Cognitive dimensions of predator responses to imperfect
mimicry
Article (Published Version)
Chittka, Lars and Osorio, Daniel (2007) Cognitive dimensions of predator responses to imperfect
mimicry. PLoS Biology, 5 (2). e339. ISSN 1544-9173
This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/28873/
This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the
published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to
consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published
version.
Copyright and reuse:
Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University.
Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual
author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material
made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available.
Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third
parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit
purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic
details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the
content is not changed in any way.
http://sro.sussex.ac.uk
Unsolved Mystery
Cognitive Dimensions of Predator
Responses to Imperfect Mimicry?
Lars Chittka*, Daniel Osorio
M
any palatable animals, for example hoverflies, deter
predators by mimicking well-defended insects such
as wasps. However, for human observers, these flies
often seem to be little better than caricatures of wasps—their
visual appearance and behaviour are easily distinguishable
from those which they are attempting to mimic. This
imperfect mimicry baffles evolutionary biologists, because
one might expect natural selection to do a more thorough
job. Here we discuss two types of cognitive processes that
might explain why distinguishable mimics could enjoy
increased protection from predation. Speed–accuracy
tradeoffs in predator decision making might give imperfect
mimics sufficient time to escape, and predators under time
constraint might avoid time-consuming discriminations
between well-defended models and inaccurate edible mimics
and instead adopt a “safety first” policy of avoiding insects
with similar appearance. Categorisation of prey types by
predators could mean that wholly dissimilar mimics may
be protected, provided they share some common property
with noxious prey. If predators use experience with multiple
prey types to learn rules rather than just memorising the
appearance of individual prey types, it follows that different
individual predators should form different categories, each
including separate types of novel prey. Experimental studies
to test these hypotheses should be straightforward, because
we can use the relatively simple signals (e.g., striped patterns)
with which prey manipulate predator behaviour as tools
for investigating cognitive processes that underlie decision
making and object recognition in animals’ daily lives.
species would not only enthusiastically attack bumblebees,
honeybees, wasps, and their mimics, but the birds would learn
to reject these and also avoid relatively crude mimics if they
were offered after an encounter with a wasp. The syrphids
thus engage in so called Batesian (deceptive) mimicry, where
a palatable animal mimics the display of a noxious model.
Imperfect mimics also occur in vertebrate colour displays, for
example in some North American snakes [3].
Several evolutionary scenarios have been proposed that
might explain such imperfect mimicry. One suggestion
that is relatively difficult to test is that mimics have not had
sufficient time to converge fully on the model (see [1] for a
critique). Another possibility is that models and mimics are
engaged in an evolutionary arms race, where the model is
under pressure to evolve away from the mimic [4]. This is
because predators are more likely to attack noxious prey after
encounters with individuals of similar palatable species ([2],
but see also [5]). Some researchers have related the degree
of similarity in mimicry systems to the relative frequencies
of models and mimics [3,5], while others pointed out that
there are conflicting demands on animals’ colour patterns,
resulting in compromises between signalling strategies
and, for example, constraints of thermoregulation [6]. The
number of controversial views aired in high-profile journals
indicates that biologists are clearly intrigued by the problem,
but good experimental evidence for many scenarios still
needs to be collected. Our view is that we cannot quantify
the evolutionary pressures on animal colour patterns without
considering what is known about predators’ cognitive
abilities. In some cases, we suggest that the peculiarities
of predator “receiver psychology” might result in the full
protection of mimics, even if these only partially resemble
their models and both are distinguishable by predators—
resulting in a lack of selective pressure to increase the
similarity between a mimic and its model(s).
A simple psychological explanation for predator responses
to poor mimics could be that predators innately avoid any
stripy pattern. Such innate biases do exist [7], but typically
they are weak and can easily be overwritten by learning
[1,2,4]. Therefore, current explanations of imperfect mimicry
refer to predators’ individual experience with unpleasant
Introduction
Mimicry—the phenomenon where organisms converge
in appearance on one another, often to warn or deceive
predators—provides examples of adaptive evolution so
striking that they should convince even staunch sceptics of
the principles of evolution. Perfectly harmless caterpillars
look like venomous snakes, while angler fish display lures
that resemble small fish. In many other cases, however,
the match between the mimic and its model is almost
disappointingly sloppy. Take many of the familiar hoverflies:
their yellow and black stripes might resemble a stinging
wasp to an inexperienced observer—but the body shape,
flight behaviour, and colour pattern of many species easily
identify them as defenceless flies (Figure 1). Yet, the strategy
works! The flies’ colouration pattern provides protection that
they would not enjoy if they were, say, plain brown [1]. The
suspicion that such imperfect mimics might not in fact be
mimics at all was refuted already in 1935, when Mostler [2]
demonstrated that inexperienced, lab-reared birds of several
Citation: Chittka L, Osorio D (2007) Cognitive dimensions of predator responses to
imperfect mimicry. PLoS Biol 5(12): e339. doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050339
Copyright: © 2007 Chittka and Osorio. This is an open-access article distributed
under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits
unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the
original author and source are credited.
Lars Chittka is with the School of Biological and Chemical Sciences, Queen Mary,
University of London, London, United Kingdom. Daniel Osorio is with the School of
Life Sciences, University of Sussex, Falmer, Brighton, United Kingdom.
Unsolved Mysteries discuss a topic of biological importance that is poorly
understood and in need of research attention.
PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org
* To whom correspondence should be addressed. E-mail:
[email protected]
2754
December 2007 | Volume 5 | Issue 12 | e339
travelled paths to calculate new routes [15]. In contemporary
animal behaviour, there is a general fascination with probing
the level of cognitive complexity that animals can achieve.
Not applying the fruits of this research to animals’ natural
lives would be a major oversight—we cannot continue to
regard animals as simple “conditioned reflex machines” if
we are to understand the complexity of interactions between
signallers and receivers, especially where receivers might
combine experience with multiple signallers to form rules for
adaptive behaviour. Here we discuss two cognitive abilities
that allow predators to make effective decisions about
whether or not to attack, while maintaining a low level of risk
of confusing a nutritious mimic with its noxious model. These
processes may be exploited by imperfect mimics.
Speed–Accuracy Tradeoffs in Animal Decision Making?
Everyday experience shows that difficult perceptual tasks
require more time than easy tasks do. If time is limited for
difficult judgments, one is more likely to make mistakes.
Consider a hypothetical football match where one team wears
green and the other turquoise. The two colours are easily
distinguished, but as players continuously change position
and mingle with one another, the time for classifying them as
members of one or the other team will be limited. The result
is confusion of green and turquoise that will make the match
substantially less enjoyable. Conversely, when it is essential to
avoid mistakes, more time is needed. A mushroom collector
has to make triply sure not to mistake a death cap (Amanita
phalloides) for the similar and edible false death cap (Amanita
citrina). If, after extensive inspection, there is any uncertainty,
a false alarm is obviously preferable to a fatal error.
Understanding such speed–accuracy tradeoffs is an essential
part of contemporary decision theory [16].
In bees and mice, just as in humans, sensory discrimination
typically improves with the time allowed for a decision, and
difficult discrimination tasks require more time to be solved
with high accuracy [16–19]. Such speed–accuracy tradeoffs
result from the need to sample information over time in
noisy conditions, so that evidence for competing options
accumulates until a decision threshold is reached [17,20–22].
Thus, although the mechanistic causes of speed–accuracy
tradeoffs might sometimes lie in low-level sensory processes,
devising strategies that take into account such mechanistic
limitations requires error awareness and attention, i.e.,
cognitive processes. Such tradeoffs should be of fundamental
importance to animal decision making in the economy of
nature, but their relevance in the natural lives of animals
has only recently been considered [18,23–25]. There are
obvious implications for predators when similar mimics must
be discriminated from noxious models, especially in timeconstrained situations, such as scramble competition or when
the prey might escape. Data on speed-accuracy tradeoffs for
avian predators are still outstanding, but we suggest possible
avenues of future research below.
doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050339.g001
Figure 1. Two Wasp Species and Four Less-Than-Perfect and
Palatable Mimics
(A) Dolichovespula media; (B) Polistes spec.; (C) Eupeodes spec.; (D) Syrphus
spec; (E) Helophilus pendulus; (F) Clytus arietes (all species European).
Note that species C–F do not closely resemble any wasp species. The
three hoverfly species differ in wing and body shape, antennal length,
flight behaviour, and striping pattern from European wasps. One fly
species (E) even has longitudinal stripes, which wasps typically don’t. The
harmless wasp beetle does not normally display wings, and its legs do
not resemble those of any wasps.
(Image Credit: (A, C, E, and F) by Rob Knell; (B and D) by Tom Ings)
mimics, and responses to mimics that are guided by such
experience. Previous explanations of imperfect mimicry
include the following: (a) the possibility that differences in
visual systems between humans and insectivores (typically
avian predators) might mean that what constitutes a poor
match for human observers might in fact be perfect mimicry
for some predators [8]; (b) in the presence of multiple
aposematic models, mimics attempt to find a compromise
by appearing intermediate to all of them [1,9]; and (c)
generalisation of predators to distinguishable but similar
prey might give sufficient protection for poor mimics
[4,10–12]. These explanations are not mutually exclusive,
and empirical evidence is scant [1]. However, the predator
learning processes that have been discussed in the context
of mimicry are essentially Pavlovian, in that they invoke only
simple processes of information storage, generalisation, and
forgetting [13], and thus do not fully capture the range of
cognitive abilities that predators might use. Cognition can
be defined as the ability to use internal representations of
information acquired in separate events, and to combine
these to generate novel information and apply it in an
adaptive manner [14] —a classic example is the cognitive
map, where subjects integrate information from separately
PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org
Testing the Role of Speed–Accuracy Tradeoffs in
Predators Judging Inaccurate Mimics
An appropriate test of the interaction between choice time
and precision of choice needs to involve prey items that are
only briefly on display, or moving, rather than stationary, and
with no time limitations. Because there are ethical concerns
with experimental designs where birds might be stung by
2755
December 2007 | Volume 5 | Issue 12 | e339
errors, avoiding the profitable B, and halving the intake rate.
These experiments should identify the range of similarity in
which speed–accuracy tradeoffs mean that inaccurate mimics
might not only enjoy improved protection from predators
relative to palatable insects without aposematic colouration,
but also, critically, that a further increase in similarity to the
model might confer no further fitness benefits.
Categorisation of Food Types by Animals
Categorisation allows us to classify stimuli in meaningful way
(e.g., as dogs, cats, chairs, tables, etc.) and independently of
their individual shape and colour. Note that categorisation
differs from generalisation. Generalisation allows animals
to attribute common properties to distinguishable objects;
however, the level of similarity can vary in a continuous
fashion, as when one sees a greater similarity of yellow to
orange than to red, and likewise of yellow to lime than to
green. On a continuous sensory dimension, such as the visible
spectrum, the extent of generalisation from a given stimulus
value (e.g., wavelength of light) typically has a Gaussian
or exponentially shaped function centred on that value
[10,27,28]. One might expect the extent of generalisation to
be related to sensory discrimination thresholds, and hence
to be related to the speed–accuracy trade-off. By comparison,
categories have definite boundaries—an object is either a
member of a category or not—and they can include diverse
or entirely dissimilar items, such as dogs or fruit. However, a
category has some defining feature that is common to all its
members. Categorisation may also be understood as a strategy
for being economic with memory—by extracting the cues that
define a class of objects, rather than just a single object, an
animal might circumvent having to memorise the appearance
of dozens of salient objects [29].
A predator without categorisation might make almost
inconceivably inappropriate judgments: consider an animal
that, after being stung in the tongue by a black-and-red
bumblebee, treats a black/yellow/white striped bumblebee
as potentially palatable. Hence, categorisation is adaptive, but
there is a risk of “false alarm” errors, where palatable mimics
(even if they bear no direct similarity to aposematic prey) fall
within an avoided category. Pigeons and chicks have been
shown to be able to form categories [28,29]; for example,
Cerella [30] made a good case that pigeons recognise oak
leaves as a natural category. In particular, after learning a
single oak leaf shape, they did not discriminate between a
wide range of oak leaves, but reliably distinguished oaks from
leaves of other species. As with tree leaves, aposematic insects
such as wasps, bumblebees, and shield-bugs (Pentatomidae)
have a characteristic shape that birds might recognise as
natural kinds; alternatively, they might classify patterns
according to whether or not they contain more than one
colour (independently of the particular combinations of
colours).
doi:10.1371/journal.pbio.0050339.g002
Figure 2. Colour Coats of European Bumblebees and a Stingless
Mimic
(A) Bombus lapidarius; (B) B. terrestris; (C) B. pratorum; and (D) the fly
Volucella bombylans. Note that (B) and (D) are considered part of the
same mimicry ring [31], even though they are clearly distinct. But, a
predator categorising by shape might respond equally to both, as to the
highly distinct B. lapidarius (A), and the individual of the fly V. bombylans
(D), which looks like no particular central European bumblebee species,
but captures the overall essence of a bumblebee-like appearance (body
shape, hair coat, and some form of stripes).
(Image credit: (A and B) by Tom Ings; (C) by Mike Edwards; and (D) by
Rob Knell)
insects, live prey cannot be used; instead penalties might
consist of food rendered unpalatable with bitter quinine
solution [18]. It will be essential to vary the display time
or movement speed, as well as the number (and perhaps
direction of movement) of palatable and unpalatable prey,
to mimic the crowded conditions that predators might
encounter in nature. Both sequential and simultaneous
choice should be tested.
It will first be necessary to quantify the speed–accuracy
trade-off depending on the similarity between unpalatable
models and palatable mimics. Emphasis can be placed either
on accuracy (by varying the severity of punishment for
errors) or speed (by limiting the time available for an attack).
Once such baseline data are established, two predictions are
especially worth testing. One is that if discrimination between
a model and a mimic costs appreciably more time, even
relatively inaccurate mimics might gain time to escape [26].
Consider your own response to a yellow-and-black hoverfly
approaching you on a summer day: the first reaction might
be that you are temporarily alarmed, even though close (but
time-costly) inspection might identify it as harmless. The
second prediction is that a predator, under time constraint,
will avoid time-costly discriminations between defended
models and inaccurate edible mimics, and instead adopt
a “safety first” policy of avoiding all insects with similar
appearance. This could be tested by offering three types
of prey that vary in colour and palatability: for example, A:
red, unpalatable—the aposematic model; B: red-orange—a
“mimic” similar to A, but palatable; and F: blue, palatable but
distinct from A. An optimal forager should choose B and F,
but there is of course the risk of errors (“confusing” A with
B). Thus, in a situation when time is limited, predators should
go for safe option F. However, this would involve false alarm
PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org
Testing the Role of Prey Categorisation in Insectivores
Rather than just associating one colour pattern with an
unpleasant experience, do predators learn the rules for
classifying patterns, such as those that are displayed by toxic
insects, to predict whether an unfamiliar species of insect is
safe to eat? In human education, a successful strategy is first
to learn the rules, then the exceptions. If birds first learn
the basic principles of warning colouration, then even poor
2756
December 2007 | Volume 5 | Issue 12 | e339
mimics might enjoy protection, especially when predators
have to make rapid judgements (see above). For example,
after a predator has had unpleasant encounters with two
distinct bumblebee species, it might categorise by prey shape
and not colour, and subsequently avoid all bumblebees
irrespective of colour banding pattern.
An especially interesting question concerns the way in
which animals establish categories after learning about a
number of distinct stimuli that share common properties. It is
widely thought that groups of similar but discriminable prey
species form so-called “mimicry rings” [1,4,31] (Figure 2).
Often, the participant species engage in Müllerian (“honest”)
mimicry, where multiple, defended species converge on
one another in appearance, so that individuals of one
species can profit from what a predator has experienced
in an encounter with a member of a different species [4].
There is experimental evidence that birds can establish welldefined colour categories from multiple examples [27]. In
nature, after being exposed to two or more different prey
(e.g., wasp) species that differ in shape and colour but share
a high-contrast stripe pattern, birds might categorise by
pattern and irrespective of shape, therefore including some
imperfect mimics (e.g., hoverflies) despite their difference
in body shape. These questions should be straightforward
to address experimentally by using sequential exposure to
different prey. Understanding how avian predators classify
the range of patterns that are displayed by hymenopterans
and their mimics, depending on individual experience, and
the cues that they extract to form categories will give valuable
insights into the evolution of mimicry and also provide a
naturalistic context in which to address wider questions about
the cognitive processes that underlie object recognition in
nonhuman species [32]. The differences between responses
following training to single and multiple examples will give
important information about the natural history of mimicry
rings and the underlying cognitive processes. An important
(and untested) prediction is that if predators use experience
with multiple prey types to learn rules rather than just
memorising the appearance of individual prey types, it follows
that different individual predators should form different
categories, each including separate types of novel prey—
depending on individual experience.
Competing interests. The authors declare that no competing interests
exist.
References
1. Gilbert F (2005) The evolution of imperfect mimicry. In: Fellowes M,
Holloway G, Rolff J, editors. Insect evolutionary ecology. Wallingford: CABI
Publishing. pp. 231-288.
2. Mostler G (1935) Beobachtungen zur Frage der Wespenmimikry. Zeitschrift
für Morphologie und Ökologie der Tiere 29: 381-454.
3. Harper GR, Pfennig DW (2007) Mimicry on the edge: why do mimics vary
in resemblance to their model in different parts of their geographic range?
Proc R Soc B 274: 1955-1961.
4. Ruxton GD, Sherratt TN, Speed MP (2004) Avoiding attack. Oxford:
Oxford University Press. 249 p.
5. Rowland HM, Ihalainen E, Lindstrom L, Mappes J, Speed MP (2007) Comimics have a mutualistic relationship despite unequal defences. Nature
448: 64-67.
6. Williams P (2007) The distribution of bumblebee colour patterns
worldwide: possible significance for thermoregulation, crypsis and warning
mimicry. Biol J Linn Soc 92: 97-118.
7. Rowe C, Guilford T (1996) Hidden colour aversions in domestic chicks
triggered by pyrazine odours of insect warning displays. Nature 383: 520522.
8. Dittrich W, Gilbert F, Green P, McGregor P, Grewcock D (1993) Imperfect
mimicry: a pigeon‘s perspective. Proc R Soc Lond B 251: 195-200.
9. Sherratt TN (2002) The evolution of imperfect mimicry. Behav Ecol 13:
821-826.
10. Ham AD, Ihalainen E, Lindstrom L, Mappes J (2006) Does colour matter?
The importance of colour in avoidance learning, memorability and
generalisation. Behav Ecol Sociobiol 60: 482-491.
11. Johnstone RA (2002) The evolution of inaccurate mimics. Nature 418: 524526.
12. Brodie ED, Janzen FJ (1995) Experimental studies of coral snake mimicry
- generalized avoidance of ringed snake patterns by free-ranging avian
predators. Func Ecol 9: 186-190.
13. Speed MP (2000) Warning signals, receiver psychology and predator
memory. Anim Behav 60: 269-278.
14. Markl H (1985) Manipulation, modulation, information, cognition: some
of the riddles of communication. In: Hölldobler B, Lindauer M, editors.
Experimental behavioral ecology. Stuttgart: G. Fischer Verlag. pp. 163-194.
15. Menzel R, Chittka L, Eichmüller S, Geiger K, Peitsch D, et al. (1990)
Dominance of celestial cues over landmarks disproves map-like orientation
in honey bees. Z Natforsch 45c: 723-726.
16. Wolfe J (2000) Visual attention. In: DeValois KK, editor. Seeing. San Diego:
Academic Press. pp. 335-386.
17. Abraham NM, Spors H, Carleton A, Margrie TW, Kuner T, et al. (2004)
Maintaining accuracy at the expense of speed: Stimulus similarity defines
odor discrimination time in mice. Neuron 44: 865-876.
18. Chittka L, Dyer AG, Bock F, Dornhaus A (2003) Bees trade off foraging
speed for accuracy. Nature 424: 388-388.
19. Dyer AG, Chittka L (2004) Bumblebees (Bombus terrestris) sacrifice
foraging speed to solve difficult colour discrimination tasks. J Comp Physiol
A 190: 759-763.
20. Ditterich J, Mazurek ME, Shadlen MN (2003) Microstimulation of visual
cortex affects the speed of perceptual decisions. Nat Neurosci 6: 891-898.
21. Heekeren HR, Marrett S, Bandettini PA, Ungerleider LG (2004) A general
mechanism for perceptual decision-making in the human brain. Nature
431: 859-862.
22. Chittka L, Spaethe J (2007) Visual search and the importance of time in
complex decision making by bees. Arthropod Plant Interact 1: 37-44.
23. Chittka L, Raine NE (2006) Recognition of flowers by pollinators. Curr
Opin Plant Biol 9: 428-435.
24. Passino KM, Seeley TD (2006) Modeling and analysis of nest-site selection
by honeybee swarms: the speed and accuracy trade-off. Behav Ecol Sociobiol
59: 427-442.
25. Franks NR, Dornhaus A, Fitzsimmons JP, Stevens M (2003) Speed versus
accuracy in collective decision making. Proc R Soc Lond B 270: 2457-2463.
26. Howse PE, Allen JA (1994) Satyric mimicry: the evolution of apparent
imperfection. Proc R Soc B 257: 111-114.
27. Baddeley RJ, Osorio D, Jones CD (2007) Generalization of color by
chickens: experimental observations and a Bayesian model. Am Nat 169:
S27-S41.
28. Jones CD, Osorio A, Baddeley RJ (2001) Colour categorization by domestic
chicks. Proc R Soc B 268: 2077-2084.
29. Huber L, Troje NF, Loidolt M, Aust U, Grass D (2000) Natural
categorization through multiple feature learning in pigeons. Quart J Exp
Psychol B 53: 341-357.
30. Cerella J (1979) Visual classes and natural categories in the pigeon. J Exp
Psychol 5: 68-77.
31. Plowright RC, Owen RE (1980) The evolutionary significance of bumble
bee color patterns: a mimetic interpretation. Evolution 34: 622-637.
32. Bain RS, Rashed A, Cowper VJ, Gilbert FS, Sherrat TN (2007) The key
mimetic features of hoverflies through avian eyes. Proc R Soc B 274: 19491954.
Conclusion
Mimicry is one of the most venerable and at the same time
most dynamic areas in whole-organism biology. Recent
developments in animal cognition now make it possible to
understand not only how animals perceive mimicry systems
[8,33,34], but also how they store information about such
systems, how such information consolidates and changes with
experience and with time [35–37], and how animals might
extract the general rules by which animal colouration and
palatability are linked. Incorporating realistic time constraints
into experiment designs, and the visual informationprocessing speed of predators, should help identify the
conditions under which the cognitive processes of predators
will sometimes generate space for inaccurate mimics to live.
Acknowledgments
We wish to thank I. C. Cuthill, A. G. Dyer, and J. Mallet for
discussions; and T. Ings, R. Knell, and M. Edwards for permission to
use their photographs.
PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org
2757
December 2007 | Volume 5 | Issue 12 | e339
33. Cuthill IC, Bennett ATD (1993) Mimicry and the eye of the beholder. Proc
R Soc Lond B 253: 203-204.
34. Stevens M (2007) Predator perception and the interrelation between
different forms of protective coloration. Proc R Soc B Biol Sci 274: 14571464.
PLoS Biology | www.plosbiology.org
35. Darst CR, Cummings ME (2006) Predator learning favours mimicry of a
less-toxic model in poison frogs. Nature 440: 208-211.
36. Ruxton GD, Speed MP (2005) A taste for mimicry. Nature 433: 205-207.
37. Skelhorn J, Rowe C (2005) Tasting the difference: do multiple defence
chemicals interact in Müllerian mimicry? Proc Roy Soc B 272: 339-345.
2758
December 2007 | Volume 5 | Issue 12 | e339