Discussion Paper #D-16/2004
On the Measurement of Risk Aversion from
Experimental Data
by
Mette Wik, Tewodros Aragie Kebede, Olvar Bergland and Stein Holden
Department of Economics and Resource Management
Agricultural University of Norway
PO Box 5033, NO-1432 Ås, Norway
http:/www.nlh.no/ior/
e-mail:
[email protected]
This series consists of papers intended to stimulate discussion. Some of
the papers are of a preliminary character and should thus not be referred
to or quoted without permission from the author(s).
The interpretations and conclusions in this paper are those of the
author(s) and do not necessarily represent the views of the Department of
Economics and Resource Management nor of the Agricultural University
of Norway.
1
On the Measurement of Risk Aversion from Experimental Data
Mette Wik
Tewodros Aragie Kebede
Olvar Bergland
Stein T. Holden
Department of Economics and Resource Management,
Agricultural University of Norway, P.O. Box 5003, 1432 Ås, Norway
E-mail address:
[email protected]
Abstract
Attitudes towards risk are measured for households in Northern Zambia using an
experimental gambling approach with real payoffs that at maximum were equal to 30
percent of average total annual income per capita. The results of the experiment
show decreasing absolute risk aversion and increasing partial risk aversion.
Determinants of risk aversion are investigated using random effects interval
regression model exploiting the panel data structure of the repeated experiments.
Wealth indicator variables are found to be significant and partial relative risk
aversion decreases as wealth increases. Females are found to be more risk averse
than males.
Keywords risk aversion, random effects interval regression, expected utility, Zambia
2
I. Introduction
Knowledge of how subsistence farmers make decisions is important in determining
strategies for agricultural development. There is evidence that poor peasant farmers
are risk averse (Moscardi and de Janvry, 1977; Dillon and Scandizzo, 1978;
Binswanger, 1980, 1981, 1982 and Binswanger and Sillers, 1983), and that their
production and economic environments are characterized by a high degree of
uncertainty (Roumasset, 1976). These general conclusions and observations have
stimulated extensive research into the effects of risk on peasants' adaptation.
Considerable research has attempted to provide empirical evidence of
individuals' risk attitudes. These attempts can be classified into two general
categories: econometric approach, and experimental elicitation techniques. The
econometric approach is based on individuals' actual behaviour. The pioneering work
by Moscardi and de Janvry (1977) used a safety-first rule approach. Later, individual
risk attitudes have been elicited assuming expected utility maximization. One of the
best-known methods is that of Antle (1983, 1987, 1989), but Bardsley and Harris
(1987), Love and Buccola (1991), Pope and Just (1991), Saha et al. (1994), Chavas
and Holt (1996) and Bar-Shira et al. (1997) are all examples of econometric
approaches assuming expected utility maximization. The econometric approach is
criticized for confounding risk behaviour with other factors such as resource
constraints faced by decision makers (Eswaran and Kotwal 1990). Thus, it may
appear as if individuals are more risk averse than they truly are (Binswanger 1982,
Wik and Holden, 1996). This is particularly important in developing countries where
market imperfections are prominent and production and consumption decisions,
therefore, are non-separable (Singh et al., 1986, de Janvry et al., 1991, Sadoulet and
de Janvry 1995).
3
The experimental approach is based on hypothetical questions regarding risk
alternatives or risky games with or without real payments. Dillon and Scandizzo
(1978) used hypothetical questions to elicit risk attitudes of subsistence farmers in
northeast Brazil. Binswanger (1980, 1981), Binswanger and Sillers (1983) and
Quizon et al. (1984) used risk games with real payments to measure peasants' risk
preferences in a large-scale experiment in rural India. Others who have applied the
same general experimental method are Sillers (1980) in the Philippines, Walker
(1980) in El Salvador, Grisley and Kellog (1987) in Thailand, and Miyata (2003) in
Indonesia.
The existing experimental methods have one limitation in that they have not
explored fully the potential of the available experimental data. Since the studies have
conducted the experiments repeatedly at different levels of risk, the availability of
repeated data on individuals can be explored in panel data structure to understand the
interactions and dynamics of risk aversion when individuals are exposed to different
experimental levels of risk. In this study, using the experimental approach carried out
in northern Zambia, we apply both a panel data technique and a pooled interval
regression to measure risk attitude, and identify how these estimates are correlated
with individual and socio-economic characteristics such as sex, age, wealth etc. In
Section 2, we briefly discuss expected utility (EU) theory and define some measures
for risk aversion. Section 3 presents the methodological approach for the experiment.
In section 4, we present the results of the experiment. Section 5 discusses the
empirical framework. Empirical results are discussed in section 6. Section 7
concludes.
II. Measures of Risk Aversion
4
Risk aversion is defined with reference to the von Neumann-Morgenstern expected
utility function. The three measures most commonly used are: (1) absolute risk
aversion A(W) (Pratt, 1964); (2) relative risk aversion R(W) (Arrow, 1971); and (3)
partial risk aversion P(Wo ,π ) (Menezes and Hanson, 1970 and Zeckhauser and
Keeler, 1970):
A(W ) = −
U ′′(W )
U ′′(Wo )
U ′′(π )
=−
=−
U ′(W )
U ′(Wo )
U ′(π )
R(W ) = −W
U ′′(W )
= WA(W )
U ′(W )
P(Wo ,π ) = −π
U ′′(Wo + π )
= πA(Wo + π )
U ′(Wo + π )
where W indicates total wealth, U ′ and U ′′ indicate the first and second derivatives
of the expected utility function, W0 denotes initial wealth and π denotes stochastic
income. At the point ( W = Wo + π ) the three measures are related to each other as:
R(W ) = Wo A(W ) + P(Wo ,π )
Absolute risk aversion is an appropriate measure to describe situations in
which income or gain is fixed, and initial wealth is variable. It is commonly assumed
that absolute risk aversion decreases as wealth rises, which implies that wealthier
individuals should be more willing to accept a given fair gamble. When both income
and initial wealth change proportionally, relative risk aversion is the appropriate
measure. Arrow (1971) hypothesised increasing relative risk aversion. This implies
that an individual's willingness to accept a gamble decreases when both wealth and
all outcomes of a fair gamble are increased proportionally. The measure of partial
5
risk aversion is appropriate to describe situations when initial wealth is fixed and
income is variable. Bar-Shira et al. (1997) show that decreasing absolute risk
aversion (DARA) implies decreasing partial risk aversion (DPRA) with respect to
initial wealth, and that increasing relative risk aversion (IRRA) implies increasing
partial risk aversion (IPRA) with respect to income. The opposite does not
necessarily hold. It is possible to have DRRA and IPRA at the same time.
III. Experimental Procedure
The setting
The study was carried out in 110 randomly sampled households in 6 different
villages in Northern Zambia in 1994. Three villages were situated in a fairly densely
populated area (26-82 persons/km2) close to the province capital, Kasama. The
remaining three villages were located in a rather sparsely populated area (<6
persons/km2) approximately 60 km further north. All households except 4 were
cultivating land. Farmers in this area of Zambia participate in two main production
systems. They produce several crops in a traditional slash and burn system called
chitemene, and they produce monoculture maize in “permanent” fields. On average,
each household cultivates 1.4 ha of land, out of which 0.6 ha is used for maize
production. Average total income per capita (including own consumption of major
subsistence crops) was very low, approximately 65,000 Kwi, or roughly 110 US $.
Survey procedure
In the experiment, subjects were confronted with a series of choices among sets of
alternative prospects (gambles) involving real money payment. The amounts of
money were relatively large compared to average income in the area. (The highest
6
possible gain was approximately 30 percent of average total annual income per
capita.) The subject's choice among these alternative prospects is taken as an
indication of the degree of her risk aversion.
The experiment follows a method developed by Binswanger (1980). A series
of schedules of prospects (called games) similar to those shown in Table 1 were
presented to each subject. Each game lists six prospects, each with 50% probability
of winning. Each subject was asked to select one of the six prospects: O, A, B, C, D,
or E. Once chosen, a coin was tossed and the subject received the left hand amount if
the coin showed heads and the right hand amount if the coin showed tails. If the
subject selected alternative O, she received 100 Kw whether she got a head or a tail.
If she chose alternative A instead of O, her expected gain increased by 35 Kw, but a
bad luck alternative (heads) would now give her 10 Kw less in return than she would
have received with the safe alternative O. In other words, in choosing A instead of O,
the standard deviation in gain is increased from 0 to 45 Kw. For the successive
alternatives, A to B, B to C, and C to D, the same is true: the expected gain increases,
but so does the spread between the two outcomes. Alternative D and E have the same
expected gain, but alternative E has larger spread.
(Table 1 approx. here)
When risk is viewed in terms of uncertainty in gains, income, or wealth, as in
utility-based choice theories, the prospects involve more risk the further down one
gets in Table 1. This means that a decision maker possessing a utility function
concave in wealth, income or gain would demand a higher risk premium to accept
prospect B rather than its expected outcome than she would demand to accept
prospect A rather than its expected outcome. Whether she prefers prospect B to
prospect A depends on the degree of concavity of her utility function. The different
7
prospects classified from extreme risk aversion (alternative O) to neutral to
preferring (alternative E).
To get a unique risk aversion coefficient for each game level, we used the
utility function with constant partial risk aversion (CPRA): U = (1 − γ )w(1−γ ) where w
is the certainty equivalent of the prospect. The parameter γ will then be equivalent
to the constant partial risk aversion coefficient. The fifth column of Table 1 shows
the end points of the constant partial risk aversion coefficients implied by each
possible choice.
The games were played at different levels. Each individual played games 1 to
7 (Table 2) during the first visit, and games 8 through 14 during a visit two weeks
later. All gains-only games (game 1 to 11) were derived from 100 Kw game by
multiplying all amounts by 10, 50 or 100. The 100 Kw game was played five times,
the 1,000 Kw three times, the 5,000 Kw game two times, and the 10,000 Kw game
was played once.
(Table 2 approx. here)
Most of the games were real, i.e. the individual actually received the
payment. Because of budget restrictions, we also included hypothetical games. Game
10 was played with real payment for one individual in the household and as a
hypothetical game for the other. Before starting the experiments the individuals were
told that a few of the games would be hypothetical, but they were not told which
games would be hypothetical and which would be real. After each game they were
paid the gain if the game was real, or otherwise told the game was hypothetical. In
this way we hoped the individuals would play all games as if they were real.
The three gain-and-losses games were played at 100, 1000 and 5000 Kw
level. The first two games were real, and the last game was hypothetical. In this case,
8
the subjects knew that the game was hypothetical. It is however, difficult to ask poor
peasants to participate in games with real losses and put their own money at risk.
First, it is hard to defend morally. Second, it would often not be possible to carry out
such an experiment, because many would not have sufficient cash to allow them to
select one of the riskier alternatives if they so desired. In this case the analyst would
no longer be able to distinguish between pure risk aversion and the effect of liquidity
constraints. To reduce this effect, we played the gains-and-losses games immediately
after having played four rounds of gains-only games. The gains and losses games
were only administered to those individuals who had won sufficient money in the
previous four games.
IV Experimental Results
The risk aversion distributions corresponding to different game levels are given in
Table 3. The first panel shows the distribution for the games with gains-only, while
the third panel shows the distribution for games with gains and losses. Note that the
distribution was rather widely spread over all classes of risk aversion, but as the
game level rose, the distribution shifted to the left, i.e., risk aversion increased. Even
at the lowest level of the game, more than 20 percent chose the alternatives
representing severe to extreme degree of risk aversion. When the game level
increased to Kw. 10,000, more than 35 percent chose the two most risk averse
alternatives. Considering the slight-to-neutral and neutral-to-preferring alternatives,
the percentage choosing these alternatives was reduced from 28 percent at the Kw.
100 game level to only 11 percent in the Kw. 10,000 level. The share of responses
falling into the intermediate and moderate risk aversion categories remained fairly
stable at 45 to 50 percent for all game levels. It appears that the majority of people
9
with initially low levels of risk aversion increased to moderate to intermediate risk
aversion when game levels rise. For individuals who initially had moderate to
intermediate levels of risk aversion, the level seemed to increase more slowly.
For games with gains and losses we see the tendency of increased risk
aversion when game levels increase. In addition, we see an inclination of people
being more risk averse in these games than in games with gains-only. At the Kw.
1,000 level, more than 45 percent chose the two most risk averse alternatives, while
only 12 percent chose the two most risky alternatives. For the gains-only game at
Kw. 1,000 level, we found 29 and 24 percent in the respective categories.
(Table 3 approx. here)
The data in Table 3 suggest that individuals are risk averse and they tend to
get more risk averse when the size of the gamble increases. Later in the study we will
formally test the hypothesis of increasing partial risk aversion with respect to the size
of the gamble. We will also test whether people are more risk averse in games with
losses than in games with gains only.
V Empirical Framework
The participants have, through choosing between six different prospects, revealed
which alternative gives the highest utility. Assuming constant partial risk aversion,
each observed response represents a category of risk aversion in which the true but
unobservable risk aversion falls within. The games were played repeatedly at
different game levels. Then by creating a panel data structure the availability of
repeated information can be exploited.
Suppose the latent dependent variable, risk aversion, y *gm satisfies a classical
linear model:
10
y *gm = x g β + v gm
where g is the index of individual g in the experiment, and m is the index of game
number m. Mg is the size of the experiment, and G is the number of individuals. The
1× K
vector
x g contains
explanatory
variables.
We
also
assume
v gm = c g + u gm , m = 1,..., M g where c g is an unobserved individual effect and u gm is
the idiosyncratic error. y *gm is never observed, but only the range that it falls into, i.e.
the data is interval coded. More specifically, the observed variable y gm is now
defined as:
( )
y gm ≡ t gm y *gm
=O
=A
if
=B
if
=D
if
=C
=E
if
if
if
y *gm ≥ 7.5
7.5 > y *gm ≥ 2.0
2.0 > y *gm ≥ 0.812
0.812 > y *gm ≥ 0.316
0.316 > y *gm ≥ 0 and
0 > y *gm
When risk aversion is grouped into intervals, we say that we have intervalcoded data. If we observed risk aversion y * we would just use Ordinary Least
Squares (OLS) to estimate β . However, because we only observe whether risk
aversion falls into one of several cells, we have a data-coding problem (Wooldridge
2002). We can still consistently estimate β using the method of maximum
likelihood if we make some distributional assumptions.
values are calculated across groups of observations. Assuming cg ~ N (0,σ c2 ) and
Since the observations in the panel data set are not independent, likelihood
(
)
u gm ~ N 0,σ u2 , the likelihood for the gth group of observations is
11
7.5 − x gm β − c g
M 1( y gm = O )Φ1 −
σu
g
Lg = ∫ ∏
− x gm β − c g
− ∞ m = 1
+ 1( y gm = E )Φ
σu
∞
U − x gm β − c g
D
+ ∑ 1( y gm = i )Φ i
σu
=
i
1
L − x gm β − c g
− Φ i
σu
2
1 c g
−
2 σ c2
1
e
dc g
2π σ c
where Ui and Li are the upper and lower bounds of interval i, i=A,…D; Φ (.) is the
cumulative density of normal distribution.
For a comparison, we also propose estimating an interval regression model
reduces to y *gm = xgm β + u gm with u gm ~ N (0,σ u2 ) . The pooled interval regression is
disregarding the panel data structure, i.e. on the pooled data. Hence our model
also estimated using the method of maximum likelihood. The likelihood function for
the pooled interval data is
U − xgm β − cg
7.5 − xgm β − cg D
L − xgm β − cg
+ ∑1( y gm = i )Φ i
− Φ i
1( y gm = O )Φ1 −
G
σu
σu
σu
i =1
= ∏∏
g =1 m =1
+ 1( y = E )Φ − xgm β − cg
gm
σ
u
Mg
Lgm
where Ui and Li are the upper and lower bounds of interval i, i=A,…D; Φ(.) is the
cumulative density of normal distribution. These models can be easily estimated
using the standard software, STATA 8.2.
Risk Aversion and personal characteristics
In this section we discuss why and how some socio-economic variables and personal
characteristics might be correlated with some of the variation in risk aversion.
From theory and the common assumption of DARA, we would expect
wealthier individuals to be less risk averse. We have included several different
wealth variables in the model (income per capita, cash liquidity per capita and
education).
This is because asset market imperfections severely constrain
substitution between different categories of wealth (Reardon and Vosti, 1995;
Holden et al., 1998). Under such conditions each asset category may have an
12
independent correlation with risk aversion. All the wealth variables are expected to
be negatively correlated with risk aversion.
Household size can have two opposing effects on risk aversion. On the one
hand, household size can be viewed as a wealth variable. A larger family could
represent an increased labour force for the household and thus have a negative effect
on risk aversion. Furthermore, household size may also have an indirect negative
effect on risk aversion in terms of providing insurance, diversification and coping
opportunities. On the other hand, a larger family means more people to feed, which
may increase risk aversion. We believe that in poor peasant societies, where children
start to work at a young age, the first effect is more prominent; while in a developed
economy the second would be more common. Earlier studies are inconclusive.
Moscardi and deJanvry (1977) and Feinermann and Finkelshtain (1996) found that
increased family size is leading to more cautious and conservative behaviour, while
Dillon and Scandizzo (1978) found that farmers with larger households were less
risk averse.
In most cases, total farm area would represent a type of household wealth. In
Northern Zambia, however, there was abundance of land and access to land was not
considered a binding constraint. Since access to land is free (except for labour costs
of cultivating and transactions costs due to distance from the homestead), we
suppose cultivating more land could be a risk-coping strategy for the risk averse.
Farmers in the study area participate in two main production systems. They
produce several crops in a slash and burn system called chitemene, and they produce
monoculture maize in «permanent» fields. Maize production is dependent upon use
of chemical fertilisers. This production requires access to credit and a supply of
fertilizer. Maize production is considered a more risky activity by the farmers than
13
the production of other crops in chitemene (Wik and Holden, 1996). We would
therefore expect more risk averse farmers to have a relatively smaller area for
maize-production than would less risk averse farmers. Both total farmland and area
of maize are included in the model as per-capita variables.
Due to very different roles of men and women in this society, we included a
gender dummy-variable in the model (men=0, women=1). We believe that different
attitudes to risk might reflect gender differences in the society. In this society we
expect women to be more risk averse than men. Women have more responsibilities
for providing and preparing the food and for feeding and caring for the children.
Traditionally, men were warriors, and supposed to engage in dangerous and risky
activities. They should, according to Richards (1939), be brave and willing to take
risk to achieve status in the society.
We also included a variable for the age of the decision-maker. Moscardi and
deJanvry (1977) writes, «it is generally assumed that older farmers tend to be less
prone to take risks than younger ones...» We find this to be an assumption without
any theoretical grounding, and include the variable, without any a priori expectation
of the sign.
To believe that past experience with a random process (such as tossing a
coin), would influence a person’s next choice, is not common in economic theory.
Psychologists, on the other hand, would find it surprising to think that such past
experience would not influence future choices. To check whether previous luck had
a significant effect on subject’s choices, we included a dummy variable defined as
∑Xi, where i is the game number of previous games (for game 11, i would be 1, 2,
3... 10), and X takes the value of 1 when the person wins (tails) and -1 when he
looses (heads). Binswanger (1980) found the effect of previous luck to be highly
14
significant. We expect to find that previous luck does affect people’s choices.
Subjects who have experienced previous luck will be more willing to take risk than
subjects who have experienced previous losses.
As we saw in the section on theory, it has been common in economics to
consider risk by looking at changes in total wealth. We saw that another aspect of
asset integration is that opportunity losses should be treated in the same way as real
losses. Empirical evidence has shown that this is usually not the case. As the famous
basketball player and coach Larry Bird remarked, «Loosing hurts more than winning
feels good». Research in both economics and psychology has found this to be true
(Markowitz, 1952; Kahneman and Tversky, 1979; Hershey and Schoemaker, 1980;
Sillers, 1980). People are more risk averse when it comes to losses than to gains. In
their prospect theory, Kahneman and Tversky (1979) proposed a convex utility for
losses that was steeper for losses than the concave utility for gains. Markowitz
(1952) and Hershey and Schoemaker (1980) proposed a utility function in gains and
losses, which was concave for small losses and convex for larger ones. To test for a
difference between gains-only and gains and losses games we have included a
dummy-variable for losses where 0 is equal to gains-only games and 1 is equal to
games with gains and losses. We expect to find that people are more risk averse in
games with losses.
To test whether the level of gains in the games influenced individuals’ risk
aversion, we included a variable of overall expected outcome of each particular
game. Other researchers (Binswanger, 1980, 1981; Sillers, 1980) have found
evidence of people getting more risk averse when there are bigger gains/losses at
stake, i.e., that their utility function exhibits increasing partial risk aversion (IPRA)
15
with respect to the possible income of the games. We therefore expect the sign of
this variable to be positive.
VI Empirical Results
In our econometric analysis, we have included all 11 games in the data set. In the
regression, we have assigned the same categories for the choices in the “gains and
losses” alternatives as for the gains-only alternatives. To check whether individuals
actually treat real losses in the same way as opportunity gains and losses, we
included a dummy variable for games with losses.
A random effects interval regression model and a pooled interval regression
model are estimated on the data, using the lower and upper boundaries of the interval
for the unobserved risk aversion level, corresponding to the observed choice of the
individual, as the dependent variable. Table 4 shows the results from estimating
these models.
(Table 4 approx. here)
The estimates of the random effects model and pooled OLS regression are
similar in sign and magnitude. The advantage of using the random effects model is
that it gives more efficient and reliable estimates. The Breusch and Pagan (1980)
Lagrange multiplier (LM) test provides a test of random effects model against the
pooled interval regression model. The specific hypothesis under investigation is the
following:
H0 : σ c = 0
HA :σc ≠ 0
.
The p-value of this test, shown in the table, is found to be highly significant
suggesting that random effects model is more suitable in analysing the data at hand.
The consistency of this test may be understood by looking at the education and maize
16
per capita variables. These variables are highly significant in the pooled interval
regression model but not in the random effects model. This comes from having a
more reliable and efficient estimate of the standard errors in using the random effects
model. Therefore, the discussion here after will be based on the results from the
random effects model.
Most of the variables are significant in the random effects model. The wealth
variables- log of income per capita and household size are significant at 5%
significance levels. All these variables have negative signs indicating that higher
wealth is correlated with lower degrees of risk aversion. This is consistent with the
common assumption of Decreasing Absolute Risk Aversion (DARA). The cash per
capita variable is not significant. The result on the household size variable indicates
that the effect of household size as providing labour and improved possibilities of
insurance, diversification and coping opportunities are more important than the effect
of more people to feed. In this way it seems like farm households in this area behave
as if household size is a wealth variable.
We also find that the total farm area per capita variable is positively
correlated with risk aversion, supporting our hypothesis that when land is abundant,
cultivating more land would be a risk coping strategy.
Gender differences seem to be significantly correlated (1% level) with
differences in risk aversion. We found that women were more risk averse than men.
We found no significant correlation between age and risk aversion.
Previous luck in random processes seems to influence a person's next choice.
The prior luck variable was highly significant (1% level). This suggests a strong
impact of prior luck, and may thus imply that people are correcting their subjective
probabilities as the game progresses.
17
The dummy variable for loss is also significant at 1% level, and strongly
supports the hypothesis that people are more risk averse in games with losses than in
games with gains only. This result is also an indication that people do not treat
opportunity losses in the same way as real losses, and thus, that asset integration does
not hold.
We also found that the level of the game has a strong, significant impact on
how large a risk people prefer to take in these types of games. People seem to be
willing to take less risk when higher gains are at stake. This implies that people are
revealing increasing partial risk aversion (IPRA) with respect to the game income
level.
Another important indicator in the regression is a dummy variable that
indicate whether the games is hypothetical or real. The dummy variable, type, is
found to be insignificant indicating that there is no significant difference if the game
is designed as a hypothetical or real game. This result may be induced from mixing
real and hypothetical games in the design of the experiment. If this result is
replicable in other studies, it may suggest a cost effective way of carrying out such
experiments.
VII Conclusion
This study measured attitudes towards risk for individuals in Northern Zambia using
an experimental gambling approach, similar to that of Binswanger (1980) and Sillers
(1980), with real payoffs. The games were defined as both “gains only” and “gainsand-losses” games. Highest possible real gain was approximately equal to 30 percent
of average total annual income per capita.
18
In the low levels of games, individuals' choice of alternatives is evenly spread
from severe to slight-to-neutral risk aversion. When game level rose, the distribution
shifted towards a more risk averse attitude, and 80% of the people revealed moderate
to extreme risk aversion. We also found that people were more risk averse in games
with gains and losses than in games with gains only.
The main contribution of the study is to exploit the panel data structure
arising from the repeated nature of the experiments. Random effects interval
regression and pooled interval regression models are estimated. Existence of random
effects is tested and is found to be highly significant relative to the pooled interval
regression model. Hence, using random effects interval regression model, we
obtained more efficient and reliable estimates in investigating determinants of partial
risk aversion.
The results indicate that utility functions should exhibit increasing partial risk
aversion and that they should be defined over gains and losses. Wealth does,
however, also have a significant effect on partial risk aversion. We found evidence of
decreasing absolute risk aversion (DARA) when wealth increases.
19
References
Antle, J. M. (1983) Testing the Stochastic Structure of Production: A flexible
Moment-based Approach, Journal of Business and Economic Statistics, 1,
192-201.
Antle, J. M. (1987) Econometric Estimation of Producers' Risk Attitudes, American
Journal of Agricultural Economics, 69(3), 509-522.
Antle, J. M. (1989) Nonstructural Risk Attitude Estimation, American Journal of
Agricultural Economics, 71(3), 774-784.
Arrow, K. J. (1971) Essays in the Theory of Risk Bearing. Amsterdam: North
Holland.
Bardsley, P. and M. Harris (1987) An Approach to Econometric Estimation of
Attitudes to Risk in Agriculture, Australian Journal of Agricultural
Economics, 31, 112-226.
Bar-Shira, Z., R. E. Just and D. Zilberman (1997) Estimation of Farmers' Risk
Attitude: An Econometric Approach, Agricultural Economics, 17, 211-222.
Binswanger, H. P. and D. A. Sillers (1983) Risk Aversion and Credit Constraints n
Farmers' Decision Making: A Reinterpretation, Journal of Development
Studies, 20, 5-21.
Binswanger, H. P. (1980) Attitudes toward Risk: Experimental Measurement in
Rural India, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 62, 395-407.
Binswanger, H. P. (1981) Attitudes toward Risk: Theoretical Implications of an
Experiment in Rural India, The Economic Journal, 91, 867-890.
Binswanger, H. P. (1982) Empirical Estimation and Use of Risk Preferences:
Discussion, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 64, 391-393.
20
Breusch, T. S. and A. R. Pagan (1979) The LM Test and its Applications to Model
Specification in Econometrics, Review of Economic Studies, 47, 239-254.
Chavas, J. P. and M. T. Holt (1996) Economic Behaviour Under Uncertainty: A Joint
Analysis of Risk Preferences and Technology, Review of Economics and
Statistics, 78, 329-335.
de Janvry, A., M. Fafchamps and E. Sadoulet (1991) Peasant Household Behaviour
With Missing Markets: Some Paradoxes Explained, The Economic Journal,
101, 1400-1417.
Dillon, J. L. and Scandizo (1978) Risk Attitudes of Subsistence Farmers in Northeast
Brazil: A Sampling Approach, American Journal of Agricultural
Economics, 60, 425-434.
Eswaran M. and A. Kotwal (1990) Implications of Credit Constraints for Risk
Behaviour in Less Developed Economies, Oxford Economic Papers, 13,
149-161.
Feinermann,
E.
and
I.
Finkelshtain
(1996)
Introducing
Socio-economic
Characteristics into Production Analysis under Risk, Agricultural
Economics, 13, 149-161.
Grisely, W. and Kellog, E. (1987) Risk-taking preferences of farmers in northern
Thailand: measurements and implications, Agricultural Economics, 1, 12742.
Hershey, J. C., and Schoemaker, P. J. H. (1980) Risk Taking and Problem Context in
the Domain of Losses: An Expected Utility Analysis, The Journal of Risk
and Insurance, 47(1), 111-132.
Kahneman, D and Tversky (1979) Prospect Theory: an Analysis of Decision under
Risk, Econometrica, 47(2), 263-291.
21
Love, H. A. and S. T. Buccola (1991) Joint Risk Preference- Technology Estimation
with a Primal System, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 73,
765-774.
Markowitz, H (1952) The utility of wealth, Journal of Political Economy, 60, 151158.
Menezes, C. F. and D. L. Hanson (1970) On the Theory of risk Aversion,
International Economics Review, 11, 181-187.
Miyata, S (2003) Household’s Risk Attitudes in Indonesian Villages, Applied
Economics, 35, 573-583.
Moscardi, E. and A. de Janvry (1977) Attitudes towards Risk among peasants: An
Econometric Approach, American Journal of Agricultural Economics, 59,
710-776.
Pope, R. D. and R. E. Just (1991) On Testing the Structure of Risk Preferences in
Agricultural
Supply
Analysis,
American
Journal
of
Agricultural
Economics, 73, 743-748.
Pratt, J. (1964) Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large, Econometrica, 32, 122136.
Quizon, J. B., H. P. Binswanger and M. J. Machina (1984) Attitudes Toward Risk:
Further Remarks, The Economic Journal, 94, 144-148.
Reardon, Thomas A. and S. A. Vosti. (1995) Links between rural poverty and
environment in developing countries: Asset categories and 'investment
poverty, World Development 23 (9): 1495-1506.
Richards, A (1939) Land, labour and Diet in Northern Rhodesia. An Economic Study
of Bemba Tribe. London, Oxford University Press.
22
Roumasset, J. A. (1976) Rice and Risk: Decision making among Low-Income
Farmers. North Holland, Amsterdam.
Sadoulet, E. and A. de Janvry (1995): Quantitative Development Policy Analysis.
The John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore and London.
Saha, A., R. Shumway and H. Talpaz (1994) Joint Estimation of Risk Preference
Structure and Technology Using Expo-Power Utility, American Journal of
Agricultural Economics, 76, 173-184.
Sillers, D. A. (1980) Measuring Risk Preferences of Rice Farmers in Nueva Ecija,
Philippines: an Experimental Approach. Dissertation (PhD). Yale
University, Department of Economics.
Singh, I., L. Squire and J. Strauss (1986) An overview of Agricultural Household
Model-The Basic Model: Theory, Empirical Results, and Policy
Conclusions, in Agricultural Household Models, Extensions, Applications
and Policy, (Ed.) Sing, I., L. Squire and J. Strauss. Baltimore: The World
Bank and the John Hopkins University Press.
Walker, T. S. (1980) Decision Making by Farmers and by the National Agricultural
Research Program on the Adoption and Development of Maize Varieties in
El Salvador. Dissertation (PhD). Stanford Food Research Institute,
Stanford, California.
Wik, M. and S. T. Holden (1996) Risk and Peasant Adaptation: Do Peasants behave
according to Sandmo Model?, Agricultural University of Norway
Department of Economics and Resource Management Discussion Paper
#D-24.
Wooldridge, Jeffrey M. (2002) Econometric analysis of cross section and panel data.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
23
Zeckahuser, R. and Keeler E. (1970) Another type of risk aversion, Econometrica,
38, 661-665.
24
Table 1. Payoffs and corresponding risk aversion for ”gains-only” games at 100 Kw
level.
Bounds on
Risk Aversion
parameter of
Prospect
Bad Luck Payoff
Good Luck Payoff
class
CPRA function
O
100
100
Extreme
>7.5
A
90
180
Severe
7.5-2.0
B
80
240
Intermediate
2.0-0.812
C
60
300
Moderate
0.812-0.316
D
20
380
Slight to neutral
0.316-0
0
400
Neutral to
<0
E
preferring
25
Table 2. Sequence and Level of Games
Day
Game Number
Game Level in
Type
Kwacha (Kw)
I) Gains Only
Day 1
1
100
real
’’
2
100
real
’’
3
100
real
’’
4
1,000
hypothetical
’’
5
100
real
’’
6
1,000
real
’’
7
5,000
hypothetical
Day 2
8
100
real
’’
9
1,000
real
’’
10
5,000
real/hypothetical
’’
11
10,000
hypothetical
II) Gains and Losses
’’
12
100
real
’’
13
1,000
real
’’
14
5,000
hypothetical
26
Table 3. Percentage distribution of experimental results of risk aversion
Severe
Extreme
Intermediate
Slight-to-
Neutral-to-
No. of
neutral
preferred
observations
D
E
C
B
A
O
Moderate
II) Percentages of choices at different levels: Gains only games
100 Kw
real
6.4
15.6
26.8
22.8
20
8.4
250
1000 Kw
real
11.83
18.82
22.31
22.04
16.13
8.87
372
5000 Kw
real/hyp
19.33
21.01
26.05
19.33
12.61
1.68
119
10000 Kw
hyp
16.39
19.67
28.69
25.41
8.20
1.64
122
III) Alternatives at 100 Kw. level for Gains and Losses
Bad Luck (50%)
0
-10
-20
-40
-80
-100
Good Luck (50%)
0
80
140
200
280
300
IV) Percentage of choices at different levels: Gains and Losses games
100 Kw
real
21.31
14.75
25.41
9.84
6.56
22.13
122
1000 Kw
real
23.77
24.59
22.13
18.03
4.92
6.56
122
5000 Kw
real/hyp
20.49
45.90
19.67
8.20
2.46
3.28
122
27
Table 4. Random effects interval regression and pooled OLS regression of partial
risk aversion on personal and socio economic characteristics
Random effects interval
Pooled interval regression
regression
Variables
Coefficients
p-value
(standard error)
sex
.734188
.0000687
0.026**
-1.445223
0.003***
-.1420829
0.000***
.2882947
0.000***
.0030181
0.191
-.0636008
0.774
-.5397986
0.244
-6.17e-06
0.036**
-.1002088
0.000***
.3090606
0.184
.0023044
0.755
-.0730698
0.057*
-.5149827
0.004***
(.1792722)
0.590
(.0000114)
household size
-.1473983
(.0383408)
(.2567814)
cash per capita
0.000***
(.0073843)
(.054627)
Logincome
-1.428155
(.2323843)
(.0105279)
education
0.006***
(.033019)
(.2203867)
age
.0000666
(.2169856)
(.0406036)
type of game
0.003***
(.0000244)
(.2064366
previous luck
.6953377
(.2307544)
(.0000232)
dummy for loss
P-value
(standard error)
(.3296883)
game level
Coefficients
-5.87e-06
0.466
(8.04e-06)
0.023**
-.0976302
0.001***
28
(.0439862)
1.874412
farm area per cap
(.030593)
0.025**
(.8350999)
maize
area
per -2.423155
capita
(1.505832)
constant
8.544398
Sigma u ( σ u )
Sigma c ( σ c )
(
1.896847
0.001***
(.5902671)
0.108
-2.525291
0.018**
(1.064618)
0.002***
8.376101
(2.819178)
(1.974654)
1.082802
3.126343
(.1235847)
(.0752042)
0.000***
2.93294
Rho= σ c2 σ c2 + σ u2
)
(.0739185)
.1199497
-
(.0250848)
Log-Likelihood
Number
-2840.4511
of 1353
-2864.88
1353
Observations
* significance at 10% level; ** significance at 5% level; *** significance at 1% level
29
Footnotes
i
1US Dollar ≅ 600 Kw in 1994
30