Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science Vol.20 (2012)
1〜13
1
The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method
Akihiro Kanamori∗
Abstract
I address the historical emergence of the mathematical infinite, and how we
are to take the infinite in and out of mathematics. The thesis is that the mathematical infinite in mathematics is a matter of method.
The infinite, of course, is a large topic. At the outset, one can historically discern two overlapping clusters of concepts: (1) wholeness, completeness, universality,
absoluteness. (2) endlessness, boundlessness, indivisibility, continuousness. The first,
the metaphysical infinite, I shall set aside. It is the second, the mathematical infinite,
that I will address. Furthermore, I will address the mathematical infinite by considering its historical emergence in set theory and how we are to take the infinite in
and out of mathematics. Insofar as physics and, more broadly, science deals with the
mathematical infinite through mathematical language and techniques, my remarks
should be subsuming and consequent.
The main underlying point is that how the mathematical infinite is approached,
assimilated, and applied in mathematics is not a matter of “ontological commitment”,
of coming to terms with whatever that might mean, but rather of epistemological
articulation, of coming to terms through knowledge. The mathematical infinite in
mathematics is a matter of method. How we deal with the specific individual issues involving the infinite turns on the narrative we present about how it fits into
methodological mathematical frameworks established and being established.
The first section discusses the mathematical infinite in historical context, and
the second, set theory and the emergence of the mathematical infinite. The third
section discusses the infinite in and out of mathematics, and how it is to be taken.
∗
Department of Mathematics, Boston University, 111 Cummington Street, Boston,
Massachusetts 02215, USA
E-mail:
[email protected]
This article was written whilst the author was a 2009–2010 senior fellow at the
Lichtenberg-Kolleg of the University of Göttingen; he expresses his gratitude for the
productive conditions and support of the kolleg. The themes of this article were presented in a keynote address at the 2010 annual meeting of the Japan Association for
the Philosophy of Science; the author expresses his gratitude for the invitation and
the productive discussions that ensued.
—1—
2
Akihiro Kanamori
Vol. 20
1. The Infinite in Mathematics
What role does the infinite play in modern mathematics? In modern mathematics, infinite sets abound both in the workings of proofs and as subject matter in
statements, and so do universal statements, often of ∀∃ “for all there exists” form,
which are indicative of direct engagement with the infinite. In many ways the role
of the infinite is importantly “second-order” in the sense that Frege regarded number generally, in that the concepts of modern mathematics are understood as having
infinite instances over a broad range.
But all this has been the case for just more than a century. Infinite totalities
and operations on them only emerged in mathematics in a recent period of algebraic
expansion and rigorization of proof. It becomes germane, even crucial, to see how
the infinite emerged through interaction with proof to come to see that the infinite in
mathematics is a matter of method. If one puts the history of mathematics through
the sieve of proof, one sees the emergence of methods drawing in the mathematical
infinite, and the mathematical infinite came in at three levels: the countably infinite,
the infinite of the natural numbers; the continuum, the infinite of analysis; and the
empyrean infinite of higher set theory.
As a thematic entrée into the matter of proof and the countably infinite, we can
consider the Pigeonhole Principle:
If n pigeons fly into fewer than n pigeonholes,
then one hole has more than one pigeon.
Taken primordially, this may be considered immediate as part of the meaning of natural number and requires no proof. On the other hand, after its first explicit uses in
algebraic number theory in the mid-19th Century, it has achieved articulated prominence in modern combinatorics, its consequences considered substantive and at times
quite surprisingly so given its immediacy. Rendered as a ∀∃ statement about natural
numbers, it however does not have the feel of a basic law of arithmetic but of a “nonconstructive” existence assertion, and today it is at the heart of combinatorics, and
indeed is the beginning of Ramsey Theory, a field full of non-constructive existence
assertions.
So how does one prove the Pigeonhole Principle? For 1729 pigeons and
137 pigeonholes one can systematically generate all assignments {1, . . . , 1729} −→
{1, . . . , 137} and check that there are always at least two pigeons assigned to the
same pigeonhole. But we “see” nothing here, nor from any other particular brute
force analysis. With the Pigeonhole Principle seen afresh as being at the heart of
the articulation of finite cardinality and requiring proof based on prior principles,
Richard Dedekind in his celebrated 1888 essay Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?
—2—
The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method
3
[8, §120] first gave a proof applying the Principle of Induction on n. Today, the Pigeonhole Principle is regarded as a theorem of Peano Arithmetic (PA). In fact, there
is a “reverse mathematics” result, that in the presence of the elementary axioms of
PA, the Pigeonhole Principle implies the Principle of Induction, and is hence equivalent to this central principle. Moreover, the proof complexity of weak forms of the
Pigeonhole Principle have been investigated in weak systems of arithmetic.1
This raises a notable historical point drawing in the infinite. The Pigeonhole
Principle seems to have been first applied in mathematics by Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet in papers of 1842, one to the study of the classical Pell’s equation and another to
establish a crucial approximation lemma for his well-known Unit Theorem describing
the group of units of an algebraic number field.2 Upon Carl Friedrich Gauss’s death
in 1855 his Göttingen chair went to Dirichlet, but he succumbed to a heart attack a
few years later. Richard Dedekind was Gauss’s last student, and later colleague and
friend of Dirichlet. Already in 1857, Dedekind [6] worked in modular arithmetic with
the actually infinite residue classes themselves as unitary objects. His context was in
fact Z[x], the polynomials of x with integer coefficients, and so he was entertaining
a totality of infinitely many equivalence classes.
The Pigeonhole Principle occurred in Dirichlet’s Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie
[10], edited and published by Dedekind in 1863. The occurrence is in the second, 1871
edition, in a short Supplement VIII by Dedekind on Pell’s equation, and it was in the
famous Supplement X that Dedekind laid out his theory of ideals in algebraic number theory, working directly with infinite totalities. In 1872 Dedekind was putting
together Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?, and he would be the first to define
infinite set, with the definition being a set for which there is a one-to-one correspondence with a proper subset. This is just the negation of the Pigeonhole Principle.
Dedekind in effect had inverted a negative aspect of finite cardinality into a positive
existence definition of the infinite.
The Pigeonhole Principle brings out a crucial point about method. Its proof
by induction is an example of what David Hilbert later called formal induction.
In so far as the natural numbers do have an antecedent sense, a universal statement ∀nϕ(n) about them should be correlated with all the informal counterparts to
ϕ(0), ϕ(1), ϕ(2), . . . taken together. Contra Poincaré, Hilbert [15] distinguished between contentual [inhaltlich] induction, the intuitive construction of each integer as
1
2
See for example [18].
See Dirichlet [11, pp.579, 636]. The principle in the early days was called the Schubfachprinzip (“drawer principle”), though not however by Dirichlet. The second,
1899 edition of Heinrich Weber’s Lehrbuch der Algebra used the words “in Faecher
verteilen” (“to distribute into boxes”) and Edmund Landau’s 1927 Vorlesungen über
Zahlentheorie had “Schubfachschluss”.
—3—
4
Akihiro Kanamori
Vol. 20
numeral,3 and formal induction, by which ∀nϕ(n) follows immediately from the two
statements ϕ(0) and ∀n(ϕ(n) → ϕ(n + 1)) and “through which alone the mathematical variable can begin to play its role in the formal system.” In the case of the
Pigeonhole Principle, we see the proof by formal induction, but it bears little constructive relation to any particular instance. Be that as it may, the schematic sense
of the countably infinite, the infinite of the natural numbers, is carried in modern
mathematics by formal induction, a principle used everywhere in combinatorics and
computer science to secure statements about the countably infinite. The Pigeonhole
Principle is often regarded as surprising in its ability to draw strong conclusions, but
one way to explain this is to point to the equivalence with the Principle of Induction. Of course, the Principle of Induction is itself often regarded as surprising in
its efficacy, but this can be seen as our reaction to it as method in contrast to the
countably infinite taken as primordial. There is no larger mathematical sense to the
Axiom of Infinity in set theory other than to provide an extensional counterpart to
formal induction, a method of proof. The Cantorian move against the traditional
conception of the natural numbers as having no end in the “after” sense is neatly
rendered by extensionalizing induction itself in modern set theory with the ordinal
ω, with “after” recast as “∈”.
The next level of the mathematical infinite would be the continuum, the infinite
of mathematical analysis. Bringing together the two traditional Aristotelean infinities
of infinite divisibility and of infinite progression, one can ask: How many points are
there on the line? This would seem to be a fundamental, even primordial, question.
However, to cast it as a mathematical question, underlying concepts would have to
be invested with mathematical sense and a way of mathematical thinking provided
that makes an answer possible, if not informative. First, the real numbers as representing points on the linear continuum would have to be precisely described. A
coherent concept of cardinality and cardinal number would have to be developed for
infinite mathematical totalities. Finally, the real numbers would have to be enumerated in such a way so as to accommodate this concept of cardinality. Georg Cantor
made all of these moves as part of the seminal advances that have led to modern set
theory, eventually drawing in also the third, empyrean infinite of higher set theory.
His Continuum Hypothesis would propose a specific, structured resolution about the
size of the continuum in terms of his transfinite numbers, a resolution that would
become pivotal where set-theoretic approaches to the continuum became prominent
in mathematical investigations.
3
For Hilbert, the numeral for the integer n consists of n short vertical strokes concatenated together.
—4—
The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method
5
2. Set Theory and the Emergence of the Infinite
Set theory had its beginnings in the great 19th Century transformation of mathematics, a transformation beginning in analysis. With the function concept having
been steadily extended beyond analytic expressions to infinite series, sense for the
new functions could only be developed through carefully specified deductive procedures. Proof reemerged in mathematics as an extension of algebraic calculation and
became the basis of mathematical knowledge, promoting new abstractions and generalizations. The new articulations to be secured by proof and proof in turn to be
based on prior principles, the regress lead in the early 1870s to the appearance of
several formulations of the real numbers, of which Cantor’s and Dedekind’s are the
best known. It is at first quite striking that the real numbers as a totality came to
be developed so late, but this can be viewed against the background of the larger
conceptual shift from intensional to extensional mathematics. Infinite series outstripping sense, it became necessary to adopt an arithmetical view of the continuum given
extensionally as a totality of points.
Cantor’s formulation of the real numbers appeared in his seminal paper [1] on
trigonometric series; proceeding in terms of “fundamental” sequences, he laid the
basis for his theorems on sequential convergence. Dedekind [7] formulated the real
numbers in terms of his “cuts” to express the completeness of the continuum; deriving the least upper bound principle as a simple consequence, he thereby secured
the basic properties of continuous functions. In the use of arbitrary sequences and
infinite totalities, both Cantor’s and Dedekind’s objectifications of the continuum
helped set the stage for the subsequent development of that extensional mathematics
par excellence, set theory. Cantor’s formulation was no idle conceptualization, but
to the service of specific mathematics, the articulation of his results on uniqueness
of trigonometric series involving his derived sets, the first instance of topological closure. Dedekind [7] describes how he came to his formulation much earlier, but also
acknowledges Cantor’s work. Significantly, both Cantor [1, p.128] and Dedekind [7,
III] accommodated the antecedent geometric sense of the continuum by asserting as
an “axiom” that each point on the geometric line actually corresponds to a real number as they defined it, a sort of Church’s thesis of adequacy for their construals of
the continuum. In modern terms, Cantor’s reals are equivalence classes according to
an equivalence relation which importantly is a congruence relation, a relation that
respects the arithmetical structure of the reals. It is through Cantor’s formulation
that completeness would be articulated for general metric spaces, thereby providing
the guidelines for proof in new contexts involving infinite sets.
Set theory was born on that day in December 1873 when Cantor established that
the continuum is not countable: There is no one-to-one correspondence between the
natural numbers N = {0, 1, 2, 3, . . .} and the real numbers R. Like the irrationality of
—5—
6
Akihiro Kanamori
Vol. 20
√
2, the uncountability of the continuum was an impossibility result established via
reductio ad absurdum that opened up new possibilities. Cantor addressed a specific
problem, embedded in the mathematics of the time, in his seminal [2] entitled “On a
property of the totality of all real algebraic numbers”. Dirichlet’s algebraic numbers,
it will be remembered, are the roots of polynomials with integer coefficients; Cantor
established the countability of the algebraic numbers. This was the first substantive
correlation of an infinite totality with the natural numbers, and it was the first application of what now goes without saying, that finite words based on a countable
alphabet are countable. Cantor then established: For any (countable) sequence of
reals, every interval contains a real not in the sequence.4
By this means Cantor provided a new proof of Joseph Liouville’s result [16, 17]
that there are transcendental (i.e. real, non-algebraic) numbers, and only afterward
did Cantor point out the uncountability of the reals altogether. Accounts of Cantor’s existence deduction for transcendental numbers have mostly reserved the order,
establishing first the uncountability of real numbers and only then drawing the conclusion from the countability of the algebraic numbers, thus promoting the misconception that his argument is “non-constructive”.5 It depends how one takes a proof,
and Cantor’s arguments have been implemented as algorithms to generate successive digits of transcendental numbers.6 The Baire Category Theorem, in its many
uses in modern mathematics, has similarly been regarded as non-constructive in its
production of examples; however, its proof is an extension of Cantor’s proof of the
uncountability of the reals, and analogously constructive.
Cantor went on, of course, to develop his concept of cardinality based on one-toone correspondences. Two totalities have the same cardinality exactly when there is
a one-to-one correspondence between them. Having made the initial breach with a
negative result about the lack of a one-to-one correspondence, he established infinite
cardinality as a methodologically positive concept, as Dedekind had done for infinite
set, and investigated the possibilities for having one-to-one correspondences. Just as
the discovery of the irrational numbers had led to one of the great achievements of
Greek mathematics, Eudoxus’s theory of geometric proportions, Cantor began his
move toward a full-blown mathematical theory of the infinite. By his 1878 Beitrag
[3] Cantor had come to the focal Continuum Hypothesis—that there is no intervening
cardinality between that of the countably infinite and of the continuum—and in his
4
5
6
The following is Cantor’s argument, in brief: Suppose that s is a sequence of reals
and I an interval. Let a < b be the first two reals of s, if any, in I. Then let a′ < b′
be the first two reals of s, if any, in the open interval (a, b); a′′ < b′′ the first two reals
of s, if any, in (a′ , b′ ); and so forth. Then however long this process continues, the
intersection of the nested intervals must contain a real not in the sequence s.
Indeed, this is where Wittgenstein ([21], part II, 30–41) located what he took to be
the problematic aspects of the talk of uncountability.
See Gray [13].
—6—
The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method
7
1883 Grundlagen [4] Cantor developed the transfinite numbers and the key concept of
well-ordering, in significant part to take a structured approach to infinite cardinality
and the Continuum Hypothesis. At the end of the Grundlagen, Cantor propounded
this basic well-ordering principle: “It is always possible to bring any well-defined set
into the form of a well-ordered set.” Sets are to be well-ordered, and they and their
cardinalities are to be gauged via the transfinite numbers of his structured conception
of the infinite.
Almost two decades after his [2] Cantor in a short 1891 note [5] gave his now
celebrated diagonal argument, establishing Cantor’s Theorem: For any set X the
totality of functions from X into a fixed two-element set has a larger cardinality than
X, i.e. there is no one-to-one correspondence between the two. This result generalized his [2] result that the continuum is not countable, since the totality of functions
from N into a fixed two-element set has the same cardinality as R. In retrospect the
diagonal argument can be drawn out from the [2] proof.7
Cantor had been shifting his notion of set to a level of abstraction beyond sets
of reals and the like, and the casualness of his [5] may reflect an underlying cohesion
with his [2]. Whether the new proof is really “different” from the earlier one, through
this abstraction Cantor could now dispense with the recursively defined nested sets
and limit construction, and he could apply his argument to any set. He had proved for
the first time that there is a cardinality larger than that of R and moreover affirmed
“the general theorem, that the powers of well-defined sets have no maximum.” Thus,
Cantor for the first time entertained the third level of the mathematical infinite, the
empyrean level beyond the continuum, of higher set theory.
Nowadays it goes without saying that each function from a set X into a twoelement set corresponds to a subset of X, so Cantor’s Theorem is usually stated as:
For any set X its power set P(X) = {Y | Y ⊆ X} has a larger cardinality than X.
However, it would be an exaggeration to assert that Cantor at this point was working on power sets; rather, he was expanding the 19th Century concept of function
by ushering in arbitrary functions. Significantly, Bertrand Russell was stimulated
7
Starting with a sequence s of reals and a half-open interval I0 , instead of successively
choosing delimiting pairs of reals in the sequence, avoid the members of s one at a
time: Let I1 be the left or right half-open subinterval of I0 demarcated by its midpoint, whichever does not contain the first element of s. Then let I2 be the left or right
half-open subinterval of I1 demarcated by its midpoint, whichever does not contain
the second element of s; and so forth. Again, the nested intersection contains a real
not in the sequence s. Abstracting the process in terms of reals in binary expansion,
one is just generating the binary digits of the diagonalizing real.
Cantor first gave a proof of the uncountability of the reals in a letter to Dedekind
of 7 December 1873 (Ewald [12, pp.845ff]), professing that “. . . only today do I believe
myself to have finished with the thing . . .”. It is remarkable that in this letter already
appears a doubly indexed array of real numbers and a procedure for traversing the
array downward and to the right, as in a now common picturing of the diagonal proof.
—7—
8
Akihiro Kanamori
Vol. 20
by the diagonal argument to come up with his well-known paradox, this having the
effect of emphasizing power sets. At the end of [5] Cantor dealt explicitly with “all”
functions with a specified domain X and range {0, 1}; regarded these as being enumerated by one super-function φ(x, z) with enumerating variable z; and formulated
the diagonalizing function g(x) = 1 − φ(x, x). This argument, even to its notation,
would become method, flowing into descriptive set theory, the Gödel Incompleteness
Theorem, and recursion theory, the paradigmatic means of transcendence over an
established context.
Cantor’s seminal work built in what would be an essential tension of methods in
set theory, one that is still very much with us today. His Continuum Hypothesis was
his proposed answer to the continuum problem: Where is the size of the continuum
in the hierarchy of transfinite cardinals? His diagonal argument, with its mediation
for totalities of arbitrary functions (or power sets), would have to be incorporated
into the emerging theory of transfinite number. But how is this to be coordinated
with respect to his basic 1883 principle that sets should come well-ordered?
The first decade of the new century saw Ernst Zermelo make his major advances,
at Göttingen with Hilbert, in the development of set theory. In 1904 Zermelo [22]
analyzed Cantor’s well-ordering principle by reducing it to the Axiom of Choice (AC),
the abstract existence assertion that every set X has a choice function, i.e. a function
f such that for every non-empty Y ∈ X, f (Y ) ∈ Y . Zermelo thereby shifted the notion of set away from Cantor’s principle that every well-defined set is well-orderable
and replaced that principle by an explicit axiom. His Well-Ordering Theorem showed
specifically that a set is well-orderable exactly when its power set has a choice function. How AC brought to the fore issues about the non-constructive existence of
functions is well-known, and how AC became increasingly accepted in mathematics
has been well-documented.8 The expansion of mathematics into infinite abstract contexts was navigated with axioms and proofs, and this led to more and more appeals
to AC.
In 1908 Zermelo [23] published the first full-fledged axiomatization of set theory,
partly to establish set theory as a discipline free of the emerging paradoxes and particularly to put his Well-Ordering theorem on a firm footing. In addition to codifying
generative set-theoretic principles, a substantial motive for Zermelo’s axiomatizing set
theory was to buttress his Well-Ordering Theorem by making explicit its underlying
set existence assumptions.9 Initiating the first major transmutation of the notion of
set after Cantor, Zermelo thereby ushered in a new more abstract, prescriptive view
of sets as structured solely by membership and governed and generated by axioms, a
8
9
See [19].
Moore [19, pp.155ff] supports this contention using items from Zermelo’s Nachlass.
—8—
The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method
9
view that would soon come to dominate. Thus, the pathways to a theorem played a
crucial role by stimulating an axiomatization of a field of study and a corresponding
transmutation of its underlying notions.
In the tradition of Hilbert’s axiomatization of geometry and of number, Zermelo’s axiomatization was in the manner of an implicit definition, with axioms providing rules for procedure and generating sets and thereby laying the basis for proofs.
Concerning the notion of definition through axioms, Hilbert [14, p.184] had written
already in 1899 as follows in connection with his axiomatization of the reals:
Under the conception described above [the axiomatic method], the doubts which
have been raised against the existence of the totality of all real numbers (and
against the existence of infinite sets generally) lose all justification, for by the
set of real numbers we do not have to imagine, say, the totality of all possible
laws according to which the elements of a fundamental sequence can proceed,
but rather—as just described—a system of things, whose mutual relations are
given by the finite and closed system of axioms I-IV [for complete ordered fields],
and about which new statements are valid only if one can derive them from the
axioms by means of a finite number of logical inferences.
Zermelo’s revelation of the Axiom of Choice for the derivation of the Well-Ordering
Theorem was just this, the uncovering of an axiom establishing in a “finite number
of logical inferences” Cantor’s well-ordering principle, and Zermelo’s axiomatization
set out a “system of things” given by a “system of axioms”.
As with Hilbert’s later distinction between contentual and formal induction,
infinite sets draw their mathematical meaning not through any direct or intuitive
engagement but through axioms like the Axiom of Choice and finite proofs. Just as
Euclid’s axioms for geometry had set out the permissible geometric constructions,
the axioms of set theory would set out the specific rules for set generation and manipulation. But unlike the emergence of mathematics from marketplace arithmetic
and Greek geometry, infinite sets and transfinite numbers were neither laden nor
buttressed with substantial antecedents. Like strangers in a strange land stalwarts
developed a familiarity with them guided hand in hand by their axiomatic framework. For Dedekind in Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? it had sufficed to work
with sets by merely giving a few definitions and properties, those foreshadowing the
axioms of Extensionality, Union, and Infinity. Zermelo provided more rules, the axioms of Separation, Power Set, and Choice. Simply put, these rules revealed those
aspects to be ascribed to possibly infinite sets for their methodological incorporation
into emerging mathematics.10
10
As is well-known, the Axiom of Choice came to be widely used in ongoing mathematics in the methodologically congenial form of Zorn’s Lemma. Significantly, Max
—9—
10
Akihiro Kanamori
Vol. 20
The standard axiomatization ZFC was completed by 1930, with the axiom of
Replacement brought in through the work of von Neumann and the axiom of Foundation, through axiomatizations of Zermelo and Bernays. The Cantorian transfinite
is contextualized by von Neumann’s incorporation of his ordinals and Replacement,
which underpins transfinite induction and recursion as methods of proof and definition. And Foundation provides the basis for applying transfinite recursion and
induction procedures to get results about all sets, they all appearing in the cumulative hierarchy. While Foundation set the stage with a recursively presented picture
of the universe of sets, Replacement, like Choice, was seem as an essential axiom for
infusing the contextualized transfinite with the order already inherent in the finite.
3. The Infinite In and Out of Mathematics
It is evident that mathematics has been much inspired by problems and conjectures and has progressed autonomously through the communication of proofs and
the assimilation of methods. Being socially and historically contingent, mathematics
has advanced when individuals could collectively make mathematics out of concepts,
whether they involve infinite totalities or not. The commitment to the infinite is
thus to what is communicable about it, to the procedures and methods in articulated
contexts, to language and argument. Infinite sets are what they do, and their sense
is carried by the methods we collectively employ on their behalf.
When considering the infinite as a matter of method in modern mathematics and
its relation to a primordial infinite, there is a deep irony about mathematical objects
and their existence. Through the rigor and precision of modern mathematics, mathematical objects achieve a sharp delineation in mathematical practice as founded on
proof. The contextual objectification then promotes, perhaps even urges, some larger
sense of reification. Or, there is confrontation with some prior-held belief or sense
about existence that then promotes a skeptical attitude about what mathematicians
do and prove, especially about the infinite. Whether mathematics inadvertently promotes realist attitudes or not, the applicability of mathematics to science should not
extend to philosophy if the issues have to do with existence itself, for again, existence
in mathematics is contextual and governed by rules and procedures, and metaphysical existence, especially concerning the infinite, does not inform and is not informed
by mathematical work.
Mathematicians themselves are prone to move in and out of mathematics in their
existential assessments, stimulated by their work and the urge to put a larger stamp
of significance to it. We quoted Hilbert above, and he famously expressed larger
Zorn entitled the paper [25] in which he presented his lemma, “A remark on method
in transfinite algebra”.
— 10 —
The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method
11
metaphysical views about finitism and generated a program to establish the overall
consistency of mathematics. In set theory, Cantor staked out the Absolute, which
he associated with the transcendence of God, and applied it in the guise of the class
of all ordinal numbers for delineative purposes. Gödel attributed to his conceptual
realism about sets and his philosophical standpoint generally his relative consistency
results with the constructible universe L.
What are we to make of what mathematicians say and their motivations? Despite the directions in which mathematics has been led by individuals’ motivations it
is crucial to point out, again, that what has been retained and has grown in mathematics is communicable as proofs and results. We should assess the role of the
individual, but keep in mind the larger autonomy of mathematics. A delicate but
critical point here is that, as with writers and musicians, we should be dispassionate,
sometimes even critical, about what mathematicians say about their craft. As with
the surface Platonism often espoused by mathematicians, we must distinguish what
is said from what is done. The interplay between philosophical views of individual
mathematicians, historically speaking, and the space of philosophical possibility, both
in their times and now, is what needs to be explored.
There is one basic standpoint about the infinite which seems to underly others
and leads to prolonged debates about the “epistemic”. This is the (Kantian) standpoint of human finitude. We are cast into a world which as a whole must be infinite,
yet we are evidently finite, even to the number of particles that makes us up. So
how can we come to know the infinite in any substantive way? This long-standing
attitude is part of a venerable tradition, and to the extent that we move against it,
our approach may be viewed as bold and iconoclastic. Even phenomenologically, we
see before us mathematicians working coherently and substantially with infinite sets
and concepts. The infinite is embedded in mathematics as method; we can assimilate
methods; and we use the infinite through method in proofs. Even those mathematicians who would take some sort of metaphysical stance against the actuality of the
infinite in mathematics can nevertheless follow and absorb a proof by induction.
There is a final, large point in this direction. As mathematics has expanded with
the incorporation of the infinite, several voices have advocated the restriction of proof
procedures and methods. Brouwer and Weyl were early figures and Bishop, a recent
one. How are we to take all this? We now have a good grasp of intuitionistic and
constructivist approaches to mathematics as various explicit, worked-out systems.
We also have a good understanding of hierarchies of infinitistic methods through
quantifier complexity, proof theory, reverse mathematics and the like. Commitments
to the infinite can be viewed as the assimilation of methods along hierarchies. Be
that as it may, an ecumenical approach to the infinite is what seems to be called
for: There is no metamathematics, in that how we are able to argue about resources
and methods is itself mathematical. As restrictive approaches were advocated, they
— 11 —
12
Akihiro Kanamori
Vol. 20
themselves have been brought into the fold of mathematics, the process itself having
mathematical content. Proofs about various provabilities are themselves significant
proofs. It is interesting to carry out a program to see how far a strictly finitist or
predicativist approach to mathematics can go, not to emasculate mathematics or to
tout the one true way, but to find new, informative proofs and to gain an insight into
the resources at play, particularly with regard to commitments to infinity.
Stepping back, the study of the infinite in mathematics urges us to develop a
larger ecumenicism about the role of the infinite. Like the modern ecumenical approach to proofs in all their variety and complexity, proofs about resources provide
new mathematical insights about the workings of method. Even then, in relation to
later “elementary” proofs or formalized proofs in an elementary system of a statement, prior proofs may well retain an irreducible semantic content. In this content
aspects of the infinite reside robustly, displaying the autonomy of mathematics as an
evolving practice.
References
[1] Georg Cantor. Über die Ausdehnung eines Satzes aus der Theorie der trignometrischen
Reihen. Mathematische Annalen, 5:123–132, 1872.
[2] Georg Cantor. Über eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen Zahlen.
Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 77:258–262, 1874. Translated with
commentary in Ewald [12, pp.839–843].
[3] Georg Cantor. Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. Journal für die reine und angewandte Mathematik, 84:242–258, 1878.
[4] Georg Cantor. Über unendlich, lineare Punktmannigfaltigkelten. V. Mathematische
Annalen, 21:545–591, 1883. Published separately as Grundlagen eine allgemeinen
Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. Ein mathematisch-philosophischer Versuch in der Lehre des Unendlichen; B.G. Teubner, Leipzig 1883. Translated with commentary in Ewald [12,
pp.878–920].
[5] Georg Cantor. Über eine elementare frage der mannigfaltigkeitslehre. Jahresbericht der
Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung, 1:75–78, 1891. Translated with commentary in
Ewald [12, pp.920–922].
[6] Richard Dedekind. Abriss einer Theorie der höheren Kongruenzen in bezug auf einen
reellen Primzahl-Modulus. Journal für reine und Augwandte Mathematik, 54:1–26,
1857. Reprinted in Dedekind [9, pp.40–67].
[7] Richard Dedekind. Stetigkeit und irrationale Zahlen. F. Vieweg, Braunschweig, 1872.
Fifth, 1927 edition translated with commentary in Ewald [12, pp.765–779].
[8] Richard Dedekind. Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? F. Vieweg, Braunschweig,
1888. Third, 1911 edition translated with commentary in Ewald [12, pp.787–833].
[9] Richard Dedekind. Gesammelte mathematische Werke. F. Vieweg, Baunschweig, 1930–
2. Edited by Robert Fricke, Emmy Noether and Öystein Ore; reprinted by Chelsea
Publishing Company, New York, 1969.
[10] Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet. Vorlesungen über Zahlentheorie. F. Vieweg, Braunschweig,
— 12 —
The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method
13
1863. Edited by Richard Dedekind; second edition 1871, third edition 1879.
[11] Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet. G. Lejeune Dirichlet’s Werke. Reimer, Berlin, 1889/97.
Edited by Leopold Kronecker.
[12] William Ewald, editor. From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of
Mathematics. Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1996. In two volumes.
[13] Robert Gray. Georg Cantor and transcendental numbers. American Mathematical
Monthly, 101:819–832, 1994.
[14] David Hilbert. Über den Zahlbegriff. Jahresbericht der Deutschen MathematikerVereinigung, 8:180–184, 1900. Translated with commentary in Ewald [12, pp.1092–
1095].
[15] David Hilbert. Die Grundlagen der Mathematik. Abhandlungen aus dem mathematischen Seminar der Hamburgischen Universität, 6:65–92, 1928. Translated in van Heijenoort [20, pp.464–479].
[16] Joseph Liouville. Des remarques relatives 1o à des classes très-étendues de quantités
dont la valeur n’est ni rationelle ni même réductible à des irrationnelles algébriques; 2o
à un passage du livre des principes où newton calcule l’action exercée par une sphère
sur un point extérieur. Comptes Rendus Hebdomadaires des Séances de l’Académie des
Sciences, Paris, 18:883–885, 1844.
[17] Joseph Liouville. Sur des classes très-étendues de quantités dont la valeur n’est
ni algébrique ni même réductible à des irrationnelles algébriques.
Journal de
mathématiques pures et appliquées, 16:133–142, 1851.
[18] Alexis Maciel, Toniann Pitassi, and Alan R. Woods. A new proof of the weak pigeonhole
principle. Journal of Computer and System Sciences, 64:843–872, 2002.
[19] Gregory H. Moore. Zermelo’s Axiom of Choice. Its Origins, Development and Influence.
Springer, New York, 1982.
[20] Jean van Heijenoort, editor. From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical
Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1967. Reprinted 2002.
[21] Ludwig Wittgenstein. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics. Basil Blackwell,
Oxford, 1967. Edited by von Wright, G. H. and Rhees, R. and Anscombe, G. E. M..
Second printing.
[22] Ernst Zermelo. Beweis, dass jede Menge wohlgeordnet werden kann (Aus einem an
Herrn Hilbert gerichteten Briefe). Mathematische Annalen, 59:514–516, 1904. Reprinted
and translated with commentary in Zermelo [24, pp.81–119].
[23] Ernst Zermelo. Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I. Mathematische Annalen, 65:261–281, 1908. Reprinted and translated with commentary in Zermelo
[24, pp.160–229].
[24] Ernst Zermelo. Collected Works I. Springer, 2010. Edited by Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus
and Akihiro Kanamori.
[25] Max Zorn. A remark on method in transfinite algebra. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 41:667–670, 1935.
— 13 —