition of these works, rather than of what they themselves cognize by virtue of their concrete existence as works of art.4 To say that an artwork cognizes anything is of course a figure of speech, a catachresis whose purpose is to marshal an existing term to a meaning for which there is no adequate name. I place cognize in scare quotes because the kind of knowledge implicit in artworks does not resemble the knowledge we expect to have of objects as framed by propositional utterances. And yet this is the very thing that aesthetic theory has been at pains to explain: that while artworks are indeed objects, the truth-content of art is of the world while also offering critical reflections upon it. This truth-content is inseparable from the sensuous particularity of the works in question even while it remains irreducible to sheer sensuousness; it is a truth-content that is likewise inseparable from the fact that artworks are made. Indeed, Adorno located one of the great paradoxes of aesthetic theory in the fact that art offers us something that is at once made and true: Today the metaphysics of art revolves around the question of how something spiritual that is made, in philosophical terms something merely posited can be true. The issue is not the immediately existing artwork but its content [Gehalt] (AT, p. 131). Adornos response to this puzzle, to which various contributors to this volume turn, revolves around one of the oldest issues in aesthetics, namely, the semblance character of art. What is
12
Anthony J. Cascardi
made in art is semblance, and what must be rescued for truth is precisely the semblance-quality of art: The question of the truth of something made is indeed none other than the question of semblance and the rescue of semblance as the semblance of the true.... Of all the paradoxes of art, no doubt the innermost one is that only through making, through the production of particular works specifically and completely formed in themselves, and never through any immediate vision, does art achieve what is not made, the truth (AT, p. 131). Semblance must be rescued not only because it has been held suspect since at least the time of Plato but also because the commodity structure of capitalism has transformed most things into ghostlike appearances of themselves.
13
only because it immediately continues the work of the sciences and completes their discoveries ... but also because it points out the limits of scientific competence and takes over at the point at which further knowledge can be acquired only along paths which cannot be trodden outside of art.5 These arguments may be true, but they risk producing exaggerated versions of the very dichotomies they would hope to overcome. The thesis according to which rationalization defines modernization means that certain norms of reason came to be regarded as if they were reasons only valid forms.6 These forms were destined to exclude whatever is sensuous in the work of knowing. One critique of rationalization points out that all forms of reason are built upon some material ground; however, an aesthetic critique suggests that the sensuousness of art strives to assert what rationalized concepts have let slip away from the world. Thus, while the process of rationalization may well be pervasive in the West, and increasingly so globally, it remains nonetheless true that artworks can demonstrate its limitations within a particular historical framework. Herein lies the critical force that artworks carry in the context of their historical existence, but herein also lies a principal source of the frustrations, anxieties, and evasions of aesthetic theory over the long course of its history, beginning roughly in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries and continuing, with but few exceptions, until the present day: how to theorize a field comprising works that are essentially sensuous and particular, historical and concrete. Aesthetic theory has been at pains to explain the fact that some essential component of truth seems to get lost in the course of any theoretical attempt to bring a work of art itself to cognition; there is just as little (or as much) shared between a theory of aesthetics and a work of art as there is between a theory of love and Botticellis Birth of Venus. And yet the one can hardly exist without the other. The point is that while art makes claims as a form of knowing, it presents us with insights that are not reducible to their conceptual equivalents.
14
Anthony J. Cascardi
Artworks are sensuous, material, and particular; but they are not for that reason any less true. In attempting to locate whatever is distinctive about art, critics and theorists alike have sometimes called its noncognitive element beauty and have associated special qualities, pleasures, and emotions with it. Indeed, beauty is but one of the more familiar names for whatever it is that seems to elude the grasp of concepts in a work of art. But beauty is not all, and as Jay Bernstein has argued, modernism in particular has found it necessary to sacrifice whatever in beauty may oppose ugliness, require harmony, or demand the felicitous integration of parts. (Bernsteins essay on Picasso in this volume speaks directly to this point.) Adorno offers one reason why this may be so: [Modern art] has taken all the darkness and guilt of the world onto its shoulders. Its entire happiness consists in recognizing unhappiness; all its beauty consists in denying itself the semblance of beauty. 7 And yet beauty has returned in the last several decades with a new critical edge, just as aesthetic pleasure has reasserted itself with a new political force in the work of photographers like Robert Mapplethorpe and Sebastio Salgado. Beauty has been the subject of a revival in recent writings on aesthetics, and this revival offers evidence of what the abstractions of theory had let slip away. A 1999 exhibit at the Hirshhorn Museum in Washington, D.C., under the title Regarding Beauty gives some indication of the desire to recapture the force of beauty for a field that seemed to have become increasingly fascinated by theories of history and politics, not to mention by the conceptual mystique of analytical philosophy. So too have a number of related writings, ranging from the anthology edited by Peg Brand, Beauty Matters (2000), to Dave Hickeys The Invisible Dragon: Four Essays on Beauty (1993); an earlier anthology, Uncontrollable Beauty, edited by Bill Beckley and David Shapiro (1988); Wendy Steiners The Scandal of Pleasure (1995); and Arthur Dantos collection of essays The Abuse of Beauty (2003). These works speak, first, to the desire to recapProlegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
15
ture arts sensuous appeal from the theories designed to explain it and, second, to the desire to align the power of arts sensuousness with various moral and political projects (as in Elaine Scarrys On Beauty and Being Just, 1999). These, in turn, are indicative of a desire to claim, or to reclaim, the importance of art, a desire that appears ill at ease with the notion that arts importance ought to be self-evident. Standards of beauty may have changed since a century ago, when the character Adam Verver in Henry Jamess The Golden Bowl described art as providing human beings with a release from the bonds of ugliness; indeed, there is hardly a consensus about whether beauty and ugliness do, or should, stand opposed. Still, the appeal to beauty has put some pressure on theoretical debates, in part because it shows that there is more at stake in questions of aesthetics than matters of vogue or standards of taste. What is at issue is arts desire to serve as a form of sensuous cognition. This is something that aesthetic theory ought to be able to explain. If aesthetic theory runs aground when asked to account for what is specifically beautiful about art, this is partly because the notion of beauty can seem frightfully thin when measured against the breadth and depth of what art can encompass, and even more so in view of the fact that art is a category whose boundaries seem to shift in relation to domains external to it (for example: nature, politics, society, religion, science). It is hardly clear whether, or how, the beauty of art differs from natural beauty, or how art is to be held apart from craft, if in fact it is. Indeed, beauty and art are both deceptively simple ideas that, in their simplicity, mask complex processes operating at both the historical and conceptual levels.8 For instance, it remains unclear whether the concept of art can be applied to artifacts whose historical function was not so much artistic as religious (icon, chalice, temple, urn). But the additional problem, which surfaces at the theoretical level, is that notions like art and beauty seem not to work like other concepts, if indeed they work at all.
16
Anthony J. Cascardi
This question has been the subject of much debate since at least the aesthetics of Kant, and it is worth recalling. In Kants formulation, aesthetic judgments are unusual in being at once subjective and universal; they are rooted in particular feelings and yet they lay claim to universal validity. This is paradoxical, and while Kant attempts throughout the entire Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgment to resolve it, the results are unclear, even by his own standards.9 And yet in spite of the failings of theory in this regard something seems to be right in Kants idea that art is equally tied to the particularity of sensuous experience (and, moreover, tied to that particularity in its affective form) and grounded in the desire for claims that would have the same universality as other concepts. Kants aesthetics is thus an expression of a desire that, however unfulfilled and in tension with itself, remains central to aesthetic theory: the desire to acknowledge claims that would make sensuous particulars the bearers of a kind of truth that is not beholden to preexisting categories and concepts. By appealing to the logic of what he calls reflective or nonsubsumptive judgments, Kant challenges us to find universal grounds of agreement on the basis of the particulars, rather than to presuppose that ground. And yet Kant leaves us with the question of whether the affects incited by representations of sensuous particulars can in fact resist judgments normativizing force. This worry is heightened in Adornos claim that the bindingness of every style may be a reflex of societys repressive character (AT, p. 207). Seen in this light, it is hardly a surprise that aesthetic theory has so often been foiled in its attempts to provide any reliable calibration for terms like beauty and art. But neither is it clear that the twobeauty and artbear any essential relationship to one another. For one thing, the field of art, toward which aesthetics has come to direct itself, is historical and so necessarily variable and unstable even in its distinction from nature. Art beauty and natural beauty remain entwined. And yet it seems
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
17
that the notion of art has also been variable at the level of what is expected of it normatively. Art has been taken as the designation of a particular class of works, as a name for things that are appreciated as more than mere things, as a set of practices whose ends lie in something other than their usefulness, and as an honorific designation granted to artifacts that have achieved a significant degree of cultural distinction. Beginning with the avant-gardes (witness Duchamps readymades) it became clear that, while we do not call just anything a work of art, it is also true that just about anything may become a work of art.10 The nominalism that Adorno associated with the work of Benedetto Croce may provide one response to this problem insofar as nominalism can proliferate concepts as the instances demand. But nominalism is a poor excuse for a theory, and rather indicates its frustrations. Indeed, the very idea of an aesthetic theory makes demands and introduces difficulties of quite a different order. As a theory of art aesthetics has wavered between a psychological empiricism, various forms of ontology (which have pursued questions about the essence of artworks), expressivism, functionalism (the uses of art), and the theory of values (in which the terms art and beauty are meant to impute judgments of quality and degree). As for its evaluative powers, aesthetic theory has been hard pressed to establish consistent or convincing links between beauty and the works to which this designation is intended to apply. This embarrassment points up the more general problem of what may count as judgments of aesthetic value and taste, and of what may count as evidence for them. In response to aesthetic theorys ambitions in this regard, one might imagine the simple Wittgensteinian exercise of attempting to point to the beauty of a work of art, or to whatever particular element distinguishes it from a mere thing. (Here, no doubt, is a place where Wittgenstein would say that language is idling.) Adorno observes that the answer to the fundamental aesthetic question of why a work can be
18
Anthony J. Cascardi
said to be beautiful amounts to the pursuit of casuistic reasoning rather than a priori logic. As judgments, aesthetic claims stand at odds with the determinability that attach between concepts and their objects in conventional terms. Adorno: The empirical indeterminability of these reflections changes nothing in the objectivity of what they grasp.... That whereby it is possible to distinguish what is correct and what is false in an artwork according to its own measure is the elements in which universality imposes itself concretely in the monad (AT, p. 189). There is an important point to be gleaned from Adornos insight that universality is evident in artworks and not simply in the judgments brought to them. This is that the universality of art is necessarily a concrete and particular universality, which is to say a form of universality that is fundamentally at odds with what we take to be the concept in its dominant form. This is true both at the level of individual works and as regards the more general notion of art. The mounting evidence of decades of revisionism, a heightened self-consciousness about the contextuality of the languages of criticism, the reevaluation of art through various forms of ideology-critique, and, not least, an explosive heterogeneity among the practices that are taken to count as art, all suggest that any aesthetic theory with systematic and universalizing pretensions is bound to be defeated unless it can come to grips with the needs that drive theory to produce abstractions in the face of something as asystematic as the field of artworks. And unless aesthetics can somehow grapple with the fact of its own externality to art and proceed from that awareness to discover the deeper ways in which art still needs philosophy, one can be sure that notions like beauty and art will be nothing more than the reflections of isolated judgments or expressions of bare social interests and needs. To regard art, as Adorno does, as having a need for philosophy would be to pursue with an equally critical force the desires of art for a validity that might be recognizable in the culture of the concept and the unspoken needs of phiProlegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
19
losophy to anchor itself in the concrete. Regrettably, this project has scarcely begun. A few exceptions aside (among which may be counted the essays in the present volume), the result has been a series of merely partial encounters between aesthetics and art. But as the art of the late nineteenth and twentieth centuries began to put increasing pressure on some of the notions central to aesthetic theorybeauty, taste, the transparent immediacy of experience itselfit was hardly surprising to find that the philosophy of art soon reached the point where its only options seemed to be what Adorno characterized as a dumb and trivial universality on the one hand and arbitrary judgments usually derived from conventional opinions on the other (AT, p. 333). The bifurcation of the sense lodged in particulars and the universal demands of the rational concept are all too visible in this sorry choice.
Embodied Meanings
The questions of arts resistance to aesthetic theory and of the misrecognition of art by the theory designed to comprehend it are issues I take as central. How and why did this happen? At what cost did it occur? The general tenor of my response, for which I take Adornos work in Aesthetic Theory as an instigation and as a provisional guide, has two prongs, one directed toward questions of history, the other directed toward more conceptual matters. One prong involves the development of aesthetic theory in relation to a desire for embodied meaning during the period in which one form of reason, the rationalized form, came to be institutionalized as normative.11 To speak of embodied meaning is to register arts way of demonstrating the inadequacy of purely conceptual ways of knowing the world. It is at the same time a way of staking claims for the values that it makes in the world. To account for these facts we need to engage not only Adornos negative-dialectical materialism but also Hegels convictions about the role of art as a sensuous manifestation of the idea, in spite of the
20
Anthony J. Cascardi
fact that Hegels claim was coupled with the belief that art could be surpassed by a form of spirit somehow more satisfactory than itthat is, by the Absolute. Art, he writes, is not ... the highest way of apprehending the spiritually concrete. The higher way, in contrast to representation by means of the sensuously concrete, is thinking, which in a relative sense is indeed abstract, but it must be concrete, not one-sided, if it is to be true and rational.12 For Adorno, by contrast, the possibilities of art are set by the untranscendable horizon of history. And from this historically bounded perspective it seems that the validity of embodied meaning was suppressed even in relation to some of the most compelling efforts to realize it, or that it was relegated to the status of Wunschdenken. When seen from the perspective of conventional, abstract concepts, art may well appear inherently difficult and opaque; it seems resistant to paraphrase in part because the mode of paraphrase is reliant on propositional knowledge, on various forms of knowing that. If art is opposed to any reductivism that would privilege its conceptual content, this is because there is something more than conceptual content in it. Its way of knowing the world, which is also a way of valuing it, is lost when only conceptual content is brought into view. As Robert Brandom explained, having conceptual content means playing a role in a form of reasoning whose goal is to make things explicit in terms of propositional utterances, that is, the sort of content typically expressed by declarative sentences: by that clauses, or by what Brandom describes as content-specifying sentential complements of propositional attitude ascriptions. Because contents of this sort are the right shape to be sayable, thinkable, and believable, they can be understood as making something explicit. The claim is that to have or express a content of this kind is just to be able to play the role both of premise and of conclusion in inferences.13 Moreover, the role of propositional utterances in making things explicit reinforces the sense that they serve as privileged means for disclosing the truth. By contrast, Adorno has much to say about the
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
21
opacity of art (for example, that artworks say something and in the same breath conceal it expresses this enigmaticalness from the perspective of language; AT, p. 120). But why this opacity demands attention, and whether it can be grasped as the source of claims not to be dismissed for lack of clarity, requires a deeper understanding of the Weberian thesis about the role of rationalization in modern social life. The notion of rationalization itself has antecedents in the philosophy of aesthetics, most notably in Schillers Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man and in Hegels Lectures on Aesthetics. The critique of rationalization that reaches from Weber to Horkheimer and Adorno in fact begins as an aesthetic critique. For Hegel, this is a critique of a world of reflection:
The development of reflection in our life today has made it a need of ours, in relation both to our will and judgment, to cling to general considerations and to regulate the particular by them, with the result that universal forms, laws, duties, rights, maxims, prevail as determining reasons and are the chief regulator. But for artistic interest and production we demand in general rather a quality of life in which the universal is not present in the form of law and maxim, but which gives the impression of being one with the senses and the feelings, just as the universal and the rational is contained in the imagination by being brought into unity with a concrete sensuous appearance. Consequently the conditions of our present time are not favourable to art. (LA, p. 10)
The suppression of the immediacy of art and the emergence of a desire for the reconciliation of sense and concept emerge as part of a history in which the pervasive form of self-consciousness is reflection; reflection happens only with the loss of immediacy and carries with it what Hegel takes as the virtual guarantee that art will fail as the highest bearer of the truth (LA, pp. 1011). Reflection stands at the root of the abstraction of the concept, of the loss of arts power to serve as the bearer of truth, and of the
22
Anthony J. Cascardi
desire to surpass art in some higher manifestation of the embodied meaning. It is linked to Hegels idealization of the golden days of classical antiquity and the Middle Ages, which serve as nostalgic points of reference for everything that art might achieve and as a basis for a mournful contrast with the present. If the prospects of an aesthetic critique in a rationalized society are truly limited, this is because art has in turn become constrained in its ability to disclose the truth. Art is a sensuous manifestation of the Idea but not in the highest possible way. Hegels hope, which remained unachieved in the Aesthetics, was to make an opening for a more complex and adequate version of the concept than what art could provide. Indeed, Hegels understanding of the history of art and of aesthetic forms (architecture, sculpture, painting, music, and poetry) is such that art itself makes progress by jettisoning that which is most central to it, namely, its sensuous form. Some of the paradoxes of Hegels aesthetics grow out of the tradition that he inherited. They begin with the invention of aesthetics as the theory of a new kind of knowledge by Alexander Baumgarten in his Aesthetica of 1750. Baumgartens wish to make aesthetics a science of sensation was bound to be fraught with difficulty because it worked with accepted divisions of body and spirit. For Baumgarten, aesthetic cognition was double or, as he would say, confused. Kants response to Baumgarten was to say that aesthetics does not in fact give us knowledge in the form of knowledge of objects at all, not even, as Baumgarten thought, in a form that fuses together corporeal and mental elements.14 The conditions underlying the misrecognition of art by aesthetic theory are the very same ones that allowed for the configuration of a relatively independent aesthetic sphere of culture, where arts irreducible materiality could be afforded a place under the pretense that art was also of benefit to those seeking knowledge, or aspiring to virtue, or interested in improving themselves or society. These things may well be true, and indeed are still heard among the justifications for art in contemporary pedagogical
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
23
and political contexts. But the consolidation of a separate aesthetic domain was never and could never be complete. Art could neither be wholly divorced from the broader world of praxis, nor could reason in its purely rationalized forms suppress the validity of the claims that art makes sensuously. The two are linked by a structure of identity and difference. This complex structure is often ignored by aesthetic theory. Indeed, the invention of modern aesthetics happens alongside the widespread acceptance of empirical and mechanistic views of the natural world, together with the institution of practices designed to support it; with the consolidation of nation-states; with the invention of liberal democracies; with the rise of commodity capitalism; with the establishment of bureaucratic institutions of the kind described especially well by Weber; and with changes in social practices related to the arts in a more direct and relevant way: the decline of patronage, the beginning of newspapers, the rise of caf society, and the establishment of modern museums and concert halls as commercial institutions, first supported by paying subscribers and then by open ticket sales. By the time the field of literature had become what Pierre Bourdieu described as a separate universe,15 there already existed a flourishing salon culture in which matters of taste could compete on equal footing with questions about politics or society. (Bourdieu writes: The salons are also, through the exchanges that take place there, genuine articulations between the fields: those who hold political power aim to impose their vision on artists and to appropriate for themselves the power of consecration and legitimation which they hold, notably by means of what Sainte-Beuve calls literary press; for their part, the writers and artists, acting as solicitors and intercessors, or even sometimes as true pressure groups, endeavor to assure for themselves a mediating control of the different material or symbolic rewards distributed by the state.)16 In identifying itself now with questions of taste of a more normative and empirical kind, now with reflective judgments
24
Anthony J. Cascardi
that originate in subjective feelings of pleasure and pain, now with the aims of moral philosophy, now with politics, now with empirical approaches to experience, now with the theory of material production, now with the dynamics of desire, now with the social organization of experience, and so on, aesthetic theory has consistently been pointing toward the very domains of praxis from which art has been set apart. Such separations may have been necessary in order for art to identify and validate itself as an integral and autonomous sphere of activity during a time when other such spheres were also consolidating themselves in independent ways.17 But because these separations were not complete, that is, because art still retained recognizable traces of its relationship to what may more broadly be called the praxis of life, the misrecognition of art by aesthetic theory can itself provide critical insights into the ways in which those extra-aesthetic domains were enmeshed in the conditions that rendered art unfamiliar. Indeed, the process of rationalization was not something that happened to any greater or lesser degree inside or outside of the aesthetic sphere but was completely woven into the fabric of Western modernity. In spite of its apparently autonomous existence, art was and has remained entwined with politics, history, morality, desire, and the materiality of production, even as these domains in modern life were themselves, in their own spheres, transformed by the suppression of the embodied concept. What art offers, which these domains may not, is a critical reflection upon these conditions. This is because art is semblance, hence not completely incorporated in the processes of rationalization. As already hinted, the questions I am raising became especially sharp in the broad stretch of time that has come to be known as modernity. This is the period when something like the theory of art began to fashion itself as coextensive with discourses concerned with truth and morality, politics and utility, and when the practice of art itself began to emerge as a domain of artifactual production no longer intelligible within the praxis of life. The
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
25
result was the creation of a conceptual vocabulary for the theory of art that relied on the ancillary disciplines mentioned earlier, but that also came to invoke special, honorific terms like beauty, sublimity, and disinterest in order to describe the ways in which its objects and experiences did not conform to what those discourses counted as normative. Such considerations, and others like them, are crucial to an understanding of what became the field of aesthetics in the modern age. But it would be equally false to think that the underlying issues are in any sense unique to the culture of modernity. Recall that Horkheimer and Adorno never argued that rationalization, qua enlightenment, began with the displacement of myth. On their account, myth was already a form of enlightenment. Moreover, the question that Adorno identified as central to the metaphysics of arthow something made can also be trueis the recapitulation of an issue that is central to the Platonic critique of poetry. What the Platonic critique of poetry suggests, beyond what it says directly, is that art and the discourse of truth are joined by a structure of identity and difference; truth and beauty constitute an antinomy. On the one hand, each of them must exclude the other as part of its project of self-definition, and yet beauty presents itself as truths forgotten face, just as truth strives to articulate what beauty is able to make manifest. If the historical component of any critical aesthetic theory involves showing how the antinomy of truth and beauty took the particular shape it did in the modern age, and if its critical task lies in an analysis of the misrecognition of art by conventional aesthetics, it does so in light of the distant ideal in which truth and beauty might each be able to say what the other holds dear. The truth content of an artwork requires philosophy, writes Adorno (AT, p. 341). And yet, aesthetics has long failed to be the discourse of such recognition; indeed, the through-line of its development in Western modernity is the history of multiple evasions and displacements of this very fact. As a result, the truth of art has all too often been regarded as subordinate to some other truth,
26
Anthony J. Cascardi
including the truth of the abstract concept; it has systematically been dislocated into arts cognate fields.
Alternatives
Adornos Draft Introduction to the Aesthetic Theory points the way toward some alternatives. The importance of the Draft Introduction derives as much from the thoroughness of Adornos critique of the discourses of aesthetics that precede him as from his commitment to the principle that art has always had the power to reveal things that theory seems to lack. Indeed, one goal of Adornos Aesthetic Theory is to raise awareness of those things that aesthetic theory has allowed to be lost in our conception of arts engagement with the world. This restores art to the position of responding critically to the various theoretical approaches that have been devised to explain it, even while it participates in the same history that has conditioned aesthetics as a theory of art. A sketch of Adornos basic position, an outline of his critique of modern aesthetic theory, and some brief remarks regarding his own dialectical approach can serve as a further guide to these issues. The Draft Introduction to the Aesthetic Theory begins with a powerful statement of the fact that aesthetic theory seems to be set systematically against what art reveals. The force of Adornos point goes considerably beyond the truism that theory is conceptbound and so destined to ignore what sense seems directly to show. The ubiquitous and irreparable separation of any concept from any thing is not in and of itself the dilemma Adorno wishes to capture. As Terry Eagleton writes, It is a pity that we lack a word to capture the unique aroma of coffeethat our speech is wizened and anemic, remote from the taste and feel of reality. But how could a word, as opposed to a pair of nostrils, capture the aroma of anything, and is it a matter of failure that it does not?18 There is indeed an answer to Eagletons worry that in turn is the basis for Adornos negative-dialectical approach: that concept and thing are in fact but two moments of the same world. As
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
27
for aesthetic theory, the puzzle is that aesthetics seems to misrecognize art even while it seems committed to the idea that concept and sense ought to participate in one another; indeed, aesthetics seems to misrecognize the ways in which art is a form of cognition, albeit in the sensuous realm. As against the kind of theoretical work in which a conceptual apparatus is brought to bear on works of art from the outside or from above, or in which the qualities of a particular work are used in order to generate normative principles or rules (for genre or style or periodization, or indeed for taste or beauty itself), Adorno acknowledges that art is a domain in which the expectations customarily placed on theoryfor example, that it should have a certain level of generality, that it should provide a systematic and complete account of the cases it is meant to covermay not hold. It is not enough for aesthetics to be inductive or for it to be deductive in its approach to art. This is because artworks refuse equally to grant access from above and from below, neither from concepts nor from a-conceptual experience (AT, p. 343). But how, then, might one fashion a theory of art? The question begs response equally in the form of a vision of what the future of aesthetics might look like and in terms of a statement of the conditions that have informed it historically. What Adorno seeks is an account of something that idealism and materialism in aesthetics both ignore, namely, their undisclosed entanglements with one another. In Adornos case the alternative lies in a realignment of aesthetic theory with the principles of negative-dialectical thinking: The only possibility for aesthetics beyond this miserable alternative is the philosophical insight that fact and concept are not polar opposites but mediated reciprocally in one another (AT, p. 343). Adorno also means, of course, that aesthetic theory provides an index of the ways in which sense and concept are split from and implicated in one another. Since this process occurs historically, it would only make sense for aesthetics to be both historical and philosophical or, as Adorno, following Lukcs, puts it, his28
Anthony J. Cascardi
torico-philosophical.19 Rather than regard history as structured by underlying ideas seeking tangible expression in art(much less by the Absolute Spirit of Hegelian dialectics)Adorno takes art as a historically specific, material domain of culture composed of objects that cannot be reduced to mere matter. Artworks have a thingly character, but they are not mere things. The more than material quality of artworks is given various names throughout the Aesthetic Theory, some more remarkable than others. In speaking of beauty, for example, Adorno refers to the quality of the plus or the extra; the same could be said of the unquantifiable extra measure that style adds to the ontology of a work of art. Often Adorno calls this element spirit. Keeping track of spirit while dealing with artworks as artifacts means striving for the kind of account of art that modern aesthetics has by and large failed to produce because it has come to accept, or merely to lament, the vacuity of sense in comparison with the concept. Increasingly, the philosophical element in aesthetic theory has tended toward the overtheorization of artworks at the expense of what can best be called the force of their sensuous and material particularity. Along with this, the historical component of art has gone undertheorized, in spite of having been amply explored. During the period when art was theorized principally in terms of historical systems and subdivided by nation, century, and genreas in the various taxonomies common in standard versions of the history of literature, history of art, history of music, and so onthe various histories in question were derived largely from the categories established in Hegels Lectures on Aesthetics, minus the speculative overlay and idealist underpinnings of the Hegelian system. Idealisim became orthodoxy. By Adornos account, the most prominent exceptions to the then-prevailing tendencies in aesthetic theory were to be found in the efforts of Walter Benjamin and Georg Lukcs.20 Consider, by contrast to their efforts, Adornos critical assessments of the
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
29
mainstream directions in modern aesthetics. In the course of the Draft Introduction, Adorno passes under critical review a vast array of theoretically informed approaches to art: work-immanent studies, phenomenological aesthetics, a form of nominalism that he associates with Benedetto Croce, empiricist aesthetics, and hermeneutics, along with Kants Critique of Judgment and Hegels Lectures on Aesthetics. Given Adornos critical assessment of this entire, heterogeneous tradition, his work might well be taken as constructing a space for the understanding of art by systematically excluding every conceivable approach to it: art would be defined as the structural remainder, as the thing that theory consistently fails to explain. But this is hardly the project that Aesthetic Theory sets for itself. Quite the contrary. Each of Adornos negations is designed to disclose some element of aesthetic truth and each can in turn be incorporated into a dialectical understanding of the relationship between aesthetic theory and art. Aesthetic Theory aims to hold the objective status of art firmly in place rather than to locate it as a function of the affects or the judgments of the subject. (Adornos critique of the association of art with subjective inwardness is evident in his early work on Kierkegaard.)21 In his insistence upon art as an object-domain Adorno follows Hegels response to Kant, who identified the task of aesthetics as universalizing the subjective judgment-power required for the mediation of the sensuous and supersensuous worlds. Adorno can hardly refuse Kants idea that aesthetics must address itself to what the division of experience into the separate domain of cognition (sense) and morality (the supersensuous) fails to grasp. For Kant, this was experience as a whole. Adornos aesthetics is Kantian in its commitment to the principle of arts incongruity with the realm of the cognitively true and the morally good. But it is resolutely un-Kantian in that it refuses to make art a function of subjectively grounded claims, even as universals. For Adorno, aesthetic theory is directed neither toward questions of taste and judgment nor toward questions of
30
Anthony J. Cascardi
experience rooted in the subjective apprehension of forms. Rather, it offers a window onto a domain of works that are nonidentical with both the concepts we bring to them and to the materials of which they are composed. Artworks are things, and their thingly qualities ought to be respected; but artworks are not mere things. Insofar as they are woven into the fabric of social and historical relations, Adorno regards artworks as the social antithesis of society. Grounding this view is the claim that art plays a crucial role in preserving what I have been calling embodied meaning. Terry Eagleton is no doubt right in pointing out that modern aesthetics began as a discourse about the body. This much was clear from the ways in which Burke and Hume engaged the question of sensation. In The Standard of Taste, Hume, for instance, hoped to set judgments of taste on solid ground by identifying empirical grounds for agreement about aesthetic pleasure. But this also implies regarding artworks as bundles of stimuli. The result was something that Hume himself could hardly have imagined, namely, the obscuring of whatever was special about works of art. At the other end of the spectrum, the appeal to indeterminate and unknowable qualities as the key to the specifically aesthetic element in art (for example, the je ne sais quoi), or the linkage of art with the unfathomable creative powers of genius, yields a vision of aesthetics that is bound to seem remote from what artworks ask us to grasp as tangible, objective, and concrete. Aesthetic theory has a history of dividing art between one reductivism grounded in the empirical and another that gestures toward the ineffable. To this Adorno replies with a tersely articulated antinomy: The beautiful is no more to be defined than its concept can be dispensed with (AT, p. 51). To be sure, one can replace an aesthetic theory qua theory of art with descriptions of aesthetic experience, as certain branches of phenomenology have sought to do. Insofar as phenomenolProlegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
31
ogy takes its bearings by lived experience, it might appear to be uniquely suited to the development of a philosophical aesthetics. The reasons are hardly obscure. Like art itself, phenomenology deals with the realm of embodied experience as complex, integrated, and irreducible. Its procedures defy any approach to the world that would begin from the top down or from the bottom up. Phenomenology attempts to register the fact that any engagement with the world must commence in the middle. It is equally discontent with the reduction of experience to its conditions of possibility and with mere descriptions of the content of experience. In the view of one of its most aesthetically minded practitioners, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, phenomenology is a philosophy that takes the facts of the subjects embodiment and of the materiality of the world as co-equal. Its philosophical task is to account for the engagement of the two in the production of meaning. Phenomenology is a philosophy for which the world is always already there before reflection begins ... and all its efforts are concentrated upon re-achieving a direct and primitive contact with the world, and endowing that contact with a philosophical status.22 The point of departure for phenomenological reflection, the human body, occupies a position that is hardly originary but is itself remarkably in-between. There is a human body when, between the seeing and the seen, between touching and the touched, between one eye and the other, between hand and hand, a blending of some sort takes placewhen the spark is lit between sensing and sensible, lighting the fire that will not stop burning.23 Especially in the essays Eye and Mind and Czannes Doubt Merleau-Ponty gives an account of the ways in which art is an intelligent sensing of the world, offering an engagement with the world that gives evidence of the kind of knowledge that has been occluded by the dominance of abstract concepts in the preponderantly rationalized cultures of modernity. In Merleau-Pontys view, the eye and the hand transmit the intelligence of the world. But, unlike science, art (painting) is credited by Merleau-Ponty
32
Anthony J. Cascardi
with an encounter with the brute meaning of the world. As such, it carries out the work of thinking in a manner that conceptual thought cannot accomplish. Moreover, arts intelligent sensing of the world is free from the desire to know things as true or false, and likewise free from the kinds of judgments about ends that are implicit in morality. The contrast between the certainties embodied in the visual domain of painting and the philosophies that ground certainty in the expurgation of doubt could hardly be greater: A Cartesian can grant that the existing world is not visible.... A painter cannot grant that our openness to the world is illusory or indirect, that what we see is not the world itself, or that the mind has to do only with its thoughts or with another mind (Eye and Mind, pp. 18687). Painting is thus as much a form of ontology as it is a mode of cognition: Because depth, color, line, movement, contour, physiognomy are all branches of Being and because each one can sway all the rest, there are no separated, distinct problems in painting, no really opposed paths, no partial solutions, no cumulative progress, no irretrievable options (Eye and Mind, p. 188). Likewise, art is an engagement of the world that is itself a form of valuing, which is to say that it is a form of realizing and tracking value by means of material making and embodied perceiving. In it, values are not simply invoked or applied but enacted: as color, depth, line, volume, and so on. Painting thus becomes a mode of embodied meaning that returns us to those very things that have been alienated from the concept as a simple abstraction: body, gesture, style, manner, tone, mood, and the like. In Adornos view, however, the phenomenology of art runs aground because it strives to be just as presuppositionless as the concept.24 It wants to say what art is. The essence it discerns is, for phenomenology, arts origin and at the same time the criterion of arts truth and falsehood (AT, p. 351). Phenomenology understands that essences cannot be isolated from the continuum of existence. As Merleau-Ponty remarks at the very beginning of the
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
33
Phenomenology of Perception, phenomenology puts essences back into existence, and does not expect to arrive at an understanding of man and the world from any starting point other than that of their facticity (p. vii). Artworks for their part call for reflection on experience by semblances of experience, in which we follow themes, reconstruct images, or relate empathically with what a given character may feel. Undialectical and nonreflective appeals to experience are bound to yield a revalidation of the subject when in fact the experience of art seems to require something closer to what Adorno calls a counter movement to the subject (my emphasis). As he put it, [Aesthetic experience] demands something on the order of the self-denial of the observer, his capacity to address or recognize what aesthetic objects themselves enunciate and what they conceal (AT, p. 346). The incomprehensibility to which we are given free and open access through appearances stands at the core of what Adorno calls the enigma of art. It is also arts best defense against the ravages of aesthetic theories that seem bent on schematizing it: This incomprehensibility persists as the character of art, and it alone protects the philosophy of art from doing violence to art (AT, p. 347). If aesthetic theory has an obligation, it is to bring the opacity of art to consciousness, to remain eloquent and articulate while resisting the temptation to regard the enigmas of art as puzzles to be solved: The task of a philosophy of art is not so much to explain away the element of incomprehensibility, which speculative philosophy has almost invariably sought to do, but rather to understand the incomprehensibility itself (AT, p. 347). Merleau-Pontys idea of essences put back into existence ranges well beyond mere facticity to a more complex form of experience. And yet Adornos response to phenomenology may help clarify the fact that embodied meaning is not simply the result of concretizing an idea, much less of subtracting whatever in the concept is or was abstract so as to reach its material substratum.
34
Anthony J. Cascardi
It is rather an attempt to grasp the ways in which art, as a mode of material praxis, offers a sensuously intelligent way of grasping the world. If art is, in Hegels famous phrase, the sensuous manifestation of the Idea, then it is a manifestation in which the forces at work in bringing about the manifestation of the Idea are an integral part of the work itself. Art is the production of things that are not mere things in part because their material madeness brings forth a set of qualities that mere material things seem unable to disclose. Adorno offers this as his redescription of Benjamins notion of the aura (Aura is not onlyas Benjamin claimedthe here and now of the artwork, it is whatever goes beyond its factual givenness; AT, p. 45). These are not just sensuous qualities that oppose the concept, but a range of qualities, including affect and force, which go beyond the brute materials of any given work. It seems only right, then, to consider philosophical appeals to the notion of forceas in Deleuzes appeal to the notion of puissance and to the logic of sensein aesthetic theory. (Deleuze: In art, and in painting as in music, it is not a matter of reproducing or inventing forms, but of capturing forces. For this reason no art is figurative.)25 Can force and sense stand in some relation to the concept other than that of opposition or remainder? Phenomenology rests with the lived body, but it does not take power or forces into account. As Deleuze writes, The lived body is a paltry thing in comparison with a more profound and almost unlivable Power.26 If Deleuzes effort to develop a new aesthetics seems to be more radical than what phenomenology proposes it is largely because in place of lived experience Deleuze proposes an engagement with the forces that drive and organize it, including at the supra-individual level. In this he remains resolutely Nietzschean: forces present themselves as fundamentally aesthetic regardless of whether they are manifested in art or elsewhere. Whatever may provide the impetus for art cannot be lim-
35
ited to it; force is at work in every domain of human existence in spite of the fact that it has been so often masked by conventional understandings of the concept in its isolation from issues of power. For Deleuze, the crucial relationships are between the concept, perception, and affects. These follow a combinatorial logic, in which no element is privileged over and above any of the others. It allows for what Fredric Jameson has called the Deleuzian flux of perpetual change.27 But Deleuze makes a lucid distinction among the elements that comprise this fluxamong percept, affect, and concept. Rather than representing or imitating anything (least of all ideas in the conventional sense), or realizing the concept, as Hegel would have it, Deleuze regards art as a matter of recombining and objectivizing elements whose status remains co-equal. None of these is the ground for any of the others: there is no priority, implicit or otherwise, of concept over percept or affect, and so for all these terms. Drawing implicitly on the aesthetics of the baroqueto which Deleuze devoted an influential book where he explores the figures of the pli (fold) and the bel composto (artful arrangement)art is the site where percept, concept, and affect combine like the threads of a fabric whose strands are completely interwoven with one another.28 Or, evoking a different figure, it is a territory in which every habitat, joins up not only its spatiotemporal but its qualitative planes or sections: a posture and a song, for example, a song and a color, percepts and affects. And every territory encompasses or cuts across the territories of other species, or intercepts the trajectories of animals without territories, forming interspecies junction points.29 Deleuzes insistence on combinations carries with it a resistance to the synthetic orientation of dialectical thought. Likewise, the Deleuzian alternative to the dialectical versions of aesthetics (including Adornos negative dialectics) strives to remain anchored in the flux of forces without falling into a materialist reductivism. True to his Nietzschean roots, and to a transcendental empiricism that is inspired by Hume,30 Deleuzes philoso36
Anthony J. Cascardi
phy regards itself as fundamentally aesthetic, not a theory of art. But it may miss the fact that concept and sense (including affects and percepts) always in fact mediate one another, with each one striving to complete what the other seems unable to do or say. And rather than think that an aesthetic philosophy can accomplish what art attempted to do in its role as a bearer of a truth denied by concepts, we might do better to ask how aesthetics came to misrecognize the very things it hoped to theorize. Given the changes in aesthetics and in art over the course of modernism and its aftermath, it might well seem that the task of aesthetic theory ought now to be an explanation of the conditions of the impossibility of art. But if this is so, then I would suggest that it is a task best begun by reflection on the history in which aesthetic theory was drawn to model itself along lines drawn from other disciplines, some quite inconsistent with the ambitions of art. Can the successor discourses to our many theories of art adequately respond to the ways in which beauty still stakes claims to truth? As the history of aesthetic theory makes abundantly clear, asking about the ways in which truth and beauty interanimate one another poses questions that the philosophy of art has only begun to take up.
37
Endnotes
1
Walter Benjamin, The Origin of German Tragic Drama, trans. John Osborne (New York, 1998), p. 31. Adorno cites Geiger without specific reference in Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis, 1997), p. 332 (henceforth AT ). See Moritz Geiger, The Significance of Art: A Phenomenological Approach to Aesthetics (Washington, D.C., 1986). See Eckbert Faas, The Genealogy of Aesthetics (Cambridge, 2002), on the overemphasis on spirit rather than the body in most aesthetic theory. Adorno writes, Art itself thinks (AT, p. 99). Arnold Hauser, Social History of Art (London, 1951), p. 5. See J. M. Bernstein, Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics (Cambridge, 2001). Theodor W. Adorno, Philosophy of Modern Music, trans. Anne G. Mitchell and Wesley V. Blomster (London, 1973), p. 126. This is the formulation of Michael McKeon, Origins of the English Novel, 16001740 (Baltimore, 1987), p. 20. In the preface to the Critique of Judgment, Immanuel Kant writes of the deduction of the transcendental aesthetic that the difficulty of unraveling a problem so involved in its nature may serve as an excuse for a certain amount of hardly avoidable obscurity in its solution; trans. James Creed Meredith (Oxford, 1986), p. 7. Regarding the hope that aesthetic reflective judgment will span the gulf between the sensuous and supersensuous realms, Kant writes in the introduction that it is not possible to throw a bridge from one realm to the other (p. 37).
4 5 6 7
10
See Arthur Danto, The Transfiguration of the Commonplace (Cambridge, MA, 1981), and Anything Goes (Berkeley, 1998).
11
This is a major thrust of Bernsteins Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics. But, whereas Bernstein speaks of the complex concept, it seems to me that arts interest lies preponderantly with embodied meaning. The differences lie especially in what the notion of meaning conveys, which concept (whether abstract, embodied, complex, or otherwise) does not. G. W. F. Hegel, Lectures on Aesthetics, trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford, 1975), pp. 7172 (henceforth LA).
12
13
Robert Brandom, Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism (Cambridge, MA, 2000), pp. 3637. I am indebted here to Bernstein, who discusses Brandoms work in Adorno: Disenchantment and Ethics.
14
This is Kants analysis in the Critique of Judgment, 15, where Baumgarten and Wolf are referred to simply as philosophers of reputation (p. 69).
Anthony J. Cascardi
38
15
Pierre Bourdieu, Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste, trans. Richard Nice (Cambridge, MA, 1984), p. 6.
16
Pierre Bourdieu, The Rules of Art, trans. Susan Emanuel (Stanford, 1992), p. 51.
17
This is roughly the line that Jrgen Habermas takes, following Max Weber, in The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, trans. Frederick Lawrence (Cambridge, MA, 1987). Terry Eagleton, The Ideology of the Aesthetic (Oxford, 1990), pp. 34243.
18 19
Cf. Georg Lukcs, The Theory of the Novel, trans. Anna Bostock (Cambridge, MA, 1971), which bears the subtitle A HistoricoPhilosophical Essay. Adornos many disagreements with Benjamin are well known. See the letters between them in Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetics and Politics (London, 2007), pp. 11041.
20
21
Theodor W. Adorno, Kierkegaard: Construction of the Aesthetic, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis, 1989). Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, trans. Colin Smith (London, 2000), p. vii. Legitimate questions can be raised about the fact that Merleau-Ponty favors painting above all the other arts. One of the worries waiting to be expressed is that the fascination with painting may lead to a form of ocular-centrism that may in the end defeat the concreteness of its version of the concept and undermine the force with which it enacts its perspectives. In his defense is the argument that painting involves a kind of vision that is not the transformation of things into mental schemas but is, instead, a kind of corporeal thinking, one that deciphers and realizes signs that are given within the body. Painting may well be visual but it is not ocular-centric for Merleau-Ponty in the way that it is for someone like Descartes, who regards it as yet another mode for the conceptual possession of the world. See Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Eye and Mind, in The Primacy of Perception, ed. James M. Edie (Evanston, 1964), p. 171. Moreover, Merleau-Pontys approach to painting offers one possible response to an issue that has plagued aesthetic theory throughout its history: the antinomy of experience and judgment as a form of the strife between beauty and truth.
22
23
Merleau-Ponty, Eye and Mind, p. 163. Adorno does not say this without good reason. Merleau-Ponty writes that Phenomenology is the study of essences; and according to it, all problems amount to finding definitions of essences: the essence of perception, or the essence of consciousness, for example; Phenomenology of Perception, p. vii.
24
25
Gilles Deleuze, Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, trans. Daniel W. Smith
Prolegomena to Any Future Aesthetics
39
Fredric Jameson, Late Marxism: Adorno, Or, the Persistence of the Dialectic (London, 1990), p. 16. Gilles Deleuze, The Fold, trans. Tom Conley (Minneapolis, 1993).
28 29
Gilles Deleuze and Flix Guattari, What Is Philosophy? trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham Burchell (New York, 1994), p. 185. Gilles Deleuze, Hume, in Desert Islands and Other Texts: 19531974, ed. David Lapoujade, trans. Michael Taormina (Los Angeles, 2004), pp. 16269.
30
40
Anthony J. Cascardi
Fred Rush
of early critical theory is to combat the transfiguration of suffering and its main apparatus, idealism, by challenging the predilection of philosophy for ahistorical and systematic foundationalism, especially neo-Kantian and positivist developments in the foundations of the social sciences. So dedicated was Adorno to dialectically ferreting out remnants of idealism that he extended his critique of it to those who count as idealists only at a stretch, like Husserl and Heidegger. Nor were Adornos own philosophical forebears exempt: he charged Lukcs, Bloch, and, most tellingly, Benjamin at various times with utopianism stemming from etiolated idealism. Under every rock and upon every pedestal, it seems, was a Kantian of the wrong bent. Nor was Adorno of a particularly utopian disposition when he looked around him at what was, for him, contemporary culture. On the utopian side, Adornos disparaging analysis of mass art and popular culture can seem to require a standard for true art no longer found in human experience, if it ever was to be found there in the first place. This approach to the value of contemporary culture on Adornos part sometimes gives rise to charges thatif, indeed,
Adorno After Adorno
41
his views are not just expressions of bitter antiquationhis dismissal of what many would be happy to allow as art is even falsely utopian.2 The category of false utopia is distinctively Adornos, so the criticism, when redirected at Adorno, has a special sting to it.3 The topic of this volume of essays, art and aesthetics after Adorno, assumes that Adornos philosophy of art reorients the discipline of aesthetics as well as the objects over which aesthetic theories range. Only with this assumption in place would a treatment of art and aesthetics after Adorno be anything other than merely chronological and anodyne. Now, one might regard the importance of Adornos aesthetics to be well settled; after all, isnt it obvious that Adorno has been quite influential both inside and outside the academy since the 1960s? But empirical questions concerning popularity are quite distinct from conceptual ones of leading significance. Moreover, what form the significance has takenwhat specifically it is about the content of Adornos aesthetics that makes it a bellwetheris a matter for interpretation, analysis, and disagreement. Adornos reconception of the very category of the aesthetic marks the significance and scope of his contribution to contemporary aesthetics and philosophy of art. But the force of this reorientation is often misunderstood. Correctly understanding the nature of aesthetics according to Adorno does not go far enough to settle the issue of his continued relevance for art or contemporary art theory. Conceiving of the activity of theoretical aesthetics as Adorno does calls into question the very possibility of the enterprise of contemporary aesthetics. If one grants the general thrust of his interpretation of what counts as properly aesthetic, it is quite possible that there are no contemporaneous objects that are aesthetic by the lights of that theory. Adorno holds that much of what many take to be the art most expressive of contemporary experience is not truly aesthetic. This claim has to do with the connection Adorno forges between the aesthetic vocation of art
42
Fred Rush
and the continuing struggle of subjectivity to keep its distance from modern forms of culture that threaten to engulf it. In other words, one might understand the issue framed by the phrase art and aesthetics after Adorno by placing emphasis on a sense of the word after that is somewhat antiquated in English but is still present in common usage of the German word nach. This is the idea of practicing aesthetics as a follower of, or in accordance with, Adorno. Can one have an Adornian aesthetic any longer if Adornos aesthetic claims are correct? Can there be an Adorno after Adorno? Adornos anti-utopian and utopian tendencies intersect just here. On the one hand, Adornos views on what can count as aesthetic experience might be thought to be overly ideal and demanding and, in this sense, utopian. If this is so, then his pessimism concerning contemporary art is (falsely) dystopian. On the other hand, if Adornos claims concerning the nature of the truly aesthetic are more or less correct, his account may permit a much more realistic assessment of the potential of art for freedom. His views are then anti-utopian, revealing the false utopia of an ersatz aesthetic experience.
43
ment finally yields a single, entire system that is closed as to its logical features. Hegels term for the relation of humanity to the world at this endpoint is reconciliation (Vershnung). Calling this endpoint a reconciliation registers that humans experience their relation to the world in an alienated form up to that point the world is thought to consist in basic dualities, which cause ones experience of the world to be experience as of an Other. This gradual elimination of alienated experience is fraught; each stage of thought is experienced initially as providing a firm footing only to be shown through failure to be insufficient in securing a stable view of the relation of humans to the world. The true end is experienced as a release from this development, as well as a return to what has been the hope from the beginninga world in which humanity is at home. Reconciliation marks the completion of the process of overcoming otherness and healing the divide between spirit and world. Adorno demurs precisely at this point of Hegelian doctrine. He rejects the proposition that reason is driven to a final, most rational resting place. Irreconcilability is, then, a standing basic condition for Adornothis is part of what he means when he reverses Hegels formulation and asserts that the whole is the false.4 This denial of Hegelian teleology in Adorno is well known, but its import is often underappreciated. In particular, there is a tendency to overassimilate it to the German Romantic view that one finds in Fichte, Novalis, and Friedrich Schlegel that dialectic is infinite striving. Fichte and the Romantics hold that there is a stepwise, progressive dialectic, and that means they argue for at least a minimal positive relation of dialectic to what they call the Absolute, the final cause for the activity. While there well may be remnants of this Romanticism in Adorno (of which more later) it is a mistake to think of Adornos negative dialectic as a species of asymptotic approximation or a mere removal of the closure condition on Hegelian dialectic.5 This can give the impression that any one stage of dialectic or dialectical transition would
44
Fred Rush
receive very much the same analysis as it would receive under the Hegelian understanding of dialectic, with the simple proviso that there would not be the underlying cumulative unfolding of the final end of dialectic at each and every stage. But the rejection of teleology governing the endpoint of the system (the system generally) requires reformulating the nature of any one stage of dialectic. Rejecting the overall ends-direction of dialectic leaves one, that is, with very potent skepticism at every dialectical stage, which skepticism must extend to the very issue of the possibility of dialectical transition and thus to any assurance of positive dialectical development. This is just to say that the stock Hegelian doctrine of Aufhebung itself must be radically reformulated.6 Adorno never achieved a satisfactory reformulation of that doctrine, but for present purposes what is important to mark is that, for Adorno, dialectic can describe an inward spiralingdown as well as an outward stepping-up. Progression in this sort of dialectic consists in finer and finer negative assessments of purportedly stable categories. The cognitive superiority of one dialectical stage over another does not consist in resolving contradiction; it consists rather in driving the standing contradiction deeper into the given dialectical structure. From the canonical Hegelian perspective, this raises the concern that contingency infiltrates the deep structure of dialectic.7 In particular, Adornos ethical outlook embraces contingency to an extent intolerable in idealism. Underlying his ethical views is a broad understanding of the significance for ethical understanding of what Weber called the disenchantment (Entzauberung) of nature.8 Disenchanted nature gives rise to an awareness that ones ethical projects are, even with best intents, subject to circumstances beyond the control of even the most perceptive agents. This in turn is part of a more general recognition that human purposes have no guarantee that they will be answered by a purposeless world. All that one can hope for is coincidence of circumstance and intent. In the face of this realization, there
Adorno After Adorno
45
are two basic positions open to one: naturalism and idealism. If one embraces naturalism, then classical understandings of normativity on the model of strict law seem problematic. If purposes are causal impulses on a par with the rest of the fabric of the universe, how can norms be any less contingent than any other part of the world? Idealism preserves the concept of strict ethical law in the teeth of purposeless nature, but only by positing that ultimate ontological structures are beyond the realm of empirical experience, governed as it is by natural law. The idealist accepts that the truth of ethical judgments and the realization of good will in the world are strictly indemonstrable. Kants moral theory is a version of this option. Kant argues that what is ultimately valuable in ethics is good will, not its effects. Still, he realizes that finite discursive beings are also empirical beings and have interests in the worldly success of their ethical projects. Kant posits as rationally necessary a number of compensatory thoughts meant to secure a harmony between the empirically real and transcendentally ideal realms, thereby making it possible to persist in being ethical without being a defeatist. They are akin to what Kant calls transcendental but merely regulative principles. For Adorno, the Kantian doctrine of regulative reason and its sibling, the doctrine of reflective judgment, are of consequence.9 This is not because Adorno wants to accommodate something like reflective judgment in his aesthetics or the Kantian idea of regulative posits in his ontology. The importance lies rather in what the doctrines display about idealism. They show idealism in extremis, that is, they reveal idealisms incapacity to face up to the residuum of theoretically salient contingency that it must admit. For Adorno, ethical judgment must fully acknowledge that even basic acts that we take to be constitutive of ethical agency may go astray. Nevertheless, many such acts do succeed if the conditions are right.10 A philosophically respectable account of ethics would locate increased ethical success in the ontological conditions that make it the case that such action can in principle come off but,
46
Fred Rush
as a matter of empirical circumstance, can just as easily misfire.11 Any other view is a version of reconciliation that requires positing a false utopiain either a notional hereafter (Kant) or in the complete closure of a rational system (Hegel). This detour through Adornos ethical ontology is important because it is in his consideration of ethics that he develops most perspicaciously one of his main philosophical themesone that is crucial for understanding his views on art. This is namely the issue of false reconciliationfalse in the sense that any reconciliation, unless considered provisional, is de facto falsifying. Such falsification is a standing threat in culture and, in particular, in the making and understanding of art. Art is always under siege by the impulse to reconciliation, subject to various claimed reconciliations that would fix arts significance in terms of its representation or expression of the current state of culture in everyday understanding. Art is not truly art so long as it remains fixed in this way. Moreover, ethical goodness is dependent on retaining ones connection to an impulse that cannot be rationalized away. This impulse pertains to an inner nature of a mimetic (or close to mimetic) relation to things and others that is rational yet not controlling. This capacity is precisely what is under siege in modern life. Art is, in Adornos estimation, a primary way to explore the relation of reason to impulse in a way that circumvents rationalization.12
47
sees arts materiality in terms of its historical developmentthe material is given as demanding change in order to maintain and advance its historical character. Art for Adorno is a refuge from overadministered rationality and, as such, is a promising vehicle for developing a less false access to experience that can yield new understanding. Under conditions of modernity, where instrumental reasoning and discursive closure predominate, arts partly nondiscursive character is uniquely suited to both (a) introduce enough indeterminacy among standing concepts that one is able to begin to noninstrumentally imagine a next step in their development and (b) rescue the idea that nondiscursive elements of experience are inherently valuable. But art must also express the state of play between freedom and dominance present in the society at the time of its making. An analog of the divide in society between implicit demands of freedom and explicit lack of it is embedded in the work as a tension between two elements: (a) the superficial integration of the aesthetic components of the work, in many cases tending toward totality, that is, near seamless synthesis, and (b) an undercurrent of disintegration, present in the work in the form of its gaps or, in the case of works that are self-conscious of this tension, fragmentation.13 An artwork is a dynamic entity whose unity is not a matter of integration at the expense of differentiation within the work but is rather the tension between integration and disintegration. For Adorno art must be at the cutting edge of what counts as modern in order to fulfill this critical function. Its dialectical relationship to past art not only requires innovation on given material but also can be a response to the past that sees value in what has previously escaped, perhaps by mere accident, commodification. Largely following Benjamin, Adorno endorses the practice of artistically and critically investigating the marginalia of past and present cultures for materials that may be innovative just because of their lack of prior discursive importance. In fact, this lack
48
Fred Rush
of utility is but one component of the content of such ephemera; it is the conjunction of inutility with the property of being a failed commodity that is crucial. Such objects have a native dialectical structureboth part of and apart from capitalismthat is pregnant with artistic possibility. The importance of the materials of found, discarded culture is an aspect of Adornos aesthetics that is often downplayed or missed; its demand for formal innovation in art does not entail that the material on which innovation operates comes from canonical high art and does not preclude the use of mass culture as its material. Nor is formal innovation limited to technical experimentation of the sort one finds in the Second Vienna School, in analytic cubism, or in Joyce and Beckett. Ironic juxtaposition, parataxis, and other rhetorical approaches to material can comprise critical art. Still, such art must oppose its own impulse to reconciliation in structural harmony; it must will its incomprehensibility.14 For art to express such essential disunity and lack of freedom, it must undercut its own pretensions to authority and posit at the deepest point of its structure a skeptical impulse directed back on itself.
The New
The artist must struggle with the material against the materialhe cannot so abstract himself from his given social environment that he doesnt feel its pull. Nevertheless, the artist can bring something new to the material that animates its latent tendencies, that is sensitive to elemental experience, and that is not exhausted by mass culture. Adorno at times characterizes what he takes to be wrong with mass culture in an extremely abstract way. His analysis has three levels. The first, and most abstract, is an attack on discursive experience generally. Generality of conceptsthinking of things as mattering in terms of their shared featuresis the culprit. Any conceptual thought whatsoever threatens sensitive response. But this stringent and implausible form of noncognitivism does not sit well with Adornos rejecAdorno After Adorno
49
tion of immediacy. One cannot think without generalizing, and art is after all a form of thought for Adorno. The second level of analysis is slightly less arcane. Concepts track given regularities and, therefore, by themselves are not spurs to think anew. Moreover, Adorno holds that the past experience that comprises concepts can rise to such a normative pitch that imagining other possible modes of experience is extremely difficult. Adorno holds that modern informational technology delivers fixity of concepts almost without a trace of their origins; it is part of the efficiency of late capitalism to do so. These first two points are formal; the third is not. Adorno is also concerned with the particular content of the concepts that are on hand for the artist. This is a more concrete dimension of Adornos analysis that focuses on the power of certain kinds of generalized content, not just generic content but content-genera. It is the first two levels of analysis that are paramount to Adorno and the second one that, in his best moments, takes precedence. The problem is not generality; it is to generalize in the right way. The right way for Adorno involves vigilance concerning any putative resting place for artistic meaning. Criticism depletes the art objects reserve of stability that otherwise would cause it to relapse into the material status quo. Given the extreme efficiency of consumer culture in absorbing what were at one time expressions of artistic freedom and its capacity to craft new objects that limn aspects of what was once free art to create pseudofree art, being an artist becomes increasingly difficult, and the shelf lifeto take a term from 1950s consumer cultureof art is apt to be very short. Humans need pseudosubjectivity almost as much as they need the real thing, and they think they need the former more than the latter. A conductor like Arturo Toscanini is paradigmatic of Adornos concern. The concatenation of Toscaninis music prodigy (which Adorno doesnt contest) and the Madison Avenuestyle marketing of the excellence of the NBC Orchestra and of his own identity as maestro indicate a general and generic phenomenon, according to Adorno.15 A work
50
Fred Rush
of true meaning is produced as a commodity, the nature of which is obscured by its association with the composer. Adorno considers the susceptibilityeven the willed susceptibilityof high art to become pseudo-art to be inherent in European art music, a trend that starts quite early in the development of art-music, beginning with Beethoven and reaching something like an apogee with Wagner.16 Even Mahler, a composer whom Adorno greatly esteemed, was only problematically able to balance composing with satisfying public expectations foisted upon him as the conductor of major orchestras.
51
tic as suchappearances to the contrary, Habermas still avows some form of dialectical analysisit is rather the negativity of the dialectic. For Habermas, Horkheimer and Adornos Dialectic of Enlightenment (1944/47) is already a catastrophic misunderstanding of the potentialities of reason in modernity that is far too skeptical of Enlightenment as a source for free rationality. Habermas hammers home the allegedly pernicious continuity in Adorno of rational and aesthetic modes of awareness. Put in the terms of a category first crafted by Horkheimer, Habermas charges that Adorno falls into the dreaded camp of irrationalism malgr lui.18 This is rhetorically astute on Habermass part, whether or not the charge betrays misunderstandings of Adorno, irrationalism, or both. Because Habermass criticisms have more to do with the pride of place Adorno assigns to aesthetic theory and experience than with the propriety of his aesthetics as such, I shall not explore them further here. I wish to discuss two potential avenues along which Adornos views might be extended, nevertheless, to achieve contemporary currency. The first involves an aspect of Adornos work that is downplayed and might seem closest to poststructuralism. Although I believe that this is an aspect of Adorno that merits further discussion than it sometimes receives, it is likely that it will not be greeted as a very productive source for the works contemporary salience, since it keeps in place Adornos stringent formal progressivism. The second line of thought I shall sketch is much more recognizably Adornos but, for that very reason, reintroduces a point that always looms in the background of Adornoinspired contemporary criticism, that is, whether there is any application for Adornos theory if the theory is correct about the structure of well-formed aesthetic objects.19
Stabilized Art
The Toscanini case shows that high art can be mass artand a particularly pernicious form of mass art at that. Much of the
52
Fred Rush
phenomena covered by what Adorno meant by the term mass art is now called media. It is safe to say that Adorno was hardly media-ready, even when judged against the standard of other upper-middle-class Weimar intellectuals. His own involvement with the popular art of his time was selective, prejudiced by prior theoretical commitment, and generally more a product of sociological study than of participation.20 Still, it is a mistake to tax Adorno with the view that all popular art is regressive or that mere entertainment is odious. Although his writings on certain popular arts (jazz) can aggregate to give the opposite impression, Adorno was not dismissive of all popular art or even of all mass art.21 It is undeniable that Adorno tended to judge musical seriousness in terms of formal innovation. This alone might explain his distaste for jazz, which he alleges remains within the harmonic confines of Debussy and Ravel. The nerve of Adornos account, however, is that jazz is a popular art that pretends to be serious: the subaltern of the Toscanini case. What concerns him is not so much the recycled harmonic Romanticism of the music but rather its pretense to be taken seriously as an expression of musical democracywhat would be for him a matter of false reconciliation. The musicological and sociological complaints are connected. Because the music is constrained by antiquated harmonic structure, its performance cannot qualify as an expression of collective freedom that measures up to todays requirements. Notwithstanding these biases, if they are such, popular art forms can be serious for Adorno if an artist deploys them in the context of autonomous arthere the examples are the use of folk music, jazz, and cabaret song, most notably in Mahler, Bartk, Berg, and Weill. Of course, such folk or mass art is no longer popular when it is given this different context, since the context calls for an ironic or satiric attitude toward the art so deployed absent from its truly popular experience.22 In his music criticism from the 1920s and 30s, Adorno considers a type of composition he terms stabilized or hybrid-negative music, including among its pracAdorno After Adorno
53
titioners Bartk, Janaek, Hindemith, Weill, and the Stravinsky of Lhistoire du soldat.23 This type of music integrates what would otherwise be regressive material with progressive elements. If the regressive material is subject to further critical assessment within the work, then it does not tell against the works overall progressive natureit is, in fact, what constitutes that nature. The case of Weill is illustrative. The regressive material would be cabaretstyle swing jazz, which Weill handles with true critical acumen Adorno cites the opera Mahagonny as exemplary.24 Neoclassicism is the antipode.25 Unlike hybrid negative or stabilized music, in which popular or historically remote musical forms coexist in a dialectical tension in a work, neoclassicism is insufficiently dialectical and, thus, purely regressive. The hope that the mere passage of time or their alleged folk nature alone can allow the forms to escape commodification is delusional. Inserting wholesale prior musical Weltanschauungen into the musical present fails to engage with the demands of modern times in its own terms. In truth, Adorno leaves imprecise the dialectical relation between the regressive and progressive elements in the music that allow for this critical status, and perhaps the imprecision is due to a lingering general formal bias against popular, folk, or mass music. He was never wholehearted about the ability of the composer to use dated material, distinguishing himself from other Marxist music critics of his timefor instance, his correspondent and friend Ernst Krenek. His main models for progressive art remain the Second Vienna School and, specifically, Schoenbergs atonalism.26 (The analog in literature, Adornos other main artistic concern, is Beckett.) One might think that Adornos allowance that art can be progressive by deploying diffuse cultural material offers a point of contact with poststructuralist criticism, which often seems to prize works of this sort. But this superficial similarity has to do more with the extensional overlap of the works counted as having potential aesthetic interest than with any theoretical dtente. Inclusion of Adornos theory in a world littered with pop culture
54
Fred Rush
deconstructions cannot have its basis simply in the category of stabilized art. Put another way, while Adorno allows that irony can be critical in artists like Weill, irony as it operates in much poststructural criticism is not critical by Adornos lights. There are of course many varieties of irony abroad. One that has claimed a good deal of currency in poststructuralist circles was propounded, if not minted, in Jean-Franois Lyotards monograph on the postmodern condition, which identifies irony with conceptual play.27 Irony, on this understanding, is less concerned with the internal relation of the object of irony and the ironizing subject than it is with instituting a destabilizing movement from concept to concept. The poststructuralist understanding of the significance of irony, that is, depends on there being minimal conceptual barriers that would impede the sheer calisthenic movement of thought. For Adorno, irony would not be interesting unless it had a dialectical structure with requisite negativity. If one thinks of irony as having a dialectical structure, irony need not and indeed cannot involve diffidence about its object resulting from a scintillating play of concepts; rather, it consists in a dynamic tension between concepts between the forces at work in innovation (distance) and the demands of history (commitment). Schoenberg is exemplary again; invention with dissonance is an achievement all the greater because of the deep appreciation of the historical undertow of harmony that informs it. Atonality has its dialectical bite in part because it is mindful of what it leaves behind.28 This circumspection is what, to Adornos mind, essentially marks Schoenberg as superior in musical comprehension to Boulez.
Aesthetic Experience
The point of departure for developing Adornos aesthetic theory nowadays cannot, then, amount to a selective appeal to certain of the more mass-art friendly categories he deploys within the theory. It must come to grips with Adornos reformulation of what counts as aesthetic experience. Modern aesthetics emerges
Adorno After Adorno
55
in the eighteenth century in the empiricist theories of Addison, Hutcheson, and Burke and in the rationalist treatments of Wolff, Baumgarten, Winckelmann, and Lessing. There was a rich tradition in both camps with a good deal of variety on many issues. But there was general agreement that aesthetics is concerned with pleasure taken in sensuous experience. Aesthetics, as Adorno uses the term, however, does not refer primarily to an account of arts significance in terms of either pleasure or sensuality. Adorno does discuss the sensuous aspects of art and considers them, at times, to be centrally involved in aesthetic experience proper. But sensuality is not a necessary condition on such experience, and it is usually not a sufficient one either. For Adorno what is aesthetic in the broadest terms about a work is a product of its negative dialectic, the aspects of the work that escape reduction to mass culture. The category of the aesthetic for him classifies structural features of the interaction of historical material and the innovation of the artist. Any aesthetics after Adorno that takes Adornos analysis of the condition of subjectivity in late modernity seriously would have to be structural in this sense. It is in this structural or ontological register that there is a deep connection between aesthetics and ethics for Adorno. When he writes that there is no good life in false life, he means not merely that there is no good life possible when many bad states of affairs obtain.29 Good life and false life are for him ontological categories with discrete, integrated structures. False life is constituted by entirely general pathological structures that not only make good action highly problematic but also make it extraordinarily difficult to tell what would constitute a good action in the first place. The good often is misconceived under conditions of falsity, making it very unlikely that one could realize even part of a life that is good. Art that is properly aesthetic evades the false life of consumption; arts native ground is at the margins of society where consumption wins the day. These margins can dilate or contract in principle, of course. The point is not the protection of suc56
Fred Rush
cessful art; it is rather to protect the way in which true art fails. Arts success in evading consumption is dialectically tied to its potential failure, and not just possible failure. That is, to be art is to be a necessary failure, given time. Still, art can only succeed on its own terms if it can fail on its own terms. If its failure is dictated by the ever-shrinking margins of modernityso Adornoit is not its own failure. The falser the world becomes, the harder it is for art to evade the falsity from without.30 This compromises a main way humans can see over the horizon of falsity that continually presents itself as if it were a physical feature of the world. Although it can seem as though Adorno sounds the death knell on artand more than onceone never gets the sense that he gives up on arts alleged critical potential. But that is certainly a possibility. Like it or not, it may be that art can no longer deliver the philosophical punch that Adorno ascribes to ita claim that is, in essence, a historically extended version of Hegels end of art thesis. Adornos aesthetic theory is, as usual, a bit ahead of the game, including within it an anticipatory form of mourning arts threatened demise and, therefore, intimations of the theorys own belatedness. In any case, it is far from clear that one can settle the case of Adorno after Adorno in Adornos own terms. Adorno builds that very doubt into his theory.
Formalism
One of Adornos central insights is that general culture can and will subsume almost any art that is critical of it. This is not
Adorno After Adorno
57
merely a matter of the sheer power of popular culture, or of the desire on the part of general culture to operate on the borrowed prestige of art. If it were just a matter of the former, there would be no rationality to the subsumption, and it is not a matter of the latter because most truly revolutionary art as such is not recognized as prestigious within general culture. General culture has an interest in assimilating the cutting edge simply on the grounds that what the edge cuts is society, as Adorno well knew. It is no good arguing that some art will never be domesticated in this way; the only argument is over how one is to think about the phenomenon. Some will not see it as fatal; like Benjamin, they may see it as a matter of arts evolution. Others, like Adorno, will see this as highly problematic. And, indeed, Adornos favorites Schoenberg and Beckett have fallen prey to the phenomenon. Atonal music, sometimes of great sophistication, is a staple of horror films. And Becketts oeuvre, except perhaps the most obscure later works, has been reabsorbed into the clowning from whence it came. It may be difficult to imagine how Pasolinis Sal might be made part of the next Volkswagen ad campaign, but that may say more about ones imagination than about possibility. Of course artists and art theorists are aware that culture generally has a great deal of interest in domesticating art in ways that conceal the domestication. But it seems the main way in which artists and theorists attempt to forestall such domestication is to pack art with explicit countercultural content. Art is nowadays often message-centered, full of personal revelation, and trades directly in identity transmission. Whatever their other cultural pros and cons, these approaches would have been dismissed by Adorno as insufficiently formal. The grounds for the dismissal are, I think, worth serious consideration. Content-based art, even if the content is politically progressive, is much more apt to be incorporated into popular culture at large because content is inherently containable and submits to replication much more simply than does artistic form. Reacculturation of form can and does
58
Fred Rush
happen. But because formal experience of art is itself a difficult achievement even for the very practiced, requiring a good deal of knowledge and perceptual acuity, once one gets it one is less likely to view cultural expropriations as the real thing. Moreover, if Adorno is right, formal experience of art always involves a measure of self-skepticism concerning the sufficiency of ones responses. Of course stressing the formal experience of art hardly settles the problem of cultural subsumption. Difficulties shift to preserving responsive perspicuity over and against culture that aims at general responsiveness. Considering art from the perspective of performance may be key here. This is a recognizably Adornian idea, and there is a certain plausibility to the proposition that, say, someone who plays a musical instrument with seriousness is in a better position both to appreciate a musical work of art and to fend off pretenders than one who does not, although it is no guarantee, of course. Thinking of the significance of works from the point of view of performers has a degree of currency in the academy just now, but one has to stress that, no matter how desirable taking this point of view might be, actually taking it is very difficult for most of us, even those who practice criticism.31 There is a second point to Adornos formalism worth considering. The formal experience of works impacts experience more deeply and from more angles than does the shallow stuff of message. One experiences formal qualities in art by means of formal (forming) capacities. Such capacities not only have a hand in a wide range of human experience spanning the discursive and the nondiscursive; they also are centrally involved in the operation of imagination. Imagination is for Adorno a central political category and so, by implication, formal art has a better chance at base stimulation of a very important capacity for social and political change.32 Third, as I have noted, aesthetics in Adornos sense has little to do with feeling, at least as that concept is usually understood in modern philosophy and criticism. Adornos aesthetics requires objective ascription of aesthetic properties and not the subjectivism
Adorno After Adorno
59
usually associated with either the representational or expressivist branches of traditional aesthetic theory. Casual readers of Adorno sometimes miss this point because of Adornos concentration on the issue of modern subjectivity. But Adorno does not have what one might call a subjectivist theory of subjectivism. What he is interested in is the plight and promise of subjective experience, where being subjective is precisely not a matter of boiling the invariant structures of the world down to the possibility of experience, transcendental or otherwise. Reinterpreting aesthetic theory to deal with the residua of fixed categorical thought is crucial. Construing aesthetics to concern primarily feeling, pleasure, or beauty allows categorical thought too much leeway. It makes too many concessions to an instrumental specification of what can count as a fundamental object for aesthetic experienceotherwise meaningless affect. Adorno refuses this gambit. Whether one thinks that early critical theory overdraws the distinction between instrumental and noninstrumental reasoning (is mere predication really a prime instance of instrumental thought, as Adorno seems at times to think?), it is implausible to deny that some substantial overlap between the concepts of rationalization, reification, and instrumental thought charts the horse latitudes of theoretical aesthetics. Theoretical approaches to art must preserve the particularity native to art where the specific art in question requires this approach. Theories of art often dictate what count as proper modes of understanding or experience of art. In some cases, where the art itself calls for very theoretical engagement with it, theory itself neednt be problematic. But in cases where works are not quite so conceptual or where they are only partly so, theory must be on guard against itself.
Theory Theory
The late twentieth century was a period in which art criticism became more explicitly philosophical and, with that, more general and abstract. Literary theory was at the forefront of this
60
Fred Rush
development, but critical writing in the visual arts, in music, and in architecture soon followed. What Roland Barthes called writerly textsby which he meant a select group of literary textswas expanded to include all art.33 Such art had meaning under, and only under, the critical microscope. More often than not, the microscopic inspection was followed by a critical dissection, meaning being a form of sacrifice on the part of the work. Adorno is representative of this priority of criticism or theory over art, even though he devotes much attention and effort to guarding against theoretical encroachment on the particularity of art.34 Still, it is undeniable that when Adornos aesthetic judgment deserts him, as it does in the case of all art music that falls outside the Austro-Germanic compositional line extending from Beethoven to Berg, it is because the theory distorts its relation to its object. Anglo-American philosophical aesthetics blithely imports approaches to objects developed in metaphysics and epistemology into the aesthetic arena, and the potential for theory-object mismatch and theoretical predation is great. After all, metaphysical and epistemological theories in the United States, Britain, and Australia are themselves modeled to take account of allegedly foundational aspects of mathematics and the empirical sciences. What is needed is a nonessentialist approach to art that is attentive to the conditions necessary for the theoretical reclamation of arts particularity. The particulars in question are hardly univocal of course; if they were, they wouldnt be particulars. Some art is perceptually demanding and qualitative acuity is demanded in its experience and criticism. Other art is explicitly historical, and understanding it involves attention to its expression of that feature. One could go on. No matter the attention to particularity called for, criticism must be sensitive to the fact that whatever descriptions, judgments, or interpretations are true or apt about the work, they are true or apt about that work. This is to say that criticism after Adorno will have to be multivalent. Art is not one thing. Not only are there the several artsmusic, literature,
Adorno After Adorno
61
painting, architecture, and danceeach of which diverges greatly from others, there are also within the several arts a great degree of plurality. The history of aesthetics is replete with attempts to analogize or reduce one art to anotherarchitecture is frozen music, ut pictura poesis, music is a language of its own, and so on. When one takes seriously the demand of particularity together with a caveat against hegemony across the arts, one comes up with what one might call deep aesthetics.35 The idea is basic: one deploys ones philosophical resources where and as needed. If understanding a particular work of architecture, say, requires an idea of embodied experience, then one will investigate the resources available in the phenomenological literature stemming from Merleau-Ponty and the emerging field of consciousness studies. Balzacs Sarrasine may indeed call for a writerly approach. The very concept of detail in painting, seemingly at home at the far end of the particularistic spectrum, may be properly subject to historical treatment.36 The quandary of Adorno after Adorno informs the question of art and aesthetics after Adorno, then, in two ways. First, it raises the possibility that aesthetics in the fashion of Adorno may cease to have a field over which to range. Of course, one can always play the game of arguing whether contemporary works of art might be cutting-edge for Adorno. But that is largely beside the point. The point is that there is no guarantee that the cuttingedge will be extant, and every reason to believe it will become even less so. Adornos main claim is that greater sensitivity to particularity in art is in the service of exploring the mimetic impulse and its relation to noninstrumental rationality, which in turn informs the kind of resistance necessary to the ethical good. But one might demur from Adornos account of the ethical good, from the impulse that he holds undergirds it, or from his position on the relations of aesthetics to both, and still think it a very bad thing for aesthetics to lose sight of its theoretical imitations. It is entirely open to one to challenge the idea that standard views
62
Fred Rush
on what theories are and what they are meant to accomplish are applicable in the context of art. Attention to Adornos aesthetic theory can serve notice indirectly on aesthetic theory generally to pose the question of what might make such a theory adequate to its objects. In this way, Adornos reorientation of aesthetics around what remains after culture has its say may inspire a move toward greater theoretical sensitivity to particularity and pluralism in aesthetics even if it is not able to go far enough down that road on its own.
63
Endnotes
Many thanks to Karl Ameriks, Lydia Goehr, Gregg Horowitz, and Christoph Menke for very helpful comments on a draft of this paper. Very different versions of it were presented at the Department of Philosophy at the University of Toronto in fall 2006, at the annual meeting of the American Society of Aesthetics held in Los Angeles in fall 2007, and at the Czech Institute of Arts and Sciences in Prague in spring 2008.
1
The English utopia has its proximate and controlling etymology in the Renaissance Latin of Thomas Mores Utopia (1516), as do its many cognates in other European languages. Mores term is an adaptation of the Greek , i.e., no-place. More also plays upon the nearhomophone Greek prefix (conveniently closer in sound in English than in Greek, as More notes in an appendix to the work), and connects the idea of no-place with that of a place of abundance or prosperity. Conceptually speaking, of course, there neednt be such a connection; i.e., there is no reason to assume that an imagined place that either doesnt or cant exist is a good place. But, historically speaking, there has always been a strong implication that a utopia is a good unreachable place, or even that it is unreachable because it is so good. English commentary on More sometimes deployed the word eutopia as a synonym. See, e.g., Sidneys An Apology for Poetry (1595).
Of course (1) false and (2) negative utopias (i.e., dystopias) are distinct categories. Conceptually speaking, one might have true utopias of either positive or negative character and false utopias of either kind as well. So, for instance, Adorno would likely hold the dystopia of Orwells 1984 to be false because it projects a lack of human freedom predicated on something like capitalism to be the negative feature of that utopia. Many commentators on Adornos aesthetics treat the phrases popular culture and mass art as if they were synonymous. They are not. Mass art is a term of art for Adorno that refers to art structured in terms of a Marxist understanding of the nature of commodity. There is a tendency to think that Adorno means the qualifier mass to signal the broad cultural instantiation or appeal of such art. While mass art often has that broad appealas one might think a commodified object wouldit neednt in fact. The important point is that mass art is art that is intended for fungible distribution and delectation. Popular art is a sociological category that describes art of widespread influence and appeal. There is a great deal of overlap between the categories of mass art and popular culture under modern conditions, which are governed by a commodity concept of cultural significance. But there are times in the history of art when there is popular culture without mass arti.e., when the concept of commodity either doesnt exist or has not sufficiently infiltrated art production. This is not to say, of course, that there might not be other features of the social significance of art that retard its progressive role. Adorno analyzes folk art in this way and rejects any analysis of such
Fred Rush
64
art as a cure-all for overcommodification of contemporary art. Adornos view is at heart Rousseauian. Art only emerges as a possible vehicle for fundamental human truths when it is commodified. It operates, as it were, under constant conditions of guerilla warfare.
4
Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia 29, in Gesammelte Schriften (hereafter AGS), ed. R. Tiedemann, 29 vols. (Frankfurt am Main, 1970 97), 4: p. 55 ([d]as Ganze ist das Unwahre). Kant has a view, articulated in the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic of the Critique of Pure Reason and again in the two introductions to the Critique of Judgment, that dialectical reason has positive asymptotic roles, but of course these are merely regulative. There is a dodge: one can attempt to recast Hegel as a transcendental philosopher. While that strategy might be plausible in limited contexts, it is decidedly less so as an overall account of dialectic in Hegel. When one puts matters in this way, it becomes obvious why Kierkegaard held such interest for Adorno. Adornos negative dialectic is very close to what Kierkegaard calls his ironic inversion of Hegel. Cf. Lydia Goehrs claim that Adornos critique of Hegel utilizes a conception of the nonconceptual that is borrowed from a domain or sphere external to philosophy that she characterizes as the musical or aesthetic domain; Lydia Goehr, Doppelbewegung, in Elective Affinities: Musical Essays on the History of Aesthetic Theory (New York, 2008), p. 32. See Max Weber, Wissenschaft als Beruf, ed. W. Mommsen and W. Schluchter (Tbingen, 1992). See Fred Rush, Dialectic, Value Objectivity, and the Unity of Reason, in The Oxford Handbook of Continental Philosophy, ed. B. Leiter and M. Rosen (Oxford, 2007), pp. 31520.
10
Cf. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Phnomenologie des Geistes, in Werke, ed. E. Moldenhauer and K. M. Michel (Frankfurt am Main, 1970), 3: p. 447 ff. The outlook is broadly Aristotelian.
11
Much of the analysis here was developed in conversation with Christoph Menke, for which I am very grateful. See pp. 5557 for further discussion. See sthetische Theorie, in AGS 7: p. 266 for a particularly clear statement of these ideas.
12 13
14
Incomprehensibility is not, for Adorno, primarily an epistemic matterit is ontological. The structure of the art object is not comprehensive and, therefore, is not comprehensible. See Dialektik der Aufklrung, in AGS 3: p. 182; Minima Moralia 30, in AGS 4: p. 56; ber den Fetischcharakter in der Musik und die Regression des Hrens, in AGS 14: p. 21; Einleitung in der Muskisoziologie VII, Dirigent und Orchester, in AGS 14; 292307; Die Meisterschaft des Maestro,
Adorno After Adorno
15
65
in AGS 16: pp. 5267. Joseph Horowitz, Understanding Toscanini: A Social History of American Concert Life (1987; reprint, Berkeley, 1994), pp. 22943, is an evenhanded treatment of Adorno on Toscanini.
16
See, e.g., Resum ber Kulturindustrie, in Ohne Leitbild / Parva Aesthetica, in AGS 10.1: pp. 33745; Minima Moralia, in AGS 4: p. 242 f. Sibelius is a particularly easy case according to Adorno, but to this group he would add all French music after Berlioz, not only the chanson tradition of Faur, Chausson, and Poulenc, but also the much more controversial Debussy.
17
For the sake of exposition, I am not discussing the social realist criticism of Lukcs. Jrgen Habermas, Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne (Frankfurt am Main, 1985), pp. 13057. There is another less philosophical complaint that one hears now and then concerning Adornos philosophy of art. It was once put to me, in a question and answer period following a paper I had read on the subject of Adornos views on the political potential of artistic innovation, that the facts that the art world is no longer composed of artistic modernists, and that much of what used to count as the counterculture has been made into consumer products, amount to a refutation of Adorno. To be charitable, I supplied the required suppressed premise that Adornos views were so formed by modernism that they were stalled within its bounds. This is a stock reaction to Adorno in some quarters. But Adornos point is conceptual. One might attack the idea that marginalized subjectivity should be the primary content of art, but the mere fact that there is very little of this art around is neither here nor there. One may just as well interpret such nay-saying as the result of the problem, not its solution. That the counterculture has become a form of consumer culturewho could doubt that it has?does not tell against counterculture tout court.
18
19
It is worth noting that Adornos art theory is precisely unlike Dantos on a crucial point marking, as it were, a divergence between two Hegelian views on the role of theory in aesthetics. For Danto, the question of whether an art object counts as a real art object is otiose. The role of the philosophy of art is to take what the art world treats as art as data and answer the question of how that is so. Dantos is an entirely nonmetaphysical theory (in fact, it is antimetaphysical). For Adorno it always makes sense, and indeed is something on the order of an aesthetic duty, to ask whether a thing is really art or not. For a follower of Adorno, Dantos main work is question-begging. For a follower of Danto, Adorno has mistaken the proper nature of art theory. Adornos participation in the Paul Lazarsfeldled Princeton Radio Research Project is sometimes put forward as a credential for Adornos deep involvement in popular culture. Lazarsfeld found Adornos work repugnantempirically weak, obfuscating, and mandarin. But one
20
66
Fred Rush
doesnt need to be the positivist Lazarsfeld to see in that workmuch of it unpublished at the timea disdain born of remoteness. Yes, Adorno could dance the foxtrot (apparently), but could he foxtrot?
21
One might attempt to defend Adorno on jazz by arguing that he deploys the word jazz to refer only to mostly white, small combo, swing jazz as it would have existed in the 1930sPaul Whiteman, for example. It is true that he uses the term in this way in one early essay, but in later writingswhich would have had the benefit of the experience of more interesting forms of swing, bebop, hard bop, cool, modal post-bop, and even the stirrings of experimental jazz, had Adorno cared to educate himself about the history of that musiche does not back away from his rather broad claims. Of course, it is another question whether, if he had had sufficient knowledge of jazz, he would have affirmed his earlier views anyway. (I think he would have.) My point is simply that his lack of empirical knowledge leaves his philosophical claims about the music undermotivated. Adorno understands folk art to be expressive of collectivity and immediacy rather than the heightened isolation and subjectivity required of truly cutting-edge art.
22
23
Die stabilisierte Musik, in AGS 18: pp. 72128 and Zur gesellschaftlichen Lage der Musik, in AGS 18: pp. 72977. Max Paddison, Adornos Aesthetics of Music (Cambridge, 1993), pp. 4447 provides an excellent discussion. By Weills time the incorporation of jazz into art music was not uncommon by any means. Stravinskys Ragtime (1918) is one of the first pieces in this mode, but there was an avalanche of such material in the 1920s: Poulenc, Milhaud, and Ravel were all experimenters. In Germany the appetite for jazz spilled out onto the stage in the form of Zeitoper, most famously, Kreneks Jonny spielt auf (1925).
24
25
Adornos understanding of Stravinskys neoclassicism is simplistic. His view that Stravinskys earlier expressionistic works are proto-Fascist better stands up to scrutiny, as Richard Taruskin points out, now that we have Stravinskys correspondence from that period in hand; Defining Russia Musically (Princeton, 1997), pp. 38586. One might say as a shorthand: Adorno was able to take seriously the Tristan chord (difficult to characterize absolutely under either functional or nonfunctional analysis, but consisting of the following intervals: augmented fourth, augmented sixth, and augmented second above the root) but not the Petrushka chord (i.e., two major triads a tritone apart). This is the period dating roughly from 1908 (the fourth movement of the second string quartet, op. 10) to 1923 (when Schoenberg revealed to his circle of intimates his ideas for tone-row composition). The first throughcomposed twelve-tone piece is the Suite for Piano, op. 25 (192023).
Adorno After Adorno
26
67
27
Jean-Franois Lyotard, La condition post-moderne (Paris, 1979). I recall my disappointment as a teenager when I obtained a copy of Schoenbergs Harmonielehre from the local public library. I was expecting an iconoclastic treatise whose subject matter would abandon all manner of tonality. Instead what I got was a book about tonal harmony, albeit at the far reaches of theory. One of the main points of the book was entirely lost on me then, i.e., that it is a valediction.
28
29
Minima Moralia 18, in AGS 4: p. 43 (es gibt kein richtiges Leben im falschen). The novelist Paul Auster has written of Paul Celans late poetry that it set[s] the stakes so high that he must surpass himself in order to keep even , push[ing] his life into the void in order to cling to his identity; The Poetry of Exile, in Collected Prose (New York, 2003), p. 359. Celan was a poet whom Adorno admired for just this reason.
30
31
There are always counterexamples of course. Geoff Dyer specializes in writing about art with great understanding without even minimally practicing the art in question. See his The Ongoing Moment (New York, 2007) (photography) and But Beautiful (London, 1991) (jazz). Within the Frankfurt School the idea that imagination has political salience receives its most thorough treatment in the early work of Marcuse. Adornos aesthetics, as well as his thought generally, has an attenuated relation to anything political. The degree of attenuation is a topic beyond the scope of this essay.
32
33
Roland Barthes, S/Z (Paris, 1970), pp. 1011; cf. Quest-ce que lcriture? in Le degr zro de lcriture (Paris, 1972), pp. 1117. Adorno is but one of several thinkers in the wake of German Romanticism who held that the structure of a theory should be as isomorphic as possible to the particularity of the experience it is to model. The tension in his thought between fidelity to the singularity of art and theory-driven analysis perhaps expresses a greater tension between neo-Romanticism and modernism in his thought generally.
34
35
See Fred Rush, On Architecture (London, 2008). See Daniel Arasse, Le dtail (Paris, 1996).
36
68
Fred Rush
Claudia Brodsky
The moment of the objectivity of truth, without which dialectics cannot be imagined
T. W. Adorno1
[N]ow everyone wants to add something, to put something into the paint. If they dont, the work is called, a little pejoratively, traditional. But painting doesnt back up. It spins its wheels a lot, yet somehow it tries to creep forward.
Frank Stella 2
69
his lifeincluding, self-reflexively, an essay on the essay form itselfimmerse the reader immediately in the special density of his dialectical thinking, a process of reflection at once opaque in origin and unremittingly rigorous in its development.3 Just as these specifically focused essays often contain sharper theoretical insights than does Adornos attempt to articulate an aesthetic theory in general, so the piecemeal quality of Adornos final work-in-progress may have as much to do with enduring divisions within his view of what constitutes the aesthetic as with its own ultimately unfinished status, divisions that, as the present essay attempts to demonstrate, have lived on in the conception of art, in both the abstract and concrete senses, after him. In that they consider the aesthetic in each instance as the staging of something inassimilable, the essays allow Adorno to analyze the aesthetic in the course of sounding its fundamental resistance to analysis, an arresting sensuousness whose traditional conceptual qualification as aesthetic renders it no less impenetrable in its depths. Among the most trenchant of the essays is Adornos now canonical study of the peril of abdicating critical analysis of the aesthetic in the name of its appropriation and legitimation by culture, that equivocal catchall, at once transparent and masking, for the objectification, social mediation, and commodification of art. An apparent attack on the self-importance of cultural criticism by the very theorist who made Kulturkritik central to Ideologiekritik in the last century, Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft (Cultural Criticism and Society), included in Prismen. Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft (1955), begins by skewering the inevitable narcissism of the culture of cultural criticism itself: The cultural critic can hardly avoid the suggestion that he has the culture which culture lacks. His vanity comes to the aid of its own.4 The progress of the essay defeats any such self-flattering suggestion, even on the part of the critic who satirizes it. The development of its argument, at once dialectical and nonlinear, resembles less a work of discursive analysis than a discursive work of art. While avoid70
Claudia Brodsky
ing the blinding power of dramatic theoretical gestures, its own predominant trope is peripeteia: a critique of cultural criticism proffered by one of its leading practitioners, the essay continually reverses the expectations it creates as well as those it rejects with regard to its subject. That subject, so pervasive to everyday experience as to pass unperceived, is not the aesthetic nor any object of art per se but the mostly invisible web in which art is caught, the weave of interdependent relations, stemming from no single thread of causation, among culture, its socially approved arbiters or critics, and society. Working through a maze of critical prose rarely matched in complexity even by its author, the reader of Adornos delineation of the intellectualideological as well as criticalinteractions in which the aesthetic is embedded is granted no higher ground from which to order, let alone subordinate these. The relations that constitute Adornos subject remain instead just that, relations; even though they refer to entities understood to be conceptual to begin with, the terms culture, cultural criticism, and society defy predictive definition in this essay with each new sentence predicate. The one prediction and single phrase, however, for which the essay is most famous, is the peremptory definition of the act of writing a poem after Auschwitz as barbaric that occurs within the course of its lengthy penultimate sentence, one whose full, explicitly dialectical development will be more closely examined in what follows.5 Made to serve as a touchstone of cultural criticism ever since, this widely cited statement would indeed be Adornos most celebrated if, indeed, Adorno had ever made it as it has been universally cited, that is, as a definitive equation of the highest form of culture with the opposite of culture, barbarism. The logic of such a paradoxical equation would, in addition, effectively imitate that of its subject. For any statement declaring the fact of Auschwitz to have redefined the undertaking of all imaginative art after it would redefine art in much the same way
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
71
that the camp concretely redefined the imagining of mass murder, determining it, precisely, in predominantly temporal rather than spatial terms. Like an act of annihilation aimed not at territorial expansion but at the erasure from all places on earth for all time of an inherently interterritorial, because already diasporic, people, art defined henceforth as barbarism would annihilate everywhere the possibility of art. By exchanging rather than opposing acts of culture and barbarism in a single phrase, Adorno gives us an arresting glimpse of what it means for the concept of culture, or, for that matter, of a culture industry, when the industry of murder includes culture in its mechanized routines. What, one may well ask, is music, for example, when its performance in vivo accompanies acts of extermination: is it still music, a formal organization of sensory impressions abstractable from any performance or context, or is it barbarism brought to another, almost abstract level, barbarism that attacks the mind through the senses even in the act of destroying the body that houses those senses, that insists the mind know nothing is free of its power nor can be. And how can poetry still be poetry if the music that naturally inhabits it as meter, euphony, and beat is no longer simply music, the purest, or least information-laden,6 and thus most universal of the arts, but a means to destroy, along with the life of the body, the recollected and immediately receptive, aesthetic, and imaginative lives of barbarisms victims? Negating the identity of artaffirming its undertaking to be barbaric after Auschwitz, Adornos comment implies that history kills not only the victims of history but the survivors of history too.7 Conveying the impossibility not of art but of that paradoxis the challenge informing Adornos thinking in general, and not only of a single phrase isolated and circulated like a Delphic oracle by the very culture it critiques. Any study of art after Adorno the cultural critic culturally reputed to have proclaimed the impossibility of producing art once culture and
72
Claudia Brodsky
barbarism have become indistinguishablemust first ask itself what, for Adorno, objectively constitutes art to begin with, or, if these are indeed the same, what defines an art object in Adornos individual writings on art?
If the difficulty in answering these apparently straightforward questions can be attributed to the particular intellectual demands of Adornos writing, it also speaks, after Adorno, to another more general problem: the ongoing difficulty of defining the concrete reality of art today. To ask what an art object is in Adorno is both to pose a question that Adornos writings on art bring forcefully to mind and to begin to rethink the aesthetic after Adorno by way of Adorno in ways that the theorist and cultural critic could not have foreseen. Ars longa, vita brevis est in deed, but no less in deed is life like art: uncertain of the identity of its object, the intellect hesitates, while the imagination goes to work, subjecting the mind to the challenge of understanding, among other objects, new forms of the production and conceptualization of art. Because dialectical thinking does not usurp but works with imagination against the rule of objectification, already in Adorno, and, through Adorno, after him, our understanding of the identity of the object of art becomes, no less than that of the subject who objectifies art, a problem.
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
73
Generically speaking, this should hardly be surprising. Perhaps the most important theorist of the aesthetic after Hegel, Adorno was, of course, a student and theorist of musical form to begin with, the same art form with which Hegel equated the passage of spirit out of aesthetic embodiment and into the conceptual prose of philosophy. Romantic music, in the Lectures on Aesthetics, dovetails with Romantic poetry to bring concrete objecthood itself to an end.10 As Hegel describes it, the preponderance of subjective content in Romantic music overwhelms the perceptible contours of form, submerging the external markings of composition and structure in such an immeasurable outpouring of interiority as to render that content, now fully externalized, into its contrary: an uncontainable and thus subjectively uninterpretable exteriority. This is subjectivity so fully turned outside that it leaves nothing inside, subjectivity as mere sensuousness or, as Hegel remarkably calls it, a mere sounding (ein blosses Tnen).11 While the enormous power of Hegels interpretation of Romantic music as the dissolution of meaningful artistic form may well meet its strongest counterweight in Adornos analysis of modern music as, first and foremost, a formal art, it remains no less powerfully unclear what in Adornos, as opposed to Hegels, aesthetic theory defines an object. This is not merely because music, of all the arts, may be the least likely exemplar of objecthoodtransitory by nature, fixed only in its notation, inherently available to formal and performative variationbut because Adorno, writing on art in general, resists all exemplary definitions of what constitutes his theoretical object. That resistance to defining and thus objectifying the object of ones contemplation is not adequately explained by the dialectic alone: with respect to its object, Hegels dialectic of art appears unequivocal. The Lectures on Aesthetics divide neatly not only into three theoretically defined historical periods (Symbolic, Classical, Romantic) inhabited, in differing proportions, by three major genres (architecture; sculpture and painting; poetry and music)
74
Claudia Brodsky
and a host of subgenres all defined by their expression or exclusion of mimetic content but also into objects defined dialectically in the first place by the very prevalence (or, in the Classical period, the purported equivalence) of subjecthood and objecthood they embody. In direct contrast with the objects of Hegels dialectical aesthetics, Adornos primary object of aesthetic analysis may hardly be one at all, but whether music, Adornos initial and enduring practical preoccupation, is the origin or outcome of his conception of the aesthetic remains no less a real question. For Adornos aesthetic theory, like the intangible sensory nature of music, is, in its conceptual nature, inherently hard to grasp. Unlike Hegels, his dialectical analysis does not understand itself as transitionally but rather as persistently negative, and nowhere is that negativity and its ever-changing destruction of certainty in greater verbal evidence than in Adornos differing articulations of what is, and is not, an art object. Still, and for the very same reason, it is within the difficulty of defining the art object negatively that Adornos most illuminating contribution to the understanding of art in our time may lie.12 For, if art at presentor, at least, since Duchampappears to designate an infinite and fragmented field of particulars, none of which can be excluded a priori from, and few of which can rest secure a posteriori in, the name, the immediate difficulty in defining the object of art in Adorno is that object in Adorno goes by too many names. To some extent this owes to the history and lexicon of the German language itself. The indigenous, Old High German compound term Gegenstand (from gagan and Stand) is doubled in Grimms Wrterbuch by the Latinate Objekt, while the differently inflected German terms for thing, Sache (descendent of the Old High German sahha and Old Saxon saka) and Ding (the preservation of ding in Old High German and twin of Thing in Old Saxon), also carry with them different senses of a kind of perceptual or conceptual object (Sache meaning both material thing and the matter under discussion; Ding meaning
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
75
both material thing and the matter immediatelywhether physically or conceptuallyat hand). While object and thing in English obviously overlap with Objekt and Ding, Adorno can and does employ the alternatives to these terms available only in German: Gegenstand as well as Objekt, Sache as well as Ding. Yet, just as these doubling words remain distinct from each other, not only historically but also semantically, so Adorno uses them noninterchangeably. He sometimes employs Sache (but not Ding) for example, when referring back to an Objekt, but, even while employing them differently, he uses the alternate terms for thing both positively (as something real, or, that really matters) and negatively (as something solely construed as such by ideology). That the excellent translation of Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft by Samuel and Shierry Weber cannot incorporate these incongruences of synonymity and nonsynonymity into English is as unavoidable as the occasional substitution of object (in English) for thing (the German Sache or Ding) in their rendering. When, for example, Adorno writes a sentence employing three of the aforementioned German terms discretely, the English translation, in order to avoid an inevitable appearance of tautology or, at best, redundancy, is compelled to juggle the only two terms at its disposal as if two were three, making one (object) appear where the other (thing) had been:
Gerade seine Souvernitt, der Anspruch tieferen Wissens dem Objekt gegenber, die Trennung des Begriffs von seiner Sache durch die Unabhngigkeit des Urteils, droht der dinghaften Gestalt der Sache zu verfallen. [Yet his very sovereignty, the claim to a more profound knowledge of the object, the separation of the idea from its object through the independence of the critical judgment threatens to succumb to the thinglike form of the object.]13
That the meaning of Adornos dinghaft[e] Gestalt der Sache might appear more obscured than clarified if translated instead
76
Claudia Brodsky
in the only literal terms available in English as thinglike form of the thing does not alter the fact that the semantic distinctions between object and thing as between thing (Sache) and thing (Ding), and object (Gegenstand) and object (Objekt), are not immediately clear in Adorno either.14 Their usage can be quantified, but understanding their statusas object and/or thingremains as problematic as the relation between Ding (thing) and its substantivized verbal form, Verdinglichung (reification). Adorno uses the former for the most part in a neutral, even positive sense, to mean a thing recalcitrant to its own reification,15 to being conceptualized as a thing, while he employs Verdinglichung, the word for making something into a Ding, uniformly negatively in the essay, to signify those irreversible acts of objectification that are the death mask of life itself.16 If object (Gegenstand) is the word Adorno uses instead of thing (Ding) to imply the product of an act of objectification that is at once an act of reification,17 and if object (Objekt), used more frequently by Adorno, can convey, unlike object (Gegenstand) but like thing (Ding), either positive or negative connotations, the derivative terms, objective (objektiv) and objectivity (Objektivitt), gradually shed any such semantic ambivalence in the essay.18 First used in the wholly negative sense of the fictional impartiality claimed by culture critics on the basis of professional information and privilegeDas Vorrecht von Information und Stellung erlaubt ihnen, ihre Ansicht zu sagen, als wre sie die Objektivitt. Aber es ist einzig die Objektivitt des herrschenden Geistes [The privilege of information and position permit them to say their view as if it were objectivity. But it is solely the objectivity of the ruling mind]19 the very notion of objectivity, of an abstract capacity for being objective in general, for perceiving the reality of any object as such, undergoes, to use Adornos terms, an evaluative Umschlag (reversal) within the course of a single sentence:
77
Kulturkritik teilt mit ihrem Objekt dessen Verblendung. [Das volle Bewusstsein einer Gesellschaft von sich selbst] zu hintertreiben, bedarf es nicht erst der subjektiven ideologischen Veranstaltung, obwohl diese in Zeiten des historischen Umschlags die objektive Verblendung zu verstrken pflegt. [D]ass die Gesellschaft, so wie sie ist, trotz aller Absurditt doch ihr Leben unter den bestehenden Verhltnissen reproduziert, bringt objektiv den Schein ihrer Legitimation hervor. Der Schein ist total geworden in einer Phase, in der Irrationalitt und objective Falschheit hinter Rationalitt und objektiver Notwendigkeit sich verstecken. [Cultural criticism shares with its object the blindness of its object.To drive back {the full consciousness of a society of itself} does not require first a show of subjective ideology, although the latter serves to strengthen objective blindness in times of historical reversal. {T}he fact that society as it is, in spite of all absurdity, does nonetheless reproduce its life under existing relations, objectively produces the appearance of its legitimacy. The appearance has become total in a phase in which irrationality and objective falsity hide behind rationality and objective necessity.] 20
Just as objective blindness is not the same blindness cultural criticism shares with its object, but rather the real or objective condition of being blind; and just as a society that objectively produces the appearance of its legitimacy also lays the groundwork for the perception of that appearance as it really is, an appearance alone; and just as only objective falsity may be recognized for what it is, a real act of deception masked as objective necessity, so the word objective, used by Adorno to qualify the nonobjective, the blind and the untrue, negatively attains to the meaning of that which ideology can be seen to conceal and thus concretely reveals (through the objective fact of its concealment) to the world. An attention to and an abstraction from the concrete, perceptual object, objectivity ultimately names
78
Claudia Brodsky
the power of the mind to fulfill and so be unswayed by ideology, thereby changing the theory that is its articulation from speculation to action, to real violence:
Dass die Theorie zur realen Gewalt werde, wenn sie die Menschen ergreift, grndet in der Objektivitt des Geistes selber, der kraft der Erfllung seiner Ideologischen Funktion an der Ideologie irre werden muss. [That theory becomes real violence when it shakes and moves men is based in the objectivity of the mind itself, which is compelled by the fulfillment of its ideological function to stray from ideology.]21
The real violence exercised by theory that moves men is based in objectivity that is not theoretically projected by but part of the mind itself, an objectivity unconfined to objects and thus uncontrolled by ideology. In this startling observation Adorno defines theory as its oppositea violence directly affecting menand reveals the conventional sense of theory, that it must be abstracted from immediacy, to be part of the ideological function that objectivity of mind instead fulfills and goes beyond. Yet still more powerful than an object-free objectivity of the mind is an objectivity unconfined to the mind, one that Adorno attributes neither to objects, whether in themselves or as ideology presents and peddles them, nor to our enthrallment by or rejection of them, but to what he calls truth. The truth Adorno namesagain, unlike Hegelsis not the ultimate end or transcendence of the dialectical progress of the aesthetic in a synthesis of the mind with its object, the objective truth of a subjectivity rendered indistinguishable from the sensory, a mere sounding. Nor does its objectivity rest upon the given reality of a perceptual object. Rather, the objectivity of truth, according to Adorno, does not rest at all, but occurs at what he calls a moment defined only negatively by its passage: The moment of the objectivity of truth, without which dialectic cannot
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
79
be imagined (or conceived), is silently replaced by vulgar positivism and pragmatismultimately, bourgeois subjectivism.22 The moment the object of art, embodying an objecthood unlike any other, brings to perception, succumbs to the inevitable process of its conceptualization by the false objectivities of positivism and pragmatism. Yet, without that moment it would be impossible at any moment to conceive of the dialectic, to recognize the minds real distinction from the object, and vice versa. Rapidly replaced in this sentence by its oppositethe incapacity, here called bourgeois subjectivism, to perceive objects without falsely perceiving oneself in themthe moment of objectivity that Adorno ascribes not to man but to the most general of man-made abstractions, truth, may in turn shed light on Adornos concept of the most particular of man-made things, the art object. For, as opposed to a reified culture-object (Kulturobjekt), death mask not of life but of art, in whose contemplation dialectic risks entrapment, the art object is composed, like the dialectic, of contradictory moments.23 Taking aim at the contempt for objectivism that serves as pretext for cynical terror (whether in the Soviet sphere he criticizes or any other), Adorno describes an object-immanent critique that, rather than dwelling in general knowledge of the servitude of the objective mind seeks to transform this knowledge into the power of the consideration of the thing itself (der Sache selbst), one that,
where it comes across something that does not suffice, does not rapidly ascribe it to the individual and his psychology, the mere cover for failure, but seeks to derive it from the irreconcilability of the moments of the object.24
That an art object can be made of, can contain, moments, and that such moments rather than any specific content are what compose its objectivity, like that of truth, must render such an object nonobjectifiable in the very manner Hegel rejected as nonaesthetic, that of an object that is always chang80
Claudia Brodsky
ing, and thus not properly an art object at all.25 Yet, an object made of moments may well be the only proper object of a subject that alternately perceives and fails to perceive it, the mind to whose own immanent movement Adorno had attributed the overreaching claim of culture to begin with: the overreaching of the cultural claim, which is, however, immanent to the movement of the mind.26 Occurring at the opening of the essay, between negative characterizations of culture, on the one hand, and its professional critics, on the other, the descriptive phrase movement of the mind is easy enough to overlook.27 It is echoed and reflected, however, later in the essay, when Adorno defines the only objective basis of immanent critique to be an object in movement itself. Referring to what he calls the self-movement of the object, Adorno describes the necessity of freedom to any consciousness that would follow it, one that can oppose object-immanent critique to the all-engulfing immanence of culture: Without such freedom, without the departure of consciousness from the immanence of culture, immanent criticism would itself not be thinkable: the self-movement of the object can only be followed by whomever does not already belong to it.28 For Adorno, the object of immanent contemplation is the opposite of an object in any traditional philosophicalwhether ontological or dialecticalsense: it is not itself but, instead, at any moment, movement. Like, and along with, the movement of the mind, the self-movement of the object makes objectivity possible, separating the object from the immanence of culture in which it is immersed, embodying and extending outward its moments of truth. Moments of objectivity relate the movement of the object with that of the mind, and the basis for that relationfor the perception that is never fixed long enough to merge with ideology, of an object that never is one in any static senseis the form of immediacy without which there can be no art, let alone aesthetic theory, the experience by the subject of a spontaneous relation to the object:
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
81
No theory, not even that which is true, is secure from perversion into delusion when it has abdicated the spontaneous relationship to the object. Dialectic must protect itself therefrom no less than from entrapment in the cultural object. The dialectical critic must and must not take part in culture. Only then does he do justice to the thing and himself.29
The spontaneous relationship to the object cuts through culture, its accretion of information, its reification of objects. Such spontaneity, occurring and experienced involuntarily, inarticulately or, what we like to call without thinking, is not conceptual but sensuous in nature, and its absolutely necessary involvement in the impact of the aesthetic of every genre and stripe has been confronted and acknowledged in theory of the aesthetic at least since Kant, who first transformed Platos exclusion of the dangerous immediacy of the aesthetic from the dayto-day functioning of the rationally organized state into the no less dangerous premise that the immediate availability of aesthetic experience to any subject at any time is in fact necessary to the possibility of free, that is, non-object-related and noncognitive, moral action. Adornos aesthetic theory, while related by the dialectic to objects, unlike Kants, alters, no less than does Kants critical analytic of aesthetic judgment, how it is we conceive the aesthetic object we spontaneously perceive. For Adorno such an object is conceived objectively, not as it is but in its moments, moments perceptible only by a mind itself in movement. Yet, for this to happenfor an object to be perceived as moments of the objectthe immediate sensory reality of the aesthetic must be separated from its objectification: this, and not the destruction of the sensory, is the real violence of theory. Finally, for perceived moments to be further perceived as the movement of the object rather than the mind alone, the sensory must be maintained while being perceived to change, given no objective identity but the identity of objecthood, of being and remaining some thing
82
Claudia Brodsky
outside the subject. The sensory must be perceived objectively, perceived at each moment as never before, for it to appear to move independently of the subject, to move as if through the mind on its own, and the basis for such a perception of the sensuousnot in itself, as if such perception were possible, or in its identity as an object (both equal grist for ideology)is not sensuousness itself but abstraction.
The movement of the mind and self-movement of the object occur in the interaction of sensuousness with abstraction. Nowhere is the negative dialectic between the two more evident than in Adornos account of the artistic history of the artist he most admired, Arnold Schoenberg. While the thoroughly speculative Cultural Criticism and Society, abruptly interrupted in closing by the naming of Auschwitz, takes the equivocal relationships between culture and society, critic and culture, critic and society, and art and culture as its subject, the Schoenberg essay, arguably Adornos greatest on a single artist, reveals, through the specific prism of the composers technical development, a dialectical production of the objectivity of art closest to Adornos understanding of the term. Combining analysis with commemoration, it regards Schoenbergs compositions both formally and historically from the individual angles defined by the intersecting dynamics of their internal structure, relation to tradition, and contemporary reception, drawing the sinuous abstractions of the cultural criticism essay into an individual narrative that, while concrete in each instance and particular, borders closely on the allegorical, the story of a single subject matter that is at once the story of art.
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
83
On Adornos analysis, that subject matter first attains to objecthood by destroying the effortless identification of sensoryor prima facie aestheticexperience with an object, the customary crutches of a hearing that always already knows what is coming.31 In the place of these,
[Schoenbergs music] demands, that the listener spontaneously compose its inner movement along with it, and exacts of him, as it were, praxis instead of contemplation. With this Schoenberg blasphemes against the expectation cultivated in contradiction of all idealist protestations that music present itself as a series of pleasant sensory stimulations to the comfortable listener. With Schoenberg all comfortableness ceases.32
Musical objects consist naturally of the tonal moments that constitute them, moments that, in music, compose movement by definition. Yet Schoenberg demands that the subject who perceives the musical object compose its inner movement along with it. The argument for the composition in the subject of a movement accompanying (mit-komponiert) the internal movement of the objectfor the perception of a made object as form of praxis rather than contemplationis one that Schoenbergs music makes for Adorno, rather than the other way around. No dialectical critique is needed in the case of this musician for whom the language of music was self-evident and whose compositions, instead of aiming at making abstractionsa second-order language, or system of formal ideogramsout of musical sound, were thus able to invest the concrete form of music with spirit.33 It is rather Schoenbergs own movement of mind as artist his objectivization of the subjective impulsethat proceeds dialectically in Adornos analysis.34 For in order to write music that moves in freedom from the culture of music, Schoenberg had to recompose the sensory material of music whose language he already intuited, endowing sound not with recognizable sono-
84
Claudia Brodsky
rous identity but with identifiable complexity. MusicAdornos first theoretical and practical occupationprovides a name for such complexity: polyphony. Retrieving that technical term from the lexicon of Western musical history, Adorno invests it, objectively, with spirit, stating, in the plainest descriptive terms, the formal content of its experience, what we actually hear when we perceive it: the multiplicity of the simultaneous (die Vielheit des Simultanen).35 For Adorno no less than for Schoenberg, such a description describes musical and, moreover, aesthetic thinking. The separation of the sensuous from the contours of a single, identifiable objectthe very division without which there would be neither theory nor artrequires that sensuousness and abstraction be brought together in simultaneity, neither one definitively overshadowing, or overpowering, the other. And this remarkable combination of sonority with abstraction from sonorous familiarity, the ability to pull pure sound out of obscurity, was, Adorno argues, Schoenbergs greatest strength from the beginning. What its cultural reception dismisses under the preferred reproach of intellectualismreflection that remains external rather than immanent to the thingis an intuitive grasp of formal musical syntax that does not separate the intellectual from the aesthetic. And because neither structure nor sound is univocal in music, Schoenbergs refusal to subordinate one to the other produces a music of multiple simultaneities, of identity in nonidentity, that appears doubly hard to hear.36 The most common complaint against Schoenbergs music may thus be its lack of melody; yet it is not the absence of melody but the simultaneous presence of a multiplicity of melodies, of cotemporaneous musical lines, that, rather than serving a single overarching theme, are and remain distinct, which makes the music of this composera melodist to the core for whom every part of music singsappear antimelodic to the formula-bound listening habits it disorients and outstrips:
85
The reproach of being an intellectual goes together with that of a lack of melody. But he was a melodist to the core. Instead of the accepted formula he produced new forms without cease. His melodic talent can hardly be contained within one sole melody; instead, all simultaneous musical events are profiled as melodies and the perception of them thus rendered more difficult. The original musical mode of reaction of Schoenberg is itself melodic: everything is actually sung in his music, even the instrumental lines. That lends his music its articulated nature, at once free in its movement and structured down to the last tone.37
Schoenbergs transformation of inherited melodic culture makes his music appear abstract. Yet, rather than reject melody in principle, he expands the melodic field, redefining even the conventional buttresses of instrumental lines as melody-bearing, and coordinating individual melodies as simultaneous musical events. The disconcerting sound of melodies brought into structural instead of harmonious concert not only makes the immediate perception of them more difficult; it also conceals (even as it embodies), Adorno argues, its own profound rootedness in tradition. For Schoenbergs multiplicity of the simultaneous in music looks backward and forward at the same time; its dialectical organization is avant-garde in that it recalls a now distant musical (and social) past, the objective polyphonic structures, long buried under the ideology of aesthetic subjectivity, of Bach. Redefining Schoenbergs vaunted experimentalism as the rigorous unearthing of a classical anachronism, the carrying of a now alien past into a future to which the limits of the present demonstrate it pertains, Adorno offers his most compelling analysis of art as indication of historical progress-in-regress, a dialectical model of modernity that, even as it lauds technical innovation as the concrete medium of aesthetic change, aligns rather than opposes modernes with anciens. I quote from this extraordinary interpretation of Schoenbergs experimental musical practice in
86
Claudia Brodsky
relation to musical history at length, as it speaks directly to the question of the objectivity of the composition of art today:
Schoenberg thinks the unfulfilled promise of Classicism through to its end and thereby breaks down the traditional faade. He took up again the challenge of Bach, from which Classicism, Beethoven included, withdrew, without however falling behind Classicism. Classicism had neglected Bach out of historical necessity. The autonomy of the musical subject outweighed every other interest and critically excluded the historically transmitted form of objectivization, preferring to make do with the appearance of objectivization, just as the unhindered interplay of subjects seemed to guarantee society. Only today, now that subjectivity in its immediacy no longer reigns as the highest category, but is perceived to be in need of complete social realization, can we recognize the insufficiency even of Beethovens solution, which extended the subject to the whole without reconciling the whole in itself. Schoenbergs polyphony determines development as the dialectical dissolution of the subjective melodic impulse in the objectively organized multiplicity of voices.38
In the alternation of objectivization and subjectivity that Adorno outlines here, every step forward is, in hindsight, a step backward from a past moment whose promise remained unfulfilled. This, and not the traditional Hegelian plotline of the development of art (itself belied by Hegels own analysis of the production and interpretation of the aesthetic symbol as inherently ambiguous sign),39 is what Adorno calls historical necessity: the necessity, inhering in the movement of the mind, of negating the reification of the mind. Schoenberg is not Bach reborn; he is the anamnesis of Bach at a time when Bach cannot be recalled. His experimental, twelve-tone technique presents the past of music as it now is, technically and thus historically estranged. Only insofar as he makes Classicism unrecognizable as Classicism by recalling a prior objectivization of musical form, does he carry Classicism en avant, to an end
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
87
that makes its eclipse by subjective reification a part of history. The avant-garde in Adornos dialectical aesthetic history is thus not the arrire-garde but a kind of arrire-arrire-garde, avatars of forgotten forms whose transmission into the present of sensory experience makes them appear unintelligible, abstract. As such, the simultaneous multiplicity of sound that characterizes the musical avant-garde also dramatizes the nonsimultaneity across time of senses and mind. Another word for such nonsimultaneitythe transmission of classical forms into present unrecognizabilityis, Adorno suggests, tradition:
[T]he artistic extreme is responsible for obeying the logic of the thing [Sache], an objectivity no matter how hidden, or merely a private caprice, or abstract system. Its legitimacy however derives essentially from the tradition that it negates. Not only the religious but also the aesthetic tradition is the remembering of something unconscious, repressed. Tradition is present in works shunned as experimental and not in those whose own aim it is to be traditional.40
Tradition, in other words, must be lost in order to be found, and the founding of a tradition entails its certain loss. This was the fate of Schoenbergs experimental art, whose technique suffered its own stifling classicization by the twelve-tone schools, followers [who] succeeded only in displaying their own weakness, their impotent longing for security.41 Such hypostatization of art in turn follows its own historical trajectory. Whenever technical-aesthetic systems become models, retreating from self-reflection, Adorno observes, the system cripples the very impulse that had propelled it to begin; as fixed idea and universal recipe, it excludes whatever is other to its premises, all that stands outside its analytic scope.42 Multiplicity in the simultaneous, a sensuousness always abstracted at any moment by an other sensuousness from itself, constitutes the movement and art of Schoenbergs music, and,
88
Claudia Brodsky
inasmuch as that movement gives new objective life to Bach, its own life must be unsustainable, vulnerable to objectification, in the present. This fact of the irresolvable dialectic of art was lost least of all on Schoenberg, who, Adorno writes compellingly, himself experienced it as a subject: The experience that no musical subject-object can constitute itself here and today was not wasted on him.43 Indeed, rather than waste that experience, ignoring, stylizing, or ironizing it, Schoenberg put it to good historic use: he betrayed it. In doing so, he made a model of musical innovation prove nothing less than the paradoxical impossibility of the end of art: that the experience of the impossibility of uniting subject and object in art here and now is equal to the impossibility of experiencing its opposite, the overcoming or annihilation of art by absolute abstraction. For, beginning with his attempt to retreat from the rigors of twelve-tone technique, to dress it up externally in just those traditional larger forms its polyphonic structure rendered superfluous, Schoenberg belied his art by moving away from it, discarding its premise of internal forms turning outward in multiple melodic lines by exposing and then draping those lines in a sensuous skin of manifest music instead.44 Schoenberg lived to make of his own music a kind of revenant rattling mechanically, the skeleton of a previous incarnation revealed as such by an ill-fitting costume of traditional garb.45 And because the fit of old music to new music is poor, and no composer, including Schoenberg, can alter thiscan make a living body from a second skin of borrowed clothesSchoenberg jettisons the life of music, tone. Viewing all sound as mere faade, he strips it as he might strip history itself from the structure of music alone. The name for such sound as had once served not merely to adorn but to compose structure in Schoenberg is color:
Not the least of Schoenbergs acts integrating musical means was his definitive removal of color from the sphere of orna-
89
mentation and raising of it to a compositional element in its own right. It changes into a means for the elucidation of the contextual whole. Its being integrated into the composition, however, becomes its condemnation. The more nakedly the construction represents itself, the less it requires coloristic assistance. Mature music creates suspicion of all real sound as such. The inclination to silence, which shapes the aura of every tone in Weberns lyric, is directly related to this tendency originating in Schnberg. No less is its ultimate outcome, however, that, in abolishing sensuous appearance, maturity and intellectualization virtually abolishes art itself.46
Whether, per Hegel, the aesthetic is the sensory appearance of the idea, sensory appearance in Adorno is the experiential medium without which there can be no art. The desire to abolish all sensuousness may stem from the wish to preserve art from its own perversion, to abstract its objectivity from the always imperfect here and now of its reception and reification in history, yet such intellectualization of art, Adorno concludes, rather than saving art, converges with barbaric enmity to art.47 The penultimate sentence of the cultural criticism essay appears to state, of course, the exact opposite, to define instead a historic boundary beyond which the very composition of art and barbarism are one, and it is in the context of Adornos historical account of Schoenbergs art that the full measure of his reflections on writing a poem after Auschwitz should be cited and read:
Cultural criticism finds itself confronted by the last phase of the dialectic of culture and barbarism: to write a poem after Auschwitz is barbaric; and this corrodes even the knowledge which articulates why it has become impossible to write poetry today.48
The equation of art after Auschwitz with barbarism is, in the words of the Schoenberg essay, the reflection of a tendency toward maturity and intellectualization [that] virtually abolish[es] art itself (see note 46). As such it is in itself anti-art,
90
Claudia Brodsky
barbaric, corrod[ing] our very ability to know and articulate exactly what is most worth knowing: why it has become impossible to write poetry today (emphasis added). By negating the independent objecthood of the sensuous appearance of art to comeby defining the future history of art as a history of barbarism in the makingsuch an abstraction from art does not render art itself but rather our ability to reflect upon it (in whatever form it appears to us) impossible. Easier to cite ad infinitum in part than to read once to its completion, Adornos difficult, doubly negative observation here has proven positively apt: nothing has demonstrated the accuracy of its conclusion more effectively than the innumerable instances of its quotation that leave this conclusion out. Whether employed to introduce another plastic work of next-generation German or American art, or theindeed unequalledpostwar achievements of the German-language poet, and survivor of a Romanian labor camp, Paul Celan (n Antschel), cultural critics have pointed to Adorno, or, rather, their monophrastic surrogate for him, in the conviction that they, with art on their side, have proven his prediction wrong. The noncritical pieties that have invariably ensuedone part moral outrage to two parts praise for the ennobling virtues of art, as a rulehave instead served precisely to make Adornos point. To consider art not only as fully available to but also as fully transcendent of human life is, in Adornos aesthetic theory, to misunderstand both profoundly. Abstract and sensuous by nature, part of culture and free of culture, the objecthood of art is no substitute for the subjecthood of life and approaches barbarism when it pretends to be. Since art is instead already a part of life and of subjecthood, the medium of our abstraction from abstraction, of a sensuous immediacy not given but made, the abstract abolition of art, its mature prohibition, must also abolish history, the very possibility that every day is not today, another anniversary of the act of total objectification, birthday of death by daily mass murder.
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
91
Schoenberg, Adorno notes, understood this perfectly, or at least as perfectly as the nonidentical lives of history and art would allow. Any art whose promises appeared capable of being fulfilled in reality is already an emasculated art; and anyone who, unlike Schoenberg, chooses art over surviving death by barbarism is, in a critical sense, already dead.49 Rather than sacrifice sensuous life to art and the sensuousness of art to its totalizing abstraction, the late Schoenberg, Adorno concludes, produces art in the form of the fragment, art that is itself a sensuous representation of the impossibility of art here and now.50 The brief Jewish song sung by the Survivor from Warsaw represents the whole [of mankind] not as its model, or timeless intellectualization, but as victim, a body able to give voice to its own negation as voice and objectification as body, a subject that is not whole. Schoenbergs sensuous manifestation of knowledge of life annihilated, sung by one who knows himself alive only in part, is his refusal to abdicate a spontaneous relation to the object, no matter how fragmentary, just as he refused to sacrifice life for art. For, in the absence of the spontaneous relationship to the object that allows us to experience what we do not know, life as well as theory undergo perversion into delusion, the barbarism of an intellectualism and fascism according to which no object need be experienced since all objects outside the subject are superfluous. To return to the terms of the cultural criticism essay, Schoenbergs final fragments contain the freedom of consciousness to go beyond and so negate the identification of art with either pure sensuousness or intellectual objectification. In contemporary visual art in which the identity of the object of art is in question, we may call this negative freedom framing.
92
Claudia Brodsky
If Clement Greenberg had not written, the artists he advocated might have had to invent him, but certainly modern art itself would never have gained the clear contours of a conceptual history. By defining the art object, specifically painting, as a made thing uniquely determined by its medium, Greenberg famously translated Kants nonmimetic aesthetics and, in particular, his mathematical and dynamic sublimeexemplified in the Third Critique by infinite number and magnitude, the violent force of nature, and purely verbal reality of poetryinto the field of traditional aesthetic objects proper. Greenberg saw the sublime substantiated in the least Kantian of sublime perceptual objects, painting, and in so doing he not only severed modern art from the trompe-loeil presentation and reception of images but did so in a manner reminiscent of Hegels theory of the origin of all art in the pyramids. The power of abstract expressionist painting for Greenberg, like that of Hegels properly (eigentliche) inscrutable (unentzifferbar) symbols (Symbolik), was to render abstract the very notion of expression by expressing objective opacity, its own shaped reality, alone, remaining infinitely enigmatic (rtselhaft) in remaining material, nonrepresentational, to the core.52 Like Hegel and unlike Kant, Greenberg defined a particular moment in art containing within it the possibility of all art, a moment that Hegel, unlike Greenberg, circumscribed theoretically to be, in its highest determination, a thing of the past (nach der Seite seiner hchsten Bestimmung fr uns ein Vergangenes).53 That Hegel defined the highest determination of art as its specifically religious use and meaning, one that, paradoxically, already outstrips art itself, is a consideration as routinely deleted from
93
the frequent citation of this first philosophical pronouncement of the end of art as is the dialectical negation with which Adorno immediately succeeds his own paradoxical equation of art after Auschwitz with barbarism. There is no doubt that, just as the pyramids, pummeled by natural and human history alike, still stand, and art in its enigmatic determination as art continues after Auschwitz to be made (including, not least of all, some of the greatest poetry ever to be written in German), the abstraction in art Greenberg championed as identical with art in its essence continues to be made with moving power or, in Adornos words, with the objectivity of truth, the movement of the object perceived rather than reified by that of the mind it brings about. Yet, once we know that the art object is composed of moments in Adorno and recognize in Schoenbergs polyphony Adornos fundamental theory of multiplicity in simultaneityan aesthetic theory that makes movement rather than an identifiable object the defining quality of objecthood in artwe may begin to perceive the continuing schisms in contemporary visual art, both between nonfigural art and pervasive image reproduction and between the making of art objects and the making of art out of objects, as less definitive than they appear in their high-modern delineation by Greenberg or, for that matter, in the account of their origin in ancient Egypt given by Hegel. As in Schoenberg, the sensory element of color, here in a real rather than aesthetic-metaphoric sense, is central to the development of abstraction in modern painting, just as the crafted questioning of color in series of black or, alternatively, white paintings has composed a common step in the many diverse paths that have led painting away from the figurepaths forged in the work of Kazimir Malevich, Ad Reinhardt (whose comments on colors uncontrollable and thus amoral nature are well known), Clyfford Still, Frank Stella, Jackson Pollock, Mark Rothko, and Sean Scully among others.54 Color being what it is, it has no proper ideological provenance or terrain, and the roster
94
Claudia Brodsky
of modern painters who, since Ruskin, have made colorimpossibly pure or composite color, thickly or thinly layered, materializing or dissolving before our eyes; color flattening the depth of objects or deepening the painted plane, presented in an indivisible spectrum or solid geometric shapesinto the visceral things and building blocks of modern art is similarly varied and long.55 Including, of course, such twentieth-century masters as Henri Matisse and Piet Mondrian, bourgeois rebels sui generis, it extends back, with Ruskin, to the extraordinarily productive career, spanning over half a century, of the barbers son-cum-academician, Turner, whose aesthetically revolutionary and popularly appealing paintings remained as committed to the traditional mimetic genres of landscape, architectural, historical, and travel painting, as they were to the production on canvas of a central drama of color and light. To look at Turners sunsets, daybreaks, and storm- and fire-filled skies, overpowering in their expanse the delicate structures and actions they touch, surrounding these mimetic objects in chasms of modulated color, whether in the form of mountains forever rising or in amorphous reflecting surfaces, is to wonder, first, in the age of Joshua Reynolds, how he got away with it, and second, if the dissolution of the object into an immediate vividness of color constitutive of the abstract art object hadnt reached its apex some two hundred years before abstract expressionism began.56 To this list of artists for whom color became the object of art, and depicted objects became in turn the body and occasion of color no matter how exquisitely detailed or broadly brushed into being these objects may have been, in the manner of Turner or Matisse, respectivelywe may, of course, add our own nominees. Scully includes Rembrandt, Masaccio, Vincent Van Gogh, and Giorgio Morandi in the tradition of painting color that is Rothkos and his own, and alongside these we may include several of Rothkos own near and exact contemporaries, each of whom presents the primacy of color to the shaping of perception, Wassily Kandinsky,
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
95
Morris Louis, Helen Frankenthaler, and Ellsworth Kelly, among others. Curt Barnes calls the effect the concentration upon the painterly application of color has had upon the history and definition of the art object dialectical and offers an excellent analysis of its recent evidence. First describing the attempt of Stellas shaped polyhedral and aluminum relief paintings to include threedimensional space within painting without resorting to colorist methodsnever a colorist, Stella may not have understood the potential of color to create its own authoritative space, one that could rival and work in counterpoint to the physicalBarnes highlights the role of color in deepening the physical/pictorial, or spatial/planar, dialectic of modern painting:
Sean Scully, James Biederman, Larry Brown, and others developed multiple-paneled pieces whose obtrusive physicalities depended primarily on the panels varying thicknesses or distances from the wall plane. For all of these artists, the painterly application of color, the sensitive, complex, banal, historically charged practice of applying paint with a brush was key to the complex kinds of interaction they achieved with the painting support. Reframed in the physical/pictorial equation, paint could acquire new potentials for mystery and paradox, ambiguity and irony, and at the same time plant itself firmly in the physical continuum. Paint application can parallel the shape of the support. Color can move continuously across separate panels, or jump their boundaries. The scale of painted form, as for example Scullys varying width of stripe, can contradict the topographic locationthat is, the thicknessof the panels. And then there is the power of color itself to advance, recede, hover, pulsate, merge, expand, contract.57
A nonmimetic art object made of color applied to canvas, whether densely layered within irregular rectangles or poured into diaphanous curves it creates, is sensuousness abstracted from the objects of the world, a framing of sensuousness as such.58 Sensuousness in itselfas present as it is unperceived in every96
Claudia Brodsky
day objectsis made, through its framing, its separation from the subjective experiences of which it is a part, to embody the quality of objecthood even while resisting the blindnesses of conventional sight and conceptual reification. In the place of things known and ignored, sensuousness set apart from the things in which it takes part presents an unsettling multiplicity of the simultaneous in visual form: the sense of what is, as never before, and what is not available to the senses. Sensuousness framed creates an object of perception that, for no conceptual reason, commands rather than serves our attention, a thing whose experience has neither timeframe nor expiration date, that never appears one with any end it could serve. The framing of sensuousness in visual art after Adornothe sensuousness without which Adorno declared there can be no artallows us to see, or at least to approach the experience of seeing sensuous experience in itself, which is to say, it makes visible in at once immediate and modern allegorical form our own ability to abstract not (an abstract) meaning from (sensuous) pictures but the purely sensuous from the nonpictorial, the abstract. In the absence of mimetic mediation, in the identity of their appearance with their medium, sensuousness and abstraction contain each other in the manner of Hegels permanently illegible symbol. And for the same reason they are also free, in the manner of Kants imagination and reason, to conflict violently, making of the mere act of sensuous perception a form of sublimity. Such a description of sensuousness abstracted from objects appears at odds with that artistic tendency now long thought to have put abstraction to bed: the collection of circulated objects, images, and all species of information into an art object, often through flagrantly anti-aesthetic methods.59 Mechanical acts of insertion and attachment by which an artificially composed three-dimensionality calls attention to itself, and technologies of reproduction that, lacking all real physical and conceptual boundaries, appear to emphasize the essential flatness of images, their kinFraming the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
97
ship with information itself, rather than the three-dimensional subjects they represent, are sensuous only in the most explicitly arbitrary or implicitly secondary sense. These are art forms whose content Adorno condemned as mere communication, whose techniques Scully identifies with advertising, and that Barnes calls not art at all but novel forms of documentation to which he opposes the physical/pictorial dialectic of painting as follows:
Given an art world whose furnishings have to change like the frames in a music video to keep its public interested, it may now be time for us to move beyond the flattening accessibility of the literal to acknowledge the more persistent challenges of the visual.60
Habermas has referred in strikingly similar terms to the flattening of the semantic threshold that obtains whenever arbitrarily encountered objects are recontextualized as art: Just as Joseph Cornell administers his found oddities to the imaginary place of a display cabinet, we can also see how the things one might encounter on a beach cross the semantic threshold, as soon as they are removed by the collector from the context of the place where they were originally discovered.61 Yet perhaps the greatest and certainly most prolific of artists to have shuffled the decks of life and art togetherto have made art out of the transposition, combination, and interchangeability of images and objects and treated the world as if it were a canvas, applying color equally to objects and images alikeespoused and practiced the view that such semantic distinctions are inimical to art, a deathly abstraction from an art object now defined as the original construction of a context. Asked to comment on the subjects of the photographs employed in his series Ground Rules (1997), Robert Rauschenberg responds that the very question misses the point:
Thats one of the things that I feel is a distraction from the reality of a work. It pulls it out of contextmakes it a foreign reference to something that has all been integrated into a new
98
Claudia Brodsky
life and relationship. Taking each image out of context is a question of manageability and encourages the separation that I think is false.62
The joys of juxtapositionof transferring disparate unknown and familiar images together onto new, self-evidently extrinsic surfaces, coloring them and/or their support, mixing them with three-dimensional objects, found or fabricated or notmight seem in Adornos view a fully negative version of aesthetic freedom, one that accepts ideological content as either unimportant or perversely integral to art. Of the method he employed in his unfruitful collaboration with Alain Robbe-Grilleta case of two extremes that, pace Pascal, did not meetRauschenberg stated: I dont fiddle with the code of language, I accept it as a second nature which I dont put into question. The work that I do attack is the code of narrative.63 One might say in response that, while leaving the code of language intact, Rauschenberg attacks narrative tout court: not the code or second-order system for combining different known grammatical and semantic identities, for sorting and joining the information that the messages of narrative transmit, but the structural possibility of achieving any form of meaningful sequencing that Hal Foster has called narrative syntax, sequencing whose performance is consequential in effect.64 Little distinguishes Rauschenbergs work more and distinguishes it from the separation of sensuousness and secondhand information called abstract art more thoroughly than such an attack on syntactic form: from Willem de Kooning, to Rothko, to Scully today, not to speak of their myriad contemporaries and predecessors, nothing could be more integral to nonfigural art than its syntax, the placement of each line, layer, and shape of pigment in relation to each other.65 And perhaps nothing represented more dramatically the power Rauschenberg derived from defying or ignoring syntactic relations than his midcareer work Hiccups (1978), ninety-seven sheets of solvent-transfer images, as unrelated by any overarching formal structure as they are disconFraming the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
99
nected in content, whose aleatory extension, at nearly sixty-three feet, impeded its being seen in full even when fully exhibited. Yet, confronted with compilations and translations of images by an artist who, as Faye Hirsch suggests, has perhaps seen too much, a question regarding our own experience of his art arises: what do we see, who do not see with his eyes? Reviewing the Ground Rules series, Hirsch goes on to speculate:
In a paradox that characterizes the series as a whole, the quality in the photographs of lost origins (of rarely knowing, for example, where they were shot) and their subject matter (the worlds preoccupation with itself) seems even more hermetic when offered up in a package that so generously proffers the immediate, visually tangible pleasures of color. One almost expects to retrieve from them what can never be had.66
Adornos dialectical theory of the objectivity of art indicates that what can never be had from immediate sensory pleasures, whether of visually tangible color or familiar harmonic melody, is not merely information, the lost origin and subject matter of the particular art object, but the very freedom to appropriate all objects at which Rauschenberg aims. The negation of that freedom for Adorno, even as the immediate sensory quality of artof color and songremains in effect, makes tangible the decidedly mixed pleasures of art as fragment. The intersection of exhaustion and exuberance that characterizes Rauschenbergs art objectsfrom the juxtaposition of the compositionally stunning Combine paintings with the surrealist association of objects in the freestanding Combines, to the unfinished 1 4 Mile or 2 Furlong Piece, which, started in 1981 and projected, at 189 contiguous panels, to be the longest art object in the world, has been exhibited only at stages of its developmentexpands Adornos definition considerably: all art in Rauschenberg is merely a fragment of possible art, and all the worlds information is arts lost origin.
100
Claudia Brodsky
If Jasper Johnss very different handling of information seeks to depict the possibility that a wholerepresented in the abstract ways in which alone we may perceive it, that is, as series, graphic symbol, or iconcan be thrown, as Johns stated, into a situation in which it is only a part; and if Warhols magnification of information into art instead elided the hierarchical opposition of part and whole, as of commercial object and art object, by negating, as Arthur Danto has observed, the perceptual grounds for distinguishing art from reality in the first place; then Rauschenberg, with an ever-expanding palette of reproductive processes and parts of the perceptual world at his disposal, submerges the cognitive opposition between sensuousness and information: between Hegels hard, illegible symbols and his encyclopedic taxonomy of comparative art forms, between the pyramid at the origin of art and the pyramid of the postcard image. Rauschenberg suggests that pyramid and postcard pyramid, the origin and end of the production and experience of art, are one, and he does this in artworks that present recontextualizations of information to the senses.67 Neither identical with nor possible without their particular sensory media, equally at odds with the objective movement of art and the objectification of art as kitsch, Rauschenbergs juxtapositional art resembles a multiplicity of the simultaneous effected in the absence of polyphony, one piece of information and one sensuous medium no more necessarily conjoined to each other than to any other, one image as transferable at will as another. This is an immediacy that flattens not so much semantic thresholds as our very ability to perceive the difference between sensuous matter and abstraction. It may be too neat, and certainly too glib, to say, even if only by way of illustration, that Rauschenbergs art represents in many ways the necessarily nonliteral translation of his literal dyslexia, the turning ever outward of his minds internal eye toward an open lexicon of perceptual images embraced in all the seeming contingency of their actual appearance in the real world; and
Framing the Sensuous: Objecthood and Objectivity in Art After Adorno
101
that the inexhaustible interrelatedness of Scullys compositions of layer to layer of paint within each stripe, of stripe to stripe within and across blocks, and of each block of slightly different dimension and density to each otheris the anamnesis and animation, in an unfathomable interplay of geometry, color, and light, of a syntax already made clearly materially visible to and by him when he worked as a young typesetter, horizontally and vertically positioning blocks of different point sizes within fixed rectilinear spaces. For Scullys paintings allow us to guess at the depth behind the surface that the superficial imprint of typeface does not record, the weight and heft of the geometrical solid that sustains and holds it in place, here simulated not by an object attached combine-like to the canvas but by surfaces betraying other surfaces of paint and, emerging from between their uneven delineation, the present view and future prospect of the contradiction of solidity, light.68 In taking and assembling information out of context, Rauschenberg, by contrast, renders information sensuous. By substituting no formal aesthetic syntax for the lost syntax of history, he lends the images he places on surfaces the self-contradictory immediacy of wistfulness. Abstracted from the origins of their individual significance and circulation by culture, Rauschenbergs are images and objects applied to the pursuit of something other than happiness. The shadow of their own uselessness that they cast upon the viewer projects not the continuing conceptual reification of the object but the space and occasion for a disorienting perception of depth. Shorn like orphaned words and letters of syntactic relation and construction, it remains entirely unclear, however, what this unfamiliar depth portends. If the paradox of the impossibility of art after Adorno was that the survivors of barbarism have not survived barbarism, just as fragments can no longer be fragments, parts that remain of what was never whole, then the paradox of the possibility of art after Adorno is that the object of art itself is split. Yet this, we may now
102
Claudia Brodsky
also say, is the difficult guarantee of its objectivity. The critical movement the viewer must make between abstract forms rendered sensuous, thick, and uneven with history, in an irreversible sedimentation of pigment, and images and objects whose abstraction from history casts all historical experience in an eerie light, maintains a spontaneous relation to the object while perceiving in it the multiplicity of the simultaneous. In abstracting information, and in making color informative in its own right, these art objects are certainly antithetical to each other, yet no more so than is the undertaking of cultural criticism itself, whose flagrant contradiction, Adorno reminds us, is first made known to us by way of the senses themselves:
Whoever is used to thinking with his ears, must be annoyed by the sound of the word culture-critique not only because, like automobile, it is pieced together of Latin and Greek. It recalls a flagrant contradiction. Culture does not suit the culture-critic.69
Adorno describes Schoenbergs compositions in the same heterogeneous terms used here, as music of the intellectual ear.70 Unlike the trajectory toward the overcoming of art recursively traced by Hegel, the objecthood of art after Adorno persists in pieced together antithetical relations perceived whenever, thinking with our eyes or ears, we abstract the object from its reification. Just as the art object embodying a movement of moments, of multiplicity in simultaneity is any thing but an object in Adorno, so this act of abstractionspontaneous in its relation to the object, historical in its transmission or traditionis temporal, experiential, and not abstract. It objectively perceives the apparently impossible object, whole fragment, and flagrant contradiction that art frames as sensuousness for the mind.
103
Endnotes
1
T. W. Adorno, Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft, in Prismen. Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft (Frankfurt, 1955), pp. 29, 22: Keine Theorie, und auch die wahre nicht, ist vor der Perversion in den Wahn sicher, wenn sie einmal der spontanen Beziehung auf das Objekt sich entussert hat; Das Moment der Objektivitt der Wahrheit, ohne das Dialektik nicht vorgestellt werden kann. All subsequent citations from Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft are from this edition. (All translations from the German, unless otherwise indicated, are my own.) Frank Stella quoted in Felicity Barringer, Matisse: Hes Kind of Cast a Spell on Me, Artnews 92 (April 1993): p. 150. T. W. Adorno, sthetische Theorie, ed. Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedemann (Frankfurt, 1970), Editorisches Nachwort, p. 537. Adorno and Tiedemann state of the unfinished volume: Ihr Bruchstzuckhaftes ist der Eingriff des Todes in ein Werk, bevor es das Gesetz seiner Form ganz verwirklicht hatte ([The] fragmentary nature [of Aesthetic Theory] is the intervention of death in a work before it has realized the law of its form; p. 538). The self-critical essay, Der Essay als Form, in which many of Adornos reflections on cultural criticism are mirrored, first appeared in Theodor W. Adorno, Noten zur Literatur, vol. 1 (Frankfurt, 1958). Der Kulturkritiker kann kaum die Unterstellung vermeiden, er htte die Kultur, welche dieser abgeht. Seine Eitelkeit kommt der ihren zu Hilfe; Adorno, Kulturkritik, 7. Ibid., p. 31: [N]ach Auschwitz ein Gedicht zu schreiben, ist barbarisch. The three-part sentence in which these words appear is cited in full and further analyzed later in this essay. It is exactly this already abstract quality of music, as pure medium of sensation, that has made it a model for modern abstract art. Cf. Clement Greenberg, Towards a Newer Laocoon, in Clement Greenberg: The Collected Essays and Criticism, vol. 1, Perceptions and Judgments, 19391944, ed. John OBrian (Chicago, 1986), pp. 2337 (31): Aside from what was going on inside music, music as an art in itself began [after Romanticism] to occupy a very important position in relation to the other arts. Because of its absolute nature, its remoteness from imitation, its almost complete absorption in the very physical quality of its medium , music had come to replace poetry as the paragon art. It was the art which the other avantgarde arts envied most, and whose effects they tried hardest to imitate. [T]he advantage of music lay chiefly in the fact that it was an abstract art, an art of pure form incapable, objectively, of communicating anything else than a sensation, and because sensation could not be conceived in any other terms than those of the sense through which it entered the consciousness. The most thorough consideration not only of Adornos statement and
Claudia Brodsky
104
the ongoing critical reaction to it but also, perhaps most importantly, of Adornos own dialectical response to the controversy his comment ignited, is Robert Kaufmans Poetrys Ethics? Theodor W. Adorno and Robert Duncan on Aesthetic Illusion and Sociopolitical Delusion, New German Critique 97 (Winter 2006): pp. 73118. See esp. pp. 98104 for Adornos reflections on his earlier statement in the 1965 lectures on metaphysics subsequently incorporated into Negative Dialectics (1966) and the centrality of aesthetic semblance to the conception of negative dialectics itself. See also pp. 11314 for Kaufmans fine reading of the relation Adorno draws between the seeming impossibility of poetry after Auschwitz and that of life, and his interpretation of Adornos insight that the apparent unavailability of [the] semblance-character of art is itself a negative knowledge that can be gained only through the attempt at semblance-character (114).
8
Sean Scully, quoted in R. Eric Davis, Sean Scullys Preoccupations: An Interview, On Paper (JulyAug. 1998): pp. 2429 (29). Adorno, Kulturkritik, p. 25: Dialektik heisst Intransigenz gegenber jeglicher Verdinglichung.
10
Perhaps it should be underscored at this point that the use of the term objecthood in the present analysis of the art object after Adorno relates, first, to the Hegelian subject-object dialectic, including the abstraction or, in the case of the aesthetic object, the nominalizationof the object Hegel predicts; and, second, to Adornos development of the notion of an object-immanent objectivity to counter the underlying subjective bias of objective reasoning in Hegel. The significance attributed to objecthood here should not be confused with the meaning given it by Michael Fried, who, employing the term to reference the rejection of pictoral illusion and anthropomorphism in favor of the creation of Specific Objects advocated by Donald Judd, viewed its achievement as the goal of a specific movement in modern artminimalist, or as Fried calls it, literalist, non-artthat, in his view, seeks to replace art, defined as object and painting, by singleness of shape. See Michael Fried, Art and Objecthood, Artforum 5 (June 1967): pp. 1223, later incorporated in Art and Objecthood: Essays and Reviews (Chicago, 1998), see pp. 14853 esp. As the attempt is made here to demonstrate, objecthood, understood dialectically instead of derivatively, i.e., as deriving from the givenness of objects, suggests nearly the opposite of Frieds description of the anti-art view of art as nothing more than objects. Rather, it refers to our dynamic experience of a thing made to remain outside us, to resist reification in Adornos sense, an object that, in that it originates in relation to a subject (no matter how contingent or determined that relation may be), must contradict the subjects view of it as nothing more than an object, whether that nothing equates to mere externality, instrument, or even mirror of the self. In the pages that follow, objecthood, then, names the inassimilable, because sensuous and
105
abstract, quality of the art object, the quality that compels the subject who perceives it to follow out its movement mentally, an objectivity composed of sensuousness framed or sensuousness made by framing. Finally, while Fried understandably employs objecthood historically to distinguish divergent paths through the conflictual landscape of visual art in the second half of the last century, this analysis understands under objecthood the quality, difficult (as Hegel already demonstrated) for any path of aesthetic development to maintain over time, in which distinct kinds of art objectsabstract and figurative; painterly, sculptural, and photographic; combined, copied, and foundconverge in the challenge each poses to the mind through the senses and, through the mind, to the future history of art. A similar view to Frieds early critique of Judds rejection of the painted illusion of space for real space, and of the relational rendering of space in and around marks and colours for specific, threedimensional objects, is developed by Donald Kuspit; see Nuance and Intensity in Sean Scully: Humanism in Abstract Disguise, in Sean Scully: Body of Light (Melbourne, 2004), pp. 4551 (48, 50).
11
See G. W. F. Hegel, Vorlesungen ber die sthetik, vol. 1315 of Theorie Werkausgabe, ed. E. Moldenhauer and K. M. Michel, 20 vols. (Frankfurt, 1977), 14: pp. 140ff. On the further equation of sound with sign in Hegel, and consequent circularity of the notion of the end of the aesthetic his dialectical history of art forms proposes, see my From the Pyramids to Romantic Poetry: Housing the Spirit in Hegel, in Rereading Romanticism, ed. Martha Helfer (Amsterdam, 2000), pp. 32766. Cf. Adorno, Kulturkritik, p. 15: Versperrt ist dem Kulturkritiker die Einsicht, dass die Verdinglichung des Lebens selbst nicht auf einem Zuviel, sondern einen Zuwenig an Aufklrung beruhe und dass die Verstmmelungen, welche der Menschheit von der gegenwrtigen partikularistischen Rationalitt angetan werden, Schandmale der totalen Irrationalitt sind (The cultural critic is blocked from the insight that the reification of life rests not on too much but on too little enlightenment, and that the mutilations that present, particularistic rationality inflicts upon man are the stigmata of total irrationality).
12
13
T. W. Adorno, Cultural Criticism and Society, in Prisms, trans. Samuel and Shierry Weber (Cambridge, 1981), pp. 1734 (23; emphases added for clarity). On at least one important occasion, when redundancy in English is not at issue, the Webers similarly translate Sache as object, perhaps so as to underscore preceding uses of the latter term: No theory, not even that which is true, is safe from perversion into delusion once it has renounced a spontaneous relation to the object [Objekt]. Dialectics must guard against this no less than against enthrallment in the cultural object [Kulturobjekt]. It can subscribe neither to the cult of the mind nor to hatred of it. The dialectical critic of culture must both participate in culture and not participate. Only then does he do justice to his object
Claudia Brodsky
106
Throughout sthetische Theorie, for example, Objekt is used whenever Hegels subject-object dialectic is directly under discussion (see pp. 24462 esp.), but that is where Adornos specification of object as word or meaning more or less ends. While Gegenstand and Sache are sometimes distinguished from Objekt in their connotation of concrete things, that distinction, untenable in its English translation, often does not hold up well in Adornos own phrasing, Gegenstand sometimes taking on a connotation of mimetic content along with its literal meaning of object, and Sache conveying at least the following disparate senses: that of an intellectual issue or question; of a literal thing; or of a dialectically required apposite term to Objekt: Die Subject- Objekt-Dialektik trgt bei Hegel in der Sache sich zu. Zu denken ist auch ans Verhltnis von Subjekt und Objekt im Kunstwerk, soweit es mit Gegenstnden zu tun hat. Es ndert sich geschichtlich, lebt jedoch nach auch in den ungegenstndlichen Gebilden, die zum Gegenstand Stellung beziehen, indem sie ihn tabuieren (p. 24445); Im Gebilde ist Subjekt weder der Betrachter noch der Schpfer noch absoluter Geist, vielmehr der an die Sache gebundene, von ihr prformiert, seinerseits durchs Objekt vermittelt (p. 248; emphases added for clarity). The Lenhardt translation, T. W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. C. Lenhardt (London, 1984), of the passages that follow renders Sache alternately as the thing under discussion and object, and redefines Gegenstnde as concrete tangible things (rather than maintaining its literal meaning, objects), but translates ungegenstndlichen as nonrepresentational, and finally Gegenstand as object, these last three semantic versions of a single word all occurring in the course of two consecutive sentences: In Hegel the subject-object dialectic occurs in the thing under investigation (in der Sache [sic]). Another problem might be that of how subject and object are related when art deals with concrete tangible things [Gegenstnden]. This relation has changed historically, and yet it lives on even in the non-representational [ungegenstndlichen] works of today, for they too take a position on the object [Gegenstand], if only tacitly: they taboo it.The subject in a work of art is neither the viewer nor the creative artist nor some absolute spirit. It is spirit, to the extent to which it is embedded in, and mediated and performed by, the object [Objekt] (pp. 234, 238; emphases added for clarity).
Such a lexical analysis of the Lenhardt and Weber translations is aimed not at critiquing their individual versions of Adornos texts, but rather at indicating the real uncertainty of how we are to view and name the object variously designated in those original texts themselves, an uncertainty that the problem of the translation of object makes evident, but only insofar as it is already part and parcel of the full thrust of Adornos theory of art.
15
107
Verdinglichung already appeared in the past participle form of a related verb, of which Ding is the root, in the epigrammatic definition of the artwork in Minima moralia (1951; reprint, Frankfurt, 1993), p. 142: Jedes Kunstwerk ist eine abgedungene Untat (Every artwork is a crime that has been paid for [or paid off; from dingen: to pay someone to commit a crime]; emphasis added).
16
Leben verwandelt sich in die Ideologie der Verdinglichung, eigentlich die Maske des Toten (Life transforms itself into the ideology of reification, properly the mask of the dead); Adorno, Kulturkritik, p. 24. The impenetrable Ding and its derivatives appear in the following instances in the essay: unabdingbares Element (ineluctable, or, literally, ununthingable element; p. 11); dinghafte Gestalt der Sache (thingly form of the thing; p. 13); Verdinglichung des Lebens (reification of life) and [L]ieber soll das Ende aller Dinge kommen, als dass die Menschheit der Verdinglichung ein Ende macht ([O]ne would rather the end of all things come than mankind put an end to reification; p. 15); als Mass aller Dinge (as the measure of all things; p. 17); wie gelungene Verdinglichung, also Trennung (as successful reification, that is, separation; p. 25); der Gegensatz der von aussen und von innen eindringenden Erkenntnis selber als Symptom jener Verdinglichung (the opposition of knowledge imposing itself from inside and from outside as itself symptom of that reification; p. 28); [D]ie Methode [macht] eben jene Verdinglichung sich zu eigen, die sie zum kritischen Thema hat ([M]ethod makes the very reification that is its critical theme its own; p. 29); Begriffe verdinglichten Wesens benutzt, wie die Gesellschaft selber vedinglicht ist ([It] uses concepts of reified essence or being insofar as society itself is reified; p. 29); Je totaler die Gesellschaft, um so verdinglichter auch der Geist, und um so paradoxer sein Beginnen, der Verdinglichung aus eigenem sich zu entwinden (The more total the society, the more reified the spirit, and the more paradoxical its beginning to disentangle itself from reification on its own; p. 30); [D]er absoluten Verdinglichung ist der kritische Geist nicht gewachsen, solange er bei sich bleibt in selbstgengsamer Kontemplation ([C]ritical spirit is no match for absolute reification as long as it remains in self-sufficient contemplation with itself; p. 31). In contrast to Ding, Sache is used, often idiomatically, to convey both material and conceptual connotations of thing; see pp. 13, 23, 27, 28, 29.
17
Cf. Indem [der Kulturkritiker] Kultur zu seinem Gegenstand macht, vergegenstndlicht er sie nochmals. Ihr eigener Sinn aber ist die Suspension von Vergegenstndlichung (In that the cultural critic makes culture into his object, he objectifies it again. Its own meaning, however, is the suspension of objectification); Adorno, Kulturkritik, p. 12. See ibid., pp. 12, 28, 29, 30, for uses of Gegenstand; pp. 13, 19, 22, 27, 28, 29, for positive and negative uses of Objekt.
18
108
Claudia Brodsky
19
Ibid., p. 9 (emphases added for clarity). Ibid., pp. 1920 (emphases added for clarity). Ibid., p. 20 (emphases added for clarity). See also: Kultur ist ideologisch geworden nicht nur als Inbegriff der subjektiv ausgeheckten Manifestationen des objektiven Geistes (Culture has become ideological not only as the very essence of subjectively fashioned manifestation of the objective mind; p. 24, emphasis added for clarity). Ibid., p. 22: Das Moment der Objektivitt von Wahrheit, ohne das Dialektik nicht vorgestellet werden kann, wird stillschweigend durch vulgren Positivismus und Pragmatismusin letzter Instanz: brgerlichen Subjetivismusersetzt (emphasis added). Ibid., p. 27: Solche Kritik bescheidet sich nicht bei dem allgemeinen Wissen von der Knechtschaft des objektiven Geistes, sondern sucht dies Wissen in die Kraft der Betrachtung der Sache selbst umzusetzen. Wo sie aufs Unzulngliche stsst, schreibt sie es nicht eilfertig dem Individuum und seiner Psychologie, dem blossen Deckbild des Misslingens zu, sondern sucht es aus der Unversnlichkeit der Momente des Objekts abzuleiten (emphasis added).
20 21
22
23
Ibid., p. 29.
24
25
It is for their own objective permanence and inscrutability, as well as the embalmed bodies they remove in perpetuity from the world, that Hegel identified the Egyptian pyramids as the symbolic proper (eigentliche Symbolik) or true origin of art, in direct contrast to the ongoing metamorphosis of organic bodies celebrated by the Hindus. See Hegel, Vorlesungen ber die sthetik, 13: pp. 29094, 393, 45265, in particular, and Brodsky, From the Pyramids to Romantic Poetry, pp. 35162. Adorno, Kulturkritik, p. 8: Die berspannung des kulturellen Anspruchs, die doch wieder der Bewegung des Geistes immanent ist.
26
27
Ibid.: Solche Vornehmheit macht der Kulturkritiker zu seinem Privileg und verwirkt seine Legitimation, indem er als bezahlter und geehrter Plagegeist der Kultur an dieser mitwirkt (The cultural critic makes the distinction [of culture] into his own privilege and gives up his legitimation in collaborating with culture as its paid and honored pest). Ibid., p. 22: Ohne solche Freiheit, ohne Hinausgehen des Bewusstseins ber die Immanenz der Kultur wre immanente Kritik selber nicht denkbar: der Selbstbewegung des Objekts vermag nur zu folgen, wer dieser nicht durchaus angehrt.
28
29
Ibid., p. 29: Keine Theorie, und auch die wahre nicht, ist vor der Perversion in den Wahn sicher, wenn sie einmal der spontanen Beziehung auf das Objekt sich entussert hat. Davor muss Dialektik nicht weniger sich hten als vor der Befangenheit im Kulturobjekt. Der dialektische Kritiker an der Kultur muss an dieser teilhaben und nicht
109
teilhaben. Nur dann lsst er der Sache und sich selber Gerechtigkeit widerfahren.
30
T. W. Adorno, Arnold Schnberg, 18741951, in Adorno, Prismen, p. 211: Mndigkeit und Vergeisterung der Kunst mit dem sinnlichen Schein virtuell die Kunst selber tilgen. All following citations from this essay will be from this edition.
31
[D]ie blichen Krcken eines Hrens, das immer schon weiss, was kommt, from Adorno, Arnold Schnberg, 18741951, p. 181. Ibid.: [Schnbergs Musik] verlangt, dass der Hrer ihre innere Bewegung spontan mitkomponiert, und mutet ihm anstelle blosser Kontemplation gleichsam Praxis zu. Damit aber frevelt Schnberg gegen die im Widerpruch zu allen idealistischen Beteuerungen gehegte Erwartung, dass Musik al eine Folge geflliger sinnlicher Reize dem bequemen Hren sich prsentiere. Bei Schnberg hrt die Gemtlichkeit auf. Bei Schnberg wird die Objektivierung des subjektiven Impulses zum Ernstfall (With Schoenberg the objectivization of the subjective impulse becomes a serious matter); ibid., p. 191.
32
33
Ibid., p. 182.
34
35
Ibid., p. 181. Dem [des Blauen Reiters Programm des Geistigen in der Kunst] hielt Schnberg die Treue, nich indem er auf Abstraktion ausging, sondern indem er die konkrete Gestalt der Musik selber vergeistigte. Daraus wird ihm der beliebste Vorwurf gemacht, der des Intellektualismus. Die immanente Kraft der Vergeisterung wird entweder verwechselt mit einer der Sache usserlichen Reflexion, oder es wird dogmatisch Musik von jener Forderung der Vergeisterung ausgenommen, die als Korrektiv der Verwandlung von Kultur in Kulturgut fr alle sthetischen Medien unabsweisbar ward (Schoenberg remained true to the Blue Rider program of the spirit of the mind in art, not in proceeding from abstraction, but in endowing the concrete form of music itself with intellectual spirit. This is the basis of the preferred reproach against him, that of intellectualism. The immanent power of fusing art with intellect is either confused with a form of reflection that is external to the thing, or music is dogmatically exempted from the demand of such intellectual effort, that which became the necessary corrective to the transformation of culture in cultural good for all aesthetic media), ibid., p. 182. [Schnbergs] ist eine Musik der Identitt in Nichtidentitt ([Schoenbergs] is a music of identity in nonidentity), ibid., p. 188.
36
37
Ibid., p. 184: Der Vorwurf des Intellektuellen geht mit dem des Mangels an Melodie zusammen. Aber er war der Melodiker schlechthin. Anstelle der eingeschliffenen Formel hat er unablssig neue Gestalten produziert. Kaum je kann seine melodische Eingebung mit einer einzelnen Melodie
110
Claudia Brodsky
hinaushalten, sondern alle gleichzeitigen musikalischen Ereignisse warden als Melodien profiliert und damit gerade die Auffassung erschwert. Die ursprngliche musikalische Reaktionsweise Schnbergs selbst ist melodisch: alles bei ihm eigentlich gesungen, auch die instrumentalen Linien. Das verleiht seiner Musik das Artikulierte, zugleich frei Schwingende und bis zum letzten Ton Gegliederte (emphasis added).
38
Ibid., p. 192: Schnberg denkt zu Ende, was der Klassizismus versprach und nicht hielt, und darber zerbricht die traditionelle Fassade. Er hat die Bachische Forderung wieder aufgenommen, der der Klassizismus, Beethoven einbegriffen, sich entzog, ohne dass Schnberg doch hinter den Klassizismus zurckgefallen ware. Dieser hatte Bach aus geschichtlicher Notwendigkeit vernachlssigt. Die Autonomie des musikalischen Subjekts berwog jedes andere Interesse und schloss kritisch die berkommene Gestalt der Objektivierung aus, whrend man mit dem Schein der Objektivierung vorlieb nehmen konnte, so wie das ungehemmte Zusammenspiel der Subjekte die Gesellschaft zu garantieren schien. Heute erst, da die Subjektivitt in ihrer Unmittelbarkeit nicht lnger als hchste Kategorie waltet, sondern als der gesamtgesellschaftlichen Verwirklichung bedrftig durchschaut ist, wird die Insuffizienz selbst der Beethovenschen Lsung, die das Subjekt zum Ganzen ausbreitet, ohne das Ganze in sich zu vershnen, erkennbar. Schnbergs Polyphonie bestimmt die Durchfhrung als dialektische Auseinanderlegung des subjektiven Melodischen Impulses in der objektiv organisierten Mehrstimmigkeit (emphasis added).
39
Cf. my Szondi and Hegel: The Troubled Relationship of Literary Criticism to Philosophy, Telos 140 (Fall 2007): 4563, for an extended discussion of Hegels analysis, in Lectures on Aesthetics, of the inherent semantic and historic ambiguity stemming from the identity of the symbol, in the first [and last] place, as sign. Adorno, Schnberg, p. 189: [D]as knstlerische Extrem zu verwantworten, ob es der Logik der Sache, einer wie sehr auch verborgene Objektivitt, oder bloss der privaten Willkr oder abstrakten System. Seine Legitimitt aber zieht es wesentlich aus der Tradition, die es negiert Nicht nur die religise, auch die sthetische Tradition ist Erinnerung an ein Unbewusstes, ja Verdrnglichtes. Tradition ist gegenwrtig in den als experimentell gescholtenen Werken und nicht in den der eigenen Absicht nach traditionalistischen.
40
41
Ibid., pp. 206, 208. Ibid., p. 206. Ibid., p. 211: Die Erfahrung, das kein musikalisches Subject-Objekt heut und hier sich konstituieren kann, war an ihm nicht verschwendet. Ibid., pp. 207, 187.
42 43
44 45
Ibid.
111
46
Ibid., p. 210: Unter Schnbergs Akten der Integration musikalischer Mittel war nicht der letzte, dass er endgltig die Farbe der Sphre des Schmckenden Entriss und zum Kompositionselement eigenen Rechtes erhob. Sie verwandelt sich in ein Mittel der Verdeutlichung des Zusammenhangs. Solche Einbeziehung in die Komposition aber wird ihr zum Verhngnis. Je nackter die Konstruktion sich darstellt, um so weniger bedarf sie der koloristischenHilfe Mndige Musik schpft Verdacht gegen das real Erklingende schlechthin Die Neigung zum Verstummen, wie sie in Weberns Lyrik die Aura jeden Tones bildet, ist dieser von Schnberg ausgehenden Tendenz verschwistert. Sie luft aber auch nicht weniger hinaus, als dass Mndigkeit und Vergeisterung der Kunst mit dem sinnlichen Schein virtuell die Kunst selber tilgen (emphasis added).
47
Emphatisch arbeitet in Schnbergs Sptwerk die Vergeisterung der Kunst an deren Auflsung und findet sich so mit dem kunstfeindlichen und barbarischen Element abgrndig zusammen (The intellectualization of art in Schoenbergs late work works emphatically toward the dissolution of art and so converges abysmally with the anti-artistic and barbaric element), ibid. Ibid., p. 31: Kulturkritik findet sich der letzten Stufe der Dialektik von Kultur und Barberei gegenber: nach Auschwitz ein Gedicht zu schrieben, ist barbarisch; und das frisst auch die Erkenntnis an, die ausspricht, warum es unmglich ward, heute Gedichte zu schreiben (emphasis added).
48
49
50 51
Cited in Oliver Meslay, Turner: Life and Landscape (New York, 2005), p. 102. Greenberg states of abstract artists what could well be stated of him: Purists make extravagant claims for art, because usually they value it much more than any one else does; Greenberg, Towards a Newer Laocoon, p. 23. He famously defines the purity arising from a knowing separation of the arts, and of painting from the representation of things and communication of messages proper to literature (thereby inverting Lessings own epoch-making argument regarding the descriptive properties of spatial-pictoral, rather than temporal-verbal, media) as follows: Purity in art consists in the acceptance, willing acceptance, of the limitations of the medium of the specific art; The history of avant-garde painting is that of a progressive surrender to the resistance of its medium (32, 34). Reinhardts provocative pronouncementThere is something wrong, irresponsible, mindless about color, something impossible to control. Control and rationality are part of any moralityis cited as part of an argument on behalf of color in Glen Dixon, Sean Scully, Artforum 34 (Oct. 1994): 97.
Claudia Brodsky
52
53
54
112
In his Norton lectures, Working Space (Cambridge, MA, 1986), Stella contributes to the debate surrounding the divide between abstractly sensuous color and representational shape by attributing the lack of a convincing projective illusionism, of a self-contained [pictorial] space in painting since Pollock and Morris Louis to a misguided search for color, linking, by contrast, his own early black paintings with Caravaggios ability to create the sensation of real space (1112).
55
See Dixon, Sean Scully, p. 97, on the felt sensuality of color in Rothko and Scully; see Reinhard Ermen, reviews of Rothko and Scully exhibits, Basel and Dsseldorf 2001, in Kunstforum International 155 (June/July 2001): 42528, esp. 427, on Scully: [E]r hat seine Streifen zu einer Art Baukasten weitergedacht konkrete Krper, die die Farben vor oder zurcksetzen und den Betrachter in den Bildraum einlassen ([H]e has thought his stripes out into a kind of building block concrete bodies that set the colors forward or backward and let the viewer into the picture space).
Reminiscient of Adornos analysis of the peculiar objecthood of the art object, Jonathan Lasher has written persuasively of the ability of Mondrians paintings to present the visual in purely objective terms while taking on a resonance that is not objectively there when they are completed in the mind of the viewer; see Lasher, New Math, Artforum 34 (Oct. 1995): 83. In his eloquent essay on Rothkos development and achievement, Bodies of Light, Art in America (July 1999): pp. 6070, 107, Scully states the decisive effect of Matisses new, non-descripti[ve] use of color (in The Red Studio) on Rothko: It was Rothkos exposure to Matisses painting The Red Studio (1911), when it came to New York in 1949, that opened a huge door to his own future. The Red Studio, as radical as Picassos Les Demoisiselles dAvignon (1907), was painted with a flat red colour that completely coveredand thus simplified and unifiedthe entire surface of the painting. This work profoundly affected Rothko and made it possible for him thereafter to put down color without bothering to model it for the sake of description.
56
Rothko himself had evidently come to the same conclusion, if slightly differently conceived, suggesting, according to Tate curator Norman Reed, that Turner had learned a great deal from him; interview with Sir Norman Reed, Rothkos Rooms, dir. Keith Alexander, 2000. Extending beyond this happy admission that the history of abstract color painting had proceeded backwards, Rothkos acceptance of Reeds proposal that the Tate house his Seagram paintings rested in no small measure, Reed reports, on the proximity of the room to be devoted to them to the Tates gallery of Turners.
57
Curt Barnes, Travels Along the Dialectic: Hit-and-Run Observations on Interdimensoinality, Art Journal 30 (1991): pp. 2632 (28). Kuspit, citing Scullys use of the term in discussing Van Gogh, explains
58
113
the particular sense of Suchness created by Scullys own abstract sensuousness as follows: In the altered state of consciousness, which is Scullys abstract painting, geometry becomes intense and colour becomes profound. Their Suchness becomes self-evident. The doors of perception are flung wide open. The sublime Suchness of relational patterns and of moving light becomes evident; Nuance and Intensity, p. 50.
59
Historically astute and experientially accurate accounts of the enduring participation of abstraction in art are offered, by contrast, by Kuspit, especially in his writing on Scully. See, in particular, his Sean Scully, Artforum International 38 (Sept. 1999): p. 168; Nuance and Intensity, pp. 4551, and Sacred Sadness, in Sean Scully: A Retrospective (London, 2007), pp. 1418. For Kuspit, Scullys paintings do more than merely prove that abstraction is not dead; rather, they epitomize the essentials of abstraction and give them what one might call, literally and figuratively, new depth; Sean Scully, p. 168. Adorno, Kulturkritik, p. 17; Davis, Sean Scullys Preoccupations, 29; Barnes, Travels Along the Dialectic, p. 32. In distinction from, but no less opposition to, Warhols objectivization and weirdly transcendent historicization of the imagery and methods of commercial art, Scully views art made with the circulatory aims and techniques of advertising as a pure and unbridled form of capitalism, i.e., a form exercised in necessary disregard for the consequentiality of art; see Interview with Eric Davis, in Sean Scully, Resistance and Persistance: Selected Writings (London, 2006), p. 135.
60
61
Jrgen Habermas, A Modernism that Turned into a Tradition: Glosses and Associations, in Sean Scully: Body of Light, pp. 3942 (4041). Habermas continues: Sean Scully objects to the flattening of this threshold (41). Faye Hirsch, Weatherman: Robert Rauschenbergs Ground Rules Series, Art on Paper 2 (Nov.Dec. 1997): pp. 1015 (14).
62
63
Hal Foster, review, Artforum (Sept. 1979): pp. 7274 (74). Ibid.
64 65
While Rothkos creation of overlapping shapes and borders of color that we experience not as affixed to canvas but afloat has often led to especially mystical ruminations on the content of his work, an excellent account of the visual syntax that, relating the surface figures of his paintings, composes at the same time their extraordinary, apparently untethered spatial effect, is offered in Sheldon Nodelmans Rediscovering Rothko, Art in America (July 1999): pp. 5865, 106 (62). Of Rothkos now classic works from 1949 onward, Nodelman writes: Rothkos great discovery, and the key to the unprecedented achievement of these paintings, was his exploitation (for the first time systematically and at large scale) of a fundamental perceptual mechanism, relational
114
Claudia Brodsky
See Majorie Welish, interview with Jasper Johns (Feb. 22, 1990), in When Is a Door Not a Door? Art Journal 50 (Sep. 1991): pp. 4851 (50); see Arthur C. Danto, Philosophizing Art: Selected Essays (Berkeley, 1999), p. 65. See Davis, Sean Scullys Preoccupations, p. 2; cf. Kuspit, Sacred Sadness, p. 17: [The] structured plane [of Scullys paintings] is suspended over and generally blocks out an amorphous plane of implied depth. Whatever the mood suggested, this double layer effect confirms that the paintings are formal masterpieces. They acknowledge the physical surface of the canvas while subverting (transcending?) it, by creating the illusion of behind the surface as though Scully was an archaeologist digging up the darkness, with its rotting colours, in search of a living memory of light.
68
69
Adorno, Kulturkritik, p. 7: Wer gewohnt ist, mit den Ohren zu denken, der muss am Klang des Wortes Kulturkritik sich rgern nicht darum bloss, weil es, wie das Automobil, aus Latein und Griechisch zusammengestckt ist. Es erinnert an einen flagranten Widerspruch. Dem Kulturkritiker passt die Kultur nicht (emphasis added).
70
115
Robert Kaufman
charged an afterlife as that notorious 1949 aphorism: [A]fter Auschwitz, to write a poem is barbaric (nach Auschwitz ein Gedicht zu schreiben, ist barbarisch). Ubiquitous as those words become in a reception history extending impressively far and wide and continuing still, their epigrammatic sting has more often than not been radically detached and misleadingly abstracted: detached from the contexts and multiply oriented directions of the 1949 essay titled Cultural Criticism and Society that had housed them; detached from that essays explicit analysis of what it might mean for art and cultures emancipatory engagements to be rethought in relation to a contemporary capitalist-administrative society putting the worlds confrontation with the National Socialist genocide behind it and extraordinarily interested in integrating and neutralizing art and cultures tendencies toward protest and critique; detached also from the essays knowing, unsparingly self-critical analysis precisely of aesthetic and cultural criticisms critical awareness and oppositional impulse to deny the force of the aforementioned sociocultural and socioeconomic dynamics of assimilation and co-optation; and detached, finally, from that aphorisms construction of a simultaneously essay-ending and
116
Robert Kaufman
discourse-generating gesture, whichfar from any banning, enjoining, stigmatizing, or the likerather presents lyric poetry as objectivating the strongest version of a postwar dilemma certainly shared, on lower frequencies, by much philosophy and criticism (and as being in accord with Adornos, Benjamins, and other Frankfurt School figures and kindred artists lifelong views that lyric carried unique critical powers). Not to mention that Adorno had composed his refractory thought so that the infamous words were embedded within a long, complexly frictive German sentence subsequently parceled, in the best-known English translation, into three separate sentences whose effect might seem strikingly different from that comprehended in the original.1 Adorno had actually, if naively, imagined that his barbed, tensile aphorism, provocation though it surely was, would nonetheless straightforwardly join other immediate postwar efforts to make thought and writing grapple with and palpably enact a questioning of the meanings of humanitys after-living its sur-vivalof the 19331945 Third Reich, of what Paul Celans poetry would soon begin to call that which happened (das, was geschah), that which happened not only to the immediate victims of the genocide but also to the world itself and to the ongoing aftermath of human experience.2 In this essay I pursue poetrys immanent explorations and contributions, not only to the initial poetry after Auschwitz question but also to what comes historically after that initial question. It turns out that one of later-modernist, later twentieth-century poetrys most consequential responses to the what follows poetry after Auschwitz? query will be, in significant part: poetry after poetry after Auschwitz. It will be among this essays abiding concernsas it was among the abiding concerns of the poetry itselfto show how and why this following involves more than mere statement of obvious, inevitable, next-step outcomes, more than mere play on the words follow and after, more even than the combination of conceptually determined
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
117
logic itself plus linguistic-temporal sequencing or succession; instead of all these, whats operative in poetry after poetry after Auschwitz proves to be extraordinarily hard-won recognition of actual, specific historical developments and conditions of possibility that would go largely, if not completely, unapprehended but for artistic-aestheticin this case, poeticagency, effort, and achievement. For not least interesting are the profoundly historical character and meanings of poetry after poetry after Auschwitz. This poetry after poetry after Auschwitz will compel, via its particular aesthetic illuminations, the re-opening of several other crucial historical questions that had only appeared to beor had appeared to be only literary, cultural, or aesthetic and that had at any rate seemed settled, or destined to remain mysterious, but now urge their renewed necessity and contemporaneity and, in a certain sense, their ability to shuttle us to certain extrapoetic and extra-aesthetic matters. What really finally happened to modernism, from within and without, to cause its demise; did modernism actually die? Why does a reinvention of lyric-Romantic critical agency with a differenceor rather, a rediscovery and reinvention of the lyric-Romantic strains secretly animating so much modernist poetry and artloom so large in these investigations of modernisms life and afterlives? How do both these historical investigation-engagements (of lyric-Romantic critical agency; of what finally happened to modernism) constellate themselves together with developments in todays poetry, poetics and aesthetics, criticism? In Celan himself, the Romantic strains at least would not seem newsworthy. A deep, rich, and explicit relationship to Hlderlin and other German Romantics suffuses Celans poetry and the critical literature. Less obvious is that Hlderlins curious statusthat of a radically experimental Romantic lyric poet whose revivification early in the twentieth century gave him new life as a guiding spirit of modernism, a lyric constructivist par excellence whod grasped that paratactical construction, far from refusing mime118
Robert Kaufman
sis semblance-expression, actually constructs new mimetic-expressive, and thus new experiential, capacity (a description that, re-placed into the direst and most desperate of contexts, likewise describes Celans art)already stands as one of the foundation stones of modernisms own self-conception as a radical reinvention or continuation of Romanticism. One thereby eventually arrivesor shouldat the curious and curiously undiscussed question of whether Celans poetry is itself still modernist. Well return to this consideration, but suffice it to say here that with a crucial and by no means determinist or simply oppositional twist, Celan devastatingly reimagines rather than eschews the richest of Romantic-modernist meditations on and enactments of how lyric poetry, and aesthetic experience more generally, spark a sensing of life; of generative, living form; of the critical sensing of an expressivist-constructivist agency synonymous with dynamic artistic-aesthetic form, synonymous with imaginative, forming activity. Such meditations will hold even, and especially, for the incomparably grim limit-cases of life, of nonlife as life, that Celans poetry engages. Celans work suggests, moreover, how poetic forms abilities to configure or constellate an in-motion structure or force-field composed from the very materials of our understanding-experience of life, reality, recent sociopolitical catastrophes, and whats taken place in their various aftermaths, and of lyric modality, can allow us to tell the timeor tell some missing timesof the histories demanding our attention. For reasons that will emerge more fully in what follows, postwar American poetrys remove from this dramas ostensible main (German, European) stage will carry its own special charge. For the moment its enough to observe that American poetrys role will prove less a parallel with, than another chapter in and extension of, Celanian literary history, even as American poetry likewise finds itself becoming a crucial testing ground for the reception and activation of Frankfurt School aesthetics and critical theory (for situational reasons that Adorno and his colleagues
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
119
had imagined might well obtain). Like some of its European and Latin American contemporaries, American poetry after 1945 often seeks to hold on to modernist achievements while reaching back to various Romantic practices and theories. From at least Ginsberg and other Beat poets onward, it cannot be gainsaid how crucial the Romantic currents within but unacknowledged by modernism become to American poetrys fraught attempts to come to artistic terms with the Holocaust.(The generally unremarked double strangeness of William Carlos Williamss famous introduction to Howl bears noting as an example of how perplexed even the best-intentioned or most astute figures in American poetry could be when confronted with this unprecedented donne: Williamss introduction offers not a word about poetic form, be it line, meter, image, diction, or anything else; but Williams does see fit, in focusing on the poets personal experience, amazingly if not bizarrely to equate Ginsbergs experiences with the experience of those whod just survived Hitlers concentration camps.)3 Indeed, a more general effort freshly to see and hear the Romantic poetics and the Romanticism-conceived notion of reflective critical agency (itself perhaps just another way of saying life, organic form, or expressivist-constructivist form) inside what was formally revolutionary in Poundian modernism (despite Pounds, Eliots, and others denials of the Romantic sources) is central to those tendencies within the postwar poetry and criticism seeking to retain yet reorient attractive legacies of modernist experimentalism. But of course this experimental art and criticism proceeds with an especially acute awareness of why the defeat of Nazi Germany should occasion an ever more urgent reconsideration of aspects of modernismaspects at one with modernisms anti-Romantic, antidemocratic strainsthat had once seemed to make critical agency, if not reflection itself, beside the point. (We need only remember Eliots and related salvos against the Hamletian sublime, their dire warnings about the sociopolitical dangers of aestheti120
Robert Kaufman
cally sparked interpretation altogether.)4 Postwar experimental poetry thus consciously involves itself in a terrible, unavoidable irony: The reconsideration of and recommitment to critical aesthetic reflectionto mimesiss or semblances enactment of living formis brought to bear on an unprecedented mass destruction in and of real life, brought to bear on the calculated, systematized elimination of millions of lives. Though certainly cognizant of the specialand here specially chargedresources that German poetry, poetics, and aesthetics (from Naturphilosophie onward) hold for thinking about this compound question of life and critical reflection, American later-modernist poets quite understandably tend, after World War II, rather to emphasize their recourse to and rethinking of the English-language poetry whose literary and social histories lie sedimented within the formal dones of the very art these postwar Americans are in the process of making. In this light, but with an intentionally internationalist twist, they return especially to Whitmans extensions of Emersonian transcendentalism and to the British Romanticism informing Emersonianism. The result appears as a collectively composed, militant though extraordinarily pained tone poem configured to stretch at least from Percy Shelleys 1821 protest against early industrialisms suppression of the poetry of life to Muriel Rukeysers revivifying intent to underscore, if not transpose, that poetrys music, ethics, and politics when she answers an incomparably blood-soaked eras death message with The Life of Poetry (1949).5 Near the far end, if not already the afterlife, of this history come Celans poetry and Adornos critical meditations. I try in what follows to do justice to the particularity of each, to their work in their lifetime and after, by undertaking sustained engagement with some other very well-known particulars whose poetry and criticism exist in urgent dialogue with Celan, Adorno, and their cohort, focusing above all on the American postwar poet notorious for saving experimental modernist poetry exactly by means of an unabashed yet rigorous tracing, and a subtle
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
121
rewriting and refunctioning, of the Romantic roots of modernist poetic, and especially lyric, practice in an effort to have life make real contact with especially recalcitrant aspects of the historical, to make otherwise missing histories live after, or at least live in and as, their apparent disappearance.
Its not unheard of, but neither is it exactly common for a challenging, much-recited, and often orally discussed poem by a significant and influential poet to have received virtually no published commentary, particularly when many of that poets works have been treated in articles and books, and where there are abundant testimonies concerning the poems influence on poets and critics alike. Because the very title of the 1976 or 1977 Robert Duncan poem in question signals a concern with some of the great sociopolitical and ethicaland, finally, historicalquestions engaged by later twentieth-century American poetry and culture, it might be tempting to explain the absence of published commentary via some version of a repressed or semi-subterranean political unconscious. But that would probably mislead us, for among the intriguing features of this poems circulation and reception histories appears to beincluding most recently, in the months just after September 11, 2001, and then again at the beginning of and throughout the Iraq Wara rather widespread awareness of the stakes and issues the poem calls forth; and this may in turn suggest that the poems lately renewed reception, by poets and by some critics, hints at relations rather different from those most frequently articulated, in these last few decades, among aesthetic form or Romantic and modernist formalism and the generally competing counternotions of politico-ethical engagement, or of the political unconscious itself. In short, we may here be encountering an object lesson in how hastily applied notions of a political unconscious actually intensifies formal-historical suppression and forgetting. At any rate, what perhaps instead underlies the
122
Robert Kaufman
three-decades absence of published commentary is a daunting sense that so much is involved in this poem that its politicalethical enunciations or mappings might take forever; that there might also be sidestories and backstories whose narrative events are perhaps not well enough known or even available for reconstruction; and finally, the overwhelming sense that, formally and stylistically, this poems resolute, almost unleavened abstraction can feel strange, off-putting, so that the poem can be and often is mentioned as a rigorous though unsatisfying experiment. (Its apparently been deemed unsatisfying because its level of abstraction and emphatic recourse to philosophical diction far surpass even that of the Duncan poems where formalist aesthetic abstraction, while a crucial element, nonetheless tends to be constructed, apparently unlike the poem at hand, in tension with concrete imagery and at least semigraspable allusiveness, as well as with familiar or semifamiliar historical and mythological materialsthe sort of constellating that Duncan felt hed learned from Ezra Pound and, with far more openness to modernisms Romantic legacies, from Charles Olson and, especially, H.D. [Hilda Doolittle]).6 Heres the poem, which Duncan wrote sometime in 76 or 77, possibly in his San Francisco home but probably in Paris during an extended working visit; the poem subsequently appeared in his book Ground Work: Before the War, published four years before his 1988 death.
A SONG FROM THE STRUCTURES OF RIME RINGING AS THE POET PAUL CELAN SINGS : Something has wreckt the world I am in I think I have wreckt
the world I am in. It is beautiful. From my wreckage this world returns to restore me, overcomes its identity in me.
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
123
Nothing has wreckt the world I am in. It is nothing workt this or my world I mean in the world that has wreckage of me
as I go
the something is
obscured in the proposition of No-thingness. It is Nothing that has beautiful, being something Nothing in me
Without the words Paul Celan in its title, this would be a very different poem: an arresting ordepending on ones judgment not so arresting attempt to enact once more, on the far side of late modernism, a Romanticism-derived interweaving of familiar dramatic, generative, destructive, and reconstructive encounters among world, self or subject, thingness or objectness. It would
124
Robert Kaufman
appear to be an exploration of the alternately animating and abjecting experience of consciousness; a meditation on the potentially transformative character of the aesthetic or the beautiful; and, ultimately, a whole lot of nothingno thing, nothingness, the blank or nothing status of so-called nonobjective, nonconceptual thought, and so forth (with these blanks threatening, at moments in the poem, to seem as if theyd been written on flowing banners of ribbon meant to be manipulated elegantly though parodically by fugitive stagehands from either the Reduced Hegel Company or its crosstown rival, the High Diggers). Yet the ear, eye, and rest of the body register genuine poetic technique, feeling, and structure, starting with the poems circular, seemingly unending lyric movement of undoing, negating, redoing. One hears the allusions to, the resonances and rewritings of, poetrys own history, working backward from the final lines play on the final line of Wallace Stevenss The Snowman (with its Nothing that is not there and the nothing that is), tracing back further still toward the negatively capable Nobodies and Nothings in Dickinson, Keats, Shakespeare, and too many more to count. Those nothings and zeros or cipher-spaces or estranged numberings start to bring other registers of poetic structure and experience into focus. Theres a hint of Duncans trying out the sort of metrical and rhythmic play with number and form more typical of his friend the Objectivist poet Louis Zukofsky, for Duncan has given this poem twenty-eight lines and, as often for him, an almost but not quite identifiable pattern of rhythm and rhyme, where the point is rather to invoke teasingly and then let dissolve the suggestions of established metrics, sound likenesses, forms, and genreshere with suggestions of a fugitive rhyme scheme, of a double sonnet, of there possibly being two octets, two sestets, two voltas (though just where, or just before, a doubled volta might be marked, we encounter the at once decisive and ambiguous line It is totally untranslatable). As it happens, sound affinity, word and phrase repetition with more and less
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
125
difference, and bare-bones homonymic rhyme (n-o and k-n-o-w, for instance) do much of the poems texture work. But these formal features fall quite literally under the sign of the Romanian-born Celan, whose German-language poetry, inextricable from the experience of the Holocaust and its aftermaths, Duncan had been reading for some time. (And Celan in the poems title begins, on reflection, to amplify linked sound allusions the reader might have dimly begun to sense on first encounter, linkages the poem itself appears to hear as being conjoined with the other internalized poetic histories of nothing: namely, the nobodies and no ones and nothings in Celans own poetry; in, for instance, the well-known Psalm.)8 Like other veterans of the Black Mountain College experimental arts scene and kindred communities, Duncan had known the 1950s and 1960s translations of Celan by poet-translators Cid Corman and Jerome Rothenberg, the signal events being, for Duncan, the 1959 publication of Rothenbergs Celan translations in Rothenbergs journal Poems from the Floating World and in the Rothenberg-edited City Lights Pocket Poets anthology New Young German Poets.9 But it seems to have been a sustained reading and rereading in the early-mid 1970s of Celan both in German and in translationespecially in Michael Hamburgers 1972 facing-page German and English Selected Poems of Paul Celan (and possibly also in Joachim Neugroschels 1971 likewise facing-page Speech-Grille, and Selected Poems)that simply knocked Duncan out.10 Amid all that reading, Duncan accepted the 1977 invitation from a group of French poets to come to Paris. A number of these French poets had known, worked with, and in some cases translated Celan (and had been translated by him) during the postwar decades that he lived and worked in Paris (until his 1970 suicide), and they had long been avid readers of Duncan as well. It appears that this living with Celans poetry, combined with the anticipation or experience of being around a number of Celans French colleagues (including the poets Jacques Roubaud, Jean Daive, Claude Royet-Journoud,
126
Robert Kaufman
Anne-Marie Albiach, Emmanuel Hocquard, and Raquel Levy) provided the stimulus for Duncan to compose the poem. Duncans Celan poem was first published in Paris in 1977 by Hocquard and Levys Orange Export Ltd. in an English-language edition of, per Duncans request, nine rectangular palm-sized copies, for which Duncan had also requested, without further explanation, that these minipamphlets or chapbooks of the single poem be no fewer than three and no more than five pages in length, and that no page have fewer than two, nor more than eight lines.11 Seven years later the poem appeared in a more standard mannerthat is, across a single pagein Ground Work: Before the War. Duncan begins Ground Work with an important preface on prosody, Some Notes on Notation. Carrying evident significance for Duncans thinking about Celan in relation to how poetry jointly composes soundings and mutenesses, and how such composing works finally to create the poems experience of time (and thus, formally, a key aspect of poetrys relation to historical experience), the preface emphasizes that the volumes poems all work with various silences, with [s]ignificant pauses for the syncopation of suspense or arrest, including caesuras as definite parts of the articulation of the line, with turnings at the end of the verse, with intervals of silence in the measures between stanzas, so that caesura-spaces make [s]ilences themselves [into] phrases, units in the measure, charged with meaning. The poem threads these charged, silence-filled measures into [t]he cadence of the verse in relation to the dance of [the] physical body. These various pauses, suspensions, arreststhese caesuraewill have everything to do with the effort to convey historys arrests, pause-interruptions, its own caesuras. And, simultaneously, they will signal the effort to pry open a place in timethe stop-time space of the poemin which the materials of what did happen, or what could have happened differently, can be replayed, reanimated, reconfigured. Duncans emphasis on prosodic measure and poetic form more generally thus begins to ask that we grasp these as at every point
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
127
constituting a structure and phenomenology of historical silences and of what was silenced in them: The caesura space becomes not just an articulation of phrasings but a phrase itself of silence. Space between stanzas becomes a stanza-verse of silence: in which the beat continues; silence itself is sounded, a significant or meaningful absence, its semiotic value contributing to and derived from our apprehension of the field of the poem it belongs to. In some poems, specific, even visually identifiable techniques derived from other poets participate in this silence-construction: The space-period-space [ . ] taken over from the later poetry of William Carlos Williams, at first undefined, now means a sounded silence, followed by the period in which the beat stops, and out of that cessation the beginning of the beat again. Finally, while initially for the reader the literal time of the poem is experienced as given, even as the literal size of a painters canvas is given, among the poems effects is the readers awareness of the construction of temporality itselfand of what would fill any particular historical temporalityfor ultimately, [w]hat is advanced in the process of the poem is the configuration of given time.12 Duncan proceeds to say a good deal more about prosody; the meditations reflect decades of work toward a music able to do justice to the social history and ethical commitments inside of, summoned, or kindled by his poetry. Of particular importance to Duncan are what his letters and essays identify as Wordsworthian and Emersonian notions about the philosophical and aesthetic courting of experience and, indeed, an especially Emersonian admission of or even insistence upon the grounding of open, process-focused experience in the encounter with grief. To that sort of overarching philosophical sense (which he often traces through not only Wordsworth and Emerson but also William James, John Dewey, Alfred North Whitehead, and beyond), Duncan brings specific lessons in poetic form and style, based partly in Dickinsons genius for compression and Whitmans opposite impulse of expansion.13
128
Robert Kaufman
All this side and background information is important not so much for sourcing as for an understanding that Duncan himself appears to have regarded such context, in the act of writing A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings, as preparatory for what poets like Michael Palmer have called one of Duncans masterpiece[s] of elegy and negative lyricism, though who and what are being elegized is no small question.14 Suffice it to say for the moment that, rather than stepping into the place of Celan, or of others who directly experienced the National Socialist genocide, Duncans poem works toward discovering what it means for American poetry and culture, in their remove but also their connectedness, to participate in attempts to generate reflective experience of, and in, the Holocausts aftermath. The poems title already starts to tell as much; this Song from the Structures of Rime (bringing within the poems title the larger Structures of Rime sequence) is ringingchiming rather than equally singing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings. As vibrates with multiple meanings that seem to fuse: like the poet Paul Celan; but also, while the poet Paul Celan sings, so that in Duncans poem the fundamental gestural-dynamic of the aesthetics necessarily metaphorical as if transforms itself into what is, in line with the givens of the poems presumptive true fictions, a literalization accomplished when as transforms itself into temporality. The poem is now felt to intervene in and reopen time, and therefore historys medium, in the very act of echoing, citing, and alluding to Celans song. Well return to this point later, but its worth pausing here to remark Duncans suggestion that not only social but likewise artistic-aesthetic history is being reanimated, an action that renews with an at-first barely noticeable sting the question of there having been an unacknowledgedin direct proportion to its having been an inconceivably murderouscaesura in modernism, and whether the very ability to ask or raise the question is itself somehow modernist. The Structures of Rime was one of several open-ended sequences
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
129
or seriesincluding the Passages that Duncan began in the 1950s as part of what he conceived, in dialogue with Charles Olson, Robert Creeley, Denise Levertov, and others as an open-form and composition-by-field poetics. These sequences worked their way through various of Duncans books across three decades, ceasing only with the poets 1988 death. Duncan spelled rime archaically, and throughout the Structures of Rime he appears to have Coleridge and other eighteenth- and nineteenth-century poets in mind for their play on the poetic and scientific meanings of the word. Were evidently meant to encounter rhyme poetically as sound-likeness and as synonym for the poem or for poetic form per se, but also to engage r-i-m-e scientifically yet still also obviously poetically, as another term for hoarfrost or for condensation as it approaches the condition of frost. Hence, the temporary solidity assumed by water eventually dissolves back into fluid, literally to become physically ungraspable substance-as-movement-orprocess, but whose movement continues to carry with it charged notions of poetic and aesthetic structure, concretization, dissolution and condensation, and sequence. The activity of apprehending these metaphoricsof grasping that the figures when artfully and convincingly constellated get at a meaning partly already in nature or in scientific understanding themselvesis for Duncan an almost direct inheritance of Romanticisms (perhaps, above all, Coleridges and Shelleys) articulations of organic form and its construction of reflective-critical agency, all of which Duncan comes to call organic-constructivist form.15 Poets from Robert Creeley and Denise Levertov to Thom Gunn have noted some of the ways that Structures of Rime takes off from Rimbauds Les illuminations, particularly in the formal admixture of verse and prose poem. It might be added that Blakes The Marriage of Heaven and Hell seemed also to Duncan to have shown the way, and one might go on to stress Duncans interest in bringing that Blakean or especially Rimbaudian admixture, in heightened degree, into individual poems themselves (rather
130
Robert Kaufman
than primarily staging this tension between the differentiated verse and prose-poem moments within the overall, predominantly prose-poem, sequence), so that something like movement in and out of different forms or structures of water can be enactedwithin the moments of a particular poemas movement in and out of verse or prose. But Duncan writes this Celan-poem entirely in versea relatively rare occurrence within the larger Structures of Rime. Its conventional, even something of a clich, to say that modern notions of artistic and aesthetic beauty have often left prettiness far behind in order to enunciate the beautiful as being synonymous with the trueat times, as synonymous with the true pain and suffering of specific historical instances of Being (as Celan often puts it in partial borrowings from Heidegger, and as Duncan puts it in homage to Celan, Heidegger, and others). And as this essay began by observing, when thats the territory at issue and the discussion assumes a 1945-and-after frame of reference for art and culture in general, and for poetry in particular, the acknowledged or unacknowledged bull in the china shop almost always goes by the name Theodor Wiesengrund Adorno. The usually difficult, sometimes poignant interactions, communications, misunderstandings and tentative apologies between Adorno and postwar German-language poetsCelan above all hardly needs recapitulation here.16 Somewhat less known are the echoes outside the German-speaking countries; it is neither accidental nor sarcastically intended when, for example, Antonioni, in his 1961 film La Notte, has Marcello Mastroianni and Jeanne Moreau walk grimly into the Milan hospital room of their terminally ill frienda fellow writerand try to comfort their dying comrade with words of decidedly postwar reassurance about the value of the doomed patients just-published essay: his essay, that is, on Adorno.17 However much one might expect the United States to have been far removed from such reverberations, things didnt work
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
131
out quite that way. On the contrary, and for reasons that seem interestingly to have been anticipated by Adorno and various of his Frankfurt colleagues, American poets and critics have in great numbers weighed in, since its 1967 translation, on that 1949 Adorno essay that had offered the first of what, through the decades, would become the various formulations, reformulations, semiretractions, and all-around worryings about Lyrik nach Auschwitz, about the alleged barbarism and impossibility of writing a poem after 1945.18 For his part, Duncan had his Adorno and Benjamin mediated for him largely via the Frankfurt critic who probably more than any other undertook the task of translating Frankfurt aesthetics and critical theory into American oppositional culture and vice-versa: Herbert Marcuse. Some of this mediation occurred through Marcuses and Duncans mutual friendship with Norman O. Brownthough Duncan found himself less than pleased when his poetry became an exhibit in an amiable if finally not very enlightening public dispute between Brown and Marcuse about contemporary arts ability to critique commodity culture. And it seems Duncan may have indeed appreciated Marcuses vociferous defense of Adornos thoughts about post-1945 poetry, which Marcuse chose to conjoin with his own little-read (and less than generous) analyses of the formal and social weakness, and of the related literary, cultural, and political self-delusions, as Marcuse initially saw them, of Beat and adjacent countercultural or Left poetry.19 And Duncan seems likewise to have much appreciated Marcuses vociferous defenses of Adornos thoughts about the extraordinary challenges facing post-1945 poetry. Duncan appears also to find sympathetic the way Marcuse really becomes an American. At issue, in significant part, is Marcuses process of linking, though not insisting on the identity of, Jewish and African American culture, from his difficult 1947 interchanges with his former teacher Heidegger to the early 1970s cover photos on Time and Newsweek of his and Adornos perhaps
132
Robert Kaufman
most famous former student, Angela Davis.20 Not the least important link here is to an earlier stage of Duncans career. In 1944 he had published, in Dwight MacDonalds journal Politics, The Homosexual in Society, an essay that was simultaneously a sociological analysis, a coming out, and a poetics; the essay had been refused publication by the Nation.21 Among the different but partially converging American histories the essay tries to explore by means of philosophical and aesthetic notions of universality and particularity were those of African Americans, Jews, Native Americans, and gay people. In this, Duncans work converses intriguingly with someone whom a number of those in his circle periodically felt they could hardly avoid reading, and who happens to present a remarkably similarand similarly given to further imaginings or reinventions of Romanticismpicture of the value of lyric poetry for the groundwork of critique, historical understanding, and the construction of a critical-progressive culture: W. E. B. Du Bois.22 The paeans to Emerson, Whitman, and emancipatory traditions in British and German Romanticism are often remembered in discussions of Du Boiss books on John Brown and his writings on education and sociology, but its less frequently recalled that Du Boiss 1946 text The World and Africa: An Inquiry into the Part Which Africa has Played in World History reserves a special place for Emersons lyric poetry (characterized by Du Bois as a poetry of resistance), and that Emerson will continue to suffuse Du Boiss most radical texts until the latters 1963 death. The significance of Emersons 1854 Second Address on the Fugitive Slave Law to both Duncan and Du Bois in their notions of critical aesthetic and critical lyric could hardly be overstated. The address, presented to a mass meeting in New York City, was a ringing, enraged denunciation of the prohibition and criminalization of attempts to assist Black peoples efforts to free themselves. In ways that were hardly lost on Du Bois and, later, Duncan, Emersons address begins with an epigraph taken from a then-signal moment in recent
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
133
lyric history, Robert Brownings poem decrying Wordsworths capitulation to Toryism, The Lost Leader (a poem important to both Duncan and Du Bois). Brownings poem equates the abandonment of the struggle for social justice with the betrayal of lyric form, modern lyric vocation, and a Romanticism-generated revolutionism (Just for a handful of silver he left us, / Just for a riband to stick in his coat / / Shakespeare was of us, Milton was for us, / Burns, Shelley, were with us,they watch from their graves! / He [Wordsworth] alone breaks from the van and the freemen, / He alone sinks to the rear and the slaves!).23 In any case, its hardly irrelevant that in The World and Africa, and then with more focused attention in his 1952 essay The Negro and the Warsaw Ghetto, Du Bois undertakes a series of analyses attempting to think recent Jewish and African American history together. At some level one can see Du Bois building on certain moments in his and others previous writings and experience in this area, including a group of Langston Hughes poems very familiar to Du Bois. Though hardly sharing Du Boiss positive view of the Soviet Union and really existing socialism, Duncan nonetheless partakes of much in Du Boiss rubric and methodology in trying to think about universals and particulars in a manner that might keep both terms alive without either term or group itself being made, as a group, the universal under which other related but distinct groups could be subsumed as mere, already determined particulars whose particularity would thus lack significance.24 The shadowy reality of universals that exist but are not necessarily right there, empirically available, is prominent among the reasons, Duncan insists, that I read my Emerson darkand it belongs to why Duncan believes this darkness is not an imposition on, but inherent in, Emerson.25 This was in practice the way Du Bois also approached and relied on Emerson, much as the apparent requirements of Du Boiss characteristically upbeat progressivism might not permit the admission in quite these terms. But these are terms that help explain the status and vocation
134
Robert Kaufman
of the lyric work that lend Duncans final book, volume two of Ground Work (first published in 1987), its subtitle: In the Dark. The darkness evoked is not that of original, inherited, or assimilated sin, but rather the darkness of beginning in, moving in, inhabiting domains of experience and knowledge not yet lit by what is already known. In that sense, darkness, or working in it, is the precondition or first moment of new knowledge, of a poetry, a poetic or aesthetic knowing, of life. It is also an Emersonian conditionfound most dramatically in Emersons essay Experience itselfbased in grief over a loved ones death, a grief that can be known but never really overcome, calling into question critical commonplaces that present linear advancement as Emersons (and other Romantics) model for progressive development. Such a view of darknessnot as the dwelling place of evil, but as containing bedrock layers of pain never ultimately transcendable, so that a recurrent provisionality, incompleteness, jaggedness, or fragmentariness will in some ways characterize all subsequent consciousness, experience, lifebears also on why Duncan tells his friend Levertov that he cannot share her enthusiastic response to Los dictadores estn dentro de nosotros (The Dictators Are Within Us), part of a text by the Nicaraguan poet Ernesto Cardenal (later to become Minister of Culture in the Sandinista-led Nicaraguan government of the 1980s). However grateful Duncan may be for Cardenals Ezra Poundinspired poetry in general, and for Cardenals very important editing and translating work on the 1963 Antologia de la poesia norteamericana (which had lent a degree of attention previously unknown in Latin America to the work of the poets in and around Duncans circle), Duncan nevertheless is fundamentally opposed to following Cardenals ethic of positing our inherent assimilation of evil or oppression in a manner requiring self-cleansing through a metaphoric leaching, homeopathy, or self-critique (not to mention Duncans opposition to what seems to him the next, radically intended but self-deluding step, whereby art is recruited to help
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
135
accomplish this already problematically conceived self-ablation). Duncan links his refusal to a profound, militantly formalist, reinvented Romantic-modernist defense of aesthetic value and provisional aesthetic autonomy (over against what he sees as the misguidedness or delusionality of Left artistic-cultural practices that in effect constitute an aestheticization dressed up as political commitment in the effort to identify to unite in mutual collapse, in the mutual dissolution of their heretofore provisional autonomyaesthetics and politics, aesthetics and ethics).26 Duncan will go so farin order to contest what he sees as an inevitably determinist (and hostile to organic-constructivist form), aestheticist identification of poetic or aesthetic activity with substantive ethicsas to insist on the sheerly formal character, illusion-character, mimetic- or semblance-character (Scheincharakter) of poetrys and arts presentation of sociohistorical or ethico-political matters. Whats projected is certainly not the condoning of what might seem referentially presented, but the mimesis itself, the presentation-for-apprehension, of aspects of objective reality that have been subjectively called forth, including undesirable, even evil, aspects; and its the same with beauty or goodness, whose semblance-form (whose formal aesthetic mimesis) isnt meant ultimately to be mistaken for substance (or else, Duncan believes, were in serious, self-delusionary, ethical and political trouble). Again, in intriguing parallels and sometime-crossings with Adorno and the other Frankfurters, Duncan develops, throughout his life in Left politics and experimental modernist poetics, stances notably similar to the Adornian-Frankfurt distinctions between protocritical aesthetic semblance or illusion and the ethical or sociopolitical delusion resulting from attempts to overcome mimesis and provisional aesthetic autonomy. Telling how these poetics and aesthetics evolve in Duncan would require book-length treatment. For our present more limited purposes itll do to show thatwhile Duncan hardly needs to crib here from Adorno, or from, say, the more familiar (to Duncan)
136
Robert Kaufman
Marcusean restatements of Adornos Aesthetic Theory (in, for example, Marcuses late text The Aesthetic Dimension)this is an area of significant overlap with the whole poetry after Auschwitz question, and its an area where the poetry itself starts to indicate why that now sixty-year-old question and its attendant materials was, and continues to be, such a burning, overarching problem for contemporary poetry, the other arts, and criticism. There are numerous points of entry to the life of this afterlife, even after a provisional narrowing of focus to the American scene; yet it happens that the American poetry and poetics emerging from the Vietnam experience becomes a special crucible. Consideration of some key Duncan contributions to the painting of this collective work will shed significant light on the larger picture.27 We noted earlier the double strangeness of William Carlos Williamss 1957 introduction to Howl, in which Williams had said absolutely nothing about Ginsbergs formal-technical, indeed about his artistic, abilities, while proceeding virtually to equate Ginsbergs experiences with those of the Jewish people under Nazism. What ought now to be added is Williamss earlier insistence to Duncan, in seminal 1947 and 1950 lettersin other words, in correspondence beginning about a decade before Howlthat poetry utterly lacks value if its formal power, and above all, the kinetic movement of its lines, doesnt carry the poem:
... THE LINES THEMSELVES. The movement of the lines [in the sixteen pages of poems Duncan has sent to Williams] is the same old monotony. It isnt what the words say, its what the poem makes. Break it upsomehow.28
The genesis of this correspondence with Williams crucially involves the fact that the then twenty-eight-year-old Duncan, a young poet attracting attention in the San Francisco Bay Area and also on the East Coast, had already spent eleven years in and out of UC Berkeley, in Philadelphia, in New York, then back
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
137
in Berkeley and San Francisco and, again, sort of in and out of UC Berkeley. The attention directed toward Duncan stems above all from what seems, to keen observers of both his own age and much older, like abilities and understanding in and about poetic art that far outstrip his years. Something that really catches the eyes and ears of those responding to Duncans poetry, for better but also definitely, he gathers, for worse in their view, is that the young Duncan seems not have heard the very old news that modernist means anti-Romantic. Duncans penchant for having Shelley or Blake or Browning in there cheek to jowl with Pound and Williams is, depending on whos reading or listening, disconcerting or magical and in any case intriguing. Why not, thenDuncan thinks after these last ten or eleven years, after having already visited and spoken with Pound to mixed result, why not send now, in 1947, sixteen pages of his best work to Williams?29 Williams in his response letter holds nothing back; he is semiapologetic that his critique will seem too intense and explains essentially thats hes spared nothing because he thinks Duncans own aims and evidence of talent demand no less. As the section quoted earlier demonstrates, Williamss basic critique is that Duncans lines are monotonous. The poems teasingly suggest, in some of their barest words, what Williams considers genuine modern mood, but those suggestions of mood, Williams notes, dissipate because the lines dont find ways to become, in terms of movement itself, the mood aimed at. In short, Williams emphasizes, too much saying, not enough making and the more making should make more variety.30 Theres insight and justice in Williamss analysis, and generosity in his offering it at some length. Three years later, writing to Duncan again, Williams finds quite a transformation, pronouncing himself especially impressed with Duncans meter; though, Williams adds, Duncan still seems to want to say too much, to put in too much. Instead, Williams urges Duncan to distill it
138
Robert Kaufman
to, or find, or make, the essential beat.31 But theres also some sense in which from the start, Williams in these reading of early Duncan perhaps cannot see or hear part of what Duncan wishes to do with what Williams in the 1947 letter deems the language merely of reminiscence, and the wrong kind at that, a reminiscence of past manners rather than perceptions. While clearly having much to learn at every point from what Williams says about prosody, one can almost chart Duncan absorbing, from this critique, as much as he can about line and beat and movement but asking himself how those lessons can be integrated into a language that might for Duncan, if not Williams, evoke historical and imaginative-conceptual perception rather than perception of the more immediate kind. Its of no small interest that the difference between the perceptual and the imaginative-conceptual will replay itself decades later in exchanges between Duncan and poets like Levertov, who had a more extensive correspondence with Williamsand who argue, in a manner parallel to Ginsberg, for poetrys immediate political effectivity (over against Duncans claim that the immediacy of such intended engagement vitiates poetrys unique abilities to construct, and thus to make available for apprehension as content). Ironically, theres only one poem in those first sixteen pages of 1947 work that Williams likes; in fact, he gives it real praise, and says its the one hed keep, presumably meaning that hed want published. Its An African Elegy, a poem with much of Duncan himself in it but also with almost impossible to miss echoes of Garca Lorca. Apparently unbeknownst to Williams, the poem, under its alternate title of Toward an African Elegy, had been accepted some three years earlier for publication in the Kenyon Review by John Crowe Ransom but was then refused after Ransom read or was notified that Duncans essay The Homosexual in Society had appeared in Dwight MacDonalds journal Politics. At any rate, one can hear why Williams thought these lines moved, and felt their movement constructing the content: And I see /
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
139
all our tortures absolved in the fog, / dispersed in Deaths forests, forgotten. I see / all this gentleness like a hound in the water / float upward and outward beyond my dark hand.32 In these 1947 and 1950 typewritten letters to Duncan, Williams seems almost anticipatorily to play with his own later use of the space-period-space [ . ]and also warns Duncan, in the process virtually punning with the typewriter strokes and spacings, not to try to be Williams, valuable as Williamss advice on prosody may be. But Duncan famously takes pride in the originality of what he wanted to claim was his utter derivativeness. The dot or period or point was, it turned out, just waiting to seize on Duncans imagination or to be seized by it. And its almost as if Duncan hears Williams too much and too well, and thus outwaits himself, or lets the dot, the period, the point percolate and grow even beyond what it had been in Williamss own prosody, until Duncan cant keep himself from making it genuinely his own. It begins to appear across the pages of Duncans 1964 volume Roots and Branches, and then is not only exponentially more in use and noticeably thickened and blackened in 1968s Bending the Bow (much of which had been written in mid-60s encounter with the daily experience of opposing the war in Vietnam) but also, in that volumes introduction, explicitly theorized in a way that makes prosody enact in brief the aesthetics or the imaginations stretching past extant, received boundaries or conceptualizations, likewise exploring (as we broached near the start of this essay via Ground Work s Some Notes on Notation) silences role within this stretching:
The immediate eventthe phrase within its line, the adjoining pulse in silence, the new phraseeach part is a thing in itself; the junctures not binding but freeing the elements of configuration so that they participate in more than one figure. A sign appears . a beat syncopating the time at rest; as if there were a stress in silence. [The poet] strives not for a disintegration of syntax but for a complication within syntax,
140
Robert Kaufman
overlapping structures, so that words are freed, having bounds out of bound.33
With that backdrop, its instructive but hardly surprising that Duncan will come to distinguish his work sharply from that of Ginsberg and his cohort. Add to this Duncans later disgust with Ginsbergs announcement that [b]eing a junkie in America today is like being a Jew in Nazi Germany, a statement that nonetheless, for Duncan, had the virtue of capturing what he thought deeply wrong with Ginsbergs and related Beat and/or New Left poetics or nonpoetics. Finally, according to Duncan, though those poets certainly possess the talent to do otherwise, the poetic art what Duncan calls the organic-constructivist poem or organicconstructivist formis abandoned for a fused programmatic politicization and media stardom, for Left cultural capital rather than for poetrys undetermined explorations, so that the choice is made for afflatus rather than for making, for linguistic posturing or attitudinizing rather than artistic construction of and with silences, caesuras, periods, points.34 While having culturalpolitical and, to a certain extent, poetic sympathy for Howl and related Ginsberg/Beat/Left experiments, Duncan comes to feel that their seeming reliance on Williams-derived practices and theories (of diction, line, syntax, and, above all, distilled clarity) is, at best, superficial. For even before hes published anything with the Williams dot or period, thickened or otherwise, Duncan begins to arguein notebook meditations, in some essays, and, perhaps most explicitly, in his remarkable correspondence with Levertovthat Beat and Left poetics too often fail to grasp the irreducibly formal activity (and the Romanticism-articulated, still-present-in-modernism, agency) from which the militant experimentalism of a Williamsian democratic poetics actually springs. For Duncan, what Ginsberg and the Beats misswhat they are indeed too often happy to miss, because of the difficulties and responsibilities involvedis Williamss and the Romanticmodernist traditions abiding, agency-related sense of construction.
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
141
In Duncans eyes, Beat discussions of, for instance, the breathline frequently devolve into bad-faith or self-deluding notions of extending, in superficial tribute, Williamss ways with the demotic, his feel for phrase and line. The claims about extending Williams, above all through the notion of breath units, quickly become, Duncan believes, an excuse for a unit of poetic articulation not at all constructed butoften with no small degree of bombast advertised or announced by fiat as somehow having been won for feeling and spontaneity, with the additional suggestion that construction has been begun but then subversively or trangressively undone; Duncan bitterly contests the latter point, believing in such undoing but believing also that it would first require the serious imagining and accomplishment of an initial doing, making, construction.35 For Duncan, an expressivity that earns its keepthats more than individualist blab, however subversively or transgressively intendedemerges within such construction, is indeed constructed by it. Though Duncan makes recourse to various formal techniques linked to, if not invented by, Williams and other earlier modernists, that dot or period that Duncan will explicitly theorize in the introductory materials to Bending the Bow and in Ground Work s Some Notes on Notation understandably becomes an at once almost physical or palpable matter and a constructed thing. It thus simultaneously captures, to reiterate, two things Duncan finds lacking or weak in Ginsberg: construction and silence, which start in Duncan to infuse one another. For Duncanhere following Williams and many other moments of radical experiment in prosody and in poetrys engagements with the socialtheres no move toward voice and the song that can stem from speech without a genuine stretching toward the rediscovery of silences, provisional though they may be, in contradistinction to modern cultures antireflective dedication to the noise of pure products that drive America and, increasingly, everywhere and everyone else, crazy.36 The point of the point, Duncan contends, is to be
142
Robert Kaufman
able to findthat is, to construct our findings ofcaesuras at their various points within the phrase, line, or sentence, but to do so in a manner that allows first the poet and then the reader to see, hear, feel, and understand where he or she has engaged or re-engaged in the necessary and disciplined yet somehow also play-oriented activity of construction (over against becoming like Ginsberg or breathing like Ginsberg, that is, being encouraged to adopt, memorize, emulate, or imitate rather than make). Hence finally the point, dot, or periods silence potentially can come anywhere within the poem, provided the construction justifies itself expressively. In this sense the point, dot, or periods silence serves as a starting (and restarting, and restarting!) point of a theory-practice of constructivist lyric that follows and extends Williams in refusing to make poetic art either sheerly lyric (and hence prone to what Duncan sees as an almost formally inevitable narcissism in Beat poetry) or sheerly constructivist (in a manner that Duncan will come to identify with much in 1970s and 80s Language Poetrys versions of Williams). This silence is thus antithetical to subjectivitys (and radical mimesiss) crucial role in contributing to the further construction of the very ability to express human suffering:
your feet . sound time in me . bells ring in other worlds I cannot see . I see . imprint in sound . sound in the imprint . where you . enduring . where you have yet to be.37 have been
The point of the dot, the point of the period, the point of the point is first and last the always-again-in-process transformational movement of construction-expression, and first and last the interfusion of musicality (or voiced musicality) and silence. Though the Holocaust will by no means be the only history at issue, Duncans art may have learned so much from the dot or
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
143
period or point that at certain moments these may no longer have needed to appear for their work to be accomplished; at any rate, Duncans poetry in this light cannot help but lead one to reflect on the introduction to Howl, for Duncan increasingly engages the question of a particular set of inimical-to-Ginsbergianism silences that will comprehend not only the caesura that is the Holocaust but also the continuing sociopolitical meanings of that suspension and its aftermaths, as poetry attempts to become one with what is simultaneously the point and vanishing point of historical experience. Yet all this stands as something like an achieved view from near the roads end. The more in-the-moment makingand the polemics, intended and notin practice often appeared to others as they had wished to read it, that is, in line with official countercultural stances that were not quite Duncans. Take one of Duncans most famous antiwar poems, Up Rising: Passages 25, a poem written in 1965 that perhaps not so accidentally melds itself to Ginsbergs great precursor Blake while hearing and voicing a decidedly different Blake than the one drafted into Beat poetics:
Now Johnson would go up to join the great simulacra of men, Hitler and Stalin, to work his fame with planes roaring out from Guam over Asia stirrd at his will, which would be a bloated thing, drawing from the underbelly of the nation such blood and dreams as swell the idiot psyche out of its courses into an elemental thing until his name stinks with burning meat and heapt honors spent in a great potlatch, this Texas barbecue of Asia, Africa, and all the Americas . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
And men wake to see that they are used like things
144
Robert Kaufman
But the mania, the ravening eagle of America as Lawrence saw him bird of men that are masters, lifting the rabbit-blood of the myriads up into ... into something terrible, gone beyond bounds, or ... in what image? the ominous roar in the air, loosing his flow of napalm, below in the jungles any life at all or sign of life his target, drawing now not with crayons in his secret room
As Blake saw America in figures of fire and blood raging, the omnipotent wings, the all-American boy in the cockpit
and
the burning of homes and the torture of mothers and fathers children, their hair a-flame, screaming in agony, but of Johnson, for the victory of American will over its releasing his store of destruction over the enemy, of communism
38
in the line of duty, for the might and enduring fame victims, in terror and hatred of all communal things, of communion,
Duncan here discovers, in ways distinct from anything in Ginsberg and other Beats, how to use Poundian and post-Poundian prosody to develop further a Blakean ability to rant with no holds barred and yet simultaneously to build or formally construct every phraseindeed, nearly every syllablewith a lyric musicality whose starts and stops, shifts, turns, and circlings are little short of remarkable. (This is evident when, late in the text, Duncans virtuosic, momentary eruption or fall into and then out of prose poemin a manner at once unsettling and formally justified prosaically tells of backroom scenes of weapons laboratories and cocktail-party receptions, as the poems formal dynamics emerge from the poems own form-process to reveal a constructed ability to apprehend and express the new content itself.)
145
At least as remarkable will be the way Duncan comes to realize, through the later 1950s and across the 70s and 80s, that to his own utter astonishment poems like Up Rising are being treated, including by some poets, as if theyve been produced according to a predetermined Left or oppositional schema, program, or platform: in short, by an abiding, predetermined, and, be it said, ethicopolitical concept. Of course for Duncan, the power of poems like Up Rising, the power of most of Blake, the power of poetry, is precisely that it feels like it knows something beyond whats conceptually predetermined or objective, feels subjectively as if its new discovery is already there, as if already objectively present and conceptualized, needing only to be reached toward, articulated, specified. That means that for the poem, for an imaginative work, to work, its discoveries have to move immanently, spontaneously.39 Immense frustration, at times bordering on disbelief, that fellow Left poets appeared to ascribe poems like Up Rising to a programmatic or deterministic, already-conceptualized poetryas-politics finally leads Duncan to what for many seemed the most surprising of sources and connections. What occurs next becomes a later twentieth-century American episode in the long contest between Romantic-modernist provisional aesthetic autonomy on one hand, and overt conceptually predetermined political commitment on the other. In a process too intricate to trace here in detail, the reflections ventured in Up Rising and kindred Duncan poemsabout how the availability of prodigious scientific technical-technological capability, married to a tendency not to question (particularly in wartime) the use of such capacities (linked especially, in the war at issue, to the ongoing decision and then apparent unthinking nondecision to use napalm) begins to hint at what after Auschwitz might mean for Americans. It is hardly an accident that just at this time (the early and mid60s), in writings, interviews, and perhaps above all in lectures to students, Adorno and other Frankfurt School figures, in ac146
Robert Kaufman
cord with artists, critics, philosophers, and activists from other traditions, begin in earnest to develop an explosive argument theyd previously left inchoate or merely suggestive. They contend not that the contemporary wars in Vietnam, Algeria, and elsewhere directly continue Auschwitz, but rather that they cannot be thoughtand that what was happening on the ground could not be taking placeabsent the Nazi genocide. Hence Adorno, Horkheimer, Marcuse, and others start to formulate the notion of it being impossibleor reprehensiblesimply to identify, as one-with-Auschwitz, later ongoing policies of almost automatically enacted mass atrocities, yet of it being equally barbaric to pretend there could somehow be no historical or ethical link with Auschwitz when the later actions indisputably occur not only in the shadow of that which happened but also with acute awareness precisely of how whole cultures could initially, and then subsequently, let anything with such a possible logic happen, even partially, again.40 Hitler and Stalin in that Blake-inspired Up Rising had not been meant rhetorically so much as in deep internal or immanent working-through of infernal historical materials. Reflecting on the failure of others to grasp thisnot only in his own poems but also in those of other poets, and in the contemporary situation itselfDuncan begins to feel his way toward one of the most weighty reflections on formal-prosodic, cognitive, existential, and, ultimately, historical caesurae known in English-language poetics. And the Romantic, militantly formalist source text can hardly be coincidental. Puzzling through for the nth time the difference between what he on one hand calls moralizing (including, and perhaps especially, Left moralizing) in verse or the prose poem, and what he on the other hand believes organic-constructivist poetry really does with materials that are themselves shot through or seeking contact with ethical and political experience, Duncan finds himself reaching for Keats, for negative capability, and for the allied notion of the camelion poet in contradistincPoetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
147
tion to what he sees as an inevitably anti-aesthetic and therefore aestheticist identification of poetic or aesthetic activity with substantive, objective-conceptual, ethics or politics. In what would become a crucial, mutually painful letter to his dear friend the Left-activist poet Levertov, and later followed through in essays and correspondence with others,41 Duncan again insists on the sheerly formal character or illusion-character or semblance-character (Scheincharakter) of poetrys and arts presentation of ethico-political problematics, declaring in a formulation explicitly indebted to Keats that the poets role is not to oppose evil but to imagine it. He then continues Keatss Hazlitt-indebted thought (in Keatss letter about the camelion poet, the companion meditation to the negative capability letter) about taking equal delight in a Iago and an Imogen: [W]hat, Duncan queries, if Shakespeare had opposed Iago? But Duncan almost immediately emphasizes that the defense of this classically Kantian-Keatsian-Romantic (and, one might add among many analogues, Adornian) notion of the critical value of reflective aesthetic experience does not celebrate formal autonomy for its own sake. Rather, focusing on the decidedly nonutopian, let alone nonescapist, side of the aesthetic autonomy coin, Duncan contends that a conceptually predetermined political stance that dictates or guides the poem actually acts to forestall any imagination of what the system is. In other words, there are probably more, and perhaps worse, aspects of the particular reality at hand than the sociopolitical system itself makes representionallyconceptually available, more than our existing concepts for that reality can adequately represent. This more is something the poem can only get to or toward if it can find its way by subjectively feeling itself negatively capable, capable, as Keats suggests, of being in uncertainties, mysteries, doubts, without any irritable reaching after fact or reason. Duncans dwellingamid the ongoing reality of the Vietnam warin Keatsian negative capability and
148
Robert Kaufman
indeterminate or ambiguous negation and nothingness, a touchstone for Romantic aesthetic agency and modernist impersonality bothwill carry him, in just a few years, toward the revisitation of Celan.42 The convergences between Duncans threading through, over several decades, modes of formal and prosodic experimentation taken from Williams and other modernists and fused with reinvented Romantic and modernist notions of critical agency, and the parallel Frankfurt and especially Adornian meditations on post-1945 lyric, on aesthetic experience more generally, and on how the 60s might be grasped as commanding more rather than less urgency in relation to what had seemed like immediately postWorld War II questions, can be quickly sketched. In a July 29, 1965, lecture to his university students, Adorno had notedin ways paralleling the meditations on life, experience, and aesthetic activity that for Duncan had been most located in Emerson and the British Romanticsthat
nothing can be even experienced as living if it does not contain a promise of something transcending life. This transcendence therefore is, and at the same time is notand beyond that contradiction it is no doubt very difficult, and probably impossible, for thought to go.43
The related final sections of Adornos 1966 Negative Dialectics reprise this thinking about transcendence but now explicitly unite it with the workings of art, whose illusion-character or semblance-character (Scheincharakter) is conceived as almost synonymous with both its status as art and its powerful yet merely formal dynamic:
Art is semblance even at is highest peaks; but its semblance, the irresistible part of it, is given to it by what is not semblance. Semblance is a promise of nonsemblance.44
149
Art or semblance is for Adorno as for Duncan critical precisely in its formal character of aesthetic illusion as opposed to unknowing aestheticist delusion. In marking itself as illusion and in advertising its illusion-character to its audience, arts acknowledged and foregrounded formal aesthetic illusion signals the interaction and interdependence of, but also the difference between, itself and the world. (Aestheticist delusion tends toward the collapse of the different identitiesoften under the pressure of good-faith, radically intended assumptions of the burdens of responsibility for sociopolitical or ethical engagement, for changing the world, as Marxs celebrated Eleventh Thesis on Feuerbach puts itand can thus contribute unwittingly to an inability to distinguish at all between the artwork and the world from which the artwork stems but is different, a marking of difference that is actually at the heart of Marxs intentions in his frequently misunderstood Eleventh Thesis). Critical aesthetic illusion and its formal dynamic or dialectic of, to paraphrase Benjamin, charged distance of intense engagement and correspondence with, amid full awareness of difference from, the empirical, sociopolitical, and historical Realthus turns out to be at the heart of the negative dialectic itself. For semblance is, or inheres in, the possibility of a more than already completely determined life, of more than a life reduced to sheer and dwindling mechanistic immediacy, whose grimmest versionthe most dramatic version of complete determinationis the genocidal reduction and elimination of particularity on a mass scale. Thats to say that some relationship to a provisional transcendenceto a sense of, or to a sense of a capacity for, an experience of existence that exceeds prior determinationis inextricably related to our opportunity to experience semblance, to undergo the combined thought-and-affect thinking of aesthetic form that surprisingly turns out to be only form, to be only semblance, for it ultimately reveals itself to lack the determinate substance or objectivitycognitively speaking, the already determined conceptit had initially felt or seemed to
150
Robert Kaufman
possess. Semblance activity of this kind can exfoliate or construct itself into the feeling-experience, subjective by definition (that is, not predeterminable, not already conceptualized, and thus not capable of objective universality) of life that indeed lives. That is of course the guarded hope for change or reversal implied in Adornos famous epigraphic recourse, as he begins Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged Life, to Krnbergers Life does not live.45 The idea that life absent subjectivitys and agencys animating principle of semblance is damaged life, life that does not live, is known to Duncan in its German Romantic, nineteenthcentury, and modernist instantiations. But again, for Duncan, the almost instinctively reached-for first markers of the modern version of this idea of life, damaged life, and semblance-enacted living form are Wordsworth, Blake, Coleridge, Shelley, and Keats. Like many artists of his generation, Duncans access to those poets and then to the modernists themselves is to him hardly a sign of class privilege or class-climbing; it signals instead that a great contemporaneous and future-oriented achievement of Romantic and post-Romantic art has been the ability to address and enable audiences composed of decidedly unprivileged people like himself. Consequently, for Duncan and allied poets, as for Du Bois and Adorno and the Frankfurters, the crucial question on this score hardly concerns what is in any case the mere shadow-fight of high versus low culture. It turns out rather to concern, in a very Kantian-Romantic manner, whether works or phenomena of art and culture can spur a critical-reflective agency that, through what is initially a semblance-experience, stretches past the extant concepts and conceptual boundaries of reigning status-quo society; or whether aesthetic and cultural works will, on the other hand, merely repeat and echo societys reigning concepts. Duncans notion of lyric as ground work accords substantially with Frankfurt theorizations of aesthetic and lyric experience; as this essay earlier hinted, in Duncansand indeed in Du Boissview, just about the most ringing pronouncements
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
151
on these matters are found in Shelleys Defence of Poetry.46 Lyric stands for Duncan as groundwork not because it is better or nobler or more right-on than other kinds of literature, art, or cultural works, but because of the otherwise unremarkable fact that, as a formal matter, lyric maintains a special relation to the presumptive medium for significantly communicable conceptuality, language. Each art has its unique character; lyrics is to take language, the presumably bottom-line medium of objectivity (in the Frankfurters and others philosophicaltheoretical vocabulary, of conceptuality) and, first, to subjectivize it, affectively to stretch conceptualitys bounds in order to make something that seems formally like a concept but that does something that ordinary, objective concepts generally do not do: sing. For lyric song to reach a significant audience, it must then construct its own form of objectivity or coherence, though the logic is that of arthere especially involving poetic arts relation to musicalityrather than strictly mathematical-conceptual logic. Each of the arts has its mode or modes of semblance. In lyric, semblance primarily involves making speech acts appear, feel, as if their very logic has compelled them somehow to burstnaturally, justifiably, as it wereinto song, which suddenly seems necessary but certainly hadnt yet felt predetermined, and which in its bursting (in a manner inseparable from pleasure) the formal contours of extant conceptuality allows for a renewed sense of capacity or agency vis-vis materials that can eventually, postaesthetically, be grasped as sociopolitical or historical or ethical content within the newly stretched form or formal capacity. And while the Frankfurters generally resist the idea that the National Socialist genocide was an inevitable outcome of capitalism, they do stress the importance to that which happened of the socioeconomic apotheosis of sheer conceptual determinism represented by decadesif not a century or moreof rule by exchange value, under which subjective valuations made in and toward subjective universality (made from a particular subjects feeling that its pleasure could
152
Robert Kaufman
be noncoercively shared with a potentially universal community) are felt to have become, at best, superfluous vis--vis major questions of socioeconomic value. The repeated mass experience of this withering of the importance, and then inevitably the experience itself, of spontaneous, play-oriented thought-activity that contributes toward subjectivity and reflective-critical agency thus becomes crucial in various ways to the notion of damaged life, or to the preconditions that lead to mass damage.47 Adornos point really wasnt that poetry shouldnt be written after 1945, but that its very humanness would in some sense require it to be brutal, barbaric in dedicating life-giving semblance-experiencethe experiencing of dynamic aesthetic, organic-constructivist form itselfto the attempt to convey that all this, and so much more, had been almost entirely disappeared. The point was to convey as well that far too much had been left, in the aftermath or nach Auschwitz, not as life-giving, not as living, but as life that does not live in a numbed survival, a numbed after-living or beyond-living that thus required an ultimate version of artistic-aesthetic being cruel to be kind, a recourse to and further development of songful lyric semblance precisely to render the genocidal elimination of songs life. The brutal or barbaric point demands, not least because of Celans inextricable connection to these Adorno-associated questions, to be pushed even further. For perhaps no poetry has faced as intensely and devastatingly the historical volta confronting lyric after the National Socialist genocide. Among the matters Celan so acutely sees and incomparably brings to artistic-aesthetic experience (brings to life) and that he consistently indicates requires a practicehowever reinvented in darker tonesof Romantic-modernist agency to bring it to life, is this: The act of remembrance, throughout lyrics long history a crucial starting point in making the dead and the lost live on, must in Celan be radically deferred in favor of what initially seems an inexplicable violence the poem itself commits.
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
153
The poem, that is, must murder the victims precisely so that they can then be rememberedknown for the first time, so to speak as murdered. Though this verges on the old axiom about artworks killing their victim-subjects all over again, it verges there only to establish its crucial difference. The rub is the killing them all over again; the poem somehow clarifies that though the killing certainly already occurred, its status and meaning as murder has to an astonishing degree remainedagainst the wishes of countless people seeking to come to terms with the event, and hence as if in infernal, perverse accord with the original perpetrators professed intentunassimilable. The poetry therefore ruthlessly and as if for the first time brings into being, as the particular murder after particular murder after particular murder it surely was, that which happened. Whatever remembrance the poem can then with prodigious effort turn toward attempting in semblance to spark in the reader will be, to put it mildly, earned and hard won. The poems fearlessnessits willingness not only to risk but also to immerse itself brutally or barbarically in a necessary ruthlessnessacts as a self-administered inoculation against the potential ease of familiarity or final comfort that so often attach to consolatory and redemptively oriented art, and indeed to the genuinely humane intent that tends to drive them but that can arrest exactly the corrosive experience Celans poetry senses has already been suppressed and that needs voiced reconstruction. Celan grasps that the genocides vast, totalized, mass-industrial character has more often than not made it seem, in the aftermath, strange or difficult to conceive in terms of murder. Murder as a cultural, ethical, and legal concept develops historically to apply to certain kinds of forbidden destruction of human life, to unjustifiable homicide, the unlawful and usually conscious taking of ineradicably individual, particular lives, even when victims were marked collectively or en masse. This characterization differentiated murder from, among other things, historical practices (understandable or nefarious, as one may view them) of finding
154
Robert Kaufman
mass killings and eliminations of other living beings (nonhuman animals, for example) to be something other than murder. To get back behind the phenomenon wherein the very scale of mass murder starts to make it difficult to apprehend as murder, Celans poems rediscover the language of the stone; in their breathtaking formal dance, their deftness and nimbleness and indeed beauty they nonetheless gravely articulate or starkly sing the thousand darknesses of deathbringing speech; they transform the nurturant image of milk into a sullied liquid that, with still another recognitional shock-twist, reveals itself as an apostrophic beseeching of the addressee-beloved to imbibe and assimilate what the body would otherwise reject as rotten, spoiled, polluted, as this willingness to take in the address to black milk becomes the process of interacting with or provisionally becoming one withfinally, of lovingthe poems beseeching speakers, its suffering subjects: Gestern / kam einer von ihnen und / ttete dich / zum andern Mal in / meinem Gedicht (Yesterday / one of them came and / killed you / once more in / my poem).48 Apprehending the enormity and singularity of Celans achievement, Adorno clearly feltin ways that were contrastively illuminated by his readiness to write about the form-and-content difficulties and virtuosity of Beckett almost on first encounter and to continue doing so for decades thereafterthat a criticism even beginning to do justice to Celans poetry would assume a responsibility almost as impossible and barbaric, and as barbaric not to risk, as the poetry itself. Adorno famously died leaving in his desk the notes toward what by then1969, the year before Celans suicidewas evidently about to bear fruit in the writing of the long-intended and certainly long-awaited essay on Celan. Yet its easy enough to see that a kernel of the imagined essay appears in Aesthetic Theory s Paralipomena fragment on Celan as the artistic and sociohistorical apogee of the Baudelairean line most profoundly understood, Adorno emphasizes, by Benjamin. Significantly in terms of the question of
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
155
lyric and life, the Paralipomena fragment starts by threading its way through the poetry, history, and theory constellated in Benjamins seminal articulation of Baudelaires imaginative-artistic ability to convey, through aesthetic experience, a particular experience of the loss of particular experience itself (and the loss in consequence of a precondition for reflective-critical subjectivity and agency). Adorno begins to suggest how Celan incomparably understands and enacts the ways that lyric poetrys attempts to take the measure of the National Socialist catastrophe raise to the most extreme degree imaginable the fundamental problems Baudelaire delineates for an earlier modernist poetics: how, artistically, to bring experience, particularity, and/or life to materials that at their core evince the sociohistorical withering or elimination of those phenomena.49 This too rarely remarked inability of Adorno finally to write the piece on Celan has everything to do with the question of modernism, of whether it has a postwar life or afterlife. For Adorno is in one special and rare way not alone in his predicament concerning how to approach Celan; one might go further and speculate that Adornos reticence involves an extra charge precisely because of his sense of something that among other critics and commentators hardly registers if it registers at all: Celans modernism, indeed, his radicalhis necessarily barbaricmodernism. For while the critical literature has been happy to talk at length about Celans modernist sources and sympathies, in practice criticism hasnt even bothered to ask whether he might indeed still be modernist, whether Celan himself might regard modernism as the only way to make poetry after 1945. Criticism has tended either entirely to ignore the question and its difficulty, in effect treating Celan as an unnamed Movement of One, or as if he stands just past the end of modernism (though Celans poetry and prose actually gives little evidence of such a stance). In this way, Celan criticism and poetry criticism more generallyjoined here with the even broader phenomenon and overwhelming interest, for the last four decades, in establishing a
156
Robert Kaufman
poetics of post modernism characterized especially by the alleged superannuation of aesthetic autonomy and its Romantic-modernist critical agency and subjectivitystrangely recapitulates in criticism the seeming nondiscussion in art itself of modernisms mass murder.50 That is, what if Celan is graspedas it in fact should be impossible to avoid trying to doas unique and brilliant but still modernist? It would then be hard to avoid wondering whether the death of modernismin art and in arts attendant critical literaturestems in significant part from an understandable wish to interrupt brutality and barbarism, the brutality and barbarism that would make poems and other artworks pivot on the murders modernism would perforce symbolically seem to commit all over again in engaging that which happened. Modernism itself is murdered so that the murderousness it would instance can be sidestepped. It will be among the special contributions of Duncan and American poetry to manifest that their participation from a removetheir not being saddled with all the special pathos adhering to Celan and later European poetshelps illuminate the after-modernism question. The foregoing at any rate helps us see why, nearing the last pages of Negative Dialectics, Adorno appears apologetically to shift the question from poetry after Auschwitz to the question of whether you could go on living after Auschwitz. All too conscious that across three decades his words, not intended to harm anyone, nonethelessin part due to his own naivetehave caused great pain, he doesnt add whats nonetheless true: The two questions, poetry and life, are to him, as to Celan and, as well further see, to Duncan, the same question. They are the same question, that is, so long as life is understood to include the experience of an ineradicably intellectual-affective activity, a stimulus to critical agency and subjectivity allowing one to sense, and in semblance to feel the possibility of acting with, a capacity beyond whats already been conceptually determined: a phenomenon that in modernity has tended to be called aesthetic experience.51
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
157
Lyric song, songfulness, and musicality is, in Duncans Romantic later modernism as in Celan and in so much Frankfurt School writing, the aesthetics ground-form or foundational modality and is thus cognate with expressive capacitywith an activated sense of being alive in feeling and thought, capable of constructing, exercising, articulating, and developing critical agencyitself. Informed by the strains of poetics and aesthetics discussed earlier, something nonetheless weird and perhaps irritating immediately asserts itself in A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings. In its apparent withholding of imagery and related concretizations, and its concomitant apotheosis of abstraction, Duncans poem brilliantly enacts the tensions and questions before us. Engaging its materials and content via lyrics song-semblance, A Song paradoxically constructs itself, for all its evidently humane intentions, into and as extreme abstraction, in a manner that in its remoteness finally can seem brutal, if not barbaric. Concrete particularsspecific images of beauty or, for that matter, specific images of just about anythingare suppressed; it is almost unnecessary to add that this abstractionist suppression of imagery and other concrete particulars at once dramatizes and mourns the historically genocidal elimination of human particularity that, via Celan, is surely among the poems primary referents. And this emphasis contributes to what initially and for perhaps many readings thereafter disturbs or unsettles the poems audiences: the texts excessive abstraction can simply seem too much, too one-sided, obsessive, even fanatical. (It may well be that Duncans elaborate, very specific instructions for the French chapbook edition of the poem was an attempt to balance the scalesor, on the other hand, numerically to heighten the texts abstractionist tension.) Yet it begins to dawn upon the reader that the poems commitment to intense formal abstraction works through to the other side of the looking glass, because ultimately this heightened abstraction becomes inseparable from concretion itself. For
158
Robert Kaufman
what, as the canonical axiom of lyric has long (and especially since Romanticism) intoned, is simultaneously more abstract and more concrete than the sensuous but utterly ephemeral, invisible substance of music or musicality? In its homeopathically ruthless suppression of the imagistic or visual, Duncans poem not only becomes exponentially ideational, intellectual, and philosophical but its very abstractness also turns itself into one large soundimage through Duncans extraordinary way with the structuring, the sound-building, the architectural casting into musical phrase-units that come to comprise one living sound-form. This sound-image (to return to the governing tension-paradox of concretion and abstraction) is finally the apparent semantic blankness but also literally the concretely felt-and-heard sound of both music and, as the poem consistently puts it, nothing (for the poem tends toward the enactment of an ultimate sonic palpability of sheer sound that, exactly via such excessive or heightened concretion, seems to move away from concretization as it abstracts itself from any fully conceptualized or determined reference or content). This amplified abstraction allows the poem and its audiences to discover anew, but with terribly raised stakes, how lyric at once embodies and distills or disembodies into abstraction both language and music (or musicality). Duncans masterful sound-sculpting can be recognized in, for example, the poems felt-as-spontaneous cadences and precise but apparently unprescribed, not-predetermined metrics, its inescapable, ever so slightly changing repetitions and phrasings made quasi-fugally to thread through, inside, behind, and ahead of one another, which are hauntingly redolent of Celans probably most celebrated poem, Todesfuge (Deathfugue). (Todesfuge was ultimately rejected by Celan himself because of his perception that the poem had become comforting to those it should have continued to unsettle.) When we recognize that Duncans stark abstraction has been shaped to be at-one-in-process with a complex, concretized rhythmics and micromelodics (so that what rePoetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
159
sults is the creation of one grand, monumental yet self-dissolving and mobile image of lyric musicality itself, constructed from the interchange of over-insistent, mechanized or steamroller abstraction and fleeting, encased-in-silencing-marble songfulness), then we recognize as well that Duncan has somehow integrated brutality, even barbarism, with beauty and made them sequential or ultimately inseparable in the experiencing of the poem. He thereby reenforces how and why it is that here lyrics song-semblance must capture that which is least evidently beautiful, the materials most sociohistorically and ethically resistant to songful particularization because songful particularization was precisely what had been arrested and abstracted away toward liquidation. The poem packs all of this into the sign Paul Celan through the irreducible particularity and, in its own way, the almost-too-painfulto-admit gorgeousness (painful because of the hardly beautiful content this gorgeousness genuinely aims to realize) of the entire text itself, of A Song. The poems difficult but haunting song almost blasphemously particularizes the after-experience of historys recent nightmarish attempt to liquidate particularity itself; the blasphemy stems from the artworks having followed through and enacted the Adornian insight, the Celanian realization, that such creation of particularity, such creation of songful engagement, necessarily risks the purveyance of at least semicomforting untruth. This would be untruth not only in the sense that the memorialization of the dead and their suffering can suggest something redemptive where, as here, redemption is hardly the poets aim and is questionable in any case. It would also be untruth because the very particularization that is arts play-work of stretching toward undetermined universals (dramatized in lyric as the initial subjectivization/particularization of our medium par excellence for already-universalized and determined objectivity, language) here particularizesvoicesprecisely those people for whom the truth of historical experience was not only to have been murdered but also to have been eliminated in a manner
160
Robert Kaufman
meant to extirpate all traces of individual and collective particularity, of individual and collective voice. In a manner honoring and following but hardly copying Celan, lyric beauty or lyric particularizationraised in Duncans cultural and temporal remove to an even higher, more forbidding level of stylistic abstraction nonetheless here concretely enacts or names, in a gesture meant ultimately as loving conjuration-memorialization, a historically mass-scale murder whose very massiveness had tended to abstract its character as the murder of individual after individual after individual after individual, and so on. To write a poem of ethical and political engagement thus again casts itself as necessarily barbaric. On one level, the assertion that must always appear to be lyric songs definitional assertionits assertion of musical or songful capacity, of capacity for voice, of the relative freedom and availability of the play-work necessary for such voicingappears brutally insensitive to the victims experience, to the liquidation of their experiences and lives; or worse: in the poem, song kills. In other words, everything modernity has associated with robust subjectivity, and with subjectivitys presumed apotheosis in arts conceptually free or undetermined play-experience (whose effect can be the discovery and naming of not yet known or articulable experience), has in fact been incinerated with the incineration of the subjects themselves, in their millions. So the attempt to convey all this in poetic-aesthetic subjectivity, in lyric poetrys continued experimental construction of particularity, is where not only the poem but also its barbarism, and its historical truth, begins. Lest we miss this binding, Duncan from the get-go cross-threads into the poems style, mode, and content another register of formal dynamic, namely, the virtuosic handling of the pronominal shifter, its weaving into the songcirculation that makes apparently propositional statements move toward being mere alternative propositional soundings on the way toward perhaps becoming simply soundings: Something has wreckt this world, I think I have wreckt this world, Nothing
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
161
has wreckt this world Nothing has wreckt this world I am in, and so forth. Thus the poems circling movements of song-speculation, the play with different angles of responsibility and relationality and interchange (of self/subject for world, world for self/ subject, both for nothing and nothing for both) areat this most basic yet sophisticated level of forms worka profound homage to Celans much-discussed virtuosity with the shifter. In fact, the homage is startlingly immediate, more so than has been known. No critic has yet discussed itprobably because it was only recently catalogued in Duncans archivebut Duncan wrote out the one-page manuscript of A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing [As] the Poet Paul Celan Sings on the verso of a one-page, old-fashioned blue-ink mimeographed copy of the German of Celans Todesfuge (fig. 1). It is not known if the copy had been given to Duncan or if he made it himself.52 Duncans handwritten text, in black ink, makes up the reverse side of the mimeographed page (fig. 2).53 Fascinatingly, the manuscripts caret-mark reveals that the words Paul Celan are added to the title as a second thought or afterthought. Duncan had already worked on the Structures of Rime across some three decades when he composed A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings. Throughout that time, he had made a practice of titling each individual poem of the sequence simply by number: The Structure of Rime I, The Structure of Rime II, and so on. The only variations were that, at times, the series title lost the definite article and was written simply as Structure of Rime, or it was titled in the plural, The Structures of Rime VI or Structures of Rime X; or a particular books table of contents would also give the individual poems first words or first line: Structure of Rime XX: The Master of Rime told me But A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings marks the first time that a poem within the series is not numbered, that it carries a full title, and that it explicitly mentions song (though here it is the absent
162
Robert Kaufman
Figure 1. Image of Robert Duncans undated holograph manuscript of his poem A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings, Robert Duncan Collection, courtesy of the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York. 2010 by the Jess Collins Trust and reproduced by permission.
163
Figure 2. Image of Robert Duncans mimeographed reproduction of Paul Celans poem Todesfuge (Death Fugue), Robert Duncan Collection, courtesy of the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York. 2010 by the Jess Collins Trust and reproduced by permission. German text from Paul Celan, Mohn und Gedchtnis, 1993 Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt, a part of Verlagsgruppe Random House GmbH, Munich, and reproduced by permission.
164
Robert Kaufman
Celan who sings, while Duncans poem appears to allow itself only the chiming or echoing role of ringing). A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings is published, after its 1984 appearance in Ground Work: Before the War, twice more before Duncans death. The poem appears in an anthology published by Emmanuel Hocquard and Raquel Levy (who in 1977 had published the poems original edition of the nine palm-size chapbook copies). The chapbook and anthology printings added a great deal to Duncans reception and importance in French poetry, poetics, and aesthetics, where his significance has only grown with the passage of time (so that a very recent and much-discussed French meditation on Kants ethics begins with three epigraphs: from Benjamin; from the French poet Jean Daivea friend, colleague, and translator of Celan, who in turn translated Daives poetry into German; and from Duncan).54 Then, gravely ill in 1987, Duncan gives permission through the writer David Levi Straussfor the poet Benjamin Hollander to include the poem as the inaugural page of a special issue of the journal Acts titled Translating Tradition: Paul Celan in France that Hollander is editing.55 Only three more poems enter The Structures of Rime before Duncans 1988 death; two follow the Celan poem in Ground Work: Before the War; they are prose poems and are titled simply by number, though the second also announces that it is written In Memoriam Wallace Stevens. In Ground Work II: In the Dark one last stunning contribution is made to the series, and it makes retrospectively clear that A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings had been a final turning point, wherein the series moved into a new level of fully accessed songfulness. It becomes clear too that that turn had been inseparable from the exploration undertaken in A Song of how an American poet and American poetry might continue to bring into its fields of formal construction and expression the incomparable artistic achievement and unspeakable sociohistorical and
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
165
ethical materials of Celans work, and to find ways to constellate themto make them feel necessarily, rather than contingently or additively connectedwith an American sociocultural history of Emersonian darkness, with Du Boisian presentation of the glory but also the suffering of Africa. These are presumably the materials least amenable to song-making within the whole contentrange of twentieth-century poetry and culture, while formally, Celans extreme difficulty makes it seem as if his might perhaps be, among the great post-1945 poetic oeuvres, the least available to the wide circulation or echoing of its hazarded song. Yet Duncans unique technical abilities and deep insight tend to demonstrate otherwise, and it is significant that Duncan can and does rely not only on his reading of Celan and the German and French traditions informing Celan but also on a particularly American way of inheriting British Romanticisms allied figurings of voice, agency, reflection, and the like. These abilities enable Duncan, at any rate, to compose A Song and, as a result, to go on to write and publish, almost at the end of Ground Work II: In the Dark, the astonishing and influential Structure of Rime: The Five Songs, which will be the concluding song sequence within the series as a whole, a concluding song sequence that Duncan inaugurates with the following notes or prose poem preface, Of The Five Songs (while the immediately following Five Songs themselves are all in verse):
Not having found The Five Songs, a sound and then an other is sent out to search meaning. there. Songs. other. But The Five Songs is not hidden In the sounding alone there is a rumor of The Five They, the Five, are earth, air, fire, and water, and an They are four suiteshearts, diamonds, clubs, spades, Spring, summer, fall, winterfour seasons and They are the five vowel-letters and each one is an
Among the apparent kinds of otherness that Duncan here imagines, one surely is the othernessostensibly other to the
166
Robert Kaufman
determined elements of nature and matter themselvesof human agency, spirit, anima. Whatever term is used from among these, its expression for Duncan is, or begins in, songs elemental musical phrasings, whichin Duncans extensions of Pounds thinking about the undetermined yet still somehow metrical modernist experimental practice of poetic composition by musical phraserequire the voice of maker and reader to lead with the vowel tones (and hence those vowels are themselveseach one isalready an other in its distinctness).
almost there as I sang then I have always been here we are but O, Dear
releases, the heart in the earliest poem awaited, Again I have arrived.
Duncans commitment to lyric and to our aesthetic experience of it is, explicitly and repeatedly, a reinvented and remodernized American negative-Romantic and modernist commitment to the nothing that is in fact the yet-to-be determined, the yet-to-beconceived; the perception and engagement of this field as such is the apprehension-construction of it as living form. Following Celan and indeed Adorno in the poetry after Auschwitz imbroglio, Duncan contributes to the making of a poetry after poetry
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
167
after Auschwitz, and among its effects are the reopening of the question of modernism and its afterlives, perhaps simply its life. The poem in Duncan is the commitment to an imagined and made space of aesthetic illusion or semblance that keeps determination and ethico-political possibility open, alive, for exploration, over against the delusion that the poem itself is already an ethical or political act. More severely, the poem is a commitment to the exploration, through a projected illusion-space, of the twentieth centurys, if not modernitys, most wrecktbecause utterly, grimly, determinedworld, in which semblance and thus life has, or at least appears to have, no further place. Its no minor thing that A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings makes this happen in a trajectory that allows at least a distillation of Romanticisms famously full-throated lyric songfulness to help later twentieth-century American modernist poetry find a way to voice a relation to a devastating historical watershed without presuming to have assimilated or directly identified with the experience itself. Yet the need in thinking is what makes us think, Adorno writes as the curtain comes down on Negative Dialectics. It bears repeating one last time that Duncans ringing of Celans song likewise lets us know, in further understanding of what semblance-enactment of living form makes possible, how and why it is that
beyond the world I am in something nothing there. in the world longs for
168
Robert Kaufman
Endnotes
For their responses to earlier versions of this essay, I am indebted to Tony Cascardi, Norma Cole, Jean Day, Stephen Fredman, Bob Hass, Brenda Hillman, Benjamin Hollander, Chana Kronfeld, Francine Masiello, James Maynard, Michael Palmer, Eric Sundquist, Ross Wilson, and Alex Woloch. Any errors are the authors alone.
1
heodor W. Adorno, Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft (written 1949; first T published in Soziologische Forschung in unserer Zeit: Leopold von Wiese zum 75. Geburtstag [1951]; subsequently published in Theodor W. Adorno, Prismen. Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft [Berlin, 1955], pp. 731), p. 31; the English translation of the essay is Theodor W. Adorno, Cultural Criticism and Society, in Prisms, trans. Samuel and Shierry Weber (1967; reprint, Cambridge, MA, 1981), pp. 1734, p. 34 (translation emended). The original sentence:
Kulturkritik findet sich der letzten Stufe der Dialektik von Kultur und Barbarei gegenber: nach Auschwitz ein Gedicht zu schreiben, ist barbarisch, und das frisst auch die Erkenntnis an, die ausspricht, warum es unmglich ward, heute Gedichte zu schreiben. (p. 31)
Elsewhere Ive tried at length to rehearse and interpret the history of what Adorno, Celan, and others did and didnt say, what their criticism or poems did or didnt demonstrate, about poetry, art, culture, and criticisms post-1945 barbarity or impossibility, as well as the overlapping story of partial understandings and pained miscommunications. While necessarily threading modern poetrys historyand key poetry texts into itself, that account aimed mostly to offer a historical-theoretical view of the relevant poetic-aesthetic, ethical, and critical issues. See Robert Kaufman, Poetrys Ethics? Theodor Adorno and Robert Duncan on Aesthetic Illusion and Sociopolitical Delusion, New German Critique 97 (Winter 2006): pp.73118. William Carlos Williams, introduction to Allen Ginsberg, Howl, originally in Howl and Other Poems (San Francisco, 1956); reprinted in Howl on Trial: The Battle for Free Expression, ed. Bill Morgan and Nancy J. Peters (San Francisco, 2006), pp. 1920. For discussion of Hamletian poetics in relation to aesthetic experience more generally, and to the question of aesthetic experiences possible relations to sociopolitical analysis and interpretation, see Robert Kaufman,Negatively Capable Dialectics: Keats, Vendler, Adorno,
169
and the Theory of the Avant-Garde, Critical Inquiry 27, no. 2 (Winter 2001): pp. 35484, esp. pp. 37277, and The Sublime as Super-Genre of the Modern, or, Hamlet in Revolution: Caleb Williams and His Problems,Studies in Romanticism 36, no. 4 (Winter 1997): pp. 54174.
5
See Percy Bysshe Shelley, A Defence of Poetry, in Shelleys Poetry and Prose, ed. Donald H. Reiman and Sharon B. Powers (New York, 1977); Muriel Rukeyser, The Life of Poetry, with a new foreword by Jane Cooper (1949; reprint, Ashfield, MA, 1996); and see Susan Stewart, What Praise Poems are For, PMLA 120, no.1 (2005): pp. 23545; and see too Denise Gigante, Life: Organic Form and Romanticism (New Haven, 2009); on Rukeyser, see the especially illuminating discussion in Susan Schweik, A Gulf So Deeply Cut: American Womens Poetry of the Second World War (Madison, 1991).
In what might otherwise prove unjustifiably idiosyncratic use of the terms organicism, expressivism, constructivism, and later modernist, this essay, while sketching the formal and historical case for such usage, relies largely on what Ive tried elsewhere to establish by sustained argument from evidence; the notes point throughout to published versions of the fuller showing. Briefly, I assume here that the work of construction is everywhere present in what Romanticism or Romantic vocabularies in the twentieth century call organic form, and that this is fully understood by most of those who invoke artistic-aesthetic (as opposed to political) organicism. By the same token, a significant number of modernist constructivists follow and extend Hlderlins and other Romantic poets understanding that expression or mimetic affinity, far from needing to be banished from advanced art, is precisely what experimental construction constructs (or coaxes toward renewal) in the attempt to strengthen capacities for experience, reflective judgment, and critical agency. Finally, later modernist in this essay generally refers to poetry of whats usually called the postmodern period. I use later modernist descriptively, correctively, and polemically to designate a post-1945 poetry that, for all its departures from the modernist poetry that precedes it, has more in commonin terms of formal dynamics and provisionally autonomous artistic-aesthetic experience, and in terms of militant commitment to lyric genre or modalitywith earlier modernism than with what becomes the canonical version of postmodernist poetics. As the essay itself indicates, this later-modernist poetrys conjoined rethinking of Romanticism and modernism has everything to do with its abilities to see past postmodernism, and to allow the apprehension of latertwentieth century histories incapable of being grasped via postmodernist poetics.
6
On Duncans romantic later modernism more generally, see Michael Palmer, Robert Duncan and Romantic Synthesis, American Poet (Spring 1997), reprinted at http://www.poets.org/viewmedia.php/ prmMID/15949, and Robert Kaufman, Lyrics Constellation, Poetrys
170
Robert Kaufman
Radical Privilege, Modernist Cultures 1, no. 2 (Winter 2005): pp. 20934, http://www.js-modcult.bham.ac.uk/backissues.asp?issue=22&issue_nam e=Volume+1%2C+Issue+2+%28Winter+2005%29.
7
See Robert Duncan, Ground Work: Before the War (New York, 1984), p. 8. Unless otherwise noted, all further citations to A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings and to Ground Work are to the recently published book combining Before the War with Ground Work s 1988 second volume, In the Dark; see Duncan, Ground Work: Before the War, In the Dark, intro. Michael Palmer, ed. Robert J. Bertholf and James Maynard (New York, 2006), p. 12. Paul Celan, Psalm, in Gesammelte Werke in sieben bnden, ed. Beda Allemann, Stefan Reichert, and Rolf Bcher (Frankfurt am Main, 2000), 1: p. 225; see too Poems of Paul Celan, trans., with an introduction and postscript, Michael Hamburger (1972; reprint, New York, 2002), pp. 15253:
Psalm Niemand knetet uns wieder aus Erde und Lehm, niemand bespricht unsern Staub. Niemand. Gelobt seist du, Niemand. Dir zulieb wollen wir blhn. Dir entgegen. Ein Nichts waren wir, sind wir, werden wir bleiben, blhend: die Nichts-, die Niemandsrose. Mit dem Griffel seelenhell, dem Staubfaden himmelswst, der Krone rot vom Purpurwort, das wir sangen ber, o ber dem Dorn. Psalm No one moulds us again out of earth and clay, no one conjures our dust. No one.
171
Praised be your name, no one. For your sake we shall flower. Towards you. A nothing we were, are, shall remain, flowering: the nothing-, the no ones rose. With our pistil soul-bright, with our stamen heaven-ravaged, our corolla red with the crimson word which we sang over, O over the thorn.
9
For a succinct introduction to a good deal of these reading, translation, and reception histories, see Matthew Hofers excellent Between Worlds: W. S. Merwin and Paul Celan, New German Critique 91 (Winter, 2004): pp. 10115. See also Poems from the Floating World 1 (1959): pp. 1112, and New Young German Poets, trans. and intro. Jerome Rothenberg (San Francisco, 1959), esp. introduction and pp. 1624. See Paul Celan, Speech-Grille, and Selected Poems, trans. Joachim Neugroschel (New York, 1971), and Poems of Paul Celan.
10
11
For this publication and reception history, I am indebted to May 2005 conversations in Paris with Emmanuel Hocquard and Claude RoyetJournoud and subsequent correspondence with Royet-Journoud. Duncan, Some Notes on Notation, in Ground Work, pp. 3, 4.
12 13
Duncan seems also in Paris to have for the first time come across Celans astonishing translations of Dickinson into a German that somehow managed further to compress Dickinsons already incomparably condensed thought; the translations proved so remarkable that they led a number of French poets to begin translating into French Celans German translations of Dickinson.
14
Palmers own developing thoughts about the poem, ventured for years in discussions with other poets and critics, have found their way into his introduction to the new edition of Ground Work, xii. For some key instances of Duncans later-modernist rewritings of what are nonetheless still Romanticism-identified notions of organic form which for Duncan usually means, in practice, Coleridgean notions
15
172
Robert Kaufman
before all elsesee Ideas of the Meaning of Form, in Robert Duncan: A Selected Prose, ed. Robert J. Bertholf (New York, 1995), pp. 2337, and two astonishing letters in The Letters of Robert Duncan and Denise Levertov, ed. Robert J. Bertholf and Albert Gelpi, intro. Gelpi (Stanford, CA, 2004), pp. 4048. For a brilliant treatment of the poetics of rime and condensationand adjacent issuesin relation to scientific understanding in the Enlightenment and Romanticism, see Joann Kleinneiurs doctoral dissertation The Chemical Revolution in British Poetry, 17721822 (PhD diss., Stanford University, 2007).
16 17
See La Notte (1961), dir. Michelangelo Antonioni, screenplay Antonioni, Ennio Flaiano, and Tonino Guerra (1961); for the braiding of Adorno with the films primary, almost immediately projected concerns, see the screenplay text in Michelangelo Antonioni, Sei film: Le amiche, Il grido, Lavventura, La notte, Leclisse, Deserto rosso (Turin, 1964), pp. 3045, and in Screenplays of Michelangelo Antonioni: Il grido, Lavventura, La notte, Leclisse,trans. Roger J. Moore and others (New York, 1963), pp. 21415. Antonioni and his collaborators further load the dice by making Mastroiannis characterGiovanni, a novelistquickly admit that, although he has roundly praised his dying comrade Tommasos article on Adorno, hes actually only skimmed the piece (and is thus, the audience sees, incapable of thinking and talking meaningfully about it with Tomasso). Tommasos imminent death and Giovannis dedication to skimming generate much of what follows in La Notte. For the full passages, contextualizations, examination of what Adorno did and didnt say across three decades about poetry after the Holocaust, and about what it all may have meant, see, again, Kaufman, Poetrys Ethics?
18
Within American poetry, art, and criticism themselves, and to some extent in public liberal and Left American culture more generally, polemics over Adornos controversial aphorisms have been unceasing, even entering television news magazines debates centering on Bosnia, Kosovo, and Rwanda. Influential contributions to the discussion have been made by a range of American poets and poet-critics, including recent meditations by Lyn Hejinian, Joan Retallack, Susan Stewart, and Susan Gubar. See Lyn Hejinian, The Language of Inquiry (Berkeley, 2000), passim and at, e.g., pp. 3132, 4058, 89, 14748, and esp. 31836; Joan Retallack, The Poethical Wager (Berkeley, 2003), passim and esp. at pp. 162, 88; Susan Gubar, Poetry After Auschwitz: Remembering What One Never Knew (Bloomington, IN, 2003), passim; and Susan Stewart, On the Art of the Future, in The Open Studio: Essays on Art and Aesthetics (Chicago, 2005), pp. 1527, 25960 n. 3, 260 n. 7, citing her earlier Poetry and the Fate of the Senses (Chicago, 2002).
19
See Herbert Marcuse, Negations: Essays in Critical Theory (Boston, 1968), p. 245.
173
20 21
See Duncan, The Homosexual in Society, published originally in Dwight Macdonalds journal Politics 1, no. 7 (August 1944); republished in Robert Duncan: A Selected Prose, pp. 3850. On Du Boiss relationship to British Romanticism, see Robert Kaufman, Intervention and Commitment Forever! Shelley in 1819, Shelley in Brecht, Shelley in Adorno, Shelley in Benjamin, Romantic Circles Praxis Series (May 2001), http://www.rc.umd.edu/praxis/interventionist/ kaufman/kaufman.html, and The Madness of George III, by Mary Wollstonecraft, Studies in Romanticism 37, no. 1 (Spring 1998): pp. 1725.
22
23
Excerpted from Robert Browning, The Lost Leader, in Robert Brownings Poetry, ed. James F. Loucks and Andrew M. Stauffer (New York, 2007), pp. 12425.
Theres a line of concern here that leads to the contemporary poet-critic Nathaniel Mackeys ongoing championing of Duncans work in various forums, including in the Mackey-edited journal Hambone, which has featured not only poets but also other figures in the arts speakingperhaps most notably the jazz composer and pianist Cecil Taylorabout what Duncan has meant to their work, and to their understandings of lyrics place in African American culture. See, e.g., Nathaniel Mackey, Gassires Lute: Robert Duncans Vietnam War Poems, Editing Hambone, and the plethora of weavings in and out of Duncans thought in Paracritical Hinge: Essays, Talks, Notes, Interviews (Madison, 2005), pp. 71178, 24448, and passim, and Nathaniel Mackey, The World-Poem in Microcosm: Robert Duncans The Continent and Uroboros: Robert Duncans Dante and A Seventeenth Century Suite, in Discrepant Engagement: Dissonance, Cross-Culturality, and Experimental Writing (1993; reprint, Tuscaloosa, 2000), pp. 4965, 66103, and passim.
24
See W. E. B. Du Bois, The Negro and the Warsaw Ghetto, Jewish Life (May 1952): pp. 1415, reprinted in The Oxford W. E. B. Du Bois Reader, ed. Eric J. Sundquist (New York, 1996), pp. 46973. Its worth adding that as late as the 1940s, Duncan can think of Lenin as one whose impulses toward an at least kindred and ostensibly noncoercive theory of universals had been muted and then outright eliminated in the Soviet Unions development. That sympathetic, quite Du Boisian image of Lenin still explicitly animates Duncan texts like The Homosexual in Society.
25
Robert Duncan, The Self in Postmodern Poetry, in Fictive Certainties: Essays by Robert Duncan (New York, 1985), p. 226. See The Letters of Robert Duncan and Denise Levertov, pp. 54046; and Antologia de la poesa norteamericana, trans. and ed. Jose Coronel Urtecho and Ernesto Cardenal (Madrid, 1963). See too, for extended discussion of the underlying issues of poetics, aesthetics, ethics, and politics, Kaufman, Poetrys Ethics?
Robert Kaufman
26
174
27
See Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, ed., trans., and with a translators introduction by Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis, 1997), sthetische Theorie, vol. 7 of Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedemann (Frankfurt am Main, 197086), and Herbert Marcuse, Die Permanenz der Kunst: Wider eine bestimmte marxistische sthetik (1977), in vol. 9 of Schriften (Frankfurt am Main, 1987), trans. and rev. Herbert Marcuse and Erica Sherover under the title The Aesthetic Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist Aesthetics (Boston, 1978). William Carlos Williams to Robert Duncan, June 2, 1947 (underlinings in original). My thanks to the Robert Duncan Archive of the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York, and to curator James Maynard, as well as to the Estate of Robert Duncan for permission to reprint this passage.
28
29
Such mixed results included Pounds later, semi-amiable complaints about Duncans reinvented Romanticism, and, as Duncan will later tell it on various occasions, the anti-Semitic pamphlets so graciously given to Duncan by Mrs. Pound that were, Duncan said, among the most hairraising things hed ever seen. See the discussion and citations in Thom Gunn, Adventrous Song: Robert Duncan as Romantic Modernist, PN Review 17, no. 4 (March/April 1991): pp. 1423. Williams to Duncan, June 2, 1947, Robert Duncan Archive of the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York.
30
31
Williams to Duncan, February 23, 1950, Robert Duncan Archive of the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York. From Robert Duncan, An African Elegy (written as Toward an African Elegy, 1942; republished in Robert Duncan, The Years as Catches [Berkeley, 1966], pp. 3335).
32
33
Robert Duncan, introduction to Bending the Bow (New York, 1968), p. ix. For his quotation of and response to Ginsbergs comment, see Duncans 1959 note-commentary The Homosexual in Society, pp. 4647 n. 7.
34
35
Consider, for example, Duncans response to Ginsbergs Howl-period Siesta in Xbalba and Return to the States (1954); first published in Evergreen Review 1, no. 2 (1957): pp. 13747, then published in Allen Ginsberg, Collected Poems, 19471980 (New York, 1984), pp. 97110. The poem begins:
Late sun opening the book, blank page like light,
Of apocalypse
175
After reading the poem in Evergreen Review, Duncan writes to Levertov (May 8, 1958): Take Ginsbergs Howl or the earlier Xbalba that appeared in Evergreen: with the proposition NO constructionlet the mind fall down. My sense that there could be a poem is whetted. But then there is no dis-construction in itonly lazy lines, loose talk that gets looser and soon hes asking what love in the cafes of God which is both exalted and gassy; The Letters of Robert Duncan and Denise Levertov, p. 119. Cf. Duncans May 25, 1959, comments: Last Saturday we had a group reading for Measure where Ginsberg read from his Kaddish for his motherand for the first time I heard him read with emotion; once you grasp that the poemlike Howl is designed in order to wind up an hysterical pitch (at the close of the poem he was shouting like Hitler or an evangelist, so that the audience having risen with him on wave upon wave of momentous lines ROARD). As the seizure of the poem increased, the content became disorderd, then idiotic and finally disappeard. But no wonder it is impossible to attack his work as bad writingit is almost exactly calculated to be an agency for such a frenzy. And what we see (hear) when it is not used to arrive at the seizure, is like the funny expressions of a face separated from the terrifying fit it is going thru. I dislike using a poem, and thats the crux of the matter; The Letters of Robert Duncan and Denise Levertov, p. 172 (italics in original).
36
Excerpted from Spring and All (1923), Poem 18, in The Collected Poems of William Carlos Williams, ed. A. Walton Litz and Christopher MacGowan (New York, 1986), 1: pp. 21719.
37
176
From Duncan, Up Rising: Passages 25; written 1965, first published under title Up Rising in the Nation 201 (September 13, 1965): pp. 14647; subsequently published as part of Robert Duncan, Passages 2227: Of the War (Berkeley, 1966), and in Duncan, Bending the Bow, pp. 8183.
39
See Duncans December 16, 1966, comments to Levertov about even a poem like Up Rising not being personal witness but rather poeticimaginative: Even Up Rising is not this kind of witness [wearing a button, talking about war]; for ultimately [whats constructed and then expressed in Up Rising] ... belongs to the reality of that poem and a vision of Man. And I do not answer for myself in my work but for Poetry; The Letters of Robert Duncan and Denise Levertov, 563. See, e.g., Theodor W. Adorno, Lecture 13 (13 July 1965) and Lecture 14 (15 July 1965), in Metaphysics: Concept and Problems (London, 2000), pp. 1012, 1034, 1069, 177 n. 5, 179 n. 12; Theodor W. Adorno, Metaphysik: Begriff und Probleme (Frankfurt, 1998), pp. 15962, 166, 16970, 274 n.187, 27677 n. 195.
40
41
Such correspondence included, very significantly, the then-young poet and critic Michael Davidson. The Letters of Robert Duncan and Denise Levertov, 669; John Keats, letter to George and Tom Keats, 21, 27 (?) Dec. 1817 (the negative capability letter) and letter to Richard Woodhouse, 27 Oct. 1818 (the camelion poet letter), in The Letters of John Keats, ed. Hyder Edward Rollins, 2 vols. (Cambridge, MA, 1958), 1: pp. 193, 38687. For extended discussion of Frankfurt and other modernist inheritings of negative capability and the identitlyless or camelion poet, see Kaufman, Negatively Capable Dialectics, pp. 35484.
42
43
Adorno, Lecture Eighteen (July 29, 1965), in Metaphysics: Concept and Problems, pp. 14445 (italics in original translation); Metaphysik: Begriff und Probleme, p. 226 (italics in original German). Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. G. B. Ashton (1966; reprint, New York, 1973), pp. 4045; Negative Dialektik (1966), vol. 6 of Adorno, Gesammelte Schriften, pp. 39697.
44
45
Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged Life, trans. E. F. N. Jephcott (London, 1974), 19; Minima Moralia: Reflexionen aus dem beschdigten Leben (Frankfurt am Main, 1951), p. 13. Among Minima Moralias best-known aphoristic reflections are those that play variaions on Krnberger, including, Our perspective of life has passed into an ideology which conceals the fact there is life no longer, so that life has become the ideology of its own absence (Leben ist zur Ideologie seiner eigenen Absenz geworden; pp. 1516, 190; 78, 252). See Robert Kaufman, Legislators of the Post-Everything World: Shelleys
Poetry After Poetry After Auschwitz
46
177
Defence of Adorno, English Literary History 63, no. 3 (Fall 1996): pp. 70733.
47
See Robert Kaufman, Lyric Commodity Critique, Benjamin Adorno Marx, Baudelaire Baudelaire Baudelaire, PMLA 123, no. 1 (January 2008): pp. 20715. And see Ross Wilson, Subjective Universality in Kants Aesthetics (Oxford, 2007). See Paul Celan, Todesfuge, in Gesammelte Werke, 1: pp. 3942, Wolfsbohne, in Gesammelte Werke 7: pp. 45-49, and Ansprache anlsslich der Entgegennahme des Literaturpreises der Freien Hansestadt Bremen, in Gesammelte Werke, 3: pp. 18586; Death Fugue and Wolfs-Bean in Poems of Paul Celan, pp. 31, 33, 34045; Paul Celan, Speech on the Occasion of Receiving the Literature Prize of the Free Hanseatic City of Bremen, in Collected Prose, trans. with an introduction by Rosmarie Waldrop (New York, 2003), pp. 3335 (trans. emended). On the relation of this suffering to lyric expressivity, and on why the formal experimentation necessary to construct such expression becomes part of lyrics content (becomes, in fact, lyrics form-content), see the discussion of Brecht, Michael Palmer, and Frankfurt School aesthetics in Robert Kaufman, Lyrics Expression: Musicality, Conceptuality, Critical Agency, in Adorno and Literature, ed. David Cunningham and Nigel Mapp (London, 2006), pp. 9916. For a profound consideration of how Celans poetry must radically re-image and rework nature itself to make the suffering at issue apprehendable, see Rochelle Tobias, The Discourse of Nature in the Poetry of Paul Celan: The Unnatural World (Baltimore, 2006).
48
49
Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, pp. 32122; sthetische Theorie, pp. 47577. For a representative example of these tendenciesin this case, assuming and asserting but never really showing that Celan is at most modernisms traumatized swan song, see the otherwise fine discussion of Celan in Ulrich Baer, Remnants of Song: Trauma and the Experience of Modernity in Charles Baudelaire and Paul Celan (Stanford, 2000).
50
51
See Kaufman, Poetrys Ethics? I am profoundly indebted to James Maynard, Assistant Curator at the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York, which houses the Duncan materials, for bringing to my attention the existence of Duncans mimeograph of Celans Todesfuge and the versos holograph of A Song.
52
Besides knowing the poem in German, Duncan was also very familiar with Michael Hamburgers translation of Celans most famous poem, in Poems of Paul Celan, 3033:
Death Fugue Black milk of daybreak we drink it at sundown we drink it at noon in the morning we drink it at night
178
Robert Kaufman
we drink and we drink it we dig a grave in the breezes there one lies unconfined A man lives in the house he plays with the serpents he writes he writes when dusk falls to Germany your golden hair Margarete he writes it and steps out of doors and the stars are flashing he whistles his pack out he whistles his Jews out in earth has them dig for a grave he commands us strike up for the dance Black milk of daybreak we drink you at night we drink in the morning at noon we drink you at sundown we drink and we drink you A man lives in the house he plays with the serpents he writes he writes when dusk falls to Germany your golden hair Margarete your ashen hair Shulamith we dig a grave in the breezes there one lies unconfined.
He calls out jab deeper into the earth you lot you others sing now and play he grabs at the iron in his belt he waves it his eyes are blue jab deeper you lot with your spades you others play on for the dance Black milk of daybreak we drink you at night we drink you at noon in the morning we drink you at sundown we drink you and we drink you a man lives in the house your golden hair Margarete your ashen hair Shulamith he plays with the serpents He calls out more sweetly play death death is a master from Germany he calls out more darkly now stroke your strings then as smoke you will rise into air then a grave you will have in the clouds there one lies unconfined Black milk of daybreak we drink you at night we drink you at noon death is a master from Germany we drink you at sundown and in the morning we drink and we drink you death is a master from Germany his eyes are blue he strikes you with leaden bullets his aim is true a man lives in the house your golden hair Margarete he sets his pack on to us he grants us a grave in the air he plays with the serpents and daydreams death is a master from Germany
179
As can be seen, Duncans holograph of the poem failsas an oversight, or perhaps intentionallyto include the word As in the title. However, the poems typescript does include As; see the undated typescript in the Robert Duncan Archive of the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York. The typescript also adds some punctuation marks absent from the holograph. Duncan made additional changesprimarily involving spacing, the choice of capital or lowercase letters, and hyphens or dashes within wordsfor the version of the poem as published in France by Orange Export Ltd. and in Ground Work (reproduced earlier in this essay); Duncan also personally proofread and approved both publications. For the French publication of Duncans poem, see Orange Export Ltd.: 19691986, ed. Emmanuel Hocquard and Raquel Levy (Paris, 1986), pp. 11112; as printed in the anthology, the section breaks reproduce the page divisions of the original chapbooks layout. For the epigraphs from Benjamin, Daive, and Duncan, see the opening page in Michle CohenHalimi, Entendre Raison: essai sur la philosophie pratique de Kant (Paris, 2004).
54
55
See Translating Tradition: Paul Celan in France, ed. Benjamin Hollander, Acts 8/9 (1988). The issue features Celans poetry, translations of it, and work by a number of French and American poets and critics (including John Felstiners almost moment-by-moment recreation of Celans astounding, aforementioned translations into German of Emily Dickinson). Duncan, Structure of Rime: Of the Five Songs, in Ground Work, p. 256.
56 57
Credits
The following publishers and individuals have graciously granted permission to include the indicated material in this volume.
The Robert Duncan Archive of the Poetry Collection, University at Buffalo, the State University of New York, curator James Maynard, and the Estate of Robert Duncan: Images of Robert Duncans
manuscript poem A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing As the Poet Paul Celan Sings and mimeographed reproduction of Paul Celans poem Todesfuge (Death Fugue), copyright 2010 by the Jess Collins Trust and
180
Robert Kaufman
reproduced by permission. Passages from William Carlos Williams to Robert Duncan, June 2, 1947, and February 23, 1950, copyright 2010 by the Estates of Paul H. Williams and William Eric Williams. Used by permission of New Directions Publishing Corp.
S. Fischer Verlag and the heirs of Paul Celan: Psalm by Paul Celan, copyright 1963 by
S. Fischer Verlag, Frankfurt am Main.
New Directions Publishing Corp.: A Song from the Structures of Rime Ringing as the Poet Paul Celan Sings by Robert Duncan, from Ground Work: Before the War, In the Dark, copyright 1988 by Robert Duncan. Passages from William Carlos Williams to Robert Duncan, June 2, 1947, and February 23, 1950, copyright 2010 by the Estates of Paul H. Williams and William Eric Williams. Excerpt from the introduction to Bending the Bow by Robert Duncan, copyright 1968 by Robert Duncan. Excerpt from An Eros/Amor/ Love Cycle: 3. Structure of Rime by Robert Duncan, from Ground Work: Before the War, In the Dark, copyright 1988 by Robert Duncan. Excerpt from Up Rising: Passages 25 by Robert Duncan, from Bending the Bow, copyright 1968 by Robert Duncan. Excerpts from Structure of Rime: Of the Five Songs and Structure of Rime: The Five Songs by Robert Duncan, from Ground Work: Before the War, In the Dark, copyright 1988 by Robert Duncan. Excerpt from Spring and All by William Carlos Williams, copyright 2010 by the Estates of Paul H. Williams and William Eric Williams. Persea Books, Inc.: Translations of Psalm and Death Fugue by Paul Celan, translations by Michael Hamburger; translation copyright 2002 by Michael Hamburger. Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group: Excerpts from an earlier version of this essay,
entitled AfterNach: Lifes Posthumous Life in Later-Modernist American Poetry, in Ross Wilson, ed., The Meaning of Life in Romantic Poetry and Poetics (New York, 2009).
181
Ale Erjavec
Aesthetics, as Adorno often remarked, has lagged behind developments in art. Since its articulation as a field of inquiry, aesthetics has often been unable to accomplish its aim of offering an explanation, evaluation, or identification of its object, which remains predominantly art. Furthermore, it was often the artists who were suspicious of the role of aesthetics, asking, Why do you waste your time and mine by trying to get value judgments? Don't you see that when you get a value judgment, that's all you have?1 They warned: The danger to be avoided lies in aesthetic delectation.2 In brief, for the artists, often the maximum that aesthetics was considered capable of achieving for art was, according to Barnett Newman, what ornithology is for the birds. A similar view is shared by much of philosophy: The dominant opinion ... shows that the glorious sensible presence of art is devoured by a discourse on art which tends to become its own reality.3 If these views are accurate, why continue to carry out aesthetic analysis except for historical, documentary, and purely intellectual purposes? Adorno himself offered a persuasive answer: What
182
Ale Erjavec
is essential to art is that which in it is not the case, that which is incommensurable with the empirical measure of all things. The compulsion to aesthetics is the need to think this empirical incommensurability.4 In Adorno, the aesthetic theoryas opposed to aesthetics as an academic discipline or division of philosophy and a segment of a philosophical systemis necessary not only because of the desire to know and to reflect but also to have an effect on artistic practice.5 The philosopher is an authority for practitioners of art and those who contemplate it.6 As Adorno claims in Aesthetic Theory, Every artwork, if it is to be fully experienced, requires thought and therefore stands in need of philosophy (AT, 262). In this respect he is unlike the analytic aestheticianbut very much like the Dantoesque theorist of art who appears to have achieved the impossible, namely, a conflation of the analytic and the Hegelian lines of reasoning. Adorno in his turn succeeds in bringing together an insightful analysis of high modernist art without succumbing to the temptations of a Hegelian totalizing mindset. Traditionally, aesthetics targets the gray realm on either side of the borderline of art qua art, aims at the object at the dividing line between art and not-art, be it temporally synchronous or historically diachronous, whether what is at issue is the inclusion of a work or a body of works within the changing realm or class called art. Art is no fixed set of boundaries but rather a momentary and fragile balance (AT, 300). The identity of art is determined with the aid of borderline cases that are then included within the parameter of art. What is therefore at stake are borderline cases: instances of works that are candidates for aesthetic and/or artistic appreciation but have not yet attained such status within the current art world. While past art has often met with the designation of not-art or bad art, in contemporary art all such production purportedly falls within the realm of art. Even more: once a work is admitted into this parameter of art, with the encircled realm being the institution called art, it may lose its
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
183
artistic or aesthetic worth, but it hardly ever loses its status as a work of art. But this is only one side of the coin; on the other side, precisely such borderline cases can be regarded as the only authentic cases of art. Jean-Franois Lyotard introduced the unusual designation of artworks being first postmodern and then modernpostmodern when they are still outside the parameter of the institution of art and modern when they enter it and lose their nature as events.7 From designations such as Lyotard's (one of whose historical roots being anarchist aesthetics) arises a conflict and a contradiction between works that are already a part of the institution of art, works that are potential candidates for such an inclusion, and works that, by not yet being members of this institution, function as authentic art. A major factor in the development of art is precisely the disagreement over whether something is art or not.8 On its own terms, this disagreement reveals the conflict between art as a part of the institution of art and art as an event.9 In Adorno the negativity of art prevents its utopian realization, since this realization would cause its end. In this thought, Adorno distances himself from Schiller in his Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man where the latter claims that if we are to resolve the problem of politics in practice we must approach it through the aesthetic. It is Schiller's idea that precisely because it renounces all direct intervention in reality, art is suited to restore man's wholeness,10 namely, by bringing together the halves of man represented by sensousness and reason. Schiller's view was not isolated, or at least not for long; witness Saint-Simon's 1825 statement about the artists who will develop the poetic aspect of the new system.11 The artistic avant-garde is from its historical beginnings linked to its political double, causingBaudelaire was the first to note12the artistic avant-garde to accept, in spite of its infinite desire for freedom, the militaristic discipline of the political
184
Ale Erjavec
avant-garde. Adorno sees the characteristic feature of avant-garde art in the concept of the new rather than in the intent of the avant-garde movements to reintegrate art in the praxis of life (TA, 87), which, for him, would suffer precisely the consequences of such a discipline. The notion of the avant-garde is crucial to an understanding and interpretation of modernism in the last two centuries. Adorno also sympathizes with the notion of the avant-garde, but the aspect that would be of interest to him would today more appropriately be called modernist. This aspect is exemplified by the concept of the new and by the dissonance that prevents facile consumption of an authentic artwork in bourgeois society. The radicalthe politicizedavant-gardes partly overlap with Adorno's notion of modern art, but in their central features they represent a very different form of artistic dissonance. Their avant-garde aesthetic intent in the culture of the thirties and forties no longer meets with a supportive or indifferent social environment, which is why they cease to be considered worthy of discussion by Adorno. Around World War I their utopian potential is still present, but even then they are subversive not in the artistic manner propounded by Adorno, but in staking out another path of dissonance: that of aesthetic militarism. Nevertheless, that their aesthetic procedure is not alien to Adorno can be seen in his frequent remarks on Dadaism, as when he states that hermetic poetry (and that of Mallarm) converges with its political counterpole, Dada (AT, 321). In the debates preceding postmodernism, the notion of avantgarde art attains a variety of designations, from those that associate the debates with, or dissociate them from, the political avant-garde organizations to those associated with classical avant-gardes (Stefan Morawski); Brger's almost eponymous historical avant-gardes; Greenberg's avant-garde; and post-, trans-, and retro-gardes. Contrary to the notion of autonomous art defended by Adorno,
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
185
the avant-garde in art was conceived as art that transcends the confines of its autonomy. In Adorno, autonomous art of course cannot be subsumed under the category of Kantian disinterestedness, which, for him, is in fact pleasure masquerading beyond recognition (AT, 13), very much resembling the effects of l'art pour l'art. Modern art has eliminated the universal, but the excluded is retained through its negation. It is the specificity of this negation that is constitutive of the modern (AT, 351). The other feature of modern artof any authentic artis, for Adorno, its existence as a mediated form between the historical society and the work: the constitutive immanence of the aesthetic sphere is at the same time the ideology that undermines it (AT, 349). This mediation is a theme for philosophical aesthetics. In Adorno's opinion, the social aspect of art is its opposition to society by way of its immanence and not its political stance: by being partisan, art negates its autonomy and becomes reducible to a particular interpretation. Since society is thoroughly instrumentalizedeverything is but a means for something else, has value only in relation to something else and not to itselfautonomous art is one of the few instances of human activity and existence that does not succumb to the demands of the capitalist system. Still, as noted in the case of Dada, Adorno's aversion to partisan art (and the kitsch of the Soviet blocAT, 349) should not be confused with his implicit support for some aspects of the activities of the classical avant-gardes. In accordance with the prevailing dichotomy of the first half of the twentieth century, Adorno perceives authentic art of his epoch as that which achieves the subversion of content by form, offering as examples works by Kafka and Beckett, and Picasso's Guernica. Works of artists such as these allow for the experience of the autonomy of an artwork in its relation to the heteronomy of society. In the opinion of Wolfgang Welsch, in Adorno the autonomy of the artistic work criticizes the heteronomy of society.13 Welsch
186
Ale Erjavec
points to Adorno's accentuation of what he calls work-internal heterogeneity (Undoing, 71), namely, Adorno's opinion that a work contains a heterogeneity of the sensible that is to be understood not as raw but as a sensible diversity. In Welsch's view, a similar interpretation must be applied to the work-external heterogeneity: the variety and divergence in artistic paradigms regarding different artworks, as well as a divergence in the sphere of art on the whole, must be acknowledged. Welsch concludes that modern works no longer comply with one general canon, but each develops its own. Thus two things are self-evident for aesthetic awareness from the modern stance: that one must discover the idiolect in a singular work; and that one must be aware of the fundamental plurality of paradigms in regard to art as a whole (Undoing, 72). Welsch's assessment of Adorno is preceded by his critical view of the latter as an adherent of traditional aesthetics. It attests to Welsch's opinion regarding the recent philosophical and historical situationthat of Unsere postmoderne Moderne, our postmodern modernity, as proclaimed by the title of his influential work from 1987. His views could, nonetheless, be regarded from that (and as that) borderline between modernity and modernism and postmodernity (the postindustral epoch, the epoch of multinational capital, the epoch of information society, and so on) and postmodernism, the latter pair being specified by the emergence of the novel questioning of the possible Ausgang of modernity. Some of the questions implied by Welsch's observation are: How do we organize our understanding of what art is? How is the history (consciously viewed from the present vantage point) constructed or interpreted, and how does art change through history, especially recent history? In brief, is today's art essentially art of Adorno's modern time, or is it essentially different? The questions raised are of course fundamental questions of aesthetics understood in a plethora of ways. Let me attempt to offer some minor hints as to how they could be answered. In
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
187
what follows I shall briefly discuss some views concerning these issues, occasionally turning to Adorno and concluding with some observations regarding contemporary art. Let me begin with Peter Brger. Brger posited as the telos of the European avant-garde movements an attack on the status of art in bourgeois society (TA, 49), thereby offering, in the seventies, a novel interpretation of avant-garde art of the previous century. The deep and broad influence of this study continues into the present. While the avant-gardes discussed by Brger actually represented, as he argued, a historic break with previous bourgeois art, early modernism included, it must be noted that Brger's empirical and historical data did not fully support his theoretical positions. Thus, for example, the many provocative, revolutionary, and original gestures, procedures, devices, and inventions of the avant-gardists often owed more to Georges Sorel than to German Romanticism. Dada presents a similar case: Brger proclaimed it the most radical movement within the European avant-garde for no longer criticizing schools that preceded it, but [criticizing] the art as an institution (TA, 22). In fact, Tristan Tzara (highlighted by Brger in his study) and the Romanian circle of Tzara's Zrich friends had been deeply influenced by their native Romanian cultural backgroundthe Jewish tradition; the Dadalike performances and events; poetry and prose in prewar Bucharest; and the futurism of Marinetti, whose initial Futurist Manifesto appeared in Bucharest a day before it was published in Le Figaro.14 Much of what Brger called criticism of art as an institution may have been in fact a consequence of the transposition of a foreign culture to a West-European ambiance. In short, many of the procedures and ideas of Zrich Dada may have had more in common with cultural practices and specifics in that distant part of the European East than with a conscious attack on autonomous bourgeois culture.
188
Ale Erjavec
A very similar criticism could be raised in regard to Italian futurism (designated by Brger as yet another historical avantgarde movement), for Marinetti's prefuturist artistic practices in Paris and then his early futurist activities in Italy had much in common with anarchist aesthetics,15 with Gustave Kahn's esthtique de la rue, and with the bourgeois carnivalesque culture of European (and later American) metropolises at the turn of the century and in the period that ended with the end of the First World War.16 What is even more important is that it was within il primo futurismo (19091915) that the really radical and subversive ideas arose concerning art as an institution, making the early futurism a much better example of a critical stance toward art as an institution than Dada. What remains of import in Brger's study is that the previously mentioned avant-gardes had attempted to breach the border between art and life, although they may have realized this to a lesser degree than we would tend to conclude from Brger, less consciously than is usually thought, and more due to a cunning of reason than by a conscious adherance to Romanticist suppositions of the historic role of art as regards the realization of humanity. In Brger, the Hegelian interpretation of the history of art remains a potent factor that, while offering a totalizing view of artistic history, nonetheless distorts the more site-specific artistic, aesthetic, and historicaly specific events and acts surrounding the waracts of the kind highlighted by Welsch. The aestheticin the guise of freedom, the order of disorder, the realization of art, the breaking down of the barrier separating life and art, and so onremains an essential feature of the art and broad historical human action (or praxis) of much of the first half of the previous century. In different terms, this characteristic (or trend) was the cause of a continual introduction of new works into the institution of art, endowing such artifacts with the aura of historical authenticity and consequently aesthetic value. Brger's analysis is valid insofar as it points out that the hisAesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
189
torical avant-gardes were a cultural provocation not with the simple aim of pater le bourgeois, but with the intention to transform the whole artistic and humanperhaps the correct term would be existentialdomain into a utopian event, a dynamic state of things created according to desires, proclamations, manifestos, and often actual actions of individual avant-garde artists (persons would perhaps be a more suitable term). In their final stages of development, these avant-garde projects and acts mostly descended (or ascended) into the realm of the institution of art: the historic role of the avant-garde was lost, but the institutional role was recaptured and it blossomed. Brger's narrative could thus be regarded as one story of the recent history of art. Still, Brger himself saw his story as objective. He thus claimed that self-criticism of art (as carried out by Dadaism, for example) allows for objective understanding: [O]nly when art enters the stage of self-criticism does the 'objective understanding' of past periods of the development of art become possible (TA, 22). Brger added that this objective understanding does not mean that the understanding is independent of the place in the present of the cognizing individual; instead, it merely means insight into the overall process insofar as this process has come to a conclusion in the present of the cognizing individual (TA, 22). If this claim had been true, then Brger's attempt to fix the course of the development of avantgarde art within the twentieth century would have originated from a privileged historical position: that at which the process of development of the avant-garde has come to an end. Aside from some previously noted factual weaknesses, Brger's position is made less tenable by a further limitation, namely, the more recent appearance of new avant-garde art, that is, the politicized postmodern art of the transitional period from socialism to postsocialism,17 to which we could easily ascribe features characteristic of avant-garde art,18 making Brger's (somewhat Hegelian) claim about the conclusion in the present of the cog190
Ale Erjavec
nizing individual questionable. In brief, Brger's narrative is limited by its modern and culture-specific framework. Aesthetics as a discipline is destined to be incomplete and to promise an impossible outcome, for it attempts to make commensurable what cannot be. This initial and incessant transgression of its own domain prevents it, argues Adornoand even today we cannot but accept his pointfrom achieving its aim of grasping theoretically its continually transformed object of reflection. Such reflections are always circumscribed by historical and often also cultural specifications of their vantage points. The plethora of the latter, on the one hand, and their dialectical linkage with the object of their reflectionwhat Adorno called the philosophical insight that fact and concept are not polar opposites but mediated reciprocally in one another (AT, 343) on the other, is what makes the task of aesthetics an incessant procedure. It could be objected that we should not search for borderline cases but limit ourselves to perspicuous instances of great art, where no doubt exists as to their artistic credentials. Martin Heidegger's analysis of Van Gogh's painting A Pair of Boots could serve as an example of such a perspicuous instance. In The Origin of the Work of Art, Heidegger proclaims the decline of modern art but praises this painting as a case of great art: a contemporary (modern) work is offered as an example of great art in spite of all modern art being proclaimed in decline. It is within this philosophical horizon, charted by Heidegger and appertaining to modernism, that the issue of truth is situated. Adorno acknowledges: Only he understands an artwork who grasps it as a complex nexus of truth (AT, 262). Like Heidegger, Adorno too accentuates the role of truth in art. In Heidegger's own words from The Origin of the Work of Art, Beauty is one way in which truth essentially occurs as unconcealedness.... In the work, the happening of truth is at work.19 For both, truth is the basic ontological precondition for art and its exemplary status (and, in
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
191
Heidegger, position) in modernism and modernity. Emphatically, art is knowledge, though not the knowledge of objects (AT, 262). Truth, appearing via a specific form of knowledgeartis the fundamental category of a modernist philosophy of art. Within this horizon, philosophy offers the self-reflection of art that the latter, in spite of all its significance, by definition cannot articulate in a purely abstract way, for in that way it would reach into the realm of philosophical concepts. It is the philosopher who explains, reflects, and judges: The idea of a value-free aesthetics is nonsense (AT, 262). And [a]rtworks, especially those of the highest dignity, await their interpretation.... Grasping truth content postulates critique (AT, 128). For some time aesthetics retains the evaluative faculty; later, with the advent of pop and conceptual art, all that remains to be discussed is the position of such art within the institution of art, for there really is no art more true than any other, and ... there really is no one way art has to be: all art is equally and indifferently art.20 In juxtaposing Adorno and Heidegger regarding truth, some essential differences must be noted: Heidegger's position on past and contemporary art changes significantly over decades. Early on, he endorses Hegel's theory of the end of art and the elevated position ascribed to Greek art as the most authentic, when art purportedly provided guidance as to how to live. Art of the modern epoch is designed to provide 'aesthetic experiences.'21 Such an experience offers no more than repose and relaxation, for it accentuates beauty, not truth. The later Heidegger acquired an affinity for modern artists such as Rilke, Le Corbusier, Stravinsky, Braque, Klee, and Czanne; it appears that he wanted to write a sequel to The Origin of the Work of Art (193536) that would refer to Klee and Czanne.22 In Adorno's view, great art characteristically overcomes historical limitations: not as an atemporal entity, but as a transient, but therefore no less crucial, crystallization of truth:
192
Ale Erjavec
Authentic art of the past that for the time being must remain veiled is not thereby sentenced. Great works wait. While their metaphysical meaning dissolves, something of their truth content, however little it can be pinned down, does not; it is that whereby they remain eloquent. A liberated humanity would be able to inherit its historical legacy free of guilt. What was once true in an artwork and then disclaimed by history is only able to disclose itself again when the conditions have changed on whose account that truth was invalidated. (AT, 40)
This could be called Adorno's interpretation of the historical transformation of a work of art and therefore of art as such: works have their historical moment in which they adequately relate to their broader historical frame and thereby express and present its truth. Since this truth does not lie on the surface of a work, it must be grasped by interpretation and critique. The artistic experience meets with resistance that mirrors the resistance of the work to its historical conditions of authenticity. Great works wait. They are reborn when historical circumstances reenact the situation in which they achieved their role as exceptional artworks. It is also for this reason that a univocal construction of the history of art is impossible (AT, 210): art is not a dead entity, but a potentiality that in the case of a great work awaits its rebirth. In his correspondence with Walter Benjamin, Adorno agrees that the aural element of the work of art is declining.23 In the same breath he distances his own notion of the autonomy of a work of art from the notion of auratic art as suggested by Benjamin. It would thus be incorrect to claim that Adorno envisioned an end of art. Nonetheless, in his opinion art is undergoing some kind of a decline: he speaks of Rimbaud anticipating art's decline (AT, 4). To make matters more complicated, Adorno refers also to the progress of art, a general judgment that has to do with a difficulty presented by the structure of [art's] history. (AT, 209). The problem with the notion of progress in art arises from the specific nature of art. In art, progress
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
193
develops through forgetting: past works (great works) become alive after a period of waiting and reemerge as contemporary in spite of their origin in the past. Progress in art emerges only if past works are forgotten and some theme or artistic device, to use a different terminology, is invented anew or brought forth from oblivion. What exists in art are parallel presents: different historical lines run parallel to each other, interrelate, and are separated. This is why in Adorno's opinion art's essence cannot be deduced from its history (AT, 2). The concept of art is located in a historically changing constellation of elements; it refuses definition (AT, 2). If art were susceptible to a definition, that definition would always arise from a particular work or limit its scope to the present. It would thus exclude future instances of art, for which the main characteristic is that it cannot be deduced from the past to be applied to them. Art's characteristics change incessantly, and much of the issue of art remains the question of whether a certain work is a work of art at all. It is because of this uncertainty that [a]rt can be understood only by its laws of movement, not according to any set of invariants (AT, 3). If we were to translate Danto's claim that there is a kind of a transhistorical essence in art, everywhere and always the same, but it only discloses itself through history,24 into Adorno's conceptual frame, we would have to describe such essence as a rule or principle that generates the constellation called art. At the end of his Draft Introduction to Aesthetic Theory, Adorno makes this far-reaching Marxist proposition:
The principle of method here is that light should be cast on all art from the vantage point of the most recent artworks, rather than the reverse, following the custom of historicism and philology, which, bourgeois at heart, prefers that nothing ever change. If Valrys thesis is true that the best in the new corresponds to an old need, then the most authentic works
194
Ale Erjavec
are critiques of past works. Aesthetics becomes normative by articulating such criticism. (AT, 359)
The immediate interpretation of this statement would be, of course, that we should look at past art from our own vantage pointsomething that cannot be avoided. Adorno furthermore claims that the role of aesthetics is to criticize works of the past since contemporary works are also critiques of past works, thereby privileging such contemporary criticism. But let us interpret the statement somewhat differently and claim that the most recent artworks put all past works into a different light, thereby transforming these same most recent works. Which works of art do we bring forth from oblivion and which do we resuscitate because they waited and awaited the repetition of specific circumstances or a condition that is ours? Which are the determining factors the making visible of which allows us to grasp similarities between historical epochs? And which works of today become petrified and lose their life because they no longer correspond to our vision du monde? The issue is worthy of scrutiny not only for historical reasons, not only for being an essential issue for aesthetics as philosophy of art, but also because of its import for our contemporaneity, for shedding some light on the issue of what is this instant that is ours25 as regards art, aesthetics, and the aesthetic. It was of course Hegel who first persuasively presented a response to this question. Hegel grasped the essential issue of art in the epoch of the pervasive notion of development. He interiorized the question, exposing it for what it remains today: the question of our perception and reception of past art from our proper vantage point for our vantage point. This is also true of the instant that is ours: Hegel's concern and its articulation address our own concerns today: while he may be concerned with classical art of the past, his depiction of the situation regarding past art relates also to art of our own time and our relation to the art of the past.
195
The statues set up are now corpses in stone whence the animating soul has flown, while the hymns of praise are words from which all belief is gone.... They are themselves now just what they are for usbeautiful fruit broken off the tree; a kindly fate has passed on those works to us, as a maiden might offer such fruit off a tree. Their actual life as they exist is no longer there, not the tree that bore them.... Our action, therefore, when we enjoy them is not that of worship, through which our conscious life might attain its complete truth and be satisfied to the full: our action is external; it consists in wiping off some drop of rain or speck of dust from these fruits, and in place of the inner elements composing the reality of the ethical life, a reality that environed, created and inspired these works, we erect in prolix detail the scaffolding of the dead elements of their outward existence,language, historical circumstances, etc. All this we do, not in order to enter into their very life, but only to represent them ideally or pictorially [vorstellen] within ourselves.26
The issue raised by Hegel concerns the impossibility of authentically experiencing past artworks. This impossibility also determines our proper possibilities; it witnesses to a change in our sensibility and a change in our vantage point that arises from our proper historical circumstances. The past is closed to us in the artistic forms that were open to people of a past epoch. Hegels position is similar to Heideggers in the The Origin of the Work of Art, where the perception offered by past art is also changed in contemporaneity. Contemporary art, on the other hand, is also a path not to truth, but to sheer enjoyment. It has become beautiful and has therefore lost its potentials qua art: it no longer allows for immediacy of truth and its unconcealedness; it is an accessory to concealment. The artistic has become the aestheticized; it no longer allows for the aesthetic. A related issue is raised by Marx in the introduction to the Grundrisse where he notes that
[t]he difficulty we are confronted with is not, however, that of understanding how Greek art and epic poetry are associated
196
Ale Erjavec
with certain forms of social development. The difficulty is that they still give us aesthetic pleasure and are in certain respects regarded as a standard and unattainable ideal.27
Here Marx echoes Hegel's views regarding classical art. His thought can be divided into two related statements: First, Greek art and epic poetry are creations of their own time and dependent upon historical and other site-specific circumstances. In many respectsthe stage of development of the means of production, the import of mythical thought on the thematics of Greek art, the determining role of pagan religion and its influence on epic poetryall these features shape and determine the artistic nature and the aesthetic (pleasurable) effect of such art. What, then, do Adorno's words, [g]reat works wait (AT, 40), say in relation to or in light of Marx's observation that these works (epic poetry) still give us aesthetic pleasure? Obviously, claim both Marx and Adorno, some works remain alive, actual, and relevant in epochs that transgress their historical circumstances and places of origin. Such works are great works. Second, Marx claims, as does Hegel, that Greek art and epic poetry in some sense remain for art of his timethis is the year 1857the rule and unreachable example. As S. S. Prawer showed in his reconstruction of Marx's epoch as regards literary knowledge, influence, and tastes,28 in Marx's time knowledge of Greek art and epic poetry were still very much considered obligatory for educated men. But Prawer's study also shows that Marx was quite ignorant of art (especially fine art) that was not in the mainstream art of his time. He was thus interested in Eugne Sue and Honor de Balzac, Balzac being one of the few popular writers among his contemporaries who still remains part of the literarary canon today.29 Of course, Karl Marx may not have been an art connoisseur of his time, and his tastes may have been average and rather traditional. Still, it is fair to consider that, as regards Greek art and epic poetry, he shared the tastes and appreciation of his contemAesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
197
poraries. Today, by contrast, hardly anyone will claim that poetry remains a part of the actual cultural canon of the present. It most probably wasn't part of the mainstream literature even in Adorno's time. Still, once a work has been admitted into the perimeter of art, with the encircled realm being the institution called art, it may lose its artistic or aesthetic worth, but it hardly ever loses its status as a work of art. This is what has happened in our time to epic poetry and probably also to much of Greek arta fact intuitively manifested by Marinetti's irreverent mockery and disregard for Nike of Samothrace in his 1909 Futurist Manifesto. Something important has occured between Marx's lifetime and this instance that is ours. The diminution, if not outright disappearance, of contemporary appreciation of epic poetry signals that our own positions regarding our contemporary art have been transformed. Which art has emerged in recent decades? This most certainly was not an art familiar to Marx or his contemporaries. This new art was then in its nascent stage. In a majority of cases it was the art of European modernism. But perhaps even the art of modernism, regarded by Adorno as paradigmatic of the modern epoch and at the same time as an instance of art in its form of critical negativity, was not the art that changed the cultural paradigm of the early twentieth century. If we turn to Georg Lukcs as a central defender of critical realism of the first half of the previous century, we recognize his choices as those Marx himself would probably readily have accepted as instances of great art. What represented a central turning point were not the parallel currents of realism and modernism (with the avant-gardes representing a radical part thereof) but the advent of postmodernism, arising from European modernism, with Marcel Duchamp's readymades representing the first instance of postmodern art. If Peter Brger, when referring to Dadaism, had had Duchamp in mind, his analysis would be much more persuasive. Although Fredric Jameson was correct in claiming that cul198
Ale Erjavec
tural forms of postmodernism may be said to be the first specifically North American global style,30 that the logic of postmodern cultureits functioning, dissemination, distribution (as a symbolic and as a financial commodity), and institutionalization within the frame of historical and cultural archivesarose from the United States, the roots of this functioning are to be found in European modernism. In (continental) Europe art retained its special statusarising from the tradition of Romanticism and the fin de sicle well into the twentieth century, and this status assigned to art the special locus of creativity (as promoted by most European authors, ranging from Karl Marx to Maurice MerleauPonty) as opposed to repetition of industrial labor. With the passage into the postindustrial society, the paradigmatic role of art as the highest form of creativity has withered away, a process having as its side effect the diminution of the previous privileged role of art. This change in the role of art is noted by Grard Genette in his observation that in Heidegger and Adorno a symmetery exists between two antithetical forms of overvaluation of art,31 a fact revealed also by the ready-made nature of the readymade. A similar gesturearising from a critique of Brger, but through him from a critique of Adornois to be found in Benjamin H. D. Buchloh's reevaluation of his own views regarding American neo-avant-garde art. In his opinion,
[t]he first of Brger's many delusions (and my own as well) was of course to situate neo-avantgarde practices in a perpetual, almost Oedipal relation to the accomplishments of the parental avant-garde of the twenties.... The second and equally fatal delusion, shared by Brger and this author to some extent ... was the assumption that the criteria for aesthetic judgment would have to be linked at all times, if not to models of an outright instrumentalized political efficacy, then at least to a compulsory mode of critical negativity.32
By diminishing the import of classical avant-gardes and by elevating the neo-avant-gardes to a higher statusby discarding
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
199
the requirement that neo-avant-garde art possess the predicate of negativitythe placement of pop art also changed: the same author persuasively argued (complementing in this Arthur Danto's claim that pop art effectively transgressed the division between high and low in culture) that Andy Warhol successfuly transformed himself from a commercial artist into a fine artist, aiding in this way pop art's replacement of abstract expressionism as the leading American art of the period.33 As Jameson has demonstrated in his comparision of Heidegger's hermeneutic analysis of Van Gogh's painting A Pair of Shoes with his own analysis of a Warhol work, the contemporary issue regarding art is no longer that of truth, but meaning. In other words, contemporary art predominantly aspires to create meaning, not to reveal truth. As Boris Groys argues,
It turns out that this question [of the value of a product] cannot be answered by reaching back to reality and that the truth of the product cannot be the basis of its value. The question about the value of a product thus remains the question about its relation to tradition and other cultural artifacts.... Neither innovative art nor innovative theory can be described or argued in their signifying relationship to reality or, which is the same, in their truth. The question therefore is not are they true but are they culturally precious.34
This means that works of art do not relate to their referents (the truth of which they establish, reveal, and disclose) but form a system of equivalences within which they function according to a grid of mutually dependent meanings. Neither Adorno nor Heidegger see art forming such a system of significations. For both of them, art still reveals the truth of the referent, be it society, an epoch, or an existential artistic expression. For art arising from Duchamp's readymades and continuing with Warhol, Groys's description is more valid, for the Duchampian and postmodern art that Groys has in mind does actually function very much ac-
200
Ale Erjavec
cording to the principles of the institutional theory of art: this art no longer discloses existential or other truths, it functions exclusively within the institution of art it incessantly recreates. It is within such a framework that the previously mentioned passage from Wolfgang Welsch acquires additional significance: although Welsch was referring to modern art, he was in fact relating to the postmodern, this art being exemplified by the borderline, a borderline determining the essence of the center. Art as an institution has replaced art as part of the aesthetic, and great art of the past has been turned into marketable commodities for the culture industry. Adorno may have sensed this when he expressed his harsh criticism of the cinema. The transformation from modernism to postmodernism is global, yet it is the art of modernismmuch more than the art of the classical avant-gardesthat is still being universally disseminated, acquiring on its way across the globe local and hybrid forms. These hybrid forms, often considered postmodern products of culture (and not necessarily art) within their place of origin, apparently contradict Adorno's claims for the universalism of modernism and his value judgments regarding works that represent a negation of the bourgeois frame of reference. If in the recent past there existed a belief that the decline of art, as diagnosed by Arthur Danto, Grard Genette, Gianni Vattimo, and so on, did not exist to the same extent in the postcolonial countries as it does in the most developed parts of the world, this hope today seems obsolete. As a Latin American theorist notes,
Aesthetic innovation is of declining interest in the museums, in the publishing houses, and in film; it has been shifted instead into electronic technologies, into musical entertainment and fashion. Where there were painters or musicians, there are now designers and disc jockeys.35
The decline of art is universal. What Adorno sensed as the negativity of art of his time, and which found its authentic manifestation
201
in the opposition between content and form, no longer applies. Descriptions and judgments such as this one from Latin America are today enunciated across the globe, from China to Slovenia. While the art markets are booming, the symbolic capital of art is rapidly diminishing. One way of explaining this phenomenon is to suggest that it is a consequence of the global proliferation of art, of its increased production, of the merging of the high and the low (as in the previously mentioned case of pop art), and of the general acceptance of the idea that all art is equally art. The art of high modernism, appreciated by Adorno, has become a historical style; contemporary art in its various forms relates not so much to modernism as to the art of the historical avant-gardes with their mixing of genres, techniques, procedures, and different realms of life, these ranging from science to politics. Walter Benjamin claimed that the creation of mechanically reproduced images tends to diminish the 'aura' of the original. In fact the opposite is true. The existence of the reproduction, in all its manifold copies, actually hightens a sense of the uniqueness of the original.36 This statement says something about the auratic potentials of the extant original works vis--vis those that are devoid of Benjamin's aura, but, as Adorno had already pointed out in his correspondence with Benjamin, the issue of auratic art does not really touch upon the issue of the autonomy of art as conceived by Adorno himself. It says something relevant, though, about the changed mode of art. The theory of the avant-garde developed by Peter Brger and discussed at the beginning of this essay has been one of the important analyses of the development and broader framework of art and the aesthetic. Brger's theory can be regarded within the framework of modernism and as a theory that has, as Brger claims, become possible when the development of the avant-garde reached its end. The fact that Brger has not envisioned other parallel modernities does not refute the argument of this 1974
202
Ale Erjavec
book. To this same modern framework Heidegger and Adorno also belong. Their position toward truth is essential, for they both view it refracted through or existing in art. This overvaluation of art is also typical for bothas it is for Brger, who links his historical avant-gardes to the historic, albeit unsuccessful, attempt to overcome the division between art and life and between the sensible and the rational. Walter Benjamin offered a different narrative concerning art and its meaning within the recent historical framework, especially in his essay The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction. Disputed by Adorno and generating very little interest for decades, the essay (like its author) became influential with the advent of postmodernism. Benjamin claims that, with the technological developments represented mainly by photography and the cinema, a new artistic and aesthetic sensibility has arisen.
During long periods of history, the mode of human sense perception changes with humanity's entire mode of existence. The manner in which human sense perception is organized, the medium in which it is accomplished, is determined not only by nature but by historical circumstances as well.37
Regarded in conjunction with Adorno's observation about the necessity of viewing past works from the position of recent art, Benjamin's statement attains additional relevance, for it foreshadows from a historical distance of several decades a drastic change in, and an essential modification of, the human and social import of art beginning in the sixties. Contemporary art no longer offers a path to truth and is not historically, socially, or existentially relevant to the extent it still was in Adorno's time. Modernist art, just as epic poetry, has today increasingly turned from a truthrevealing document of its time into its monument. Benjamin believed that this change has to do with collective experience. He claimed that [p]ainting simply is in no position to present an object for simultaneous collective experience, as it was
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
203
possible for architecture at all times, for the epic poem in the past, and for the movie today.38 He noted that collective experience is dialectically linked to our mode of sense perception. Not only is the creation of certain art forms no longer possible but these forms are also perceived differently or, as the epic poem attests, not at all. This process had already begun in Marx's time, with the advent of technical advancements in representation and the emergent plurality of paradigms in regard to art that Welsch speaks of. From our contemporary position, in this instant that is ours, past art has been more quickly and radically than ever incorporated into the present or more recent art, and is being viewed accordinglyfollowing Hegel's description from The Phenomenology of Mind as the paramount work of the modern philosophy of art. Within the framework of more recent art, art of the past has become aestheticized to provide, in Heidegger's words, aesthetic experiences and has ceased to be emphatically knowledge, that is, truth, as Adorno claimed. Instead of truth, contemporary art offers meaning. Art has become but another commodity. Attempts to subvert the extant art system are few and far between. There is no longer the possibility of conflict between content and form and hardly the possiblity of conflict between an individual and the society or politics. In the highly developed part of the world, art no longer serves as an expressive means for social, national, and religious minoritiesor if it does, it is practiced for some time (before it joins the institution of today's popular culture) in subcultural forms such as rap and ethnic music, grafitti, fashion, and lifestyle.39 It is in such ways that the aesthetic today has been retained: to a small extent, on a limited scale, and without the hope of bringing together the divided halves through art. In Rancire's view, to which no persuasive alternative has yet been offered, [t]he postmodern reversal had as its theoretical foundation Lyotard's analysis of the Kantian sublime, which was reinterpreted as the scene of a found204
Ale Erjavec
ing distance separating the idea from any sensible presentation.40 Peter Brger's statement from his Theory of the Avant-Garde had a premonitional value. There he said that what was at stake in early avant-gardes was the notion of art, namely,
an attack on the status of art in bourgeois society. What is negated is not an earlier form of art (a style) but art as an institution that is unassociated with the life praxis of men.... The demand is not raised at the level of the contents of individual works. Rather, it directs itself to the way art functions in society, a process that does as much to determine the effect that works have as does the particular content. (TA, 49)
In postmodernity, total commercialization and thus commodification has permeated all segments of society, including Adorno's autonomous art. The proof of this permeation lies in the fact that not only are we no longer able to experience epic poetry, but that autonomous art that Adorno had in mind is becoming aesthetically opaque and is equally intensively being replaced by mass and popular culture. It is within this popular culture and within the new forms of emergent art that a dedifferentiation seems to be occurring, bringing together previously isolated domains of knowledge and creativitybioart and technology-based art as well as other new forms of experimental artthat art may be finding a way to continue its life in the aesthetic domain (the utopian, the avant-garde) and not so much in that of aesthetics, within which a work is viewed only as an aesthetic resource. What currently exists in much art of the past may thus be more akin to what Slavoj iek has called, in regard to politics, the complete commodification of politics.41 Art has undergone a similar commodification that is linked to another development in art, diagnosed as early as 1984 by Arthur Danto:
The age of pluralism is upon us. It does not matter any longer what you do, which is what pluralism means. When one
Aesthetics and the Aesthetic Today: After Adorno
205
direction is as good as another direction, there is no concept of direction any longer to apply. Decoration, self-expression, entertainment, are, of course, abiding human needs. There will always be a service for art to perform, if artists are content with that. A subservient art has always been with us. The institutions of the art worldgalleries, collectors, exhibitions, journalismwhich are predicated upon history and hence marking what is new, will bit by bit wither away. How happy happpiness will make us is difficult to foretell, but just think of the difference the rage for gourmet cooking has made in common American life. On the other hand, it has been an immense privilege to have lived in history.42
Somewhat paradoxically, contemporary art, then, very much resembles contemporary politics: both are commodified, in their contemporary forms most probably devoid of a future, and both remain in need of the political and the aesthetic. Perhaps the resuscitation of this pair today requires an effort no less demanding than that suggested two centuries ago by Friedrich Schiller, and a task as relevantfor aesthetics as philosophy of art, and for art as that carried out by Adorno half a century ago, for today too, [e]very artwork, if it is to be fully experienced, requires thought and therefore stands in need of philosophy.
206
Ale Erjavec
Endnotes
1 2
John Cage, quoted in Tony Godfrey, Conceptual Art (London, 1998), p. 63. Marcel Duchamp, quoted in Arthur C. Danto, The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art (New York, 1984), p. 13. Jacques Rancire, Malaise dans lesthtique (Paris, 2004), p. 11. Unless otherwise noted, all translations are my own. Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis, 1997), p. 335. (Hereafter AT.) Aesthetics presents philosophy with the bill for the fact that the academic system degraded it to being a mere specialization; ibid., p. 262. Adornos continuing influence on and import for music studies is attested, for example, by the fact that in many continental music academies his Introduction to the Sociology of Music remains part of the syllabus. Une uvre ne peut devenir moderne que si elle est dabord postmoderne. Le postmodernisme ainsi entendu nest pas le modernisme sa fin, mais ltat naissant, et cet tat est constant; Jean-Franois Lyotard, Le Postmoderne expliqu aux enfants (Paris, 1988), p. 28. See Andrew Bowie, Adorno, Heidegger, and the Meaning of Music, Thesis Eleven 56 (February 1999): p. 4. The more recent theorists of the event range from Lyotard and Gilles Deleuze to Jean-Luc Nancy and, esp., Alain Badiou.
10
Peter Brger, Theory of the Avant-Garde, trans. Michael Snow (Minneapolis, 1999), p. 46. (Hereafter TA.)
11
Quoted in Matei Calinescu, Five Faces of Modernity: Modernism, AvantGarde, Decadence, Kitsch, Postmodernism (Durham, NC, 1987), p. 103. See ibid., esp. pp. 11011.
12 13 14
See Tom Sandqvist, Dada East: Romanians of Cabaret Voltaire (Cambridge, MA, 2006). From political theorists Arturo Labriola and Georges Sorel [Marinetti] borrows the Marxist concept of transforming the world; in anarchist thinkers, such as Max Stirner, Bakunin and Peter Kropotkin he emulates especially the protesting stand towards art and cultural institutions of the past; Nomi Blumenkranz, Une potique de lhroisme. Lesthtique de Marinetti, in La Prsence de F. T. Marinetti (Lausanne, 1982), p. 51.
15
16
207
Fountain in New York in April 1917 as an act resembling many of the futurists activities?
17
See Ale Erjavec, ed., Postmodernism and the Postsocialist Condition: Politicized Art Under Late Socialism (Berkeley, 2003). Post-avant-garde art of the former socialist countries visibly displayed all the pertinent features of the neo-avant-gardes and many of the historical avant-gardes. See Ale Erjavec, The Avant-Gardes: From Modernism to Postmodernism, Journal of Contemporary Thought 22 (Winter 2005): pp. 6585.
18
19
Martin Heidegger, Basic Writings, ed. David Farrell Krell (San Francisco, 1976), p. 178. Arthur C. Danto, After the End of Art: Contemporary Art and the Pale of History (Princeton, 1997), p. 34.
20
21
22 23
Theodor Adorno et al., Aesthetics and Politics (London, 1980), p. 122. Danto, After the End of Art, p. 28.
24 25
Michel Foucault, The Politics of Truth, ed. and trans. Sylvre Lotringer and Lysa Hochroth (New York, 1997), p. 158. G.W.F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Mind, trans. J. B. Baillie (New York, 1967), pp. 75354.
26
27
Karl Marx, introduction to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, trans. S. W. Razanskaya (Moscow, 1970), p. 217. Sigfried S. Prawer, Karl Marx and World Literature (Oxford, 1976).
28 29
Fredric Jameson notes that Balzac, although an author of best sellers, escapes the designation of being a part of the culture industry, for no contradiction is yet felt in his time between the production of best sellers and the production of what will later come to be thought of as high literature; Fredric Jameson, The Political Unconscious (Ithaca, 1981), p. 208. Fredric Jameson, Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism (London 1991), p. xx.
30
31
Grard Genette, Luvre de lart. La relation esthtique (Paris, 1997), p. 11. Benjamin H. D. Buchloh, Neo-Avantgarde and Culture Industry: Essays on European and American Art from 1955 to 1975 (Cambridge, MA, 2000), p. xxix.
32
33
208
Ale Erjavec
34
Boris Groys, ber das Neue. Versuch einer Kulturkonomie (Frankfurt am Main, 2004), pp. 18, 19.
35
Nstor Garca Canclini, Hybrid Cultures: Strategies for Entering and Leaving Modernity, trans. Christopher L. Chappari and Silvia L. Lpez (Minneapolis, 2005), p. xxxix. Paul Crowther, The Transhistorical Image (Cambridge, 2002), p. 138.
36 37
Walter Benjamin, The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction, in Illuminations, ed. Hannah Arendt, trans. Harry Zohn (New York, 1968), p. 222. Ibid., pp. 23435.
38 39
See Ale Erjavec, Die neuen Vorzeichen der Kunst. Eine Fallstudie zu Mittel- und Osteuropa, in Zurck aus der Zukunft. Osteuropische Kulturen im Zeitalter des Postkommunismus, ed. Boris Groys, Anne von der Heiden, and Peter Weibel (Frankfurt am Main, 2005), pp. 50835. Jacques Rancire, The Politics of Aesthetics, trans. Gabriel Rockhill (London, 2004), p. 29.
40
41
Slavoj iek, A Leninist Gesture Today, in Lenin Reloaded, ed. Sebastian Budgen, Stathis Kouvelakis, and Slavoj iek (Durham, NC, 2007), p. 85. Arthur C. Danto, The End of Art, in The Death of Art, ed. Berel Lang (New York, 1984), p. 35.
42
209
J. M. Bernstein
[T]he demand for ugliness, the older Hellenes good, severe will to pessimism, to the tragic myth, to affirm the image of all that is fearsome, wicked, mysterious, annihilating and fateful in the very foundations of existencewhere must the origins of tragedy have lain at that time?
Nietzsche
[T]his is the tremendous power of the negative; it is the energy of thought, of the pure I, death. Beauty hates the understanding for asking of her what it cannot do. But the life of Spirit is not the life that shrinks from death, and keeps itself untouched by devastation, but rather the life that endures it and maintains itself in it. It wins its truth only when, in utter dismemberment, it finds itself.
Hegel
210
J. M. Bernstein
211
Figure 1. Pablo Picasso, Les Demoiselles dAvignon, 1907. Oil on canvas, 8' x 7'8". 2010 Estate of Pablo Picasso / Artists Rights Society (ARS), New York.
be nothing but a blooming, buzzing confusion. Reason thus becomes the lawgiver to nature, providing the very idea of a natural, law-governed world. Adorno employs Kants conception of transcendental subjectivity to summarize and model the historical rationalization of reason through which the reason that was to be the instrument of freedom and reconciliation with nature on becoming total drives out all other forms of reasoning, and consequently reverts to its opposite, a source of domination and separation: The doctrine of
212
J. M. Bernstein
the transcendental subject faithfully discloses the precedence of the abstract, rational relations that are abstracted from individuals and their conditions and for which exchange is the model.2 Adorno is contending that Kants idea of transcendental constitution is, while philosophically false, socially and historically true; what is consolidated in the idea of the transcendental subject is the socially mandated precedence of abstract categories (of exchange) over their objects. Hence, the idea of providing the Copernican turn with an axial rotationtoward the objectas the programmatic movement of negative dialectics means demonstrating how the object of cognition is more than, different from, and nonidentical with how it appears in the context of rationalized reason; how subject is also object; how subject depends upon what it assumes to dominate and control. Modernism is the operation of negative dialectic in art; it is that art practice that criticizes abstract rationality by remaining a repository for an alternativemimeticrationality. Modernism thereby becomes the voice of sensuous particularity against abstract rationality. In brief, this is the core thesis of Aesthetic Theory. It is also what Picasso accomplishes in Les Demoiselles dAvignon, giving painting an axial turn toward the object.3 Modernist painting lives or dies by its acknowledgment of and fidelity to this moment, for only the Demoiselles self-consciously demonstrates what might be asked of painting if it is to sufficiently acknowledge its object-dependence, its role as vehicle for the disclosure of irreducible sensuous particularity and the demonstration of what is more than and beyond exchange, above all, of its revelation of the inner affinity binding social sign (the practice of painting itself) and material nature (say, that practicesand thereby any cognitive practicesmaterial conditions of possibility). For theoretical and practical reasons, evaluating and demonstrating the stakes of the Demoiselles is usually a retrospective affair. Although from the outset, Picasso conceived of his brothel painting as a defining, statement-making effort (he filled sixteen
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
213
sketchbooks with preliminary studies), it was almost uniformly reviled by friends and followers who visited his studio in the autumn of 1907. It appeared aggressive, fragmented, incoherent, ugly. So indigestible was it that Daniel-Henry Kahnweiler, Picassos dealer and an excellent commentator on his work, contended ever afterwards that it was unfinished. Certainly, at that moment it was unshowable, unseeable. It was first publicly exhibited in 1916 in a small, brief show, but its true life or afterlife did not begin until it was acquired and shown by the Museum of Modern Art in New York in 1939. The Demoiselles ugliness provides a useful starting place for understanding its stakes. I will certainly want to argue that something of the Demoiselles ugliness is internally related to the works performing an axial rotation in modernist painting. Its ugliness is also connected to its difficulty in being seen at all, and hence to its coming, only retrospectively and very late, perhaps not until now, to define how modernist painting can and must mean. But this is also to say that the Demoiselles, as Picassos first ugly painting, along with the numerous ugly paintings he did throughout the 1920s and 1930s, stand at the crossroads of a core debate about Picasso and modernist painting. The matter is immensely complex, but for the purposes to hand I want to risk limning it as if it were direct and simple. This abbreviated, partial telling of the story is meant to demonstrate how getting clear about the Demoiselles is a, if not the, necessary condition for getting clear about the history of modernist painting as it presses on our artistic present: only a sufficient elaboration of the Demoiselles can address what art or aesthetics after Adorno might be, since only through placing it do we adequately clarify what modernist painting from an Adornoian perspective was in the first instance.4 On what has become the dominant theory of modernist painting, Picassos defining artistic achievement is, with Braque, the invention of cubism. One might think of cubism as a version of enlightenment rationalism in which the magic of perspective
214
J. M. Bernstein
and illusionism that allows an as-if view into a world spatially and temporally removed from our own is replaced by a threefold gesture: first, the frank acknowledgment of the picture plane, its shallow depth and delimited space as where a painting occurs, as the site of painterly meaning; second, the systematic replacement of mimetic forms by geometric forms, especially squares and rectangles whose two-dimensional form mimics and repeats that of the canvas on which they are painted; hence, third, the incremental displacement of representation and significant iconic content by abstraction and formal content. So much might be regarded as the common elements shared by most accounts of cubism, but it does not say quite enough to tell us how the cubist moment reorients painting in a way that prefigures our postmodern situation. On this more radical reading of the cubist trajectory, cubism, in formalizing painterly practice, involves the deskilling of artistic technique in the direction of mechanical technique as part of a general critique of subjectivity in art, that is, as part of a critique of all that went under the honorifics of individuality, originality, genius, and authorshipall arts prizing of painterliness, touch, and style. Cubism, continuing the scientism and rationalizing efforts of earlier modernisms, sought to move painting in the direction of a formally purified and shareable practice; for Picasso, sharing the development of cubism with Braque was, at least in part, what constituted it as formally anonymous and impersonal, and thereby as truly social and objective. Cubisms intended divorce from the shadows of a forever private subjectivity is what called up the claim that it was to be the true language of painting, paintings own autonomous language. Conceiving of cubism as a procedural and formal language, as painterly syntax or method, can itself be retrospectively construed as entailing that the ambition of painting cannot be to distinguish itself from photographyas its nearest competitor and threatening avatar of technological rationalitybut rather to perform a rapprochement with it. Assume that cubism is the defining
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
215
breakthrough that allows painting to progress toward a reconciliation with photography; it would then follow that Picassos own postcubist work, more and more, and certainly from, say, 1918 on, becomes a series a defensive strategies to save painting, which for Picasso was not that different from saving himself, his sense of the authority of his painterly performances, from the mechanical denouement that cubism itself had definitively launched. If the advance to cubism and what can be deciphered as following from it deserves recognition as painterly achievement, then all elseand especially Picassos ugly paintingsis reaction and defense, the vanity of subjectivity reasserting itself once more. Here is Rosalind Krauss saying exactly this:
In Picassos practice, classicism is merely the sublimated face of a more powerful and threatening force, the automation of art through the linked logics of the photomechanical, the readymade, and abstraction. And if Picasso acted phobically against automation, deskilling and serializationerecting the defense of classicism, uniqueness, and virtuositythis was not because the mechanical was simply an external threat to cubism but rather because it stood as a logical conclusion that could be drawn from within.5
It would be fatuous to argue that the mechanical did not stand as a logical conclusion to be drawn from cubism. And if it is the case that a dialectical strategy in which only the spear that wounds can save, then the abstract, deskilling, mechanical conclusions drawn from cubism are truly necessary: they mark out the only path painting could take if it, or the burden of human significances that the practices of painting espouse and elaborate, are to survive. Prima facie, whatever the temptations here, above all that painting should progress through being at one with technological modernity, this sounds a wildly implausible strategy: to save painting only through its rapprochement with abstraction and the photomechanical, painting in a manner that, by the slightest and
216
J. M. Bernstein
almost invisible gesture of difference, does not collapse into what at every moment threatens to absorb, devour, and extinguish it. The reason this Scheherazade version of modernism fails is that finally it can make nothing of the difference between painterly mechanism and real-world mechanism.6 Clearly, the danger has not been avoidedthe dialectical strategy has manifestly failed; paintings survival is patently being threatened, its emphases and meanings dissolving, the artful enemy of the photomechanical absorbing and extinguishing them at every turn. What is disappointing in the cubism-is-automation view, however, is not that modernism fails, but that it possesses no content apart from what it borrows from its nearest antagonist. It is that thought, above all, that licenses the counterclaim that cubism was not the great breakthrough moment for modernist painting, that, rather, the breakthrough of Les Demoiselles DAvignon can be reinscribed so that it can be seen to adumbrate both what modernism became (at its best) and still might become, and that for these purposes something in the range of Picassos ugly paintings deserves further consideration since they are in part a response to and upshot of his own disillusionment with cubism. We thus need another way of figuring modernism, one in which cubism becomes a detour in a project whose force field lies elsewhere.7 My hypothesis is not, of course, that ugliness defines this alternative approach, but that by tracking the deployment of ugliness as a painterly strategy we can prize open an alternative trajectory for modernism, a trajectory emphatically opposed to the mechanical, the geometric, the antirepresentational, and the deskilling, whose hegemony has proved no more beneficial to art than Greenbergs formalist one of which it is the direct descendent. For the purposes of this paper, I want to claim an ugly, materialist Picasso in opposition to the beautiful, idealist Picasso. Here, then, in just a few sentences, is my hypothesis: There are two irreducible transcendental schemas for the representation of space geometry and the human body; since the representation of space
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
217
is a necessary condition for the representation of the world in general, then geometry and the human body are, in the setting of modern painting, competing transcendental frameworks for making perceptual experience of the world possible. Cubism, and all that follows from it, adopts the geometric paradigm. Picassos ugly paintings are part of a wider attempt to demonstrate that the human body is a material a priori for the space of painting, and hence for perceptual experience generally. Picasso could not conceive of giving up representation not because of hubris or sentimentality, but because he took the human body as providing the necessary conditions for the intelligibility of painting in general.8 The human body is not merely an object to be represented, grasped, captured, depicted; it is simultaneously the necessary condition of representation. Ugliness is, at a certain moment in our history, the necessary means for disclosing this truth about the meaning of painting; it is a skeptical operator, the force of the negative dismantling the illusory positivity of beauty. In this setting, ugliness is on the side of materiality and truth, and beauty on the side of ideality and illusion.
tionist role women are simultaneously looked at and displayed, with their appearance coded for strong visual and erotic impact so that they may be said to connote to-be-looked-at-ness. Women displayed as sexual object is the leit-motif of erotic spectacle.10
For Picasso, this beauty system, as I shall call it, was fully operative in the art world he inhabited. Beauty as anchored in the male gaze was the way in which the repressive regime of identity thinking sustained itself, its power and ideality, in modern painting. What struck Picasso about the beauty system, however, was not its moral impropriety, but rather its dependence on unacknowledged fantasies and idealizations, hence on the perpetuation of illusionvalues simply incommensurable with modernisms self-conscious rigor. Nothing authentic or honest or authoritative could be built on such illusion-driven foundations. Hence, ugliness becomes for Picasso a means of disenchanting art, of seeking an authenticity for painting not dependent on either the easy attractions of the female form or the seductions of pictorial illusion. As Elizabeth Cowling nicely states the thesis: [H]is revolutionary purpose [in the Demoiselles] was to claim the right to regenerate contemporary art through harshness, brutality, fearsomeness, disharmony.11 The Demoiselles was, again, originally too brutal and fearsome to be seen at all; but after the failure of cubism, Picasso returns to this impulse: he would learn how to make irrevocably ugly paintings as no one had before him: The Dance (1925), The Kiss (1925), Head of a Woman with a Self-Portrait (192729), through to the weeping woman series of 1937, extending into, say, Man with a Lollipop (1938). Picassos explicitly ugly works are internally related to the pictures of, or meant to cause, horror, especially Guernica (1937). My sense that only through retrospection can the impact of the Demoiselles be gathered will mean, finally, elaborating it from the perspective of the 1929 Nude Standing by the Sea. It is worthwhile quickly reminding ourselves of what Picasso thought he needed to subvert if modern painting was to continue:
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
219
not only the sublime examples of Ingres, who was never far from Picassos mind, from the more or less discrete early paintings like The Valpincon Bather (1808) and La Grande Odalisque (1814), to the extravagance of late paintings like The Source (1856) and The Turkish Bath (1862), a work evidently on Picassos mind as he painted the Demoiselles,12 but equally the now hard to take and almost absurd Renoir nudes, from the faux discretion of Bather Arranging Her Hair (1885) to what looks from our coign of vantage like the paradigm case of the male gaze, the exorbitant fantasizing, idealizing of female sexual availability in La Dormeuse (La baigneuse endormie; 1887). Closer to home, Picasso was explicitly attempting to distance himself from Matisses recent efforts: Bonheur de vivre (19056), which Cowling describes as rapturously sensual and joyous,13 welcomes the male spectator in as emphatically as Ingres invited him into his Turkish bath or Renoir invited his libidinous gaze to devour the sleeping bather. If Matisse denaturalizes the invitation, the rule of beauty and idealization remain. A year later, in 1907, Matisse will outrage and puzzle visitors to the Salon des Indpendants with Blue Nude: Memory of Biskra. Through distortion, sculptural modeling, a posture of uninhibited exposure, and the adoption of a muscular, compact, self-possessed female form whose bodily contours are repeated by the surrounding landscape, Matisses partially realized ambition was to invoke an explosive sexuality14 his presumption doubtless being that the more flagrant the sexuality, the more honest or truthful the work. It is this equation that fails here: Matisses painting is evidently fantasized, a Western nostalgic mythologizing of a primitive North Africa; not only is the paintings primitivism and pastoral vision an overcooked fantasy but it is also impossible now to ignore how that fantasy remains essentially a vehicle for the elaboration of male desire: the nude exhibits herself in all her self-possessed sexualityher far from ugly upper torso, her long and rounded belly beneath ample breastsfor the sake of the de220
J. M. Bernstein
siring spectator, the hopeful male viewer. Because the presumptive ugliness of this painting results in a heightened exhibition of sexual candor, finally little in the rule of beauty will have been changed; on the contrary, Matisses effort at debeautification lasts only as long as it takes us to catch up with him, his distortions a declension of beauty, not a departure from it. Candor here translates not into truth, but into a more satisfying illusoriness. And if Matisse loosens the hold of certain formal and naturalistic strictures with Blue Nude, one would nonetheless be hard pressed to discover anything definitive in the language of painting that is won by it. It is the overwhelming power of the beauty system at work in even the most advanced art of the time that reveals why ugliness cannot be a side issue for Picasso, why it must become a constitutive element of what modern painting, hence modernism, must want for itself. Yet, ever since Lessings Laocon, it has been presumed that the plastic arts, and especially painting, are bound by the rule of beauty: the plastic artist cannot ignore the demands of beauty because an objects beauty is the harmonious effect of its various parts absorbed by the eye at a glance; but because the syntax of the plastic arts is one of part to whole, the material syntax of painting directly converges or overlaps with the logic of beauty.15 How can ugliness belong to painting if the syntax of painting overlaps with the at-a-glance harmony of parts and whole constituting physical beauty? Part of Picassos technical answer to this will be to loosen the at-a-glance, providing the apparently static with a complex sense of movement, hence temporality, and relocating the placement of wholeness from canvas to spectator. Such technical answers nonetheless slide past the philosophical conundrum. It is no accident that after setting up the question of the relation of art and aesthetics, and limning their situation, Adorno leads into the heart of his aesthetic theory with a section entitled On the Categories of the Ugly, the Beautiful, and Technique, a discussion that precedes his accounts of natural beauty, art
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
221
beauty, semblance and expression, and so on. Ugliness, which for the musically fixated Adorno means dissonance, comes first. That said, the discussion of ugliness is among the least satisfying, the ugliest, in Aesthetic Theory, the one I imagine Adorno reworking the most brutally for a final draft.16 Yet the leitmotif of the section is plain: ugliness must be shown to have a meaning that is not simply the absence of beauty if its role in modernist art is to begin to be comprehended. Here are four theses that I think are vindicated, at least in part, by the example of the Demoiselles. First, Inner coherence shatters on what is superior to it, the truth of content. The utmost integration is the utmost semblance and this causes the formers reversal.17 The second sentence first: Integration generates the appearance of a work being self-sufficient, whole, complete, and unique. This is semblance because the condition of such apparent completeness is an item being outside the demands of empirical experience, of being isolated in an art world. It is further the case that it is only apparently true that parts are realized or fulfilled in their placement within the whole. Although the authority of artworks as wholes depends on fully absorbing and integrating their materials and only thereby becoming fully self-realized, this always occurs at the cost of dominating the materials integrated. One feature of beautyfor which the model of the human form is insistent is the harmonious integration of materials. Because art is form, then at least in the case of modern autonomous art, the integrity of the materials formed must be sacrificed to the whole; the more formally powerful the art, the more thoroughly are the parts dissolved into a functionally assigned place. It is precisely awareness of this dissolution that marks the shift from classical modern art to modernism: as formal integration perfects itself, the sacrifice of that which has been integrated is noted and released. (Adorno locates the emergence of this movement toward disintegration in Beethovens late style.) This shift presages a reversal in the logic of the artwork: instead of its material parts being for the sake of
222
J. M. Bernstein
the ideal whole, the now no longer ideal whole becomes a vehicle for the disclosure of its sensuously particular parts. Dissonance, disunity, fragmentariness as forms that underline that disintegration of authoritative wholeness, of harmony and resolution, hence appear originally as ugly. Second, Adorno claims that inner coherence, perfected wholeness, must, in time, shatter before a higher value: the truth of content. To the degree that aesthetic wholes become vehicles for the disclosure or authorization of their parts, the goal of art shifts away from beauty to, well, something like truth or authenticity or rigor or consistencysome appropriately quasi-cognitive notion that reveals the stakes of an artwork apart from just being beautiful and delivering pleasure, however difficult. To some extent, this has always been true of modern art: shorn of its role of legitimating religious and political ideals external to itself, artistic autonomy demanded an art that obeyed only those laws immanent to its practice. But this entails that a necessary condition for aesthetic authority is that works self-consciously come to bind themselves to laws immanent to their possibility of existence. And this requires that artworks come to have as one of their constitutive goals the advance of art itself, the advance in the development and purification of the laws constitutive of the practice. Modernism is the self-conscious adoption of this entailment and requirement. But this is as much as to say that not only is there a protest against the beauty system (thesis one) but also, even formally, that modernist art possesses goals fully independent of the beauty of harmonious resolution. It is this fact that leads Adorno to claim that the deaestheticization of art is immanent to art (AT, 59). Theses one and two motivate an espousal of the ugly and ground an art that can be rationally indifferent to the claim of beauty. Neither demonstrates the falsity of the idealist theorem that makes ugliness nothing but a lack of beauty. Third, then, Adorno claims that what appears ugly is in the first place what is
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
223
historically older, what art rejected on its path toward autonomy, and what is therefore mediated in itself. The concept of the ugly may well have originated in the separation of art from its archaic phase: It marks the permanent return of the archaic, intertwined with the dialectic of enlightenment in which art participates (AT, 47). These formulations are more than usually condensed and qualified, but there can be little doubt that Adorno is here employing genealogy in order to make conceptual space for the emergence of primitivism in modernist art in a manner that is not intrinsically regressiveas he originally thought was the case with respect to Stravinsky.18 If art is itself historical, then a conceptual space is opened for a historical consideration of beauty and ugliness too. In claiming that ugliness is what appears historically older, with one swipe Adorno displaces the idealist reification of beauty. What came first on Adornos account were the cultic masks whose terrified looks were intended to be expressive passively and actively; archaic masks express both being terrified at all-powerful nature and, in the look of terror to express, that is, to cause, terror and thus to appropriate for oneself the power of the very thing that is terrifying. Masks are primitive mimetic forms, art before there was art, art as still submerged in magic. Art as mimetic comportment can only emerge fully if it separates itself from the magical heritage implied in its archaic forms. Art beauty, the beauty of form, Adorno appears to be claiming, is the sublation, the negation and preservation of the archaic ugly; or rather, what we now call ugly becomes so as art distances and separates itself from the cultic response to terrifying nature (in part because, with the advance of civilization, it has stopped being terrifying). Beauty belongs to the dialectic of enlightenment because as a series of mechanisms for forming nature, not merely as a means but as an end (which is what beauty signifies for Adorno), it both brings nature within the ambit of the civilizational process of release from bondage to natural ends and, simultaneously, dominates and represses those items it forms.
224
J. M. Bernstein
An immediate inference from this historical understanding of beauty is that the archaic or primitive is a disowned stratum of the artwork (what art repudiated in becoming art), whose recurrence in modernist art should thus be viewed not as an importation of the exotic, but as a return of the repressed. Almost certainly thinking about the Demoiselles, Adorno says just this about Picasso: Not all advanced art bears the marks of the frightening; these marks are most evident where not every relation of the peinture to the object has been severed, where not every relation of dissonance to the fulfilled and negated consonance has been broken off: Picassos shocks were ignited by the principle of deformation (AT, 287). Fourth, what goes along with the identification of the archaic as ugliness is the survey of specific kinds of contents that are condemned as ugly. Adorno conceives of ugly contents in a variety of ways: ugliness entered art as the lower classes became objects of artistic representation; their suffering and deformation at the hands of society was expressed by ugliness. Equally prohibited as ugly are simply all those items condemned by art: polymorphous sexuality as well as the violently mutilated and lethal (AT, 47). Finally, as a kind of summation or elaboration of these contents, Adorno contends that the aesthetic condemnation of the ugly is dependent on the inclination to equate the ugly with the expression of suffering, and by projecting it, to despite it (AT, 49). Evidently, this account of ugly contents merges easily with theses one and three. Les Demoiselles dAvignon mobilizes all four theses on ugliness protesting repressive harmony through dissonance, promoting artistic advance, the return of the archaic repressed, the expression of sufferingin its ambition of expressing the primitive and irresolvable ambiguity of human sexuality, where human sexuality is taken, via the beauty system, to be internally related to the very idea, the formal logic of modern painting. Hence, elaborating these four aspects of the beauty system is what painting must do if
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
225
it is to overthrow that system, where overthrowing the beauty system will amount to giving the Copernican turn an axial rotation toward the object. It is this overthrow I now want to demonstrate.
Picassos Parataxis
Leo Steinberg summarizes the Demoiselles accomplishments thus: The picture breaks the triple spell of traditionidealization, emotional distance, and fixed-focus perspectivethe tradition of high-craft illusionism which conducts the spectator unobserved to his privileged seat. Notice how for Steinberg the triple spell of tradition operates in order to place the unobserved spectator in a privileged position: contemplator, beholder, possessor of what is beheld. In order to break the spell of the beauty system the beholder must himself become beheld; in being beheld he must become undone (losing the privilege of emotional distance); in order to become beheld and undone the pictorial surface must become disordered, not incoherent, but emphatically not arranged for the sake of licensing the privileged seeing of one contemplator looking in on the depicted scene (hence breaking the rule of fixed-focus perspective); in becoming beheld, undone, and the locus of an order rather than the contemplator of it, the viewer must be corralled into the material world of painterly representation rather than the ideal world of beauty: he must undergo ugliness. It will prove useful to employ the disordering of fixed-focus perspective as an interpretive wedge. My hypothesis here is that Picasso deploys what is best thought of as the painterly equivalent of parataxis in order to accomplish this systematic disordering, a disordering into a new conception of pictorial order. Literally, parataxis is a form of syntax in which semantic unitswords, clauses, sentences, paragraphsare ordered by sheer juxtaposition rather than through logical/conceptual subordination that is signposted by the familiar connectives of hypotactic syntax: if x, then y; x because y; x necessitates y; and so on. With parataxis
226
J. M. Bernstein
there are just the items set next to one anotherxy with the character of their relation to be elicited through reflective consideration of their respective semantic/material contents. Adorno argues for parataxis being one of the central mechanisms of modernist art since it opens up the possibility of a different relation between concept and object, unity and multiplicity.19 Here then is my analogical hypothesis: what Steinberg calls the spell of the tradition leading the spectator to his privileged seat is the equivalent in the history of painting to what Adorno identified as the spell of the unifying ego subordinating the multiplicity of the world to its instrumental ends by conceptual synthesis, by, that is, unifying the complex many under a system of hierarchical subordination. This, recall, is his conception of transcendental subjectivity as the fullest expression of the Copernican turn. Since in painting it is high-craft illusionism that lends the spectator his privileged position, this illusionism can usefully be considered as equivalent to paintings version of transcendental idealism: the ideal spectator replaces the transcendental ego, the three mechanisms of idealization, emotional distance, and fixed-focus perspective thus become the forms of synthesis subordinating pictorial space to ideal unity that make the position of privileged contemplation possible. The female body is the fundamentboth in terms of form and affectsupporting the entire system. The female form in its what-is-to-be-looked-atness is technically, at least in part, the mechanism of idealization itself; however, this feature of the beauty system, like causality in the conceptual system, can be considered the pivot of the system as a whole.20 Hence, as the upshot and support of the threefold synthesis, the female form expresses the beauty systems concept of an object in general. Conceptual synthesis understood hypotactically deprives the units ordered of their particularity and material density because it subordinates them all to what will satisfy the ego, what will accord with its needs for order and control knowledge as domination. The tradition of high-craft illusionism with its threefold synthesis subordinates the female form to the
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
227
contemplating gaze of the male ego for the sake of aesthetic-sexual pleasurebeauty as sexual availability. The harmonization of truth and beauty, their exchangeability or translatability into one another is the way in which art has been complicit with the long reign of instrumental reason even as it has worked against it, even as it meant to be offering an alternative, noninstrumental rationality, even as it has sought to reveal a domain of ends beyond the sway of instrumental need and want. The beauty system is what prevents beauty from being beautiful. By dropping connectives and ordering devices, parataxis ends the rule of subordination, forcing or permitting each element or unit to become a concrete particular whose relation to what is placed against it, adjacent to it, side-by-side with it to become no longer given but what is to be worked out by the reader/observer. Painterly parataxis, I want to argue, is one of the keys to Picassos art; parataxis is to Picassos art what overallness (decorative order) is to Matisses. The Demoiselles is the founding instance; parataxis is its orienting formal device. In a way, that this is what Picasso is up to should be obvious: if the project is to move away from deep illusionist space, then the action of a painting must press up to the picture plane itself. The obvious question then arises: how does one carry on with significant representation while simultaneously acknowledging the authority of the picture plane? Picassos answer, or at least one of his answers, which he kept revising and refining for the remainder of his life, was, instead of subordinating the parts to the wholethe parts of the painting to the whole of the painting, and the parts of the human body to the ideal whole of the human bodyhe would set the parts next to one another, juxtapose them, place them side by side. (Even the terms necessary to describe parataxissetting, juxtaposing, placinglend to the parts so placed independence and solidity, with the act of painting itself coming to be depicted as acknowledging that independence, a mastering through a letting go of mastery.) In claiming parataxis to be Picassos organizing gesture in the
228
J. M. Bernstein
Demoiselles, I am doing no more than giving a procedural and aesthetic name to what Steinberg critically described in his remarkable essay The Philosophical Brothela title referring to the paintings own first name. Steinberg summarizes the upshot of Picassos paratactic practice as being, exactly, an axial rotation in virtue of which the viewer, rather than having a privileged seat, the scene for his sake, becomes the paintings object.
In the Demoiselles painting this rule of traditional narrative art [the threefold synthesis of the beauty system] yields to an anti-narrative counter-principle: neighboring figures share neither a common space nor a common action, do not communicate or interact, but relate singly, directly, to the spectator. A determined dissociation of each from each is the means of throwing responsibility for the unity of the action upon the viewers subjective response. The event, the epiphany, the sudden entrance [of the student into the brothel in the preparatory drawings for the painting] is still the themebut rotated through ninety degrees toward a viewer conceived as the pictures opposite pole.21
My procedure in what follows is to track Steinbergs account sufficiently, including various divergences from it, to reveal how Picassos parataxis entails the axial rotation, and how that axial rotation amounts to giving painting as a whole a turn toward the objectby which I will mean not the turn toward the spectator as object, although that too, but rather what Steinberg fails to grasp: the emergence of the body-object, the form of the human body itself as the transcendental condition for the possibility of pictorial space. Confirming this final move will require going beyond the Demoiselles to Picassos 1929 Nude Standing by the Sea. Let me begin by considering a small but obvious instance of Picassos paratactic procedure: the far left figures left hand, which appears to float disconnected above her head, without theorganizing, syntacticalmediation of arm length and distance. What are we to make of this? Steinberg thinks we should assume that
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
229
Picasso here wanted an oblique recession, pursued by an implied outstretched arm raised at thirty degrees. The disconnectedness of the hand at the visible terminus of the stretch then becomes emblematic of the maximum distance (25). Steinberg then lays out what it means to be employing a paratactic formula at this juncture: The aim is to express the recession of this upper flap not through linear or aerial perspective, not by way of color or physical clues such as overlaps, but through the suasion of gesture, the supposed necessity of an omitted arm between head and handa saccadic leap offered only to our anatomic intuition (26). Our anatomic intuition here does the work formally done for us by linear perspective; in making sense of her gesture in this way, we become responsible for the integrity of her body and its spacing, its integrity up to us, up to the viewer, and achieved only through the viewer rather than offered up to him. Further, to underline the obvious, insofar as it is the suasion of gesture that ignites our anatomic intuition, our judgment must be operating through mimetic recapitulation rather than constructive elaboration: we grasp her position not through observation but, finally, through identification. This is central for Adornos claim that art forms a repository for mimetic, thinglike rationality, a rationality that both acknowledges the precedence of the thing and returns the seeing eye to its bodily habitation. The next nude presents even more ferocious problems. Her left leg does not appear to reach down to the ground; rather, the left foot appears draped over her right shin, with the right leg simply disappearing. Given the slight bend of her right knee, we are forced to conclude that she is not, in fact, standing. At one point in the preparatory studies she was sitting in a chair with her left leg crossed over her right; in subsequent studies her chair dissolves and she sinks back, disposing herself at last, like an odalisque. She ends up recumbent but seen in birds eye perspective (27). The idea of verticalizing a supine figure has precedents. What nonetheless makes the idea so difficult to hold in place here is
230
J. M. Bernstein
that she is given to us as nearly vertical to the picture plane while placed in utter adjacency to the, in fact, vertical nudes on either side of her. Everything about how Steinberg goes on to describe her heightens the extraordinary paratactic formulation Picasso is working: She rests recessive but still extended, insulated in her own rocking space capsule. Adjacency without nearness; withdrawal without attenuation of presence. The full-length projection of her, claiming undiminished scope in the field, makes the beholder work harder; one has to push mental levers to keep an erected gisante lying down (28). Once we are alerted to her posture and the disposition of her limbs, we know that the second nude must be lying down; but given her location in the painting, the lack of recession from knee to head, and her consequent vertical relation to the picture plane, we are never going to see her as fully recumbent (a point Steinberg worries and fudges); we cannot ascend to the aerial view implied without losing our viewing perspective altogether. Being unable to see her as she must be seen automatically buckles illusionist pretense; illusion is just what we are missing here. But that is also what we are missing in her relation to the nudes on either side of her: her apparent verticality in relation to their actual verticality splinters or fragments the demoiselles space of habitation, so that each possesses her own space as defined by posture and gesture, a bodily space (without any of the other clues that normally provide spatial depth), without there being any space they are emphatically in. They are truly juxtaposed one to the other across the picture plane. Said differently: each nude possesses her own space in light of her bodily being; hence each nude provides orientation and structure for the picture as a whole, which is as much as to say that none doesthe idea of picture as a whole must now go into scare quotes. Each nude is a center, a place, and an orientation; hence each demands acknowledgment separately from her companions. Each nude becomes related to her companions through literal adjacency on the picture plane, on the one hand,
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
231
and through being related by the observer to the space implied by bodily posture. In the same way that in the case of the floating hand the observer must, through anatomical intuition, connect hand to body, so generally, through the possibilities of bodily orientation, the observer now becomes responsible for making room for and spacing the nudes in relation to one another. However, and here is Picassos move beyond the containing logic of part and whole, this effort will fail because the bodies provide clues sufficient only for the possibility of their spatial relation one to the other without enough systematic detail or systematic relating of one bodily amplified space to another to turn possibility into actuality; this scene can be registered but not surveyed or reconstructed. This is as much as to say that these bodies are the space of this painting, it emerges from them and collapses back on them.22 These bodies are not in space; they spatialize, give it and hold it open in just the way the far left demoiselle opens the curtain onto the scene and the back demoiselle parts the curtains that allow her to be seen. Both these figures, I am suggesting, demonstrate the difference between body-spatiality and high-craft illusionism of the kind where the curtain really is an entry into deep space, as in Vermeers Artist in His Studio or Allegory of the New Testament. Picassos overturning of this is patent in his making the figures presumably furthest away the center demoiselle and the right-hand figure emerging from the curtainspictorially the tallest. The impossibility of eliciting an overall spatial structure and the power of each of these bodies to give space by being its source achieve a fierce and wildly disorienting realization with the squatting nude on the right. While it is natural to read her as sitting with her back to the viewer, her head rapidly swiveling around at his entrance, there is sufficient counter-evidence in the other direction, above all that she casts both eyes on the intruder, her head hence so frontal as to make a back view improbable; a hypothesis underlined by the way her boomerang hand cups her face mask. Conversely, the hint of backbone and
232
J. M. Bernstein
disappearing pigtail press in the opposing direction. Picassos elision of thumbs, the purely angular thrust of arms and elbows, the odd extra flat plane of flesh adhering to the left arm resting on her knee, and, Picassos paratactic coup, no neck, her head simply sitting atop the body, leave the position of this nude systematically ambiguous. As Steinberg rightly comments, her flattened impress orients itself simultaneously inward and outward (58), which is to say, Picasso is here pursuing not flatness but a spatiality that emanates from her body alone. While Picasso is not yet quite explicitly offering multiple perspectives of the body all at oncethat will have to await Large Nude by the Sea (1909), with her sternum and backbone both equally presenthe does make her bodily orientation systematically ambiguous so that on the picture plane itself are implied competing perspectives and orientations, which in turn imply the necessity for imaginatively elaborating spatial structures concomitant with each perspectival take. Yet, in remaining systematically ambiguous, all these implied spatial possibilities themselves remain irresolvable and unmasterablethey are hinted at, implied, invoked, the sense of them palpable, all without even the glimmer of a corresponding fulfilling intuition; hence these spatial possibilities are in fact incapable of being inspected; which entails that there is, in fact, no place from which she can be seen. I almost want to say that she possesses all the conditions for see-ability while not being actually seen. And, of course, this final twist is no accident: for all her outrageous exposure, explicitness, and savagery, she sees more than is seenas do they all. Thinking through what is at stake here is complex. In a typically crescendo-building passage, in his Resisting Czanne, Part 2: The Polemical Part, Steinberg summarizes what he takes to be the formal character and innovations of the Demoiselles under the heading of Picassos discontinuity principle. What is perfect in this reprise of the painting for our purposes is that nearly every word or phrase Steinberg uses to designate feaThe Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
233
tures that are either components of or contribute to the paintings discontinuity could, with more right be said to be aspects of or features contributing to its paratactic structuring.
Comparison with the numerous studies for the Demoiselles revealed how tenaciously Picasso pursued this end; he was resolved to undo the continuities of form and field which Western art has so long taken for granted. The famous stylistic rupture at the right turned out to be merely a consummation. Overnight, the contrived coherencies of representational artthe feigned unities of time and place, the stylistic consistenciesall were declared to be fictional. The Demoiselles confessed itself a picture conceived in duration and delivered in spasms. In this one work Picasso discovered that the demands of discontinuity could be met on multiple levels: by cleaving depicted flesh; by elision of limbs and abbreviation; by slashing the web of connecting space; by abrupt changes of vantage; and by a sudden stylistic shift at the climax. Finally, the insistent staccato of the presentation was found to intensify the pictures address and symbolic charge: the beholder, instead of observing a roomful of lazing whores, is targeted from all sides. So far from suppressing the subject, the mode of organization heightens its flagrant eroticism.23
The advantage of thinking of what is depicted in the passage in terms of parataxis rather than discontinuity is that the latter term is merely negative, while the former concerns the liberation of material or semantic elements from their embedding in logical, abstract, or grammatical forms that, finally, are discovered to be indifferent to the material they bear, or worse, are an arrangement of those materials for purposes wholly extrinsic to them. I should not want to say that classical forms delivering beauty were, historically, only forms of domination (on the contrary, again, beauty bore an indefatigable emancipatory meaning), but they can become predominantly so, and had done for modern painting. As Steinberg pointedly concludes, the upshot of Picassos frag234
J. M. Bernstein
mentary style in the Demoiselles is the dislocation of viewer from his privileged position until he becomes targeted from all sides, the paintings subject, that is, who or what is subject-ed, done and undone by the nudes piercing, freezing looks: abandon all hope, ye who enter here. If there is a place where Steinbergs reading seems inappropriate it is in his claim of flagrant eroticism. In the viewer losing the privilege of viewing subject and becoming subjected to the cool or harassing views of these women, the meaning of body alters radically. Begin with the obvious: these bodies do not invite possession: none are stereotypically feminine, none invites touch, and, if sight is the erotic extension of touch, then none even quite invites being seen, or welcomes it; none is presented as expressly passively sexual. These are large, mannish women with thick thighs; angular, narrow-waisted bodies; breasts, when present at all, more often than not pointed rather than round. The three on the left have small, slit mouths, while the mouths of the two masked figures open in tight surprise to hoot an unreadable denigration of the interloper. If the posture of two central nudesthe one on the left with one arm reaching behind her head, her partner with both arms reaching backacknowledges a sexual situation, acknowledges their in-principle sexual availability, their eyes, bolted on the intruder, bespeak a saturnine indifference, as if nothing about their bodies, above all their nakedness, their exposure, should be taken as wanting or welcoming or needingon the contrary.24 These bodies and the space they carve out for themselves refuse entry. The first and most obvious conclusion to be drawn from this reversal from invitation to refusal is a generalization of the conclusion already drawn about body and spatiality: because these bodies cannot be possessed, because of their implacable character, their unavailability, together with their possession of their own objectifying gaze, the natural link between seeing and erotic, possessive desire is severed. The desire to see that is the paradigmatic sublimation of the desire to sexually possess, which itself was
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
235
classically fulfilled through the ecstatic vision of female beauty is here emphatically broken. But since the classical vision of beauty was a fantasyand no less fantastical in Matisses Blue Nude than in Ingress The Turkish Bath Picassos painting, precisely in its implacableness, its nonsurveyability, and its interruption and dismantling of the possessive gaze, strikes out toward truth against fantasy. Its overcoming of illusion is the mark of its truthfulness, its authenticity. The Demoiselles is the first true painting of the twentieth centuryit impels truthfulness or authenticity in place of beauty as the locus of painterly authority. Ugliness, in its unmasking, brings material truth against idealist illusion. What is that truth? Again, a generalization from the bodygives-space thesis seems necessary: if the depicted body is not the final object of (pictorial) perception, because seeing it is not the consummation of pictorial viewing, or better, pictorial viewing can no longer be figured as contemplation become consummation, then the bodies viewed become the condition of possibility of pictorial experience, its material a priori. As each demoiselle provides her own space, so each, more generally, opens up the very possibility of there being something intelligible, meaningful to be seen. These bodies in their implacable thereness create, open, make possible a perceptual relation to the world in general: perception leans on them. Or even: instead of vision possessing these objects, these bodies possess visiondominate, solicit, and expunge it at once. This is what I intended in claiming that the Demoiselles instigates or performs an axial rotation, a counter-Copernican turn, shifting from the identity thinking of the beauty system, through the negativity of ugliness, to the nonidentity of body-object with subject, the body viewed as in excess ofPicasso figuratively conceives of this as aboveits being viewed. Only a framework having this breadth does anything like justice to Picassos revolution. I shall return to this claim in the next section. At this juncture, however, it might be objected that in raising Picassos proj236
J. M. Bernstein
ect to the realm of transcendental philosophy I am also defending myself against the Demoiselles, its fierceness and awfulness, as, most certainly, Steinberg himself does in celebrating the paintings sexual energy in his wildly implausible claim that Picassos space insinuates total initiation, like entering a disordered bed (63). There is certainly initiation here, but nothing like immersion or entering, and certainly not a disordered bed. Earlier in the essay, Steinberg takes a different approach, which is closer but still seems wrong to me, claiming that the picture is a tidal wave of female aggression; one either experiences the Demoiselles as an onslaught, or shuts it off (15). There is some kind of onslaught on the viewer, but to think of it as simply aggression loses the disorienting coolness, almost indifference, of the two central European figures, and reduces to a single note the masks that strike me as far more ambiguous. Following Steinberg, there has been a veritable storm of interpretations, most keying their overall interpretation to the climactic moment of the mask of the crouching figure, which is taken as the upshot of Picassos exposure to African art. So William Rubin would see the painting as rehearsing an agon between Eros and Thanatos in which the different styles of painting span the polarity from Eros to Thanatosfrom the allure of the female body to the horror of it;25 Yve-Alain Bois takes that final mask as a Medusas head, her gaze consequently castrating. For Bois, not only does the Medusas head thesis link to a return of the repressed, but, more importantly, it is the pivot on which the paintings axial rotation turns on precise analogy with Caravaggios employment of it in his Medusa: It thematizes the spectators petrification and it makes the female sex organ (the Medusas head) the essential interrupter of narrative, the icon that challenges the (male) spectator by signifying to him that his comfortable position, outside the narrative scene, is not as secure as he might think.26 Each of these accounts of the vehemence of the Demoiselles strikes me as mastering and simplifying, as if getting the right
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
237
interpretation of the painting would allow us to know what we are feeling in relation to it. This is just the relation between painting and spectator that the painting repudiates and dismantles: in the same way in which Picasso provides the conditions for pictorial experience without satisfying them, so affectively and thematically the implacable bodies and inscrutable faces freeze the viewer with their unknowableness, by which I mean not their being without affect, but the utter ambiguousness and ambivalence of their presence. It is not the agon between Eros and Thanatos that Picasso rehearses, as if the left side of the painting were all Eros and the right side all Thanatos; it is that in this setting we cannot locate where Eros ends and aggression/the death drive/ castration begins. It is the female form as the power of life and death, of the erotic as knotted with and involving its opposite just as these figures knot sexual difference so that the very terms and conditions of the beauty systemactive/masculine and passive/ femininelose their visual purchase. It should be remembered that the head of the far left Iberian figure certainly draws on Gauguins The Spirit of the Dead Watching (1892); as watcher over this scene she is both madam and memento mori. If the arms behind the heads of the two central European demoiselles signify their self-display, the verticality and sharpness of their elbows do not lack aggressiveness. As Steinberg comments about Czannes earliest use of this motif, [T]he pose is struck as a provocation that tempers bland nakedness into a weapon.27 Certainly the mask of the crouching figuring is frightening, but are we so sure of what we are frightened by here? The labels sex, death, woman, desire, or castration are just so many evasions of the irreducible difficulty of sexual encounter that Picasso means to be rehearsing. He means for us to encounter in this painting sexual encounter itself as originary, as a traumatic opening to experience rather than a moment in it. This can be so only if the paratactically presented bodies are sourcesof life, death, sexual pleasure, and sexual terror; having this power is what gives these figures their
238
J. M. Bernstein
authority and coolness; experiencing this power is what undoes the viewer, undoes his detachment, undoes any idea the viewer may have of being outside and master of the space viewed. Steinberg comments that the Demoiselles [is] about the human condition, about that perpetual moment in which self-knowledge arises in sexual confrontation (52). I would elaborate this claim by saying that Picasso manages to make the Demoiselles a moment of radical self-consciousness on the part of the viewer because the painting operates a systematic dismantling of the viewers self-possession, hence his presumptive but unearned authority. Les Demoiselles DAvignon is indeed primitive, but primitive the same way that Hobbess state of nature is primitive, or even the way Hegels struggle for recognition is primitive, terminating in the dialectic of master and slave. In this painting is revealed the source of the slaves power over her master; and here, for the first time perhaps in modern painting, the master shudders, quakes, even collapses. So we come to self-consciousness in the experience of an absolute otherness. Painting can thus begin again.
239
that painting operates with a logic of part and whole, its practice will come to be shadowed by the problem of organic form. Since dependence on the normative authority of organic form can look like dependence on the authority of a premodern metaphysics of life, the temptation to turn to geometric form, the logic of part plus part, can seem overwhelming. My suggestion has been that this is in fact not a real option: either geometric form is an expression of human experience, in which case the question of the human element has simply been hidden or deferred; or geometric form is autonomous, in which case it is unclear how it pertains to art. The embarrassment of organic form, the entwinement of art and life, cannot be avoided. At this point, it may be argued that I am misstating the problem; after all, the fundamental question about works of art is not whether they are alive or dead, but how they mean, and meaning comes from human mindedness. From at least Lessing to the present the thought has been that matter does not mean on its own, rather mind or spirit breathes life into matter by giving it meaning. Among the difficulties here, the most pertinent is that this way of answering the problem generates an absolute bifurcation between the life/body system and the meaning system, a bifurcation that only makes sense in the kind of Platonic universe that no one now supposes we inhabit. Against the background of this uninviting scenario, it becomes salient to note that there is one place where the axis of dead matter versus organic life meets the axis of meaning versus dead matter, and that is paradigmatically the human body, but also necessarily, by extension, all living bodies. The human body in its sheer material givenness, in its matter-of-fact material self-presentation is alive and a source of meaning, meaningful in its aliveness. The human body itself means, and means beyond, before, after, and how we intentionally mean it. So the human body in its sheer being therestanding or sitting or lying, not even movingmeans. And what it means first is aliveness (or deadness, which for the body is a mode of
240
J. M. Bernstein
aliveness, and hence different from dead matter, material stuff). Which is to say, it is somehow the human body as itself a material presence in the world that is a source of meaning rather than consciousness or mind or spirit or language or even desire (although desire is, especially for Picasso, utterly proximate to aliveness and its absencethis is precisely the upshot of my interpretation of the Demoiselles). Because the body autonomously and automatically means, cannot be prevented from meaning except by being erased altogether, the body necessarily organizes visual space. Visual space is a precipitate of the bodies inhabiting it. Or at least this becomes Picassos theme: the bodys meaning in excess of and independently of how it is meant; or, the inevitability, the ineluctable terror or passion, of its being meant (desired, wanted, seen, painted). All these themes are already there in the Demoiselles but require the passage through cubism and its failure to become explicit. Think of this stuttering emergence this way: Let us concede that consciousness, language, desire, and so on are sources not just of meaning but of ideality, of normative rightness. Beginning with, say, Czanne, modern art discovered that although it was directed to the visual presence of the world, the terms of its practice were burdened with ideals from elsewhere, ideals that were extrinsic to the sheer material givenness of things as they imposed themselves on the perceptual experiences that painting was to be a record of. The most difficult and therefore most contested thing here must be the human body. If painting is to achieve an integrity intrinsic to its material practice, then it would have to excise all extra-bodily meaning from the body, let the body present itself, be present by itself, which in practice means either presenting it through the negation of its idealized forms or capturing it before idealization has had a chance to gain access to it: presenting it through the negation of beauty, through distortion and dismemberment, or capturing the body before beauty (which in practice may not be so different from the negative strategy).
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
241
Consider now Picassos Nude Standing by the Sea.28 I want to say that this painting recovers and deepens the Demoiselles axial rotation against the beauty system by displacing cubisms own presumptive displacement of organic form. Hence, the most salient and unmistakable feature of this painting is that this monster is, for the most part, constructed, made out of geometric solids: her head is just a ball, her body a pyramid, her legs rectangles like those of a table, her breasts small sharply pointed cones, her buttocks half spheres. Moreover, the ball that is her head is without features, just a stone ball, and it is very small, tiny in proportion to the rest of her body. Not only does the smallness of her headand I think this is general also for all the pinheaded bodies that Picasso painted at this timedrive out the possibility that her body is just an extension of her consciousness, or what self-awareness she has might be located in her head, but, for the viewer, it eliminates the possibility that in responding to her we are responding to an expressive, affect-laden irresistible human face. No eyes as windows into the soul here, no Levinas face of the other, no look or gaze or returning view. But this is also to admit that, unlike Picassos ferocious demoiselles, this figure is open to being viewed, the way some of us used to view bodies before Picasso made it impossible (at least impossible in the old, unselfconscious way it was possible to view bodies before him). But, of course, it is not really to-be-looked-at-ness that is in question here. It is the language of cubism, the language of geometry and geometrical construction that is at issue. In saying that Picasso flagrantly presses the fact of her geometric construction, I mean to be insisting that he is allowing in everything a painterly rationalist could want: here is a body that is nothing but pure geometrical forms. And the purity of her being nothing but a composite of geometrical forms matters not at all to her presence. In this setting her geometrical construction is not the source of her meaningful presence, but, if anything, an explicit form of testing it, resisting it: the resistance fails. The
242
J. M. Bernstein
geometry of her form is sublated at every moment by those geometrical forms being those of a human body, human bodily form effectively sublating, overcoming, and subsuming other contestants to the throne of originating form. We do not breath life into the human body, we do not project meaning on to it; it exemplifies meaning and life even as geometrical construction would seek to crush it. Further, I interpret the meaning of Picasso depicting her as something constructed and, indeed, as something that has been sculpted from stone as pressing the fact of her brute materiality, her sheer material presence as opposed to any illusory inwardness. I do not know whether we are inclined to ascribe soul or sapience to her; maybe she is more primitive than that, before soul or sapience the way the demoiselles may be thought of as before beauty (before the beauty system could get hold of them). And while I need to acknowledge her sapience, I do not think of it as anything inward; I do not know what it would mean for her to suffer. She feels, to the extent she does, precisely in proportion to the extent she is a living body, no more, no lesswhich is the puzzle and wonder of her. (She is emphatically turned toward the sun, soaking it in; but there is no heat or hotness here; her turning and facing thus occur the way a plant might turn and face the sun; the sun is her medium or element, like the blue of sea and sky.) So the metaphorical thought Picasso is after is that her material being in the world is no different in kind from the material life afforded by her painted representation. But this presses in exactly the opposite direction to what we may have supposed: in a presentation of the human body the exchange between obdurate materiality and material meaning is immediate: she isappears to bealive. Because of her human form, her aliveness is necessarily given; because of her geometric construction and because of her stoniness, we are given pause: how exactly is she alive? How does or can she feel in her stony body? But this pause and these questions cannot fully abrogate the sense of her as
The Demand for Ugliness: Picassos Bodies
243
alive, where the only possible explanation for the insistence of that sense is her human form. Against these thematics of her brute materiality, I take her standing and uprightness, which are undeniable, to operate here as a counterpoint; that is, what her easy unselfconscious uprightness signifies is the uprising or immanent ideality of the human form as a sheer material presence, and hence an ideality not dependent on extrinsic ideals (like all ideals of beauty). 29 It is the combination of brute materiality and uprightness that Picasso is after, therefore, not just the utter transposability of materiality and phenomenality, of deadness and aliveness, but the increment of that joining that uprightness allows: an ideal of the human rising up in sheer being there. The painting appears to insist upon an impossible union of opposites in which the up movement from dead matter to living meaning and the down movement from ideality to inert stuff were allowed to perfectly coincide. Uprightness is not meant to provide the terms of this works authenticity, but rather forms a further elaboration of how human bodily form possesses not just sense but even an incipient ideality in its mere givenness in ways that utterly dissolve the significance of the bodys geometrical material construction.30 I am hence urging that the nudes uprightness must be understood in relation to the general project of desublimation, and hence as a component of the attempt to close the space between matter and meaning, dead stuff and alivenessa component of the attempt to interrogate again and again the image of the female body as where these opposites converge and coincide. If I can put these claims in the context of my remarks on the Demoiselles, I would say that what is being asked of us here is acknowledgment, acknowledgment that what is before us is a human body with everything that means for our attitudes and comportment to it. That we can feel a curious empathic identification with the bather, wanting something from her even if we do not know what, is our acknowledgment that she is one of us, and
244
J. M. Bernstein
one of us because no matter her material substance, no matter how constructed, no matter how hewn, and no matter how geometrically contrivedstill, this is a human form: in the sheer having of head, body, arms, legs, breasts in approximately the right places she means, and she can only mean, the way a human form means, because there is nothing else for us to acknowledge.
245
Endnotes
1
Theodor W. Adorno, On Subject and Object, in Critical Models: Interventions and Catchwords, trans. Henry W. Pickford (New York, 1998), p. 248. The status of the Demoiselles is now, I suppose, secure. So Christopher Green states in his introduction to his edited volume Picassos Les Demoiselles DAvignon (Cambridge, 2001): In the mythology of modernist and postmodern art history, the status of Picassos Demoiselles DAvignon as a painting that marks a dramatic break from the past and a new twentieth century beginning is now unquestioned (p. 2). In stating the stakes in the way I do I have been partially preceded by Charles Harrison, Painting the Difference: Sex and Spectator in Modern Art (Chicago, 2005), 17274. Rosalind Krauss, The Picasso Papers (Cambridge, 1999), pp. 19394. And is not what is exquisite in Robert Ryman or Agnes Martin, precisely, touch? But then why the detour through geometry and the mechanical? And what about the standing of touch? Or, if not a detour, then a limb of a practice that can be described differently from the way cubism is now described. For example, in The Polemical Part, which is an epilogue to his article Resisting Czanne: Picassos Three Women, Art in America 66 and 67 (November-December 1978 and March-April 1979): pp. 11433, 11427, Leo Steinberg argues that cubism, as practiced by Picasso but not Braque, can be seen as one way of extending the principles of discontinuity, fragmentariness, and disunity that he pioneered in the Demoiselles. Of course, one could argue that since geometry is one possible a priori framework for the intelligibility of space, then logically Picasso must be wrong in this claim. And this way of conceiving geometry and its consorts (the mechanical, etc.), would certainly make the postmodernism that emerges with minimalism look at least plausible if not downright inevitable. What is forgotten in this is that geometry is just another human practice, grounded in human needs and human bodily practices of pacing, measuring, constructing. Sigmund Freud, Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality, trans. James Strachey, in On Sexuality (New York, 1977), p. 69. Freud proposes that the curiosity underlying visual pleasure can be sublimated into art if its interest can be shifted away from the genitals on to the shape of the body as a whole.
5 6
246
J. M. Bernstein
10
Laura Mulvey, Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema, Screen 16, no. 3 (Autumn 1975): p. 12.
11
Elizabeth Cowling, Picasso: Style and Meaning (London, 2002), p. 179. Cowling, I should state, is almost unique in defending ugliness as a recurrent productive weapon in Picassos painterly armory. Her tenacious defense of Picassos plurality of styles has been exemplary for me. For the analogies see ibid. p. 168.
12 13 14
Ibid., p. 174.
Elizabeth Cowling et al., Matisse Picasso (London, 2002), p. 55. See Leo Steinberg, The Algerian Women and Picasso at Large, in his Other Criteria: Confrontations with Twentieth-Century Art (New York, 1972), pp. 125234, for an account of ugliness in Picasso, beginning with the Demoiselles, that runs from puzzlement (p. 224) to outright denial (p. 227).
15
16
For a thoughtful effort at reconstructing Adornos logic of ugliness see Peter Uwe Hohendahl, Aesthetic Violence: The Concept of the Ugly in Adornos Aesthetic Theory, Cultural Critique 60 (Spring 2005): pp. 17096. For my own earlier effort see Against Voluptuous Bodies: Late Modernism and the Meaning of Painting (Stanford, 2006), chaps. 7 and 9.
17
Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis, 1997), 45. (Hereafter AT; subsequent references appear parenthetically in the text.) For Adornos attempt to find a space for primitivism, see Hohendahl, Aesthetic Violence, pp. 17380, which also includes a useful account of the role of Carl Einsteins Picasso-inspired account of African sculpture in the argument of Adornos Philosophy of Modern Music.
18
19
Theodor W. Adorno, Parataxis: On Hlderlins Late Poetry, in Notes to Literature (New York, 1992), 2: pp. 10949. The idealization of the female form would involve standard markers of sexual desirability including body type, youth, posture, etc. And of course nakedness.
20
21
All parenthetical references in the remainder of this essay are to Leo Steinberg, The Philosophical Brothel, October 44 (Spring 1988): pp. 774, here 13; the essay was originally published in two parts in 1972 in Art News. This essay now, deservedly in my view, dominates the field. For a summary of responses to it see Christopher Greens introduction to Picassos Les Demoiselles dAvignon. Cowling, Picasso: Style and Meaning, p. 165. Because art historians all know so well the numerous drawings that lead up to the final painting, they suppose they know the space of the painting better than they do.
22
247
23
Steinberg, The Polemical Part, p. 124. Cowling, Picasso: Style and Meaning, p. 178, seems to me to get all this just right.
24
25
William Rubin, From Narrative to Iconic in Picasso: The Buried Allegory in Bread and Fruitdish on a Table and the Role of Les Demoiselles dAvignon, Art Bulletin 65, no. 4 (December 1983): p. 635. Rubins thesis of a shift from narrative to iconic is his version of the paintings revolutionary axial rotation. Yve-Alain Bois, Painting as Trauma, in Green, Picassos Les Demoiselles DAvignon, p. 44.
26
27
Steinberg, Resisting Czanne, p. 120. Steinberg, I should note, persuasively interprets Three Women (1908) as an account of the emergence of sexual difference, just barelyout of stone. Nude Standing by the Sea (1929), is in the permanent collection of the Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York, and can be viewed online at http://www.metmuseum.org/toah/works-of-art/1996.403.4. My paragraphs on this painting were originally part of a commentary to a presentation by T. J. Clark on this painting entitled The Ordinary Optimism of Picasso at the University of California, Berkeley, March 2, 2007. For reasons of space, I have not been able to include here either an account of Clarks interpretation of this painting or my concerns about his interpretation.
28
29
Her uprightness, standingness, was the key to Clarks interpretation of the painting in the presentation mentioned in the previous note. I have said nothing about the womans position. Trying the position for myself, it is not a stretch, but just a way of standing and holding oneself, which I think is the point: she may be made, constructed, but in positioning herself she is also self-constructed and, in holding herself, fully self-possessed. The depth of her self-possession converges with the density of her material being, her indissoluble independence. This is why sun, sea, sky are her elements only; Picasso removes any hint of dependence. Thanks to Gregg Horowitz for both pressing me on her pose and his suggestions about it, which I have adopted freely.
30
248
J. M. Bernstein
Thierry de Duve
ful shortcuts in time demanding commensurate short circuits in the readers brain connections. They combine or, rather, jostle precise technical and philological knowledge of a given art form (here, music) with bold birds-eye views of the fate of humankind, mediated by strong political consciousness of history, especially of the economic overdetermination of the period the philosopher and his readers live in. Lifted from a paragraph that starts, As a bourgeois art music is young, the lines of my epigraph are inserted in a thorough discussion of Wagners original talent for orchestration as a victory of reification in instrumental practice, leading Adorno to conclude that Wagners oeuvre comes close to the consumer goods of the nineteenth century which knew no greater ambition than to conceal every sign of the work that went into them.2 Lines such as these show Adorno at his best: clever,
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
249
witty, fast, pugnacious, and flamboyantand a true writer to boot. They make you want to embrace his writing wholesale, and, by the same token, they make critique of his thinking very difficult. Resisting Adorno (my title, Im afraid, gives my intention away) does not get easier when we read on, but for reasons quite different, if not opposite:
Works of art owe their existence to the division of labour in society, the separation of physical and mental labour. At the same time, they have their own roots in existence; their medium is not pure mind, but the mind that enters into reality and, by virtue of such movement, is able to maintain the unity of what is divided. It is this contradiction that forces works of art to make us forget that they have been made. The claim implicit in their existence and hence, too, the claim that existence has a meaning, is the more convincing, the less they contain to remind us that they have been made, and that they owe their being to something external to themselves, namely to a mental process. Art that is no longer able to perpetrate this deception with good conscience has implicitly destroyed the only element in which it can thrive.3
No doubt the reader who has the famous first line of the Aesthetic Theory in mindIt is self-evident that nothing concerning art is self-evident anymore, not its inner life, not its relation to the world, not even its right to exist4 will read this paragraph as a statement of Adornos most intimate convictions and anxieties. The last sentence, in particular, all but betrays his profound desperation in the face of a world he sees as no longer capable of sustaining the, for him, fundamental illusion that makes works of art appear as sui generis entities, autonomous and as if unmade. It is no longer style and flamboyance that jump from the page, but rather ponderous gloom. The paragraph is also typically obscure. But the gloom and the obscurity, even the despair, are magnets as powerful as wit and brilliance for the committed Adorno reader.
250
Thierry de Duve
Buttressed by his immense culture and his aristocratic sense of self, they account for the unique pathosyou might call it the pain of contradictions lived and thought throughthat tinges Adornos writings in general. That pathos is irresistible, so much does it testify to the depth of his concerns, to the seriousness of his thoughts and, above all, to the lucidity at all costs that drives him. You are never left in doubt that art and culture matter to Adorno; moreover, that they matter because the course of the world matters, what he often names, in rather heavy terms, the totality. Fiat ars, pereat mundus is not an Adornian utterance. There is perhaps a measure of dandyish masochism in his writing, but not a trace of decadence. The pain is the price of compassion; the gloom is the mood the greatest mass murder ever perpetrated in the history of humankindthe destruction of the European Jewscommands: The need to lend a voice to suffering is a condition of all truth. For suffering is objectivity that weighs upon the subject.5 Because Adornos pathos is not personal and subjective, because it is out there in the world and affects you objectively, its dark seduction is very hard to resist. If you care for the world yourself, then the pain that transpires behind Adornos professorial authority and critical consciousness is likely to move you in a much more profound and durable manner than the pyrotechnics of a style capable of linking violins doubled by a flute in Haydn to primitive human beings baking bread for the first time. Of course, you might quibble with the content of the paragraph even if its tone bewitches you. You might voice your surprise at such a distinguished reader of Marx invoking the technical separation of physical and mental labour in lieu of the social division of labour in society. But then you would easily find a dozen quotes elsewhere in Adornos writings that show you how aware he was that art owes its existence not to the separation of physical and mental labour but to the brutal fact that while one man composes music or poetry, another (wo)man has to bake his bread. My
251
favorite one, from Minima Moralia, is devoid neither of the witty and insightful historical shortcuts nor of the gloomdemonstrated by the paragraph on which I am commenting:
The existence of bread factories, turning the prayer that we be given our daily bread into a mere metaphor and an avowal of desperation, argues more strongly against the possibility of Christianity than all the enlightened critiques of the life of Jesus.6
Granted, those lines are not directly about art and the social division of labor, but they are about bread (if this is an excuse) and the labor that industrially produced bread conceals. They also give a glimpse of Adornos complicated relationship to Messianism (Jewish and Christian)something highly relevant to the relationship to art and to history our paragraph displays. To come back to it, the twist may well be that Adorno chooses to acknowledge the division of labor in terms of the separation of body and mind only because he wants to stress the paradox of the mental process that gives birth to works of art as being external to them. But here we run into serious translation problems. The word rendered as mental process (and as mind in the second sentence)is actually Geist, a word with quite a pedigree in German philosophy. Its Hegelian origin would have been blatant had the translator rendered it as spirit. But he seems to have systematically eclipsed the Hegelian overtones of the whole paragraph, making it perhaps not more obscure than it is, but obscure in a way that betrays its author. We will need another translation:
Works of art owe their existence-in-the-world [Dasein] to the division of labor in society, the separation of physical and mental labor. By the same token, however, they themselves appear as in-the-world; their medium is not pure spirit existing for itself, but the spirit that retreats into worldly existence [Existenz] and, by the force of such movement, lays a claim on the unity of what is separated. This contradiction forces
252
Thierry de Duve
works of art to make us forget that they are made: the claim their existence-in-the-world stakes, and hence the claim that existence itself is meaningful, is the more convincing, the less something in them warns us that they have been fabricated, that they owe their existence to spirit as something external to themselves. Art that is no longer able to achieve this deception with good conscienceindeed its very principlehas dissolved the only element in which it can realize itself.7
The gloom is still there; the anxiety as to the fate of art is still there; the fear that Dasein itself, not just the existence of art but existence per se, in other words human life, has lost its meaning, is still there. But I hope this translation makes it a bit clearer how much all that pessimism is dressed upin Hegelian garb. To read under Adornos pen that the medium of works of art is not pure spirit existing for itself is already utterly surprising. Does Adorno need to remind us that in art spirit has material existence? Has he not accustomed us to consider the medium in its materiality and its technical specificity, first and foremost? What we witness here is Adorno presenting a Hegelian argument the better to push the anti-Hegelian counterargument according to which works of art owe their existence to spirit as something external to themselves. For Hegel, spirit was the internal medium of art, phenomenal existence the external, and when he saw their final synthesis achieved in the wake of Romantic art, it was to the benefit of spirit. For the post-Romantic Adorno, even that ultimate stage of spirit is but a particular moment of its history. The unification of matter and spirit is claimed rather than achieved, and then at the cost of a regressive movement of spirit retreating, recoiling, taking refuge, as it were, in the material existence of the artworks medium. Here Adorno concludes: This contradiction forces works of art to make us forget that they are made. In other words, this unresolved battle of forces compels us to look at works of art as though they were not artifacts but rather products of nature. And when that battle is lost, as the last sentence
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
253
dramatically announces, then arts very survival is under threat. The view that art should look like nature while we know that it is the product of spirit is so foreign to Hegel that dialectical negation of Hegel fails to account for its appearance under Adornos pen. It is a typically Kantian view, however: Nature was beautiful, if at the same time it looked like art; and art can only be called beautiful if we are aware that it is art and yet it looks to us like nature.8 I wonder whether Adornos particular brand of pathos does not result partly from his being perpetually torn between the two greatest among his predecessors in the history of German philosophy, Kant and Hegel. This is not to say that Schopenhauer and Nietzsche do not loom large in his work as well, but traveling back and forth between these two thinkers and Hegel is feasible, whereas reconciling Kant and Hegel is notexcept perhaps via Schelling, but this would mean walking the Romantic route, something Adorno avoids like the plague. That Adornos pathos results from the clash between his unrelenting longing for reconciliation and his acute awareness that reconciliation in an irreconciled world is either a lie or an impossibility is palpable everywhere in his writings. That the pain of contradictions lived and thought through, as I called his pathos, might result, in part, from his attempt to reconcile Kants critical with Hegels speculative philosophies surfaces more sporadically, but where it does, it signals how impossible a task Adorno has set himself. What would such reconciliation entail? Vershnung is a key word in Adorno, one with complex meanings and several realms of application, and it is a dialectical word, which is to say that it necessarily implies its own negation. It resonates with the word utopia in the political realm and with the word redemption in the religious one, and carries the connotation of promise as ceaselessly betrayed and yet still waiting to be fulfilled. It is the word in which Adornos hope and despair become oneno wonder it is also the most laden with pathos. For example, Dialectics serves the end of reconciliation,
254
Thierry de Duve
and The agony of dialectics is the worlds agony raised to the level of concept.9 To start with the easiest to grasp, one layer of meaning in Adornos usage of reconciliation is the practical, social, or historical meaning of cease-fire, armistice among enemies, the taming of class and other struggles, and the state of peace obtained thereby. Such a peace is always, by necessity, provisional, never durable, and therefore not much more than a truce, yet renouncing it would mean renouncing every hope of a pacified world. A second layer of meaning has reconciliation refer to the more profound and in principle more durable peace that history would make with itself if it could make up for past tragedies and catastrophes, if their victims could be vindicated once and for all without calling for revenge in their turn, in short, if the process of history itself could be brought to a halt. This would be the true redemption, and no investment in progress is thinkable without positing it on the horizon, but since it calls on a teleological notion of history implying the abolition of history, it is self-contradictory and bound to fail. For example, Utopiathe yet-to-existis the imaginary reparation of the catastrophe of world history; it is freedom that, under the spell of necessity, did not and may never come to be.10 A third layer of meaning touches on the even broader reconciliation of the sphere of human life with the global sphere encompassing all life, that is, with the order of natural phenomena, natural beings, and natural laws. This ultimate utopia must be recognized as beyond the realizable, while its promisesthose made by the beauty of nature, in particularcannot be forgotten without humanitys presence in the natural world becoming meaningless. Traversing these various layers of meaning, there runs the philosophical plane where reconciliation is defined as the dialectical uniting of opposites that resolves a contradiction; for Adorno, as for Hegel and Marx, contradictions are not just logical and formal, and they dont obey Aristotles principle of the excluded third; they are real, concrete ordeals, embodied in worldly events, disputes, and struggles; they
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
255
are the engine of history. But unlike Marx, whose materialist upturning of Hegel consists in putting the historical development of the relationships of production in lieu of the progressive unfolding of absolute spirit, Adorno articulates his critique of Hegel around a different kind of materialism: the radical refusal of synthesis, of sublation, of what Lyotard has called result.11 It is not only that contradictions cannot be solved; it is that they ought to remain unsolved. Their irresolvableness makes them vulnerable to further contradictions and thus keeps open the possibility of reconciliation as a potential. In the same way that Messianism requires the arrival of the Messiah to be perpetually postponed, so every momentary reconciliation requires the unity of the opposites to be in turn denied in the name of truly accomplished reconciliation. For example: If the utopia of art were fulfilled, it would be arts temporal end.12 Oxymoric Wahrheitsgehalt is, I believe, the main thrust of Adornos highly contradictory notion of Vershnung as it is applied, exemplarily, to works of art:
The most intimate contradiction within works of art, the most threatening and fruitful, is that they are irreconcilable by way of reconciliation, while actually their constitutive irreconcilability at the same time cuts them off from reconciliation.13
Adornos ambition, however, doesnt stop with the anti-Hegelian Hegelianism his project of a humanity (ir)reconciled with itself entails. For a philosopher of his background and caliber, the ultimate reconciliation must be the reconciliation of the practical and the theoreticalin Kants terms, of ethics and nature; in Hegels terms, of spirit and the world all this on Adornos terms, that is, as irreconcilable reconciliation. To play Hegel against himself will not suffice here. Must Kant not be played against himself too? Should a negative Hegel not be played against a negative Kant? And would that not amount to the true dialectical Vershnung of Hegel with Kant? If transcendentalism was the solution for Kant and dialectics the solution for Hegel, we might have a
256
Thierry de Duve
glimpse of the enormity of the task Adorno set himself: to somehow combine negative dialectics with transcendental materialism. The latter expression is not Adornos, but what its strategy might consist in is relatively clear: wherever Kant presupposes innate universal conditions of possibility, refer to sedimented history and ingrained social habits instead. Adorno does this systematically in the chapter of Negative Dialectics devoted to Kant. One superb example is the passage where he criticizes Kant for making the will the transcendental seat of freedom by saying that freedom is freedom of the will only insofar as men have the will to seek freedom.14 Another is the passage in Dialectic of Enlightenment where he and Horkheimer pretend that Kants transcendental schematism, this hidden art in the depths of the human soul, has been mechanized by the culture industry.15 I doubt that Adorno ever explicitly put the ultimate reconciliation of the practical and the theoretical on his agenda, but he was highly aware that Kants Critique of Judgment was an attempt at precisely such a reconciliation (though of course not on his terms): the bridging of the domains of the first and the second Critiques via the third, the making compatible of the laws of nature with the moral law via the reflecting judgment. He therefore knew the centrality of aesthetics for any such attempt, and thus of the realm of pleasure and painnot just pleasure and pain theorized by a philosopher but experienced by this philosopher. (Indeed, [s] uffering is objectivity that weighs upon the subject. And there is not much talk of pleasure in Adorno.) Given the central place aesthetics had for his philosophy in general, it is hard to imagine Adorno failing to reflect consciously on his own pain and not objectifying the scars left by the cultural issues that mattered to him. He never wrote on art and culture without engaging his own appreciation, and he never lost sight of the larger picture, convinced as he was that arts autonomy was precisely what allowed it not to be cut off from the world at largea conviction shared by both Hegel and Kant, albeit on mutually incompatible premises.16
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
257
Adorno made his home in these incompatibilities. His aesthetic theory is fraught with Hegelian readings of Kantian issues (never the other way around, of course): solvable antinomies interpreted as irresolvable contradictions, ideas of reason recast as moments of spirit, ethical imperatives rewritten as historical programs, and so on. I am tempted to read the particular brand of pathos the Aesthetic Theory yields as the symptom of the willfully impossible reconciliation of Kant and Hegel. And I want to resist the pathos and its appeal, not only because I made my choice between Kant and Hegel long ago and dont dream of reconciling them, but also because I see no way for the skeptic to engage critically and respectfully with Adornos thought other than to start by reading his pathos as the symptomatic outcome neither of his character nor of the state of the world but of his way of thinking. Indeed, negative dialectics is a way of thinking that you either embrace or reject but with which you cannot enter into discussion. If you embrace it, you cannot even settle an argument you might have with yourself. There is no arguing with someone who claims that aesthetic experience is possibility promised by its impossibility, or that, although the utopian figure of art is compelled toward absolute negativity, it is precisely by virtue of this negativity that it is not absolutely negative, or that a noncontradictory theory of the history of art is not to be conceived: the essence of its history is contradictory in itself.17 Where do you start if you dont agree? Where is your possibility to contradict a theory that makes of contradiction a nonfalsifiable motto? How do you wriggle out of the ensuing double bind? What do you make of the conundrum of the passage where Adorno claims that philosophys task is to interpret art in order to say what [art] is unable to say, whereas art is only able to say it by not saying it?18 Pardon? This is no longer dialectics, negative or other; it is self-contradiction run amok. Better laugh it off than whine with Adorno, Id say. To quote that passage out of context was a bit unfair. And to laugh Adornos pathos away may turn out to be a symptom of
258
Thierry de Duve
its own. Consider this, one of the concluding lines of Aesthetic Theory: It would be preferable that in some better times art vanish altogether than that it forget the suffering that is its expression and in which form finds its substance.19 Would you dare laugh that off and risk passing for a philistine who wants art to paint the world rosy and pink? From Grnewalds Isenheim altarpiece to Picassos Guernica; from Shakespeares Macbeth to Becketts Endgame (which Adorno wrote about and held in high esteem), would you deny that human suffering is the stuff great works of art are made of? You may laugh with Beckett, because you would be laughing at the ridiculousness of laughing, but you wont laugh at Beckett.20 So you wont laugh at Adorno either, when he prefers to see art vanish rather than have it forget the suffering of humankind. And yet the pathos of that line! Are you willing to suffer with Adorno? Will you accept the sacrifice of art against the certainty of some better times? I, for one, shall not. I simply do not entertain, even remotely, the hope that some future day the world might be peaceful enoughharmonious, beautiful, reconciled enoughto allow for the vanishing of art into uselessness (which says something about what I think is the usefulness of art). I find such hope naive and futile, if not dangerous. Thus I shall refuse to share in the pathos that wants me to suffer either way, whether it is from a life without art in an otherwise happy world, or from the damaged life of the existing world, with art as solace.21 Yet I cant honestly shut my ears to the intimation that makes Adornos pathos so hard to resist: am I therefore devoid of empathy for my fellow men? Have I abandoned all hope in a better world? Have I sold out to affirmation? And, accessorily: have I not misunderstood Adorno? Did he not write that line as a warning because he refused the alternative it offered? Has he not consistently written against art as solace? Was he really that naive, to believe in a future perfect world? Why then does the word Vershnung under his pen mean the contrary of its dictionary definition? Is the truth-value of his thinking not of practical
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
259
nature? Was he not, like good old Marx, philosophizing in order to change the world rather than interpret it? All these questions may boil down to this: what is it, signaled by Adornos particular brand of pathos, that makes the intimation that if you dont espouse his negative dialectics you fall into affirmative ideology so strong? Affirmation is another key word in Adorno, and somehow a pendant to Vershnung, because it is the Frankfurt Schools word for false and premature reconciliation. 22 It has a practical and a theoretical side, and practice prevails, in accordance with the motto of changing the world rather than interpreting it. In theory, affirmation refers to every discourse, such as positivism, that silences the negative, the dark, the inassimilable, or the contradictory nature of the real. In practice, affirmation designates reconciliation with the world as it is, submission to so-called reality, moral resignation, political defeatism, and approval of the status quo in general. No one with progressive ideasand Id add, no decent intellectualwants to be accused of endorsing such reconciliation. But precisely herein lies the catch-22 that makes Adornos pathos irresistibly communicative: if you are a progressive in practice, you must agree with me in theory, the pathos implies; and if you disagree with me in theory, then you betray progressive politics in practice, and you are a traitor to the cause. Adorno must have had this debate with himself many times and, in my view, he succumbed to its double bind. Hence the irritating fatalism of his all-encompassing (shall I risk the word totalitarian?) reconciliation project. Selfcontradictory as this project is, and ought to be, in order not to be totalitarian, it betrays a self-defeating obsession with the totality. Adorno is never satisfied with a partial or temporary or local reconciliation. Unless the totality is redeemed, redemption is illegitimate, untrue, and fraudulent. Since, however, no one but the most naive optimist will place bets on global redemption, what remains is global despair in the name of global redemption. Again, Dialectics serves the end of reconciliation, and The
260
Thierry de Duve
agony of dialectics is the worlds (my emphasis) agony raised to the level of concept. For the totality should not be redeemed: It lies in the definition of negative dialectics that it will not come to rest in itself, as if it were total. This is its form of hope.23 If despair, then hope; if hope, then despair: opting for the fragment in the name of totality is the only move desperate hope (that oxymoron!) allows. The Schlegel brothers already had a glimpse of this, and Adorno is definitely their heir. How disappointing, in a sense, and yet perfectly explicable it is to realize that Adornos micrological politics perhaps amount to no more than his own redemption from his obsession with the whole: Micrology is the place where metaphysics finds a haven from totality.24 Maybe, maybe not. Certainly, micrology was the wishful solution to Adornos own contradictions. Adorno has, it seems to me, inherited in spite of himself the worst from Hegel: the notion that total, absolute realization of spirit in the actual world accomplishes the ineluctable process of history itself. The fact that he no longer dares to call it progress only adds to the pathos. Philosophers who abide so rigorously by the consequences of their own thinking processes that they systematically think against themselves are undoubtedly courageous, and I know no philosopher who does that more courageously than Adorno. (Bourdieu is also in that category and in his writings, too, the pathos is palpable.)25 When that sort of courage is combined with great intellectual powers, immense erudition, infallible intuition of the issues that count, and keen artistic judgment, it commands the greatest respect and admiration. All this I want to salute in Adorno. I also deeply sympathize with the pain of contradictions lived and thought through that is as endearing in the man as it is frustrating in his writings. But when all is said and done, I must confess that Adorno doesnt do much for me; he rarely helps me think. Neither does the philosophical tradition to which he belongs, starting with the Romantics: the whole string of German poets and philosophers after Kant who led his legacy astray. I
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
261
said earlier that I made my choice between Kant and Hegel long ago (in favor of Kant, it goes without saying), which is roughly to say that I opted for transcendentalism against dialectics. (By transcendentalism I mean criticism in Kants sense. It need not be idealistic; as Adorno surmised, transcendental materialism is perfectly conceivable.26 Let it also be clear that my use of transcendentalism is as opposed as it can be to its usage by Emerson and the American Transcendentalists.27) As for dialectics, whether idealist or materialist, affirmative or negative, it is, in my view, wishful thinking; it articulates theory with practice by way of a vicious circle that wants correct theory to found just practice while just practice proves the theory correct. Worse, and how paradoxically ironic: dialectical thinking wants to make the irreconcilable reconcilable (all the while acknowledging its irreconcilability, the better to prescribe its reconcilability, and so on, in circles), because it refuses to reconcile itself with the irreconcilable. (Notice that reconciliation with the irreconcilable, in other words, with the fact that there are irresolvable contradictions, contains no contradiction.) Hegel refused to bow before the most absolute of all irreconcilabilities, that between the finite and the infinite; in so doing, he refused to reconcile metaphysics with human finitudeprecisely Kants landmark achievement. What Kant established once and for all, and Hegel stubbornly refused, is the possibility of a philosophy radically compatible with modern science, that is, definitively godless. Dialectics is the quixotic refuge of theology, even in Adorno (to say nothing of Walter Benjamin), and, to that extent, it needs the dulcinea of a re-enchanted world to long for, and windmills such as reification to fight against. The superiority of transcendentalism over dialectics is blatant, provided it is not confused with its affirmative derivatives such as logical positivism, based on a very un-Kantian acceptance of the division of labor among the mental faculties. Hegel railed against the nascent positivism of his time, which he accused of ratiocination, that is, of defective thought confined in
262
Thierry de Duve
the narrow limits of the understanding. Transcendentalism in Kants sense is not at all reducible to that sort of affirmative thinking. It does not forbid reason (practical as well as theoretical) to venture beyond the limits of understanding as long as reason knows that there is nothing to know beyond those limits. Kants Ding an sich is and remains the most formidable antidote to the speculative temptation that seized German philosophers and poets beginning with the first reception of the Critique of Judgment, in the 1790s. Far from embodying this profound metaphysical essence mysteriously lodged in the heart of things it is still too often taken to be, the thing-in-itself is a conceit that carries the imperative: Thou shalt not pretend to know the unknowable (reconcile the irreconcilable, synthesize the unsynthesizable, present the unpresentable, and so on). Let the thing-in-itself rest; it is a mere heuristic supposition we finite minds need in order to think properly. Hegel is of course the most monumental of German philosophers to have maniacally refused to let the thing-in-itself rest and to have sought to raise it to the self-consciousness of the thing-for-itself, but he is far from alone. One senses the same panic before Kants epistemological imperative in Heideggers obsession with the ontic-ontological distinction. I wonder, sometimes, why Adorno fell under Hegels spell, he who so cruelly and gaily (no pathos, there) dissected the pretensions of Heideggers jargon of authenticity.28 Perhaps Hegels impressive posterity, in Marx and beyond, prevented Adorno from realizing that his statement Philosophy which once seemed outmoded is now alive because the moment of its realization has been missed29 was better applied to Kant than to Hegel. I am aware of how bluntly I state my position. I make no apologies, except that I humbly admit lacking the intellectual equipment (not to mention the time and patience) needed to back my perhaps outrageous views on dialectics with the proper scholarly work; those views are more a matter of Wahlverwandschaften than of scientificity. Certainly I dont feel alone in the family of anResisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
263
tidialectical thinkers. Minds much greater than minenot least Michel Foucault and Gilles Deleuzebelong to it. As for my declared preference for Kant over Hegel, it goes back a long way, at least to the eighties, to my days at the Collge de philosophie, where I would listen to Jean-Franois Lyotard and Pierre-Jean Labarrire dueling over the timely relevance of both philosophers. As Kants champion, Lyotard won the duel for me, even though my Kant was from the outset quite different from his. In a nutshell, Lyotard, who must be credited with having initiated a postmodern return to Kantactually, to a revamped Kant that would have been unrecognizable to the neo-Kantians of yorefunnels every possible philosophical issue, from aesthetics to politics, through the Analytic of the Sublime.30 My Kant-after-Duchamp approach to aesthetics bypasses the sublime altogether.31 Its reading strategy addresses the Analytic of the Beautiful, mentally replaces every occurrence of beauty with art, and assumes that the sentence This is art is the paradigmatic formula of a modern aesthetic judgment in the truest Kantian sense. I mention this here only because, to an Adornian reader, the Analytic of the Beautiful, and by inference my own conception of art, must appear unbearably affirmative; only the Analytic of the Sublime makes room for negativity and contradiction. To stay with Adorno, I think it needs to be stressed that he held (not surprisingly) a complex and ambiguous position vis--vis the Kantian sublime, which he deemed at once complicit with domination and a protest against it.32 And he knew from experience, as I do also, that under the conditions of the culture industry, the sublime turns to kitsch. He allowed his experience and taste to shape his theory to some extent, as I think one should, in spite of the risks involved. Philippe LacoueLabarthe has reproached Adorno for having missed the properly philosophical sublimity of Schoenbergs Moses and Aaron.33 Perhaps it was Adornos aesthetic distaste for the sublime that made him deaf to it. Whatever the case, I would hope that my own distaste for the sublime has not made me deaf or blind to negativity and
264
Thierry de Duve
contradiction in aesthetic matters. On the contrary, my interpretation of Kant, which I admit often implies reading between the lines and sometimes against the grain, consistently stresses the particular negativity that resides in aesthetic disagreement. I seek to give ugliness and even disgust the voice that academic readings of the Analytic of the Beautiful silence. Critics of Kant who are under the impression that the said Analytic opens onto classical, harmonious, affirmative aesthetics only, never imagine Kant in the midst of an aesthetic quarrel.34 They are, in my opinion, victims of Kants social conformism. In aesthetics as well as in politics, Kant was reluctant to let opposition speak openly and, therefore, minimized the role dissent must have played, even against his will, in his own writings. Hence the polished, too polished, look the Analytic of the Beautiful projects. Beauty occupies center stage while ugliness coyly remains in the shadow, to the extent that for some readers, it is as if negative aesthetic judgments in the realm of beauty were for Kant a contradiction in terms, and thus impossible.35 To witness the birth of an aesthetic of ugliness, some argue, we would have to wait for Karl Rosenkranz, who was seen as a Hegelian and, as such, was supposedly able to grant contradiction a nonformal, concrete role.36 I disagree: there is room for negative aesthetic judgments in Kant, if only because it is all too obvious that without the freedom to say This is ugly, This is beautiful, would not be a judgment at all. But I also have more technical reasons to disagree. As Kant insisted, the pain occasioned by ugliness is not to be confused with the repulsion caused by disgust.37 The argument that has ugliness forbid disinterestedness makes that confusion and fails to see that when something is pronounced ugly, it is so relative to the standard of beauty that the thing in question should have met. The more serious argument that has ugliness contradict the harmonious free play of the faculties suffers from another confusion, that between logical contradiction and real opposition. Isnt it ironic that Hegelians proudly think they are ahead of Kant when they promote preResisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
265
cisely this confusion to the rank of dialectics, whereas, in fact, even the precritical Kant had already set out to undo it?38 In a short essay dated 1763 that has apparently no bearing on aesthetics, Kant speaks of pleasure and displeasurethe very feelings he would later see yielded by beauty and ugliness, respectively not as concepts in logical contradiction to one another, but as opposite sensations susceptible to quantitative measurement on a continuous scale.39 A letter contains both good and bad news; our pleasure in reading the good news is, say, rated 5; and the displeasure in reading the bad news, 3: we are left with 2 units of pleasure. We may smile at the naivet of such protobehaviorist apprehension of feelings; it is not their measurability that matters, it is the fact that Kant proposes an articulation of the positive and the negative that results from an actual opposition of forces distinct from the logical, Aristotelian principle of contradiction. I cannot help but see in Kants proposal an anticipated alternative to dialectics and its confusions. For it does what dialectics does: give oppositional negation an active, productive, political function while avoiding the confusion with linguistic negation dialectics suffers from. Psychologically speaking, pleasure is definitely a positive feeling, Kant notes. Displeasure, he then argues, can be called negative pleasure yet is a positive sensation, in the sense that it is positively a sensation rather than the cancellation of sensation it would be if negative pleasure had been a mere contradiction in terms. And he adds that, similarly, aversion can be called a negative desire, hate a negative love, ugliness a negative beauty, blame a negative praise.40 Though Kant does not adduce the argument of the negative magnitudes in the third Critique, the question of its applicability therein has great consequences for the question of whether or not the Analytic of the Beautiful is affirmative. If the positiveness of negative pleasure is read into the Analytic, as I am convinced is legitimate, then to say that ugliness negates the harmony of the faculties is not enough; ugliness positively generates the conflict of the faculties.41
266
Thierry de Duve
The notion of the harmony of the faculties is introduced in paragraph nine of the Critique of Judgment, perhaps the most obscure and frustrating passage in the Analytic of the Beautiful, inasmuch as Kant promises there the key to the critique of taste and then fails to deliver. Paragraph nine raises the question of whether in the judgment of taste the feeling of pleasure precedes the judging of the object or the latter precedes the former.42 Kant knows that the judging must precede the pleasure, for otherwise we would deal with mere agreeableness in sensation and not with a pure judgment about beauty; but he is unable to demonstrate it, and soon the initial question gets rephrased in terms of alleged differences between pleasures. In order not to be reducible to mere pleasure of the senses, the pleasure yielded by a pure judgment of taste must be of a different kind. Kant then fancies that this pleasure inheres in the state of mind in the free play of the imagination and the understanding (so far as they agree with each other as is requisite for a cognition in general).43 Without addressing here in full the considerable difficulties of paragraph nine, let us ask ourselves how we are to conceive of this free play. And let us formulate the issue in terms that Adorno might endorse: let us consider that rather than expressing natural, innate conditions, the suppositions about the human mind that constitute the transcendental subject transpose social and historically dated ones. Let us envisage the relationship of imagination and understanding as resulting from the division of labortechnical and socialamong the mental faculties, even if this implies anthropomorphizing them. Imagination, one of whose tasks is to unify the raw sense data registered by sensibility into coherent gestalts or images, presents understanding with, say, a rose, and asks: what is this?44 Understanding, one of whose tasks is to subsume images under concepts, answers: a rose. Imagination bows and then asks: what color is it? and understanding, which possesses a conceptual definition of color (for example, wavelength) and also has as its mandate to perform logical operaResisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
267
tions on concepts, answers with the predicate red. Imagination bows again. In all such dialogues, understanding is the master; it knows and gives answers; it is the superior faculty. Like a servant at the masters dinner table, imagination is content with presenting the dishes and begs for understandings approval; it is the lower faculty. There is no more conflict between them than there is between the orders of society: harmony reigns when everybody stays in their assigned places. But now imagination asks understanding whether the rose is beautiful, and understanding is obliged to respond: I dont know; beauty is not a concept, it is a matter of feeling, and I am not technically outfitted to deal with feelings. There are three possible scenarios here: in the first, the rose is neither beautiful nor ugly, and our two faculties split with a shrug of indifference. Understanding goes back to the business he knows (lets gender the faculties, in accordance with the social order of Kants time), and imagination consults with her own servant, sensibility. The latter tells her that her sensors for inner sensations register nothing: either this particular rose leaves her totally cold (indifference) or it triggers as much pleasure as displeasure, and their opposed forces compensate and neutralize each other (equilibrium). In the second scenario, the rose is objectively beautiful,45 and something unusual happens: imagination is not satisfied with understandings avowal of ignorance, and she presses him to try harder. Having received sensibilitys report testifying to an intense pleasure, she wont take I dont know for an answer, and she provokes understanding. She admits that, unlike him, she doesnt master concepts, but she relies on sensibilitys gut feelings to back her claims and to empower her. Understanding is surprised and excited by such effrontery and, although the rules of the game are not his, accepts imaginations challenge to play with her. She, in turn, feels flattered by her masters dismissal of courtly etiquette, and this prompts her to more audacities: she is happy to play a game nobody can win. Though at first he resisted, understanding, too, is now happy to
268
Thierry de Duve
indulge. He challenges imagination to convince him, by the sheer energy of her own conviction, that the rose is beautiful, even though he still has no concept of the beautiful under which to subsume the rose. And so the game goes on, yielding a particularly felicitous harmony between the two partners, a harmony made of libert, galit, fraternit. The passage in The Conflict of the Faculties where Kant rejoices at the enthusiasm of the spectators (not of the actors) of the French Revolution is well known.46 Why do they, aristocrats among them, whose class interest should align them with the Ancien Rgime, embrace the revolution? Noting the fact, Kant sees in it a signnot more than a sign but a sign, neverthelessthat political progress and faith in the moral disposition of the human race are not vain words.47 His attitude vis--vis the mutual excitement that imagination and understanding trigger in each other is exactly of the same order, political implications included. I would not be surprised if the (pre-Terror) events of the revolution, strictly contemporaneous with the writing of the third Critique, proved to have provided Kant with a Leitfaden for his reflections on the free play of the faculties in paragraph nine. The way the Schiller of the Letters shows he has read the third Critique no doubt encourages speculation along such lines.48 In aesthetic experience, and only there, the social hierarchies of the Ancien Rgime cease to rule over the faculties of the mind. Imagination and understanding are able to play with each other freely because they are on equal footing; now that they are free and equal, fraternal love reigns in their midst: such is the harmony that translates as the particular pleasure only beauty yields. Just as Kant has read the enthusiasm of the French Revolutions spectators as a sign of political progress, so he reads the harmony of the faculties in the experience of beauty as a sign, too. A sign of what? Of the universal shareability of the pleasure dispensed by beauty, which is itself a sign. A sign of what? Of the presence in all humans of the faculty of taste, which is also a sign, this time of the presence in them of
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
269
the universally shared faculty of agreeing by dint of feeling, which Kant calls sensus communis. Kants unique discovery, indeed his unsurpassable contribution to aesthetics, is to have understood that, by making positive judgments about beauty, human beings suppose their humanity to reside in their claimed common ability for having feelings in common. Call it universal empathy, if you want. The pleasure beauty yields is not the egotistic pleasure of the senses, it must be the joy one has in sharing ones pleasure with anyone and everyone. Schillers Ode to Joy, put to music by Beethoven in his ninth symphony, exactly transcribes Kants exhilarating discovery of the sensus communis. Or does it? Does it not rathermuch more soberly puttranscribe the Romantic, euphoric moment in the reception history of Kants discovery, a moment that gleefully ignored Kants prudence and skepticism (testified to by the words suppose, claimed, must be, in the previous paragraph)? Adornos reading of Kant definitely belongs to a dysphoric moment in that same historya moment I dont believe we have left or will be leaving any time soon. Not that I see an even darker future than did Adorno; I simply think our historical moment has prepared us to unearth the negativity hidden in Kants text and to bring it to the surface. Not to be inclined to confuse moments in the reception history of philosophical discoveries with dialectical moments in the (Hegelian) history of spirit is an advantage, in this respect. As I gradually realize, Kant gives me the means to accompany Adorno and to accept being led by him while addressing my resistance to his Hegelianism only. The pathos in empathy is a key, provided we use it to open doors other than Adornos psychology or way of thinking. Empathyin Theodor Lipps or Wilhelm Worringers senseis most of the time not understood as the propensity to share in someone elses pleasure. It is the inclination or the willingness to share in someone elses pain. In light of this, Beethovens Ode to Joy sounds utterly idealistic, and Kants sensus communis more than a trifle too affirmative. Not pleasure, so
270
Thierry de Duve
much, but pain, is the sign in aesthetic experience that Kant ought to have been attentive to. I take this to be the gist of Adornos admonition to Kant, which his particular brand of pathos signals over and over again. Pain, not pleasure, is the only sure sign indicating that all human beings must be endowed with sensus communis. When Adornos reading is stripped of the temptation to have Hegel fill in for Kants shortcomings, the theoretical must implied by Kants skepticism (a mssen for theory) comes closer and closer to a practical ought (a sollen for practice). Such transfer is in any case implied by Adornos credo, as it assigns pain the universalizing function pleasure had for Kant. Should one stake ones hope for a reconciled humanity on aesthetic experience, that is, on art and culture, as Adorno definitely did, then one had better invest that hope in universal compassion than in universal joy. Let pathosa pathos that even the radically pathos-alien work is unable to slough offbe the aesthetic bond that unites the human species.49 Let expression in art lend a voice to suffering.50 Indeed, for Adorno, expression is scarcely to be conceived except as the expression of suffering. He even adds that joy has proven inimical to expression, perhaps because it has yet to existwhich gives a measure of his historical pessimism as well as his transcendental optimism.51 Expressionism is one art-historical name (realism is the other) of the moment when the expression of suffering was allowed to negate the idealism of classical aesthetics. And as Adorno knew, both expressionism and realism have always been associated with the controversial, yet in the end positive, assessment of ugliness. It is not certain that Kant would have understood the positiveness of that assessment, but he would have agreed that the feeling ugliness in art stems from is suffering, for it is the feeling ugliness yields. He called it pain or, more timidly, displeasure, but there is no doubt in my mind that he conceived of it not merely as a lack of pleasure (a logical negation), but as an active and positive force of negation making pleasure difficult or impossible. This brings us back to our rose, and to our
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
271
third, not yet envisioned scenario: the rose is objectively ugly.52 Kant does not address the issue of ugliness explicitly in paragraph nine of the Critique of Judgment or anywhere else. But his problem with it is clearly the same as his problem with beauty: in order not to be reducible to mere displeasure of the senses, the pain occasioned by a negative judgment of taste must be of a different kind. There is no reason to believe that Kant went another route than with beauty, so we may surmise that the pain in question also involves imagination and understanding, but this time so far as they do not agree with each other as is requisite for a cognition in general.53 Cognition is antagonized. The technical and social division of labor among the mental faculties remains, but free play is out of the question. Insurrection of the lower faculties is the order of the day. When imagination presents understanding with the rose and asks him if it is ugly, I dont know is understandings reply, for ugliness is no more a concept than beauty, and it is equally a matter of feeling. Here again, imagination wont take I dont know for an answer, but this time she is met with downright rebuttal. Not only has her effrontery not won her understandings sympathy at all, it has succeeded in irritating him considerably. Understanding knows his own rules, and since he is the master, he is willing to abide by his rules but not by someone elsesleast of all by those of a female servant twice ranking lower in the social order! His irritation makes him phrase his response maladroitly: instead of humbly admitting that he is not technically outfitted to deal with feelings, he barks back: Feelings are irrelevant, as far as I (the master) am concerned. This of course infuriates imagination: the message she has received from sensibility spoke of such an intense unpleasantness that, as far as she is concerned, there is no doubt that feelings are relevantand no doubt either that the rose is ugly. Her conviction grows, and so does her revolt: she is no longer asking understanding for confirmation of sensibilitys gut feelings, she wants the master to acknowledge her own in272
Thierry de Duve
tuitive certainty. Understanding is impressed but doesnt budge. Though he wont admit it, he is not indifferent to such convincing display of conviction, but since the only rules he recognizes are the rules of cognition, he mistakes imaginations certainty for some mysterious feminine access to a truth that is refused to him. Now he goes after that truth. He questions imagination; he interrogates her. She is only too glad to oblige him, for she has seen in his demand her opportunity to seize power. Sensing this, and not ready to surrender his towering masters status, understanding freezes into an authoritarian posture. And so on and so forth. The game, or the conflict,goes on without ever resolving in the happiness of both parties, in a bitter stalemate at best. Marx was certainly not as disinterested a spectator as Kant when confronted with the revolutions and counterrevolutions of his time. He was also a lot less conservative. If he had witnessed the quarrel of imagination and understanding over ugliness, he, too, might have read it as a sign and, like Kant with the French Revolution, as a sign of political progressprogress spelled class struggle, though, not disinterestedness. He would have given the conflict of the faculties a reading as positive as Kants reading of their harmony, in spite of the negativity of the feelings involved. And he would have had a good reason for this: when conducted consciously under the direction of the Communist party, class struggle unfolds on behalf of classless society; the proletariat is a social class only as long as its ongoing struggle against the bourgeoisie prevents it from standing for humanity reconciled; the conflict is pursued in the name of the harmony it will eventually bring about; war is waged for the sake of its termination; negativity is legitimated by the ultimately positive, even affirmative, goal to be attained. And so on. Adorno cant afford, wont afford, Marxs optimism. He is writing his Aesthetic Theory with Stalins ghost looking over his shoulder; with the crushed Budapest insurrection in memory; with the Berlin wall facing him; with the knowledge of Marxs utopia having become a totalitarian nightResisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
273
mare; and still more intolerable, with the awareness that there is no more redress for Auschwitz ever to be expected from the self-righteous antifascism stemming from the Eastern bloc than from the amnesia reigning in Wirtschaftswunder West Germany. Historical contradictions have no happy ending in negative dialectics. Yet, as desperate an answer to Marx as it may be, negative dialectics preserve an important aspect of Marxs handling of contradictionsand one, interestingly enough, that does not appear to be dialectical: its in-the-name-of structure. It is in the name of totality that micrology opts for the fragment; in the name of global redemption that global desperation takes over; in the name of truly accomplished reconciliation that momentary reconciliations are denounced as false and premature; in the name of beauty and harmony that ugliness and dissonance were given the leading role in virtually every significant modern art movement (not just in realism and expressionism). Adorno found precious something that the Marxist art theorists who instrumentalized art (Lukcs is Adornos favorite foil) were only too eager to sacrifice: the intuition that the autonomy of truly ambitious art, its radicalism, its abstraction, its so-called formalism, its active deskilling, have a lot to do with this in-the-name-of handling of contradictions. The failure of art for arts sake was not that the artists in that movement were making art in the name of art; it was that they failed to understand that they had to make anti-art in the name of art. (Gautier not getting Manet would be to the point.) The art for arts sake artists conceived of arts autonomy as a closed territory fearfully cleansed of all inner conflict and fenced off from the totality. They did not see, as Adorno did, and how exemplarily, that only the art that willfully lets the dirt and the violence of the totality contaminate its autonomy truly establishes that autonomy. When Adorno writes, For the sake of reconciliation, authentic works must blot out every trace of reconciliation in memory, he is close to Marx.54 He is also closer to Kant than he might think. To resolve contradictions by coping
274
Thierry de Duve
with them instead, in the name of their resolution, is not exclusive to Adornos negative dialectics, or to Marxs dialectical materialism. It is also what dialectics in Kants sensethat is, the resolution of antinomiesdoes. In paragraph fifty-seven of the third Critique, located in the section entitled The Dialectic of the Aesthetic Power of Judgment, the antinomy of taste gets resolved when the concept on which our aesthetic judgments ought to be based, and which is missing, is shown to be nothing but the regulative idea in the name of which each one of our aesthetic judgments speaks: the idea of a supersensible substratum of humanity, where we are to seek the unifying point of all our faculties.55 To anthropomorphize the faculties of the mind when reading Kant, as I did, is not the most orthodox interpretive strategy. Yet it has the useful effect of historicizing and socializing the transcendental subject. Instead of the solipsistic, sovereign entity it is often taken to be, the transcendental subject is better described as a society of faculties analogous to a society of human beings, with its historical existence and its unresolved conflicts.56 (I think Hegel saw this in Kant and used it against him.) The cognitive faculties are the product of the technical and social division of labor; they are gendered; they entertain relationships of production with each other; they can play freely or enter into conflicts with one another; they ought to be living in peace and harmony, and they dont. They dont empiricallythere is enough evidence of thatand they dont transcendentally either. The supersensible substratum where we are to seek the unifying point of all our faculties is an idea, a mere idea. Orthodox, classical, or otherwise affirmative readings of the third Critique possibly including Kants own, inasmuch as he hoped to give the third Critique the level of apodicticity he thought he had given the firsttend to take the unity and the harmony of the subjects faculties for granted. (They do this with a vengeance if they are incorporated in a critique meant to dismiss Kants transcendental subject.) By the same token, they take sensus communis the intersubjecResisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
275
tive extension of the subjects facultiesto be a factual reality: humans are naturally endowed with the mutual empathy that makes them recognize their common humanity in all others. Such orthodox and affirmative readings also focus on beauty and leave the negativity of ugliness aside, or simply expel it from Kants aesthetics. When their biases are corrected, when the issue of ugliness is raised from within the third Critique and allowed to occupy center stage, when suffering, the negative feeling ugliness yields, is assessed positively, when the conflict of the faculties, of which the feeling of ugliness is the sign, is granted a place in aesthetic theory, then the violence reigning among humans comes to the fore and casts doubt on the factual reality of sensus communis; then the harmony of the subjects faculties can no more be taken for granted than harmony among humans. The faculties unity is not given; it may or may not, some day, be the outcome of their reconciliation, but there is no guarantee whatsoever that history is moving that way. Human history is no more teleologically oriented than natural evolutiona salutary antidote to the false hopes of progress as historical determinism, be they Hegelian or Marxist in inspiration. Just as the Enlightenments ideal of emancipation, seen through Kantian eyes, was not a project but rather a maxim,57 so peace among the faculties of the mind is not a goal humanity will achieve when it has grown wiser; it must forever be conceived as nothing more and nothing less than a hic et nunc requirement of reason: a mssen for theory and a sollen for practice. Between Kants time and ours, Adorno implicitly warns us, the cursor has moved a long way in the direction of the sollen, because in the meantime we have been forced to think that sensus communis is definitely not a natural endowment of humankind and therefore must be an idea, a mere regulative idea: we have had to come to terms with the fact that we humans are not graced with the faculty of spontaneously empathizing with the human in us allnot an easy thing to swallow. What demonstrates this lack of empathy to be a fact has a
276
Thierry de Duve
name, and that name is Auschwitz. Kant had left the question of sensus communis open. Rightly or wrongly, Adorno understood that Auschwitz definitively closed it with a negative answer: sensus communis is a chimera; the sad truth is that humans are wolves to one another. In one of the rare passages in the third Critique where Kant allows himself to muse on the future, he asks himself whether there is in fact such a common sense, or whether a yet higher principle of reason only makes it into a regulative principle for us first to produce a common sense in ourselves for higher ends, thus whether taste is an original and natural faculty, or only the idea of one that is yet to be acquired, and he leaves the answer pending.58 My understanding of Adornos famous statement that writing poetry after Auschwitz is barbaric is that he takes it to be a fact that sensus communis is not a fact. He reads the Nazis philosophically, as having experimentally demonstrated that humanity does not and cannot form a community of feelings. The Nazis made one exception to the unity of the human race when they decided to physically eliminate the Jewish People, and in so doing they proved that they, not the Jews, were the true exception. They exempted themselves from having to share in the common definition of what makes humans human, thereby proving that empathy does not extend to the whole of humanity; such is the fact the name Auschwitz stands for. Of course, Adorno doesnt speak in terms of sensus communis. He once again takes the Hegelian road rather than the Kantian and falls prey to its historical determinism. He sees in Auschwitz the intolerable ultimate step in the progress of reification, reached when people are exterminated administratively, not as individuals but as specimens. Auschwitz spells for him the final stage of the dialectic of culture and barbarism. The extent to which he is aware that Auschwitz also spells the final stage of his negative dialectics, the stage where he can no longer escape its philosophical impasse, is hard to tell. But he knows himself to be engulfed in a Hegelian nightmare where the absolute realization
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
277
of spirit has turned into its absolute reification. The passage in Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft (1951) where the ban on poetry after Auschwitz is pronounced is also where this Hegelian nightmare appears. It is worth quoting in full:
The more total society is, the more reified is spirit and the more paradoxical its effort to escape reification on its own. Even the most extreme consciousness of doom threatens to degenerate into idle chatter. Cultural criticism finds itself faced with the final stage of the dialectic of culture and barbarism: to write a poem after Auschwitz is barbaric, and this corrodes even the recognition of why it has become impossible to write poetry today. As long as it remains by itself in self-satisfied contemplation, critical spirit has not yet risen to [the challenge of] absolute reification, which presupposed the progress of spirit as one of its elements and is now preparing to absorb it entirely.59
The last sentence is telling. I had to add the word challenge to convey what Adorno meant, at the cost of suppressing the stunning and no doubt deliberate stylistic effect that produced an unbearable proximity between the evil of absolute reification and the elevated task critical spirit must accomplish so as to be on the level: Der absoluten Verdinglichung ist der kritische Geist nicht gewachsen.60 Such proximity leaves no room for the kind of negation-of-negation-that-denies-its-inevitable-inversion-intopositivity that negative dialectics typically requires. As Lyotard has argued, when Adorno makes of the name Auschwitz a model for negative dialectics (1966) and thus suggests that it puts an end to the affirmative kind only, he creates for himself the philosophical aporia I called a Hegelian nightmare, and which Lyotard pinpointed as the wound of nihilism, not an accidental wound but an absolutely philosophical one.61 Adornos pathos here verges on the sublime: Thought honors itself by defending what is damned as nihilism, he pompously writes at the end of a splendid paragraph where he salutes Beckett for being the only writer to have, in his literary work (Dichtung: poetry in the
278
Thierry de Duve
widest sense), reacted adequately to the situation of the concentration camps.62 I dont know what I admire most in this passage: whether it is the Beckettian somersaultif sublime, then ridiculous; if ridiculous, then sublimewith which Adorno extricates himself from the double bind Lyotard called the rule of immanent derivation that defines negative dialectics: if p, then non-p; if non-p, then p;63 or whether it is his offhand recognition that poetry after Auschwitz is possible, after all. He has admitted a few pages before and, not by chance, a paragraph or so after having mentioned Becketts Endgame for the first time, that it may have been wrong to say that after Auschwitz you could no longer write poems.64 But he has retracted a few pages down the road: Auschwitz demonstrated irrefutably that culture had failed. And, a little further: All post-Auschwitz culture, including its urgent critique, is garbage.65 Obviously, he is utterly reluctant to amend his outrageous claim of fifteen years earlier, even as he is resting his case on the work of the one great writer who he admits has proved him wrong. His embarrassment is enough of an indication, I think, that what is at stake is not whether poetry, the other arts, and culture at large have become barbaric after the unnamable. Adorno knows that its the other way round: Auschwitz is one name of the unnamable because it names that in the name of which it is impossible, without being barbaric, to write poetry, to make art, or otherwise to speak publicly.66 Yet he doesnt reach for the in-the-name-of argument. He focuses on the ultimate dialectical reversal that makes it a duty for poetry, or for art, or for critical spirit, to rise to the level of obscenity of the unnamablewitness, in Endgame, the abjection of Hamms parents having to live in garbage cans67and he leaves unattended the nondialectical reversal that justifies the obscenity in question: that poetry be written, or art be made, in the name of Auschwitz never again. What this never again formulates is not dialectical: a negation it is, but a negation that doesnt pair up with what it negates. Even negative dialectical fusion of the
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
279
contraries (whatever that means) is here impossible: the abominable event happened; the command never again forbids, but is impotent to prevent, its happening again. And it is a positive command, in spite of its negative content, which is why it affirms Auschwitz in a transhistorical, essentially philosophical way. As an imperative, it makes of Auschwitz a factin Kants Latinized German, Faktum the fact that sensus communis is not a fact. There is more than a play on words, here. I think that Adorno has had a keen intuition of this fact (italicized) but that he failed to theorize adequately its difference from a fact (roman), in the empirical sense. Should we succeed in theorizing that difference, we might find the transcendentalists way out of the dialecticians Hegelian nightmare. Or, to borrow Lyotards words: we might avoid the wound of nihilism, possibly the deepest and most hidden source of Adornos pathos. Its worth trying. Kants resorting to Latin is often indicative of some paradoxical play with usual terms. Just as sensus communis doesnt refer to common sense in the commonsensical senseindeed, it means common sentiment, not common understandingso Kants usage of Faktum instead of Fakt or Tatsache indicates that he intends it to mean something different from fact, in the factual, demonstrable sense. The word Faktum appears in the Critique of Practical Reason, where it refers to moral conscience and to nothing else.68 It is a fact,an undeniable, immediately intuitive though indemonstrable fact, that moral law is given to us, from no one knows where, and this fact is enough to call us to our supersensible destiny, which is to realize the highest good in the sensible world. Is this task within our reach, given that there are few illusions to be entertained regarding humankinds morality? Is implementation of morally good deeds in the sensible world even possible, given that free moral action, as such, produces no tangible proof of its efficiency? Ever the pessimist, Kant writes: We are fortunate, if only we can be sufficiently assured that there is no proof of its impossibility.69 Still, is there something that mediates between
280
Thierry de Duve
the arid sphere of morality, where only the categorical imperative rules, and the earthly sphere where we finite beings made of flesh and bloodas much as we yearn and may strive for the highest goodare prone to letting the penchants of our fallible human nature dictate our behavior? In less dramatic and more philosophical terms: is there a mediating ground between ethical conduct (the domain of the second Critique) and the world ruled by the laws of natural sciences (the domain of the first) to give us hope that the realization of the highest good in the sensible world is at least not impossible? Even though no feelings are admitted as the ground of moral conduct except respect, feelings such as pleasure and happiness definitely partake in the highest good and are morally compatible with it. Given that feelings can on the other hand be accounted for by psychology, physiology, and the natural sciences in general, couldnt the sphere of feelings, if not directly then at least analogically, provide this mediating ground? This becomes the great question of the Critique of Judgment, with the realm of aesthetic experience standing as the paradigm for the sphere of feelings at large. Kant reads the call on universal agreement issued by every judgment of taste as the sign that we presuppose in others the same faculty of agreeing by dint of feeling that we sense in ourselves. The issue now is whether that facultycall it in Kants Latin sensus communis or, in plain English, universally shared empathy for our fellow menis our natural endowment, or not; whether or not it exists, in fact (roman). The Critique of Judgment leaves the issue open. To quote Kant again: Whether there is in fact such a common sense or whether [it is] only [an] idea that is yet to be acquired , this we would not and cannot yet investigate here.70 It is possible to read the whole Critique of the Teleological Judgment as the investigation Kant postponed in the just quoted paragraph twenty-two, but the issue doesnt get settled there either. Sensus communis is definitely an idea, but whether it is also a natural propensity with which we come equippedsomething like an instinctKant doesnt know.
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
281
We ought to know, I understand Adorno to reply: Auschwitz reveals the fact (roman) that we are not so equipped. It is my contention that fact, here, should have been italicized, in accordance with Kants Faktum. Why the cold showerof our not being equipped with sensus communis had to take the ultraviolent form of Auschwitz is the incomprehensible scandal that I think drove Adorno (and Horkheimer) to conceive the extreme, and in my view fundamentally flawed, theory that totalitarianism, and German fascism in particular, was the logical outcome of Kants rationalism. In the chapter of Dialectic of Enlightenment entitled Juliette or Enlightenment and Morality, the caricaturing of Kant as obsessively systematic and prototypically bourgeois, and the reduction of science to the most mindless positivism, are so gross that they dont even deserve comment. On the other hand, the pairing of Kant with the marquis de Sade in that same chapter, although improperly theorized,71 is the most insightful acknowledgment I know of that Auschwitz names the factin Kants sense of Faktum that sensus communis is not a fact in the empirical, verifiable sense. Unfortunately, Horkheimer and Adorno misrepresent Kants Faktum and, therefore, mistake fact for fact:
Kant, to be sure, had so purified the moral law within the self of any heteronymous belief that respect, despite his assurances, could be no more than a psychological fact of nature, as the starry sky above the self was a physical one. A fact of reason, he called it.72
The authors conflation of a fact of reason with a fact of naturea heresy for Kant, as it should be for anyoneis crucial to the poetry-after-Auschwitz issue and beyond, to the question of whether a Kantian, more particularly, the Kant-after-Duchamp, approach to aesthetics, is able to respond to a negativity of the magnitude of Auschwitz without simply putting a ban on all art practice. Does Auschwitz name a fact of reason or a fact of nature?
282
Thierry de Duve
What is intuitively right in Horkheimers and Adornos take on the issue is that the answer is both. What is wrong is that this is no license to conflate and confound the two, not even dialectically. The fact of nature (in Kants sense of nature) is that Auschwitz happened; the gas chambers were real. The fact of reason is that Auschwitz ought never have happened. The moral law, Kants Faktum, should never have allowed it to happen, which is why the moral law now reads: Auschwitz never again. No new law is thereby uttered: Auschwitz never again is the law, Kants one and only categorical imperative, historicized under its new, postShoah name. By conflating Auschwitz as a fact of nature (that is, of history) and Auschwitz as negatively naming the moral law, Horkheimer and Adorno feign to understand Kant as upholding the theory that the moral law is deducible from the laws of nature. (I cant imagine this to be feasible without a measure of disingenuousness.)73 They might have been better (or more honestly) inspired to keep in mind the as ifreasoning with which Kant articulated the relation between the moral law and the laws of nature, for example, in the second formulation of the categorical imperative:
Ask yourself whether, if the action you propose were to take place by a law of nature, of which you were yourself a part, you could indeed regard it as possible for your will.74
This formulation gives us the exact understanding of the relation Kants Faktum has vis--vis the notion of fact in the empirical sense. Kant proposes to the hesitant ethical subject a simple test: if the action you project to accomplish were to be the outcome of a natural law (such as Newtons law of universal gravity, always on Kants mind when he thinks of nature), rather than the result of your free will, would you still approve of it? If the answer is no, then your action is immoral. Transposed to the issue of whether sensus communis is a fact of nature, the test yields a theoretical lesson. If the relationships you have with other human beings
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
283
were to obey your natural instincts and nothing else, could you still call them ethical? The answer would be yes if you were sure that all your instincts are charitable, good, and respectful of othersquite an improbable event. And it would definitely be no if you were sure that all your sentiments vis--vis others are like those of the wolf for the lamb, also an unlikely event if, like the rest of us, you have affectionate feelings at least for the ones close to you. The practical maxim Kant would draw from this test is: dont trust your feelings in ethical matters; they are sometimes good and sometimes bad, but they offer no a priori certainty because they are not universalizable; let the cold and impartial inner voice of the categorical imperative dictate your conduct. Never mind if we dont have a superego that weighs every single ethical action against the inevitability of the laws of nature; we dont need to espouse Kants moral rigor to grasp the implications the tests theoretical lesson has in store for the Critique of Judgment: if it were an established fact of nature that all of us humans are endowed with sensus communis, then our good feelingsI mean, the feelings that make us feel good, those we revel in when we are happy, those signaled to us by the free play of our faculties in aesthetic pleasure, and perhaps those we spontaneously share with our loved oneswould be universalizable, in fact. This in turn means that we would realize the highest good in the sensible world simply by following our natural inclinations. And if by any chance it were an established fact of nature that we humans are not equipped with sensus communis, then none of our good, pleasurable feelings would be universalizable. Egotism, jouissance, and self-interestHorkheimer and Adorno speak of self-preservationwould be ruling all human relations. The chances are that the only universalizable feelings would be negative feelings: fear and distrust of others, anger and aggressiveness, a sense of generalized competition that sees in anyone a potential enemy, a paranoid defense of ones identity, all sorts of ideologically mo-
284
Thierry de Duve
tivated hatreds and hate-fueled ideologies. The aesthetic culture produced by a humanity really (that is, in fact) driven by such feelings would be a Babel of stolen pleasures and a sea of grievances among competing rackets, for whom destroying the art and culture of the other is more vital than producing an art and culture of ones owna fairly good definition of barbarism. Notwithstanding Adornos constant insistence that Dialectic of Enlightenment was the joint work of Horkheimer and myself, to the extent that every sentence belongs to us both, this was hardly the case.75 Evidence from the posthumous papers of both co-authors, as well as the testimonies of Gretel Adorno, Jrgen Habermas, and Rolf Tiedemann indicate that Horkheimer wrote most, if not all, of the chapter I am discussing here, the Sade chapter, as Habermas calls it.76 If this is true, then it was Horkheimers insight to bring in Sade, and Adorno must have applauded; he might even have pardoned Horkheimer for crassly oversimplifying and distorting Kant in exchange for a peek into the Philosophy in the Bedroom that gave him an anticipated glimpse into his own future negative dialectics. As is shown by the record of their discussions in the immediate postwar years, when they were finalizing the manuscript and projecting a second volume on dialectics, Adorno already had a much darker vision of enlightened rationalism than did Horkheimer. Reason is its own sickness, he replied to his colleague, when the latter called on what remained of healthy reason in his effort to rescue the Enlightenment.77 The barbarism of all post-Auschwitz culture was already on Adornos mind, and it was the barbarism of the kind of humanity driven by mutual hate I described earlier, the barbarism of a world where we would be certain, apodictically certain, that humanity is not endowed with sensus communis. It is definitely to Horkheimers credit to have intuited that the world of Sade, or of the sadist, is, or rather ought to be, such a world. But Horkheimer made the mistake of confusing is with ought (fact
285
with fact, again), and so he congratulated Sadewhom he saluted as the most intransigent critic of Kant, while casting the latter as the epitome of the bourgeois thinkerfor having unveiled selfpreservation and material interest as the real founding ground of the respect without which civilization cannot exist.78 And he missed the true import of Sades Philosophy in the Bedroom totally. For a philosophy it is: not an empirical rebuttal of Kants morals or a genealogy la Nietzsche, but a thought experiment in inverted Kantianism, perversely but rigorously faithful to the original. How much more to the point than Horkheimers pitting of Sade against Kant is Lacans pairing of Kant with Sade:
Philosophy in the Bedroom came eight years after the Critique of Practical Reason. If, after showing that the former is consistent with the latter, I can demonstrate that the former completes the latter, I shall be able to claim that it yields the truth of the Critique.79
Alas, the sadist complains, the world where only egotism and jouissance rule is not a fact. It is our moral task to bring it to existence: Yet another effort, Frenchmen. Still too much benevolence, compassion, and weakness of heart render ethical relations impure. Let us sweep all that sentimentality away, espouse Kants rigor, and clear the air for the cold and impartial inner voice. And to make sure that this task, unlike the achievement of the highest good in the sensible world, is not impossible, let us invert Kants categorical imperative. Instead of calling it a duty for everyone never to make use of anyone else as a means to an end, let us call it a right for everyone always to use and abuse anyone else as a means to ones own ends, no matter how wicked.80 Let us create a world where delight in evil is the highest good. Lacan writes:
If one eliminates from morality every element of sentiment, if one removes or invalidates all guidance to be found in sentiment, then in the final analysis the Sadian world is conceivableeven if it is its inversion, its caricatureas one of
286
Thierry de Duve
the possible forms of the world governed by a radical ethics, by the Kantian ethics as elaborated in 1788.81
Kants test has shown that whether sensus communis exists or not is undecidable, and Sade apparently agrees. He also seems to have seen through the lines of the not yet written third Critique something Kant himself was reluctant to see: that, if it was a theoretical necessity to postulate that sensus communis exists, it was also a quasi-moral obligation to make that postulate; and that the less plausible the postulates factual reality was, the more the cursor of the quasi-moral obligation had to move in the direction of the moral tout court. Sades thought experiment in inverted Kantianism pushes the cursor all the way in the direction of the moralof the morally evil, that is. The sadist calls it a moral obligation to make the theoretical postulate that sensus communis does not exist, and follows through with the corresponding practical maxim: one ought to make sure that it does not exist; one ought to suppress all love, compassion, and sympathyall shareable feelingsfrom ones conduct. It is left to us, readers of Sade, to redress the inverted Kantianism where it must be redressed: only in the practical maxim. The theoretical postulate remains the Sadian one: that sensus communis does not exist. This is how I read Horkheimers insight in the Sade chapter of Dialectic of Enlightenment. It is as much an insight into the deepest historical sources of Adornos pathos as it is into the meaning of the Philosophy in the Bedroom. Horkheimerand Adorno with him, for, after all, he cosigned the textare wrong when they see in Sade a dialectical critic of Kant: the inversion Sade imprints on Kant is not dialectical. But they are right on target when they virtually suggest that Sade has written poetry after Auschwitz long before Auschwitz. Through the divin marquis, literature has risen to the level of obscenity of the unnamable. Perhaps Sade did worse, too, and, unlike Beckett, could afford to speak in the name of the unnamable without being barbaric because, even in those
287
days of Terror, the unnamable was still unthinkable. It was left to Pier Paolo Pasolinis film Sal, or the 120 Days of Sodom to unpack the full sadistic barbarism of the unthinkable having become a fact and to redress the in-the-name-of procedure. What kind of aesthetic theory the post-Auschwitz world requires will of course not be settled today. Adorno raised the question for everyone working in the field, and though he has not made our task easier, we are in his debt. The work that remains to be done is enormous. I hope to have convinced at least a fraction of my readers that looking toward Kant for help is far from absurd or obsolete, and less aporetic than turning to Hegel. To bring this essay to a close, I want to return to the quotation with which I began:
Works of art appear as in-the-world; their medium is not pure spirit existing for itself, but the spirit that retreats into worldly existence and, by the force of such movement, lays a claim on the unity of what is separated. This contradiction forces works of art to make us forget that they are made: the claim their existence-in-the-world stakes, and hence the claim that existence itself is meaningful, is the more convincing, the less something in them warns us that they have been fabricated, that they owe their existence to spirit as something external to themselves. Art that is no longer able to achieve this deception with good conscienceindeed its very principlehas dissolved the only element in which it can realize itself.82
What to do with the ominous last sentence that threatens art in its very existence? Should there be room in a post-Auschwitz aesthetic theory for art that is no longer able to achieve this deception with good conscience? Should the theory then accommodate art that has lost its very principleart that is only nominally art but lacks the conviction? Or is art worthy of the name still obliged to achieve this deception, albeit with bad conscience? If the former, why hold on to the word art? If
288
Thierry de Duve
the latter, how to escape the pathos of repressed guilt? In reading that passage when I embarked on the writing of this paper, I wondered why Adorno had inserted the typically Kantian view that art should look like nature while we know that it is art in an otherwise typically Hegelian argument, and I saw in this a symptom of his struggle with both philosophers. Now I realize that in selecting that passage, I must have had an inkling of a more profound question: Why was Adorno essentially right when he made the view that art should appear as-if-unmade the touchstone of the judgment that decides whether something deserves to be called art or not? The long answer would involve making deep excursions into transcendental materialism as the result of the modern disenchantment of the world and explaining why the Romantic path that led from Kant to Hegel via Schelling missed it. The place to start would be Kants theory of genius and its non-Romantic update.83 The short answer is this: Kants God died at Auschwitz for the third time. The God of the first Critique died right there, in the fourth antinomy. Modern biology, Darwinism, cybernetics, killed the God of the third Critique. The God who gets annihilated at Auschwitz is the God of the second Critique, God as postulate of practical reason. As I said earlier: not an easy thing to swallow, even a century after Nietzsche. At stake is an issue as old or, I should say, as young as modernity (what, indeed, are two hundred years compared with the one hundred thousand that separate us from the first tombs containing traces of red ochre, possibly the most ancient manifestation of aesthetic and religious behavior?): Is a truly secular art possible? Will art survive the demise of religion? Adorno never tackled the question head-on because he shared with his friend Benjamin the modernist conviction that politics have displaced religion once and for allnot their best insight in view of the overwhelming confusion of politics and religion that has recently threatened us from all sides. Todays doxa notwithstanding, I think that arts autonomy from religionand whether it is thinkable, whether it is viable at all
Resisting Adorno, Revamping Kant
289
was Adornos unacknowledged concern when he doubted the right of art to exist.84 If I may say so, my Kant-after-Duchamp approach to the aesthetic theory of art is an attempt to construct that autonomy intellectually. It rests on the conviction that the unsurpassable lesson Kant had learned from his philosophical investigation of the beautiful in nature has been transferred to the domain of art. This artifact is art replacing This fruit of nature is beautiful as the canonical utterance of a pure aesthetic judgment expresses this transfer.85 Until recently, I was content with attributing the need of that transfer to the death of the God of the first and third Critiques. In an essay published a few years ago, paraphrasing Kants double reflexive loopNature was beautiful, if at the same time it looked like art; and art can only be called beautiful if we are aware that it is art and yet it looks to us like nature86 I wrote:
In simple words: beauty in nature arises when we look at nature as if it were God-made, and beauty in art arises when we look at artifacts as if nobody had made them. No matter what creationists and religious fundamentalists believe, it is no longer possible to look at nature as if it were God-made. The question is whether we can still look at man-made things as though nobody had made them. The answer is not: yes, we can; it is: yes, we must. A strange must on the verge of ought, as if poised between mssen and sollen. A quasi-ethical obligation to endow all humans with the faculty of agreeing, that overshadows the theoretical necessity to endow all humans with the faculty of taste. 87
Barack Obama was to me an unknown name then. I find my yes we can/yes we must quip pleasantly uncanny in view of his election and its economic context, but thats an aside. I was thinking ahead of myself, then, not fully realizing, as I do better today, that the reason serious art is invested with unprecedented ethical gravity goes far beyond the intellectual solitude the modern disenchantment of the world has thrown us into. It has ev290
Thierry de Duve
erything to do with the monsters the dreadful twentieth century has engendered and the moral abandonment that has ensued. May the transcendentalist live and think through the contradictions of our time with less pain than the dialectician and face the future with more energetic optimism. But forget that the cursor has definitely moved all the way into the direction of the sollen he may not.
291
Endnotes
1
Theodor W. Adorno, In Search of Wagner, trans. Rodney Livingstone (London, 1991), p. 83. Ibid., pp. 82 and 83. Ibid. Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. Robert Hullot-Kentor (Minneapolis, 1997), p. 1. Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York, 1997), pp. 1718. Theodor W. Adorno, Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged Life, trans. E. F. N. Jephcott (London, 1974), p. 110. Here is the German original: Die Kunstwerke verdanken ihr Dasein der gesellschaftlichen Arbeitsteilung, der Trennung geistiger und krperlicher Arbeit. Dabei jedoch treten sie selbst als Dasein auf; ihr Medium ist nicht der reine, fr sich seiende Geist, sondern der, welcher in die Existenz sich zurckbegibt und kraft solcher Bewegung das Getrennte als vereint behauptet. Dieser Widerspruch zwingt die Kunstwerke dazu, vergessen zu lassen, da sie gemacht sind: der Anspruch ihres Dasein, und damit der von Dasein selber als eines Sinnvollen, gert um so berzeugender, je weniger mehr in ihnen daran mahnt, da sie hervorgebracht wurden, da sie dem Geist als einem ihnen selber uerlichen sich verdanken. Kunst, welche nicht mehr das gute Gewissen hat zu solchem Trug, ihrem eigenen Prinzip, hat bereits das Element aufgelst, in dem einzig sie sich realisieren kann; Theodor W. Adorno, Versuch ber Wagner (Berlin, 1952), p. 104. I am grateful to Christian Katti for his help with the translation of this and other quotations, as well as for his precious advice with regard to Adorno and the Adorno literature. Whether or not to leave the word Dasein untranslated was a question, because it is unclear from the context whether Adorno borrowed it from Heidegger or from Hegel. Versuch ber Wagner precedes Jargon der Eigentlichkeit by twelve years, so we cannot expect Adorno to have yet articulated the virulent critique of Heidegger the later book contains. Precisely for this reason, I preferred to forge the not-quite-Heideggerian expression existence-in-the-world to translate Dasein in this paragraph because I think that this is literally what Adorno meant. (Unless otherwise noted, all translations are my own.) Immanuel Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews (Cambridge, 2000), p.185. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 6 (translation modified).
2 3 4
9 10
292
Thierry de Duve
11
Commenting on Adornos models in the last part of Negative Dialectics, Lyotard writes: The idea of the model corresponds to this reversal in the destiny of dialectics: the model is the name for a kind of para-experience, where dialectics would encounter a non-negatable negative, and would abide in the impossibility of redoubling that negative into a result; Jean-Franois Lyotard, The Differend, trans. Georges Van Den Abbeele (Minneapolis, 1989), p. 88. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, p. 32.
12 13 14
Adorno, Negative Dialectics, pp. 26165. M ax Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford, CA, 2002), p. 98. Kants description of schematism is to be found in the Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood (Cambridge, 1998), p. 273.
15
16
Natural beauty replaces art in Kants case, but Adorno most often ignores the substitution, one sign among many that he has a Hegelian reading of Kant.
17
18 19
Ibid., p. 260 (translation modified). S ee Theodor W. Adorno, Ist die Kunst heiter? in Versuch das Endspiel zu verstehen (Frankfurt, 1972), p. 14.
20
21
I borrow the expression damaged life (beschdigtes Leben) from the subtitle of Minima Moralia: Reflections from Damaged Life. W ithin the Frankfurt School, the German word Affirmation, much rarer than the customary Bejahung, is used mostly by Adorno and Herbert Marcuse. The latter has added psychosexual connotations (false happiness through repressive desublimation) to the mainly political ones the word conveyed for Adorno.
22
23
24 25
T he pathos is especially palpable in Homo Academicus (Paris, 1984), where Pierre Bourdieu closely observed the social group in which he intimately took part, and went so far as to assumenot without pain or couragethe personal consequences of the demystification of the consensus apparently projected by academics as a class. S ee my essay, Some Philosophical Implications of Eric Camerons Routine Extremism, forthcoming.
26
293
27
A lthough Emerson claimed Kantian filiation for his brand of transcendentalism, it is as if he picked the wrong Immanuel. His definition of transcendentalism as the Saturnalia or excess of Faith, his opinion that the Transcendentalist believes in miracles and in ecstasy, and his claim that Nature is transcendental owe more to Swedenborg than to Kant. See Ralph Waldo Emerson, The Transcendentalist (1842), in Essays and Lectures (New York, 1983), pp. 196 and 198. T heodor W. Adorno, The Jargon of Authenticity, trans. Knut Tarnowski and Frederic Will (London, 1973).
28
29
Quoted without reference by Trent Schroyer in his foreword to ibid., p. vii. S ee, among other texts, Jean-Franois Lyotard, Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime, trans. Elizabeth Rottenberg (Stanford, CA, 1994).
30
31
See my book, Kant after Duchamp (Cambridge, MA, 1996). Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, pp. 19699.
32 33
P hilippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Musica ficta (Figures de Wagner) (Paris, 1991), pp. 23842. W hen I teach aesthetics, I regularly present Kant as witnessing an aesthetic quarrel (A pretending that this rose is beautiful, B that it is ugly; or A pretending that this object is art, B that it is not) into which he is dragged by virtue of the fact that, seeing the rose or the object, he inevitably forms a judgment himself. I did this once in writing, too. See my essay, Do Artists Speak on Behalf of All of Us? in Diarmuid Costello and Dominic Willsdon, eds., The Life and Death of Images: Ethics and Aesthetics (London, 2008), pp. 13956.
34
35
S ee, for example, Paul Guyer, Kant on the Purity of the Ugly, in Values of Beauty: Historical Essays in Aesthetics (Cambridge, 2005), pp. 14162; Reinhard Brandt, Zur Logik des sthetischen Urteils, in Herman Parret, ed., Kants sthetik/Kants Aesthetics/Lesthtique de Kant (Berlin, 1998), pp. 22945; Daniel Dumouchel, La laideur introuvableLes multiples visages du dplaisir, in Christophe Bouton, Fabienne Brugre, and Claudie Lavaud, eds., Lanne 1790KantCritique de la facult de jugerBeaut, vie, libert (Paris, 2008), pp. 1327; Herman Parret, The Ugly as the Beyond of the Sublime, in Christian Madelein, Jan Pieters, and Bart Vandenabeele, eds., Histories of the Sublime (Brussels, 2005), pp. 5968. For an interesting defense of the possibility of an aesthetics of ugliness in Kant, see: Christian Strub, Das Hssliche und die Kritik der sthetischen Urteilskraft. berlegungen zu einer systematischen Lcke, Kantstudien 80 (1989): pp. 41646. K arl Rosenkranz, Aesthetik des Hlichen (1853), ed. Walther Gose and Walter Sachs (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, 1968). As a Hegelian, however, Rosenkranz is utterly unconvincing. His book is not much more than a
36
294
Thierry de Duve
Only one kind of ugliness cannot be represented in a way adequate to nature without destroying all aesthetic satisfaction, hence beauty in art, namely, that which arouses loathing; Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, p. 190. Let it be said in passing that the Kant-after-Duchamp approach amends Kant so as to admit loathing or disgust into the list of legitimate aesthetic feelings. Nothing essential in Kants contribution to aesthetics is thereby put into question, even though disinterestedness gets problematized and receives a new reading. H egel showed the way by assimilating actual opposition (light vs. darkness, for example) to reflective determination (light containing its negation as part of its truth). See the three Remarks on Contradiction in G. W. F. Hegel, Science of Logic, trans. A. V. Miller (Amherst, NY, 1969), pp. 435-43.
38
39
I mmanuel Kant, Attempt to Introduce the Concept of Negative Magnitudes into Philosophy (1763), in Theoretical Philosophy, 17551770, trans. David Walford in collaboration with Ralph Meerbote (Cambridge, 1992), pp. 20541. See p. 219 in particular. Ibid., p. 221.
40 41
T he pun is not irrelevant. Of course, when Kant wrote The Conflict of the Faculties (Der Streit der Fakultten, 1798), the conflict in question involved the faculties in the sense of the schools composing the Prussian University, not in the sense of the faculties of the mind (Vermgen). Yet the idea that the conflict among the former might be the institutional transposition of a conflict among the latter (both are facultates, in Latin) must have occurred to Kant and amused him. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, p. 102.
42 43
Ibid., p. 103. I magination, in Kants sense, has both the productive function our present-day usage of the word carries and the receptive function we would assign to perception. Sensibility takes care of what we would call sensations, i.e., raw sense data not yet organized into percepts.
44
45
O f course, the rose is not objectively beautiful the way it is objectively red. The question of the objectivity of aesthetic judgment is too complex to be dealt with here. Let me simply state that, on this point, I almost completely adhere to what Adorno has to say: The strongest buttress of subjective aesthetics, the concept of aesthetic feeling, derives from objectivity, not the reverse. Aesthetic feeling says that something is thus; Kant would have attributed such aesthetic feeling, as taste, exclusively to one who was capable of discriminating in the object; Aesthetic Theory, p. 164 (translation slightly modified). I disagree only with the last
295
sentence: to discriminate among discriminating and nondiscriminating people in matters of taste was not Kants business as a philosopher. Whether he thought he could do this in real life depends on how much confidence he had in his own taste. Needless to say, the matter is speculative.
46
I mmanuel Kant, The Conflict of the Faculties (1798), trans. Mary J. Gregor and Robert Anchor, in Religion and Rational Theology, ed. Allen W. Wood and George Di Giovanni (Cambridge, 1996), pp. 3013. See Jean-Franois Lyotard, Le Diffrend et le signe de lhistoire, Change International 1 (Fall 1983): pp. 11419.
47
Kant, The Conflict of the Faculties, p. 302. S ee Friedrich Schiller, On the Aesthetic Education of Man, in a Series of Letters (1794), trans. Reginald Snell (New Haven, 1954).
48
49
50 51
A dorno, Aesthetic Theory, p. 110. Note Adornos strange turn of words in the already quoted sentence: It would be preferable that in some better times art vanish altogether than that it forget the suffering that is its expression and in which form finds its substance (p. 260, translation modified). He does not speak of suffering as a content that art expresses but rather of the suffering that is arts expression; neither does he speak of suffering finding its form in works of art, but of form finding its substance in the suffering. In the next sentence, he adds: This suffering is the humane content [der humane Gehalt, not Inhalt] that unfreedom counterfeits as positivity (ibid.). O f course, the rose is no more objectively ugly than it is objectively beautiful. (See note 45.)
52
53
Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, p. 103. (See note 43.) Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, p. 234.
54 55
Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, p. 217. A similar, less anthropomorphic and perhaps less naive description one that imparts a linguistic turn to Kants notoriously language-blind philosophycan be found in Lyotards notion of the archipelago of phrase regimens. See The Differend, passim.
56
57
S ee the last chapter of my book, Kant after Duchamp: Archaeology of Practical Modernism. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, p. 124.
58 59
T heodor W. Adorno, Cultural Criticism and Society, in Prisms, trans. Samuel and Shierry Weber (London, 1967), p. 34. I modified the
296
Thierry de Duve
translation on some crucial points where Adornos Hegelian turn of mind was lost. Compare with the German: Je totaler die Gesellschaft, um so verdinglichter auch der Geist und um so paradoxer sein Beginnen, der Verdinglichung aus eigenem sich zu entwinden. Noch das aerste Bewutsein vom Verhngnis droht zum Geschwtz zu entarten. Kulturkritik findet sich der letzten Stufe der Dialektik von Kultur und Barbarei gegenber: nach Auschwitz ein Gedicht zu schreiben, ist barbarisch, und das frit auch die Erkenntnis an, die ausspricht, warum es unmglich ward, heute Gedichte zu schreiben. Der absoluten Verdinglichung, die den Fortschritt des Geistes als eines ihrer Elemente voraussetzte und die ihn heute gnzlich aufzusaugen sich anschickt, ist der kritische Geist nicht gewachsen, so lange er bei sich bleibt in selbstgengsamer Kontemplation; Theodor W. Adorno, Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft, in Rolf Tiedemann, ed., Prismen, Gesammelte Schriften (Frankfurt, 1977), 10.1: p. 30.
60
L iterally: To absolute reification, critical spirit has not grown. The translators of Prisms, Sam and Shierry Weber, have had recourse to the same expedient as I: they slipped in the word challenge. In addition, they split Adornos long sentence in two: Absolute reification, which presupposed intellectual progress as one of its elements, is now preparing to absorb the mind entirely. Critical intelligence cannot be equal to this challenge as long as it confines itself to self-satisfied contemplation; Prisms, p. 34.
61
J ean-Franois Lyotard, Discussions, ou: phraser aprs Auschwitz, in Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe and Jean-Luc Nancy, eds., Les fins de lhomme, partir du travail de Jacques Derrida (Paris, 1981), pp. 289 and 290. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 381.
62 63
Lyotard, Discussions, ou: phraser aprs Auschwitz, p. 291. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, p. 362.
64 65
Ibid., pp. 366 and 367. A uschwitz is not the only name of the unnamable: Treblinka or Sobibor stand for the same fact.
66
67
T he just-quoted All post-Auschwitz culture, including its urgent critique, is garbage is dialectically echoed in the following, from Adornos essay on Endgame: Becketts garbage cans are emblems of the culture that was reconstructed after Auschwitz; Versuch das Endspiel zu verstehen, p. 201. I mmanuel Kant, Critique of Practical Reason, in Practical Philosophy, trans. Mary J. Gregor (Cambridge, 1996), pp. 17377. The Cambridge edition does not underline the Latin subtext in Faktum, which it translates as fact, but J. Gibelins French translation does. On its first occurrence, in the first sentence of the Deduction of the Principles of Pure Practical
68
297
Reason, the translator uses the French fait followed by the Latin factum in parentheses; Critique de la raison pratique (Paris, 1974), p. 55.
69 70
K ant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, p. 124. I allowed myself to compress the sentence somewhat because it is clear that here, as elsewhere (but not everywhere), Kant considers taste and sensus communis as one and the same faculty. Kants German for in fact is in der Tat (no trace of Faktum, here).
71
T he authors see Sade the way they see Nietzsche (in On the Genealogy of Morals): as having uttered the most intransigent critique of Kants Critique of Practical Reason, as having unearthed the natural principle (self-conservation) behind Kants lofty moralism, and as having revealed the true nature of the bourgeois subject emancipated by the Enlightenment. I shall seek another pairing of Kant with Sade a little further on, one that I think is much more to the point. H orkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, p. 74. The authors paraphrase here the often cited first line of Kants conclusion of the Critique of Practical Reason (p. 269): Two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and reverence : the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me. Kant speaks of the moral law as a fact of pure reason, p. 177 of the Critique of Practical Reason. I f the moral law were so deducible, its relation to natural laws would be schematic precisely what Kant, in the second Critique, took such great care to refute, to the point of even coining a new word to mediate that relation: moral law, he said, finds its type (not its scheme) in natural law, which means that what both have in common is no more than the form of universal legislation; Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 19498.
72
73
74
I bid., p. 196 (translation slightly modified). The first formulation of the categorical imperative was the following: Act in such a way that the maxim of your will could always hold at the same time as a principle in a universal legislation (p. 164; translation modified). A dorno (quoting himself in a letter to Karl Thieme), letter to Horkheimer, 2 June 1949, cited by Gunzelin Schmid Noerr, Editors Afterword, in Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, p. 220.
75
76
Ibid., p. 224. H orkheimer and Adorno, Rettung der Aufklrung. Diskussion ber eine geplante Schrift zur Dialektik (October 14, 1946), in Max Horkheimer, Gesammelte Schriften (Frankfurt, 1985), 12: p. 602.
77
78
H orkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, p. 67. Later in the chapter, and not surprisingly, Horkheimer congratulates Nietzsche for having unveiled the same truth in On the Genealogy of Morals: always a
Thierry de Duve
298
J acques Lacan, Kant with Sade, in Ecrits, trans. Bruce Fink (New York, 2006), p. 646. I have the right to enjoy your body, anyone can say to me, and I will exercise this right without any limit to the capriciousness of the exactions I may wish to satiate with your body; Marquis de Sade, Philosophy in the Bedroom, quoted by Lacan, Kant with Sade, p. 648. Compare with Kants third formula for the categorical imperative: So act that you use humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means; Immanuel Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, in Practical Philosophy, p. 80.
80
81
J acques Lacan, The Ethics of Psychoanalysis, 195960, trans. Dennis Porter (New York, 1992), p. 79. Adorno, Versuch ber Wagner, p. 104. (See note 7.)
82 83
I have modestly started this inquiry in two as yet unpublished essays, the already cited Some Philosophical Implications of Eric Camerons Routine Extremism, and Joseph Beuys and the German Past, Tentatively, both forthcoming. W itness, again, the famous first line of Adornos Aesthetic Theory: It is self-evident that nothing concerning art is self-evident anymore, not its inner life, not its relation to the world, not even its right to exist (p. 1).
84
85
Y es, pure. The gist of the Kant-after-Duchamp approach to aesthetics and art theory is the following: apply to art what Kant said about beauty in nature and forget everything he had to say about art. The latter is obviously dated and could not survive the demise of the Fine Arts (actually: Beautiful Arts, Schne Knste, Beaux-Arts) system enforced in his time. This is where Duchamp intervenes: he was the messenger who brought us the (good or bad) news that we have moved from the Fine Arts system to the Art-in-General system, where (1) the representation of beauty no longer mediates between nature and art; (2) the boundaries between the individual arts have been challenged and, in some cases, dissolved; (3) anything can a priori be art; (4) the decision whether or not something deserves to be called art ultimately rests on the individual aesthetic judgment. Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgment, p.185. de Duve, Do Artists Speak on Behalf of All of Us? p. 154.
86 87
299
Contributors
Anthony J. Cascardi is Sidney and Margaret Ancker Professor of Comparative Literature, Rhetoric, and Spanish at the University of California, Berkeley. Fred Rush is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame. Claudia Brodsky is Professor of Comparative Literature at Princeton University. Robert Kaufman is Assistant Professor of Comparative Literature the University of California, Berkeley. Ale Erjavec is Research Professor at the Institute of Philosophy, Ljubljana, Slovenia. J. M. Bernstein is University Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the New School for Social Research. Thierry de Duve is Professor of Aesthetics and Art History at Universit Charles-de-Gaulle Lille 3 in Villeneuve dAscq, France.