Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2020, Philosophical Studies
…
11 pages
1 file
Goodman and Lederman (Philos Stud 177(4):947–952, 2020) argue that the traditional Fregean strategy for preserving the validity of Leibniz’s Law of substitution fails when confronted with apparent counterexamples involving proper names embedded under propositional attitude verbs. We argue, on the contrary, that the Fregean strategy succeeds and that Goodman and Lederman’s argument misfires.
Philosophical Studies, 2019
We show that, contrary to conventional wisdom, Frege's distinction between sense and reference does not reconcile a classical logic of identity with apparent counterexamples to it involving proper names embedded under proposi-tional attitude verbs.
Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, 2000
My aim is to sketch a principle of individuation that is intended to serve the Fregean notion of a proposition, a notion I take for granted. A salient feature of Fregean propositions, i.e. complexes of modes of presentation of objects (individuals, properties), is that they are fine-grained items, so fine-grained that even synonymous sentences might express different Fregean propositions. My starting point is the principle labelled by Gareth Evans the Intuitive Criterion of Difference for Thoughts, which states that it is impossible coherently to take different mental attitudes to the same proposition. As a logical truth (a consequence of Leibniz's Law), this is a synchronic principle, the application of which is restricted to attitudes held at a single time. I argue that such a restriction might be reasonably lifted and, on the basis of an adequate notion of attitude-retention, I propose an admissible diachronic extension of the principle.
British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 2017
This paper identifies a tension in Frege's philosophy and offers a diagnosis of its origins. Frege's Context Principle can be used to dissolve the problem of propositional unity. However, Frege's official response to the problem does not invoke the Context Principle, but the distinction between 'saturated' and 'unsaturated' propositional constituents. I argue that such a response involves assumptions that clash with the Context Principle. I suggest, however, that this tension is not generated by deep-seated philosophical commitments, but by Frege's occasional attempt to take a dubious shortcut in the justification of his conception of propositional structure.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy
In this paper we compare the propositional logic of Frege’s Grundgesetze der Arithmetik to modern propositional systems, and show that Frege does not have a separable propositional logic, definable in terms of primitives of Grundgesetze, that corresponds to modern formulations of the logic of “not”, “and”, “or”, and “if…then…”. Along the way we prove a number of novel results about the system of propositional logic found in Grundgesetze, and the broader system obtained by including identity. In particular, we show that the propositional connectives that are definable in terms of Frege’s horizontal, negation, and conditional are exactly the connectives that fuse with the horizontal, and we show that the logical operators that are definable in terms of the horizontal, negation, the conditional, and identity are exactly the operators that are invariant with respect to permutations on the domain that leave the truth-values fixed. We conclude with some general observations regarding how ...
Mark Schroeder's Being For explores the plausibility of metaethical expressivism by isolating a few core assumptions and constraints, and then drawing out the implications of how they can be developed into a semantic theory for a fragment of English. Its main virtue is that it shows how an expressivist can handle the 'Frege-Geach problem' by constructing a semantic system in which expressive language can embed in complex sentences that have the right semantic properties. For example, considerable effort is put into explaining why the sentence 'Murder is not wrong' is inconsistent with the simpler sentence 'Murder is wrong'. Additionally, Being For claims to develop 'non-cognitivism', a family of non-descriptivist theories of normative language of which expressivism is a popular version, in the best way possible. But, ultimately, it concludes pessimistically that expressivism is 'an extremely unpromising hypothesis about the workings of natural languages' (Schroeder 2008: 179).
Disputatio
Stephen Schiffer 2003 presents six arguments against the Fregean model of propositions, according to which propositions are (a) the referents of that-clauses and (b) structured entities made out of concepts. Schiffer advances an alternative view: propositions are unstructured pleonastic entities. My purpose is to argue in favour of the main tenets of the Fregean model by countering each of Schiffer’s arguments and sketching the guidelines for a theory of concepts as basic components of propositions.
Philosophical Studies, 1995
Philosophical Studies, 2018
The Reference Principle (RP) states that co-referring expressions are everywhere intersubstitutable salva congruitate. On first glance, (RP) looks like a truism, but a truism with some bite: (RP) promises to convert difficult philosophical questions about co-reference into easy grammatical questions about substitutability. This has led a number of philosophers to think that we can use (RP) to make short work of certain longstanding metaphysical debates: for example, it has been suggested that all we need to do to show that the predicate 'x is a horse' does not refer to a property is point out that 'x is a horse' and 'the property of being a horse' are not everywhere intersubstitutable salva congruitate. However, when we understand 'substitution' in the simplest and most straightforward way, (RP) is no truism; in fact, natural languages are full of counterexamples to the principle. In this paper, I introduce a new notion of substitution, and then develop and argue for a version of (RP) that is immune to these counterexamples. Along the way I touch on the following topics: the relation between argument forms and their natural language instances; the reification of sense; the difference between terms and predicates; and the relation between reference and disquotation. I end by arguing that my new version of (RP) cannot be used to settle metaphysical debates quite as easily as some philosophers would like.
History of Philosophy and Logical Analysis, 2001
It is a commonly held view that Frege's doctrine of senses and references is not compatible with the idea that there are de re beliefs. The present paper is meant to challenge that view. Moreover, it seeks to show that, instead of forcing Frege's semantic framework to answer questions raised by twentiethcentury philosophy of language, we had better find those questions to which it might be a proper answer. It is argued that the proper treatment of Frege's views requires the acknowledgment of the central role of individualistic epistemology in his thought. Once that feature is recognized, Frege's doctrine of senses and references can be considered a theory, or at least a sketch of a theory, of cognition, which has interesting connections with Kant's and Husserl's views. 1.
In order to accommodate his view that quantifiers are predicates of predicates within a type theory, Frege introduces a rule which allows a function name to be formed by removing a saturated name from another saturated name which contains it. This rule requires that each name has a rather rich syntactic structure, since one must be able to recognize the occurrences of a name in a larger name. However, I argue that Frege is unable to account for this syntactic structure. I argue that this problem undermines the inductive portion of Frege's proof that all of the names of his system denote in § §29-32 of The Basic Laws.
Introduction
On one formulation of Leibniz's Law, terms flanking true identities are everywhere intersubstitutable salva veritate: ''given a true statement of identity, one of its two terms may be substituted for the other in any true statement and the result will be true'' (Quine 1953: 139). This may be regimented as the following schema, where U½a=b is the result of substituting an occurrence of a for b in U.
SUBSTITUTION: ða ¼ b^UÞ ! U½a=b
Codifying this, it is tempting to hold that the schema SUBSTITUTION and its instances are valid.
One way to formally handle the sort of ambiguity posited by the Fregean-what Kaplan (1968) calls fanatical mono-denotationalism-would be to introduce distinct expressions for uses of names that have distinct referents. In fact, Frege himself recommended this method:
To avoid ambiguity, we ought really to have special signs in indirect speech, though their connection with the corresponding signs in direct speech should be easy to recognise. (Frege's 28-12-1902 letter to Russell; translated in Frege 1902Frege /1980 On this approach, (1) is not an instance of SUBSTITUTION at all on account of its ambiguity. For the purposes of assessing validity, ambiguous sentences should be replaced by their disambiguations. Thus, the false reading of (1) will be disambiguated as (1*), where an underlined expression refers to the customary sense of the expression without an underline. 1 (1*) If George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans and Twain knows that George Eliot wrote Middlemarch, then Twain knows that Mary Anne Evans wrote Middlemarch.
This sentence is not an instance of SUBSTITUTION and therefore its falsity is no threat to the validity of the law. A more relaxed Fregean approach tolerates some ambiguity in assessing validity. 2 There are various ways to construe validity when dealing with ambiguous languages. We will focus on one natural way to extend the notion of validity as applied to unambiguous languages. On this approach, a schema is valid only if all uniform disambiguations of its instances are true (or at least not false). 3 The injunction not to equivocate in the course of an argument makes the ambiguities disappear for logical purposes. (Kaplan 1986, 262) The falsity of (1) on most uses is due to the fact that its terms are not uniformly disambiguated. Uniform disambiguations of (1) can be represented by (1a) and (1b). Disambiguation 1ais true because its antecedent is false if 'George Eliot' and 'Mary Ann Evans' are taken to have their customary referent, namely the woman herself-the conjunct 'Twain knows that George Eliot wrote Middlemarch' is false. 4 Disambiguation (1b) is true because 'George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans' says falsely
Footnote 1 continued Denotation in Church 1951). See also Introduction to Mathematical Logic where Church speaks of ''eliminating the oblique uses of names by introducing special names to denote the senses which other names express'' (Church 1956: 8). See also Kaplan (1964) and Klement (2002: chapter 4). 2 Instead of analyzing the different contributions of an ambiguous expression in its different occurrences by introducing two expressions which univocally make these different contributions, an alternative strategy complicates the semantics for a single expression so that it makes different contributions in its different occurrences. See Pickel and Rabern (forthcoming) for discussion of these two methods for implementing Frege's proposal (cf. Kaplan 1964: 22-23).
3 See Lewis (1982: 438-441) for discussion of various options for a logic of ambiguity. Since Goodman and Lederman (2020) make their case in terms of the Kaplanian conception whereby there is an injunction against equivocation our diagnosis does as well. 4 According to Frege, Thoughts are the only objects of propositional attitudes. But 'Twain knows that George Eliot wrote Middlemarch' on the relevant disambiguation states that Twain stands in a relation to something that's not a Thought. ''A truth value cannot be a part of a Thought, any more than, say, the Sun can, for it is not a sense but an object'' (Frege 1892(Frege /1952. This argument assumes that the sense of 'wrote Middlemarch' can compose with the referent of 'George Eliot' resulting in something that's not a Thought. One way to support this would be to assume that the sense of 'wrote Middlemarch' is a function (Church 1951;Geach 1976, and Pickel (unpublished)) and follow Frege in assuming that all functions are total. An alternative approach would say that (1a) is undefined on the relevant disambiguation, in which case it is at least not false.
of the senses of the expressions 'George Eliot' and 'Mary Anne Evans' that they are the same. Thus, the fact that (1) is false on an equivocal use doesn't threaten the validity of SUBSTITUTION. In this way the Fregean can save the principle of SUBSTITUTION.
5
2 The argument and validity Goodman and Lederman (2020) argue that this Fregean strategy of explaining away apparent failures of SUBSTITUTION-by appeal to equivocation-leads to undesirable results, when combined with certain cherished principles of epistemic logic, such as what is known must be true. In their initial presentation, Goodman and Lederman offer an argument against the validity of (1) that rests on the validity of (3).
(3) If Kripke knows that George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans, then George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans
Goodman and Lederman's argument makes use of auxiliary premises. We will first consider and reject a straightforward version of this argument that makes use of auxiliary premises that the Fregean should accept. Given these auxiliary premises, we will argue that the Fregean has reason to reject the validity of (3). We will then consider and reject a more sophisticated version of the argument-closer to the text of Goodman and Lederman-that makes use of different auxiliary premises. In the case of this more sophisticated argument, we will argue that the Fregean should reject the auxiliary premises. The straightforward version of the argument presupposes two principles that we will call UNIFORMITY and CLOSURE. UNIFORMITY: Validities are true on every uniform disambiguation. CLOSURE: Validity is closed under classical propositional logic.
We have already seen that the Fregean should endorse UNIFORMITY so as not to invalidate SUBSTITUTION. Classical propositional logic preserves truth on a uniform disambiguation. So if some sentences are true on a uniform disambiguation, their consequences will also be true on that uniform disambiguation.
The problem is that (4) follows from (1) and (3) by classic propositional logic.
(4) If Kripke knows that George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans and Twain knows that George Eliot wrote Middlemarch, then Twain knows that Mary Anne Evans wrote Middlemarch.
Therefore, by CLOSURE, (4) is valid as well. But (4) is false even on the uniform disambiguation that disambiguates all occurrences of 'George Eliot' and 'Mary Anne Evans' as 'George Eliot' and 'Mary Anne Evans', respectively. Thus, by UNIFORMITY, (4) is not valid. This contradicts the assumption that both (1) and (3) are valid. Because they take for granted at this point that (3) is valid, Goodman and Lederman would suggest rejecting the validity of (1), and more generally of Leibniz's Law of substitution. 6 However, we believe that this rejects the wrong premise. Given UNIFORMITY-that every validity is true on every uniform disambiguation-it is clear that (3) cannot be valid. This might be surprising given the acceptability of normal utterances of (3). However, there is a difference between validity and acceptability for the Fregean. The Fregean should reject the validity of (3) despite the acceptability of its normal utterances, just they endorse the validity of (1) despite the unacceptability of its normal utterances. According to the Fregean, a normal utterance of (3) that is true would involve equivocation. The Fregean will disambiguate any usual utterance of (3) as the mixed disambiguation (3*), where the expressions under the attitude verb in the antecedent refer to their customary senses, but in the consequent they refer to their customary references.
(3*) If Kripke knows that George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans, then George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans.
This disambiguation corresponds to a normal utterance of (3) and it is true, but this doesn't show that (3) is valid. The requirement on validity outlined above was that any uniform disambiguation should yield a truth. But a uniform disambiguation of (3) would either interpret the names as referring to their customary references as in (3a) or their customary senses as in (3b) (or perhaps higher level senses). Disambiguation (3a) is true. In particular, (3a) has a false antecedent since the occurrence of 'George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans' refers to a truth-value instead of a Thought. But crucially, (3b) is not true. The antecedent of (3b) is true, since it makes the ordinary claim that Kripke stands in the knowledge relation to the Thought usually expresses by 'George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans'. But the consequent of (3b) refers to something that is not the True-namely the Thought that George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans. According to Frege's semantics, a material conditional refers to the False if the antecedent refers to the True while the consequent refers to something that is not the True (see Frege (1893/2013), §12). Thus (3b) is false, and therefore (3) has at least one uniform disambiguation that fails to be true. The argument here needn't rest on Frege's own semantics for the material conditional. Most reasonable accounts will say that a conditional with a true antecedent and a consequent that is not true is itself not true. Thus, the conditional (3b) is not true. Therefore, by UNIFORMITY, (3) is not valid. 7 The argument we've given so far subtly differs from the argument first considered by Goodman and Lederman (2020) in that they rely on a premise weaker than UNIFORMITY. Rather, they rely on a principle we will call UNIFORMITY* in addition to CLOSURE. UNIFORMITY*: Validities are not false on any uniform disambiguation. CLOSURE: Validity is closed under classical propositional logic.
The premise UNIFORMITY* does not require a validity to be true on every uniform disambiguation, but only that a validity fails to be false on every uniform disambiguation. Given our discussion above, one could reject Frege's own semantics for the conditional and hold that (3) is not false on disambiguation (3b)-instead it is undefined or gappy, and so merely untrue on this disambiguation. Thus, if UNIFORMITY* is assumed instead of UNIFORMITY, the untrue uniform disambiguation of (3) does not establish that it is invalid. 8 Appealing to UNIFORMITY*, Goodman and Lederman can offer an argument against the validity of (1) with the same structure as before.
In order for this argument to work, it must be possible for a sentence to be valid while being untrue on some uniform disambiguations. In particular, the argument takes as a premise that (3) is valid according to the relevant notion of validity. But it is untrue under some uniform disambiguations. Thus, this version of the argument requires not merely the truth of UNIFORMITY*, but the falsity of UNIFORMITY. The problem, from our point of view, is that familiar notions of validity with this structure do not satisfy CLOSURE. In particular, classical propositional logic preserves truth at a disambiguation. 9 We should not expect it to preserve lack of falsity at a disambiguation. For instance, Goodman and Lederman (2020: footnote 2) themselves observe (following Smiley 1967) that the notion of Strawsonvalidity-truth in all contexts where a sentence's presuppositions are satisfied-is not closed under classical propositional logic. Strawson-validity is not closed under classical propositional logic because the conclusion of an argument may be false at a context where the premises are merely untrue due to their presuppositions being unsatisfied. Analogously, a uniform disambiguation of an argument could make the conclusion false while making the premises merely untrue.
As we have said, the argument presupposes that (3) is valid on the relevant notion of validity. Given that (4) follows from (1) and (3) and yet is false on some uniform disambiguations (and therefore invalid), the Fregean should take this as prima facie evidence that the relevant notion of validity is not closed under classical propositional logic. This is not to say that there can be no notion of ''validity'' that satisfies CLOSURE and allows for validities that are untrue at a uniform disambiguation. But the relevant notion of validity must then be shown to be relevant to the Fregean's projects, and we don't see such an attempt in Goodman and Lederman (2020).
The argument and schmalidity
We have examined the argument that Goodman and Lederman provisionally consider for the invalidity of SUBSTITUTION and argued that one of its premises-that (3) is valid-is false. However, Goodman and Lederman move to an argument that rests on a different premise, that sentence (3) typifies that ''good status, however precisely it is understood...at which systematic theorizing about knowledge aims''. They call this good status schmalidity. We'll argue that the Fregean has no more reason to be impressed by an argument that appeals to schmalidity than they do to an argument that appeals to validity.
To infer that (1) is invalid from the fact that (3) is schmalid, Goodman and Lederman offer principles governing schmalidity. Paralleling our discussion above, we first examine straightforward versions of these principles that might govern this notion. We show that the schmalidity of (3) is not compatible with these principles.
SUBSET: Validities are schmalidities. UNIFORMITY-S: Schmalidities are true on every uniform disambiguation. CLOSURE-S: Schmalidity is closed under classical propositional logic.
From the validity of (1), it follows that (1) is schmalid, by SUBSET. From the schmalidity of (1) and (3) and CLOSURE-S, it follows that (4) is schmalid. But from the fact that (4) has a false uniform disambiguation, it follows by UNIFORMITY-S that (4) is not schmalid. The argument is then taken as a reductio of the schmalidityand therefore validity-of (1).
Footnote 9 continued which each ambiguous constituent is disambiguated the same way throughout all the premises and the conclusion, the conclusion is true on that disambiguation if the premises are.'' (Lewis 1982: 440) But given that (3) is schmalid, UNIFORMITY-S is not true. In particular, the argument above showed that (3) is not true under every uniform disambiguation. At best, it is true under any normal disambiguation. But these normal disambiguations are not uniform. Thus, the good status enjoyed by (3) is not of the sort that requires truth under every uniform disambiguation.
In their text, Goodman and Lederman appeal to a weaker version of UNIFORMITY-S. That is, they appeal to UNIFORMITY-S*.
UNIFORMITY-S*: Schmalidities are not false on any uniform disambiguation.
The principle UNIFORMITY-S* is compatible with the schmalidity of (3) even though (3) has an untrue uniform disambiguation. If (3) is schmalid, then it is possible for a sentence to be both schmalid and untrue on a uniform disambiguation. But, parallel to the discussion above, this brings CLOSURE-S into question. Schmalidity again has a structural similarity to Strawson-validity. Classical propositional logic preserves truth on a disambiguation. But we see no reason to expect it to preserve lack of falsity on a disambiguation. Therefore, the Fregean should be no more impressed by this argument than they were by the argument above.
Fregean factivity
But can the Fregean do justice to the apparent ''good status'' of (3)? We think so. As we mentioned, the Fregean will disambiguate any usual utterance of (3) as the mixed disambiguation (3*), which is true. This disambiguation isn't easily statable as an obviously valid schema, such as pKnowsðUÞ ! Uq, because the instances of U and the terms they contain will need to be disambiguated differently in the different contexts. However, the fact that ordinary assertions of (3) almost always are disambiguated as (3*) is-we believe-a sign of good status.
Goodman and Lederman might still ask: can the Fregean offer a valid principle that does justice to the factivity of knowledge? Fortunately, they can. The gloss of factivity mentioned above-what is known is true-can be straightforwardly regimented as a validity. Let us introduce an operator True(.), the referent of which applies to a Thought just in case that Thought presents the True.
FREGEAN FACTIVITY: KnowsðUÞ ! TrueðUÞ
The Fregean can accept this as a valid schema. Notice that it is true on any uniform disambiguation: So long as U refers to a Thought, if someone stands in the knowledge relation to the referent of U, then the referent of U presents the True.
What's more, this factivity schema has the following valid instance.
(5) If Kripke knows that George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans, then it is true that George Eliot is Mary Anne Evans.
This instance is interesting because Frege is a redundancy theorist of truth. The sense of an utterance of pIt is true that Uq is the same as the sense of a corresponding utterance of U. 10 This means that although the Fregean should deny that (3) is valid, there is a natural picture according to which ordinary utterances of (3) express the same Thought as a uniform disambiguation of a validity, namely (5). In this respect, ordinary utterances of (3) are in very good logical standing. 11 Importantly, this good feature of (3)-ordinarily expressing the same Thought as a uniform disambiguation of a logical truth-is not preserved under logical consequence and doesn't require truth under all uniform disambiguations. Thus, if the feature we have characterised is called ''schmalidity'', then CLOSURE-S and UNIFORMITY-S are both false.
Conclusion
We have argued that the Fregean need not accept the classical consequences of whatever good status is enjoyed by sentence (3), because (3) is not true on all uniform disambiguations. This blocks Goodman and Lederman's argument for the invalidity of (1). However, the fact that (3) is not true on all uniform disambiguations does not entail that ordinary utterances of (3) are untrue just as holding that (1) is valid does not entail that ordinary utterances of (1) are true. Instead the Fregean ought to endorse the validity of (5), and more generally the schema FREGEAN FACTIVITY. In light of this, the Fregean can still maintain that (3) has very good logical status in that any ordinary utterance will be true and will express the same Thought as a valid sentence under a uniform disambiguation.
There is a methodological lesson here. The good (or bad) status of various utterances of sentences in ordinary reasoning does not automatically align with their validity. If a language exhibits ambiguities, then these ambiguities may ordinarily be resolved according to certain patterns. However, there is no antecedent reason to presuppose that these patterns correspond to the resolutions required to assess the validity of the ambiguous sentence. In the case of (1), although it is true on any uniform disambiguation, it is typically unacceptable. In contrast, although (3) is typically acceptable, it's false or untrue on some uniform disambiguations. Therefore, given the choice-adopted by Fregeans such as Kaplan-to assess validity in terms of uniform disambiguations, (1) is valid but unacceptable and (3) is invalid but acceptable. Acceptability of normal utterances should not be conflated with validity. 12 For a language that exhibits the sort of ambiguities posited by the Fregean various theoretical choices must be made about the operative notion of validitychoices must even be made about the ultimate bearers of validity. We have, for the most part, made our case in terms of Goodman and Lederman's basic presuppositions about logic. Others may well question these background presuppositions, and thereby provide a different diagnosis of Goodman and Lederman's argument. For example, one might question the assumption that the bearers of validity are ambiguous sentence types instead of disambiguated sentence types, or sentences in a context. (We are sympathetic.) A proponent of genuine opacity may make a different choice about how to assess validity in an ambiguous language. But there is still no antecedent guarantee that validity will entail ordinary acceptability or viceversa.