FEMINISM. FOUCAULT AND LAW
829
FEMINISM, FOUCAULT, AND LAW
AS POWER/KNOWLEDGE
ANNIE BUNTING•
/11 this article, Bu11ti11gcritically asses.ses Miehe•/
Foucault's theses 011powerlk11ow/edge, /all' and rite
state along with feminist writing enga,~ing witlt
Foucault.
She explores
tensions between
Foucauldia11 and feminist theories whil£' claiming
that a constrnctfre Jitsion of th£• two c,111lt•ad to a
rich analytical framell'ork for women.
811111ing
concludes witlt a disrnssio11 of the implirntions ,fa
Fmtcattldian approach for feminist legal .wrategh•s.
Dans h• presem article. Buming examine• /es tJu}sc•s
de Foucault sur le poumir et la cotmaissance, le
droit et /' £tat ai11sique dfrers travam: feministes qui
infl'111el/e11t
s011trtn•re. Elle explore /es tensions qui
exist£'11f£'11t1·,,
h•s theories foucaldic•mu•s et feministes
tout en aj]irmant qu' 11m•f11sion constructfr£• dt•s de11x
f1£'tttcmu/11ire•ci /' c1/ahoration d' 1111cadre analytiqttc•
fructtteux pmtr h•sfemmes. Elle nmclllt en disrntam
des implications cl£•/' approche de•Foucault pour h•s
strategies j11ridiq11e.\·
Jemillistes.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
I.
II.
III.
IV.
INTRODUCTION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 829
POWER / KNOWLEDGE MATRIX . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 830
LAW AND THE STATE ..............................
837
CONCLUSIONS . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 842
I. INTRODUCTION
Feminist theorists have frequently interrogated, interrupted. and/or appropriated other
schools of social thought; Marxism, liberalism. and psychoanalysis have been some of the
objects of feminist scrutiny. Recently, this critical process has been taking place within
feminist engagement with postmodern ideas in general and Michel Foucault's work in
particular. There has been a proliferation of scholarship evaluating the utility of
Foucault's methodology and concepts for feminist theorizing and political praxis. My
goal in this paper is to review feminist writing engaging with Foucault as a way of
evaluating one strand of the feminist post-structuralist project. I will also highlight the
implications of a Foucauldian approach for feminist legal strategies.
While there is no settled definition of either postmodemism or post-structuralism, the
challenges they pose have been quite clear. Metanarrative, reason, and truth are all
associated with modernity which, it is argued, has exhausted itself. In the work of
postmodemists there is a rejection of universalism. transcendental truth, and coherent
subjectivity. Postmodernism, then, is both a description of the present historical moment
and a critique of Enlightenment ideals.
For feminist legal scholars, postmodemism presents a number of far-reaching,
substantive challenges. Its analyses of power, the state. and the self undermine some of
LL.B., LL.M. The author would like to thank Brenda Cossman, Allan Hutchison, Marlee Kline, and
Bruce Ryder for their comments on the earlier draft of this paper.
830
ALBERTA LAW REVIEW
!VOL. XXX, NO. 3 1992]
the premises in much feminist writing on law. One of the most influential poststructuralist theorists in this regard has been Michel Foucault with his theses on power/
knowledge, discourse, the subject, and genealogy. At the same time, many of Foucault's
insights converge with those of feminist theorists. There is a certain level of abstraction
involved in any discussion of feminist theories and Foucault, for each requires a measure
of generalization: feminist writing is diverse and often conflictual; Foucault's body of
work is vast and sometimes unclear. I will proceed attendant to the conflicts within
feminism and within Foucault's work and explore the tensions between the two.
Most feminist theorists engaging with Foucault express some reservations about the
political implications of his methodology of the micro-physics of power, his rejection of
ideology in favour of discourse, his questioning of subjectivity, and his seeming
decentralization of law. A few writers remain resolutely hostile while a few others apply
his work without much modification. I will argue that Foucault's methodology can be
fused constructively with feminist political praxis which includes the law as a site of
struggle. The themes which will be discussed in this endeavour are power/ knowledge,
law and the state and the politics of legal action. Within the sections on power/knowledge
and law and the state, I will review Foucault's positions and various feminist analyses of
his theories.
Any brief description of Foucault's theory of power/ knowledge cannot hope to do its
complexities and ambiguities justice; 1 however, key features of his analysis will be
sketched out to situate feminist interrogations of this part of his work. I have artificially
separated his analysis of power from those of discourse, ideology, law and the state for
they each pose distinct challenges for feminist theorists. Given the centrality of power
relations to many feminist theories. this is a particularly important place to begin.
II. POWER / KNOWLEDGE MATRIX
Foucault's conception of power and how it is exercised directly affronted earlier
theories of power. Unlike Marxist and liberal understandings, Foucault sought to show
the productive and minute aspects of power in his exploration of its historical changes and
contemporary deployments. In a manner which signals his more general reaction against
Marxist problematics, he specifically challenged the notion that power is primarily the
repressive maintenance and reproduction of economic relations. 2 Rather, Foucault argues
For more thorough-going analyses of Foucault's theory of power sec M. Cousins & A. Hussain.
Miehe•/Fo11rn11/t
(London: Macmillan. 1984): B. Fine, "Power Without People: Michel Foucaull" in
Democracy and the Rule of Law: Liberal Ideas and Mm:risr Cririqm•s (London: Pluto Press, 1984)
al 189-203: H. Couzens Hoy ed .. Fournult: A Critirnl Reada (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986): J.D.
Leonard, "Foucault: Genealogy. Law. Praxis" ( 1990) 14 Legal Studies Forum 3; J. Minson.
"Strategies for Socialists"? Foucault ·s Conception of Power" in M. Gane. ed. Towards a Critique of
Fournulr (London: Routledge & Kcgan Paul. 1986) at 106-148: B. Smart, Foucault. Marxism and
Critiqu<'(London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. 1983) Chapter 4: G. Turkel. "Michel Foucault: Law.
Power and Knowledge" (1990) 17 J. Law and Society 170: and G. Wickhmn. "Power and Power
Analysis: Beyond Foucault"!" in Towards a Critiqll<'.op cit, at 149-179.
SC'lc•cted
lllf£'1'1'iell's
and Other
M. Foucault, "Two Lectures" in C. Gordon. ed .. Poll'er/Knoll'l<'dgc•:
Writings. 1972-77 (Brighton: Harvester Press. 1980) 78 at 88-92.
FEMINISM, FOUCAULT AND LAW
831
that power is a force which circulates;~ is exercised not possessed,"' produces "ongoing
subjugation,'' 5 and does so throughout the whole "political 'anatomy'." 6 The whole
social body, therefore, is the site of power struggles which form the "productive network"
through which power moves. 7
The twentieth century mechanisms of power, for Foucault, arc associated with the
growth of disciplinary society whereby the juridico-political form of power has been
interpenetrated by a technical and individuated form of power. In its disciplinary form,
power is exercised through mechanisms of surveillance. reporting, and classification which
construct subjectivity. It is not a simple equation of repression and domination as found
in its juridical form. While the latter has not been rendered obsolete. Foucault suggests
a focus on the positive, productive, and local points of power.
Resistance, for Foucault, takes place at every juncture as power meets with spontaneous
reaction within "force relations." 11 He suggests that there should be ascending analyses
of power which focus on the historical and local aspects of power relations rather than
deducing from an all-encompassing notion of domination. This leads to a "strategical
model" of specific, unstable, and multiple force relations.'}
In addition to Foucault's micro-physics of power, it is also imperative to understand
the relationship between power and knowledge which he articulates: "power produces
knowledge ... power and knowledge directly imply one another: there is no power relation
without the correlative constitution of a field of knowledge, nor any knowledge that docs
not presuppose and constitute at the same time power relations." 111 Foucault forwarded
a view of power as producing discourses of knowledge and dependent upon those
discursive realms. 11 Truth claims are, therefore, not universal but contingent claims
which silence or exclude other forms of knowledge.
/hid. at 98.
/hid. at 9X. And sec M. Foucault. Tht• 1/isrm:r,f SC'xualiry.\ '0/11111,· I: t\11/111roducrio11
(New York:
Vintage Books. 1980) al 94.
/hid. at 97.
7.
9.
Ill.
IL
M. Foucault. Discipline and Punish: Tiu! Birth of rlzt•Prison (New York: Vintage Books. 1979) al
28.
M. Foucault. "Truth and Power" in Power! Knowledg,•. reproduced in P. Rabinow. ed .. Thi' Founmlr
R,•adl'I'(London: Penguin Books. 1984) 51 at 61.
"Where there is power. there is resistance. and yet. or rather consequen1ly. this resistance is never in
a position of cxtcriorily in rela1ion lo power ... These points of resistance arc present everywhere in
the power network. Hence there is no single locus of great Refusal. no soul of rcvoll. source of all
rebellious. or pure law of the revolutionary ... h is in this sphere of force relations Iha! we must lry
to analyze the mechanics of power." M. Foucault. Hisrory of Se.rnaliry.. mJJra. note 4 al 95-97.
/hid. al 102.
S11J1ra.note 6 at 27.
Supra. note 2 at 94. Foucault's theory of discourse has been criticized for not addressing "how
discourses arc cons1i1u1cdm1d reproduced. nor how some discourses come 10 be more powerful aml
privileged than others.": S. Boyd. "Some Postmodcmisl Challenges to Feminist Analyses of Law.
Family and Stale: Ideology and Discourcc in Child Custody Law" ( I lJ9 I) IO(I) Can. J. Fam. Law
17 al 97. Some feminist authors find it necessary. therefore. lo retain a Grmnscian understanding of
hegemony or a Ahhusserian notion of ideology interpcllaling the subject. Sec e.g .. A. Assitcr.
Alrlmsser and Feminism (London: Pluto Press. 1990).
832
ALBERT A LAW REVIEW
!VOL. XXX, NO. 3 1992]
Aspects of a Foucauldian analysis of power and knowledge can fit well within a
feminist framework. For example, feminist theorists have challenged a reductionist
analysis of power as exclusively economic. 12 They have insisted over the years, as well,
on an examination of the oppressions of women including those encountered in the family,
medical institutions, and the workplace. Further, feminists have argued that dominant
discourses such as science and law have marginalized and silenced women in the guise
of universal truth claims. 13 A theory of the local, micro-physics of power, in my mind,
provides another vehicle through which to analyze the diverse dimensions of gender
oppression and women's exclusion in societies. 14
Foucault's analysis also challenges some tendencies in feminist theorizing. His
criticism of grand theory and universalism can be directed at some strands of feminist
scholarship. Over-generalization of women's experiences of gender discrimination and
claims of women's true essence would be susceptible to Foucault's analysis of
power/knowledge. 15 Some feminists see the value of his work in this insistence on
heterogeneity and diversity. 16 Jana Sawicki advocates an application of Foucault's
method and work to a "feminist politics of difference": "What Foucault offers to feminism
is not a humanist theory, but rather a critical method which is thoroughly historical and
a set of recommendations about how to look at our theories. The motivation for a politics
of difference is the desire to avoid dogmatism in our categories as well as the elision of
difference to which such dogmatism can lead." 17 Susan Hekman similarly adopts
12.
u.
,~.
IS.
16.
17.
At the same time, there arc Marxist and socialist feminists who challenge analyses of gender
oppression which do not account for the role of capitalism. Sec e.g., M. Barrett, Women's
Oppression Today; Problems in Marxist Feminist Analysis (London: Verso, 1980); Z.R. Eisenstein,
ed., Capitalist Patriarchy and the Case for Socialist Feminism (New York: Monthly Review Press,
1979); and M. Mies, Patriarchy and the Accumulation of Capital 011a World Scale; Women and
l111ematio11alDivision of Labour (London: Zed Books, I 986 ).
C. Smart, Femi11ism and the Power of Law (London: Routledge, 1989). For further elaboration of
Smart's important contributions to feminist legal scholarship, sec C. Smart, "Law's Power, the Sexed
Body, and Feminist Discourse" (1990) 17 J. Law & Society 194; C. Smart, "Feminist Jurisprudence"
in P. Fitzpatrick, ed., Dangerous Supplemellls: Resistance and Re11ewal i11Jurisprudence (London:
Pluto Press. 1991).
There has been considerable feminist writing over the past decade which has emphasized the diversity
of women's experiences of domination in society.
Feminists, too, have problematizecl an essentialist notion of women that lies within some feminist
theories. See e.g .• J. Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity (New York:
Routledge, 1990); and E. Spelman, lnesselllial Woman: Problems of Exclusion ill Feminist Thought
(Boston: Beacon Press. 1988). I will not discuss this issue here as I have explored anti-essentialism
and feminism elsewhere: sec A. Bunting, "Cultural Relativism, Feminism, and International Human
Rights Discourse," forthcoming J. Law and Society (1992).
Z.R. Eisenstein, for example, uses parts of Foucault's work to develop her "radical pluralist method"
and concept of "heterogeneous unity." Sec Z.R. Eisenstein, The Female Body and the Law (London:
University of California Press, 1988).
J. Sawicki, "Foucault and Feminism: Toward a Politics of Difference" in M. Lyndon Shanley and C.
Patcman, eds .. Feminist l111erpretations and Political Theory (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991) at 226:
and see J. Sawicki, "Feminism and the Power of Foucaulclian Discourse" in J. Arac, eel.. Afta
Foucault: Humanistic Knowledge, Postmodern Challenges (N.B.: Rutgers University Press, 1988);
and J. Sawicki, "Identity Politics and Sexual Freedom: Foucaull and Feminism" in Diamond &
Quinby, eds., Feminism and Foucault: Reflections 011Resistance (Boston: Northeastern University
Press, 1988) at 177.
FEMINISM, FOUCAULT AND LAW
833
Foucault's thesis of a contingent and non-absolute analysis of power for feminist
discourse. 18 Chris Weedon reiterates that "It is from IFoucault's] perspective that we can
best address the specific forms of power exercised in society and attempt to contest
them." 19 Irene Diamond and Lee Quinby have suggested that any apparent conflicts
between feminist and Foucauldian analyses "arc mutually corrective ... land within which!
one finds the potential for an ethics of activism that is particularly appropriate for
challenging the Faustian impulses of the contemporary era. "211
Notwithstanding these positive evaluations, there are clear tensions between the
implications of feminist and Foucauldian analyses of power that need to be explored;
Foucault's analysis of power begs a number of questions of concern to feminists. First,
if, according to Foucault, power circulates through the whole political anatomy, how is
it concentrated and exercised to the detriment of certain groups in society, including
women? 21 In a related vein, is Foucault's framework one that obviates disparities of
power between individuals and groups? 22 Secondly, does Foucault's notion of power
foreclose the possibility of transformative politics? 23 Finally, is Foucault's own work
a discursive practice which excludes an analysis of the importance of gender, as many
feminists have queried'l 2"'
Since Nancy Hartsock remains the most critical of Foucault's theory of power for
women, I will briefly discuss her concerns along the lines of the above questions.
Hartsock acknowledges the contribution that Foucault has made with his concepts of
domination/subjugation and disciplinary power but argues, following Albert Memmi's
metaphor, that he "reproduces in his work the situation of the colonizer who resists Iand
in so doing renders his work inadequate and even irrelevant to the needs of the colonized
IX.
I'>.
~I.
21.
2J.
SJ. Hekman. Gender and Knmt'/c•dgc•:E/c•11u•ms
of a Post-MO(/c'mFeminism (Cambridge: Polity
Press, 1990) in panicular 175-188.
C. Weedon. Feminist Practice mu/ Po.wstn1c111rolist
Tht'OI",\'
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell. 1987) at 125.
I.Diamond & L. Quinby. eds, supra. nole 17 al xvii.
Sec N. Hansock. "Foucaull on Power: A Theory for Women?" in L. Nicholson. ed .. Ft•mi11iJ111
anc/
Postmoc/emism (London: Roulledge. 1990) 157al 168-169and Z.R. Eisenstein . .mpra, note 16 at I013 and 16-19.
Nancy Hansock argues that "systematically unequal relations of power ultimately vanish from
Foucault"s account of power - a str.mge and ironic charge to make against someone who is
attempting to illuminate power relations." N. Hansock. /hie/. at 165.
Charles Taylor argues thal. "There has 10 be a place for rcvoll/rcsistancc aided by unmasking in a
position like Foucault"s. and he allows for ii. Bui the general rclalivity thesis will not allow for
liber.tlion through a transfonnation of power relations." C. T.1ylor, "Foucault on Freedom and Truth"
in D.C. Hoy. supm. note I at 94. Alan Hunt also says: "Where I suggest Fou<.:aultis la<.:kingis his
between the clements of micro-politics that
complete failure to address the eumul.1tivc <.:onnc<.:tions
arc essential if a counter-hegemony is going to succeed in displacing an existing hegemonic bloc."
A. Hunt. "Rights and Social Movements: Counter-Hegemonic Strategics" ( 1990) 17(3)Journal of Law
and Society 309 at 315.
Many feminisls point out Foucault's inallentiveness to gender. Sec e.g .• F. Bartkowski. "Epistemic
Drift in Foucault" in I. Diamond & L. Quinby • .mpra, note 17 al 43: S.L. Banky. "Fom:ault.
Femininity, and Patriarchal Power" in op cit, 61 at 64; S. Boyd. supra. note 11 at 3: I. Diamond &
L. Quinby. "American Feminism and the Language of Control" in Diamond & Quinby, supra. note
17 al 197: N. Hartsock. supra. note 21: and B. Martin. "Feminism. Criticism. and Foucault" in
Diamond & Quinby. supra. nolC 17 at 14.
834
ALBERTA LAW REVIEW
[VOL. XXX, NO. 3 19921
or dominated]." 25 Specifically, Hartsock argues that Foucault's notion of power eclipses
structural power relations 26 and the domination of actual as opposed to abstract
individuals. Further, she states that Foucault's ascending analysis of power, by focusing
on the "infinitesimal mechanisms" of power rather than those at the centre or the top,
could lead to a "version of blaming the victim." 27 Finally, Hartsock asserts that
Foucault's analogy of the network of power relations throughout the social body "comes
to look very homogeneous.
Power is everywhere, and so ultimately nowhere." 28
According to Hartsock, Foucault's is not a transformative theory of power and resistance
useful for women.
I think that Hartsock is wrong to suggest that Foucault's analysis of power at the
extremities and capillaries would lead to responsibility being placed on ·victims' of
domination. His ascending analysis is an inversion of the traditional understandings of
power as concentrated in the sovereign. It is a complication of the conventional depiction
of power as binary relationships. This approach seems particularly consonant with
feminist attention to the exercise of power in the "private" sphere and more generally
throughout society; indeed there is a strong affinity between the feminist slogan that "the
personal is political" and Foucault's analysis of the pervasiveness of power. In addition,
Foucault's position presupposes resistance and struggle in those micro-force relations.
This argument, too, seems to validate the view that women are resisting power in those
experiences of violence in the home, harassment in the streets, and so on.
Foucault's notion of power has become equated, as Hartsock says, with the dictum
"power is everywhere" and for her this means the negation of substantive analysis of, and
resistance to. power. Foucault's theory, I would argue. is a displacement of the concepts
of power which focus on the superstructural frameworks in which power operates and an
advocacy of historically and culturally contextualized analyses of local power relations.
As Susan Hekman argues, "A Foucauldian politics speaks to [the] peculiarity of the
subordination of women. It suggests that we oppose those knowledge/power discourses
that subordinate women everywhere throughout society. The result of such a strategy is
not, as Foucault's critics argue, political acquiescence, but, rather, a broadly based
political resistance." 2')
While I agree that his theory of micro-powers is relevant and useful for feminist
theorists, I cannot share Susan Hekman's unequivocal defense of Foucault's analytics of
power and resistance for he fails to illuminate the patterns and structures of concentrated
power relations. Hartsock may be overstating the case by describing Foucault's theory
15.
2,,.
N. Hartsock, supra, note 21 at 166. And sec N. Hartsock, "Rethinking Modernism: Minority \'s.
Majority Theories" (1987) 7 Cultural Critiq1u• 187.
Eisenstein also makes this point: "I believe Foucault's focus on micro-practices <:arries deconstruction
too far. It leaves us wilh the disconnections of power. hut lhcre arc ninneclions between sites of
power. even if no cen1cr exisls ... I criticize Foucault nol for dcl·~·ntl·ring the slale hut not for
reconnecting lhe dispersions he illuminates to lhe hieran:hical i.y,11..·111('-1
of power(s) rcprc,cntl·d
lhrough lhe discourses of the slale." Z.R. Eisenslein, .mflra, note lh ,11 llJ.
Supra. note 21 at 169.
/hid. at 170.
Supra. note 18 at 186.
FEMINISM, FOUCAULT AND LAW
835
as approximating a "blame the victim" approach, but it is nevertheless true that his
analytics are unconcerned with explaining the differences in people's abilities to exercise
power that may be related to personal characteristics such as class, gender, race and
sexuality. In Foucault's introductory volume of The History of Sexuality he argues as
follows:
We must not look for who has the power in the order of sexuality (men, adults, parents. doctors) and who
is deprived of it (women, adolescents, children, patients); nor for who has the right to know and who is
forced to remain ignorant. We must seek rather the pattern of the modifications which the relationships
of force imply by the very nature of their process:"'
Foucault is clearly not oblivious to forms of class and gender hegemony but is reticent
to explore the agents of power relations and the convergences of those shifting
relationships. 31 It is a tremendous irony in a three volume treatise devoted to the history
of sexuality that Foucault barely acknowledges the gendered nature of Western discourse
about sexuality and that he himself is participating in that long tradition of male
dominated discourses.:' 2 What is missing is an explanation of why male voices have had
greater power to speak, greater legitimacy when they do speak, and the power to silence
"others." Why are the various mechanisms of exclusion and surveillance so often
operating within gendered and other frameworks? Why have women's voices been
condemned as irrational and hysterical? The kernel of truth in Hartsock's sweeping
dismissal of Foucault is that his analysis could lead to the conclusion that women's
subordination is the result of not having spoken enough or not loudly enough.
For feminist theory, this is the fatal flaw in an unmodified Foucauldian approach
criticized by Fine as imagining the exercise of "power without people."·n Foucault's
genealogy leads him to a contradiction: he argues for an emphasis on the "individuated"
forms of power without an emphasis on the individual or groups effected by power.
People are the effects of power, rather than those exercising or experiencing effects of
power relations. 34 This is a complicated aspect of Foucault's theory for he rejects the
enlightenment notion of subjectivity and puts forward a view of the subject as constructed
through discourse. However, there is a crucial jump between recognizing multiplyconstituted subjectivities and imagining agent-less matrices of power. Masculinity, for
example, is constructed by discourse and deeply implicated in structural power relations .
.10.
.II.
:12.
\.\
,~.
.
Supra. note 4 at 99 .
Foucault sometimes refers to the hegemonic convergences of power but never uses his genealogical
method to draw such conclusions. He stales that there are cleavages in relationships of force that
"then form a general line of force that traverses the local oppositions and links them logetlw..r;lo be
sure. they also bring about redistributions. rcalignmcnls, homogenizations, serial arrangements, and
covergences of the force relations. Major dominations are the hegemonic effects that are sustained
by all these confrontations." Supra, note 4 at 94.
"What Foucaull has done is to rl·produce and produce as history the patriarchal history of sexuality."
F. Bartkowski. supra, note 20 al 47.
8. Fine, supra, note I .
Fine argues that "Foucault's rejection of [private property, law and the state] deepens the
mystification by abstracting power from its bearers altogether. In a situation where power is being
concentrated in ever fewer hands, this approach is a dangerous delusion." Ibid. at 201.
836
ALBERT A LAW REVIEW
[VOL. XXX, NO. 3 1992]
Hekman, among others who follow Foucault, 35 presupposes a structural or materialist
analysis of women's oppression. She uses terms such as "patriarchal structures" and
"male domination" without acknowledging that using these concepts necessitates resort to
tools drawn from outside of post-structuralism. While she implies that feminism can fill
in the gendered aspects of Foucault's problematics, Hekman avoids confronting the deeper
tension between the complete lack of concern for structural concentrations of power in
Foucauldian analysis and the fundamental premise of women's domination that
characterizes feminist politics. Theories of domination and oppression need not be
universalistic and essentialist to be effective for feminism but (arguably) they do need to
be grounded in some material appreciation of women's situation in societies.
In this regard, I would suggest that feminists will find useful concepts which are
consistent with Foucault's emphasis on the construction of subjects by discourses and nondiscursive practices, without losing sight of the fact that many effects of discourse are
related to the maintenance of structural power relations in society - without losing sight,
in short, of the concept of ideology. In this respect, feminists have drawn upon, and
should continue to find fruitful in understanding the operation of male domination,
concepts which emphasize the "lived" process of political domination, such as Gramsci's
notion of hegemony;1 6 Althusser's understanding of ideology interpellating the subject;n
and Bourdieu's notion of the "habitus."·"1
In sum, Foucault's work on power/knowledge offers many useful approaches to
feminist theorists precisely, I would argue, because their work is inspired by feminism.
Without the complementary aspects of a feminist analysis, Foucault's work could be "an
elaborate mystical shell" 39 without transformativc political impact for women. But it is
my contention that this fusion provides a very rich discourse for women. Foucault's
insights about power producing knowledge, permeating the political anatomy, not being
equated solely with the centralized sites of power in society, and resistance being everpresent in the power network, are worth integrating into a feminist analysis attentive to
the structural nature of male domination. Similarly, his challenge to modernist notions
.15.
.11,.
17.
.lX.
Most feminist writing that I have encountered utilizes structural notions of oppression and domination
of women, even those feminists advocating a postmodemisl approach. Frequently. the tension
between these competing paradigms or premises is left unexplored. Sec, for example, Carol Smart's
use of the categories of women's experience, women's reality, and women's oppression. C. Smart,
supra, note 13.
S. Boyd, supra, note 11; H.J. Maroney. "Using Gramsci for Women: Feminism and the Quebec Stale,
1960-1980" in (1980) 17(3) Resm11Tesfor Femi11is1Research 26; and M. Valverde, "The Rhetoric
of Refonn" in ( 1990) 18 /111.J. Sociology of Law 61. For works incorporating Foucauldian and
Gramscian insights see also, A. Hunt, "Rights and Social Movements: Counter-Hegemonic Strategics"
( 1990) 17(3) Journal of Law and Society 309: and B. Smart. "The Politics of Truth and the Problem
of Hegemony" in H. Couzens Hoy, supra, note I at 157.
Sec e.g., A. Assitcr. supra. note 11.
of A Theory of PracJice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977).
P. Bourdieu. Ott1/i11e
B. Fine, supra, note I at 191.
FEMINISM, FOUCAULT AND LAW
837
of subjectivity and political transformation are consistent with the recent feminist focus
on interrogating essentialist assumptions within feminist theory:'°
III. LAW AND THE STATE
Foucault's deccntreing of sovereign power and his emphasis on the local exercises of
power explicitly, though not unambiguously, shift focus away from state and law-based
analyses. Some assert that Foucault advocates that power as concentrated in the law and
the state has been eclipsed by disciplinary power. I would contend that regardless of his
historical description of the transition to disciplinary power, Foucault does not negate,
though nor does he adequately explore, the place of law in discursive power/knowledge
relations. In this section I will discuss the competing understandings of Foucault's
analysis of law and the state and the implications of this approach for feminist legal
strategies. Since Carol Smart draws on Foucault to argue that feminists ought to displace
the centrality of legal strategies, I will focus on her work in my discussion of feminist law
reform.
As discussed above, Foucault saw analyses of power as conceptualized in its juridical
form as wholly inadequate. He further posited that power as repression had been
overemphasized in Western thought. 41 With respect to the state and the law, Foucault
stated:
To pose lhc problem in tem1s of the slate means lo continue posing ii in lcnns of sovereign and
sovereignty, that is lo say in temts of law ... I don't wanl 10 say thal the state isn't important: what I want
to say is that relations of power. and hence the analysis lhat must be made of them. necessarily extend
beyond the statc. 4 ~
Thus, it is fundamental to Foucault's analysis of power in society that state power
("metapower"t~ be seen as complemented and dependent upon the other multiple
relations of force throughout the social body: "this metapower with its prohibitions can
only take hold and secure its footing where it is rooted in a whole series of multiple and
indefinite power relations that supply the necessary basis for the great negative forms of
power. "44 The law, therefore, stands in a symbiotic relationship" 5 to other forms of
-IO.
4J.
-1-1.
In this regard, it must be conceded that there are significant strands of feminist theory that arc
inconsistent with Foucauldian assumptions. For example, radical and cultural feminists who posit
an essential or universal female nature or sexuality, as well as psychoanalytic theories founded on
humanist conceptions of the self, arc undcmtined by a Foucauldian analysis. For a discussion. sec
L. Alcoff, "Cultural Feminism versus Pos1-S1ructuralism: The ldenlity Crisis in Feminist Theory"
(1988) 13 Signs 405. II is not surprising then that some scholars working within lhesc feminist
tradilions have dismissed Foucault outright (e.g., Sheila Jeffreys, Anticlimax: A Feminist Perspectfre
011the Sexual Rem/utio11(London: Women's Press, 1990)) or accused him of "disciplining women."
I. Balbus, "Disciplining Women: Michel Foucault and the Power of Feminist Discourse". in J. Arac.
as Critiqm• (Minneapolis:
ed., su1,ra, note 17 and in S. Benhabib & D. Cornell, eds .• Femi11is111
University of Minnesota Press. 1987) at 110.
Supra. nole 7 at 62.
/hit!. al 63-64.
/hid. al 64.
/hid.
838
ALBERTA LAW REVIEW
[VOL. XXX, NO. 3 19921
disciplinary power relations ..i6 This is not an always obvious interpretation of Foucault's
theory of the law. As we will see, there are conflicting statements in Foucault's writing
which can lead to confusion. Further, since it is the local and productive sites of power
that interest Foucault in his genealogical studies, he devotes little time to the law as a site
of concentrated power relations.
The symbiotic relationship between law and other disciplines is not always made clear
in Foucault's work. Part of this ambivalence is attributable, I believe, to Foucault's
rhetorical equation of law with sovereignty, or with repressive aspects of power, which
leads him to make statements that deny the disciplinary aspects of the contemporary
exercise of legal power. For example, he has stated that:
ll1e discourse of discipline has nolhing in common wilh that of law. rule, or sovereign will. 47
However, a careful reading of Foucault's work as a whole indicates that, far from
seeing law as irrelevant to the disciplinary society, he saw its importance increasing. He
did say that the form of law as sovereign right is dying. Thus, the repressive elements
of law as sovereign right ought to be de-emphasised in favour of an analysis of its
constructive functions as discipline, surveillance, normalization, and a discourse of
power/knowledge. This latter position is implied in Foucault's closing paragraph of Two
lectures:
If one wants 10 look for a non-disciplinary fonn of power, or mther, to struggle againsl disciplines and
dis1.:iplinary power. it is not towards lhe ancient right of sovereignly that one should tum. hut towards the
possibility of a new form of right, one which must indeed be anti-disciplinarian. but at the same time
lihernled from the principle of sovereignty.
4
x
Another ambiguity in Foucault's writing on law is whether disciplinary power is
colonizing the law or being colonized by the law. If the former is the case in modem
society. then the place of law as a site of struggle would be correspondingly decreasing.
If it is the latter, which Foucault is arguing, then the importance of law would be
increasing as a place of resistance to disciplinary power. Again it is difficult to be clear
on his arguments in this area. For example, the following statement was written in 1976
and supports the position that other disciplinary powers are superseding the law:
... in our times power is exercised simultaneously through this right [that invests sovereignty] and these
techniques and thal these techniques and these discourses. to which disciplines give rise invade the area
41,
17
Supra. note 13 at 165.
I agree with Jerry Leonard's reading of Foucault's comments on the relationship of law and other
disciplines: "Foucault maintains that political power is none other than the continuation of war by
olher means; thal is to s:iy. the 'other means' of a vast and proliferating array of institutio1ml
structures and apparnti. the language and imagery of (post)modem science. technology and mass
media. and the knowledge(ahle) disrnurses made possible by the subtle intennixing and linkage of
psychiatry. medicine and law." J.D. Leonard. supra. note I at 7.
Supra, note 2 al 106. And sec "Truth and Power". supra. note 7 at 63.
/hid. at 108.
FEMINISM, FOUCAULT AND LAW
of the right so that the procedures
colonization
of nonnalization
come to he ever more constantly
839
engaged in the
of those of law ...
It is precisely in the extension of medicine that we sec. in some sense. not so much the linking as the
perpetual exchange or encounter of mechanisms
with the principle of right.J'•
Compare the above words with those in Discipline and Punish written only three years
later concerning the modern penal system's colonization of psychiatric expertise:
what is odd about modem criminal justice
is that. although
it has taken on so many extra-judicial
elements. il has done so not in order to he able lo define them juridically and grndm11ly to integrate them
into the actual power to punish; on the contrnry, it has done so in order 10 make them function within
the penal operation as non-juridical
elcments.~
0
This apparent contradiction in Foucault's writing could be explained by the differing
meanings of law which he uses. as discussed above.
Given the lack of clarity and focus in Foucault's writing on law, it is not surprising that
legal scholarship relying on Foucault has mirrored some of these tensions. Many authors
read in Foucault a dismissal of the importance of law as a site for the exercise of power
in modern society. For example. in Carol Smart's work Feminism and the Power of Law
she states that Foucault sees "the old power (and hence the significance of law) as
diminishing." 51 To conclude from Foucault's critique of the ancient regime of repressive
power that the significance of law. in its broader sense. is retreating is to miss the subtlety
of his argument: it is a confusion of a form of power for the social spaces in which power
is exercised. While Foucault suggests that sovereignty as a form of power is diminishing,
he does not suggest that the legal system, with its multifarious forms and mechanisms of
power, is declining in importance as a site for the exercise of power.
In contrast to what she views as Foucault's position. Smart argues that "juridical power
remains a formidable obstacle to feminism and that whilst other mechanisms of discipline
develop, law itself can deploy these mechanisms to enhance its own powcr." 52 She
persuasively argues that "law is extending its terrain in every direction" 53 and
incorporating new discourses of discipline and science. I doubt. for the reasons stated
above, that Foucault himself would disagree with this thesis as Smart implies.5-t
Zillah Eisenstein also takes issue with Foucault's decentreing of the state and the law:
~I.
~-'·
Ibid. ;11 I06- I07.
Supra. note 6 at 22.
Supra. note 13 at 8.
/hid. al 6. This is consistent with Lcomml"s analysis of Foucau1t·s own position. supra. note I.
Suprn. note 13 at 20.
See Foucault"s comments quoted alxlVc at notes 4J-50.
840
ALBERT A LAW REVIEW
Instead of focusing on what he lenns 'weak continuities',
[VOL. XXX, NO. 3 1992]
Foucault instead chooses to emphasize the
•intensity of difference·. The problem with this emphasis on disparate power is that it privileges diversity,
discontinuity, and difference while it silences unity, continuity, and similarly. 55
Eisenstein proposes to focus on the privileged place of law as state language: "To the
extent that laws and the law operate as authorized discourses for the state, we must
examine how powers within the state articulate differing and conflicting views of sex
equality and sexual 'difference' ."56 Eisenstein retains a notion of the state as a
constellation ("condensation") of forces and the law as a privileged, if contradictory and
heterogeneous, language of the state. Further, influenced by Foucault, she studies law as
discourse which "occupies a space between the 'real' and 'ideal' that is a continuum.
Law reflects and impacts on the world. It is constitutive of and derivative of social and
political change." 57
It is interesting to note that two feminist scholars who have engaged with Foucault's
work come to very different conclusions concerning the place of legal strategies in
feminist politics. Eisenstein posits a "radical transformation of the present interpretation
of sex equality" 5x and explores legal policy changes implicated in her analysis. By
contrast, Carol Smart strongly maintains that since the law systematically excludes
women's accounts of sexuality and feminist discourse, the law ought to be cautiously
resorted to as a strategy of feminist resistance. She goes so far as to argue that feminism
has "conceded too much" 59 to the law and that feminist jurisprudence "encourages a
'turning to the law' for solutions, it fetishizes rather than deconstructing it."c..,
Smart presents an extremely thorough and thoughtful challenge to feminist law reform
strategies. A number of problems seem to exist, however, in her thesis that feminism
ought to decentre the law's overinflated view of itself by reducing the reliance on law.
First, Smart consciously avoids defining law. At the outset, she notes that law is a
fictitious unity but proceeds nonetheless with the singular term since she wants to explore
this aspect of the law's power to define: "the usage of the term 'law' operates as a claim
to power in that it embodies a claim to a superior and unified field of knowledge which
concedes little to other competing discourses which by comparison fail to promote such
a unified appearance." 61 Like Foucault's analysis, which frequently collapses "law" with
the form of juridical power, Smart's analysis of the penetration of legal discourses in new
areas of social life could benefit from the insights of those scholars who have analyzed
the existence and circulation in society of a plurality of different legal systems. 62
57.
sx.
l~I
h1.
Supra, note 16 at 18.
/hid. at 20.
/hid. at 46.
/hid. at 116.
Supra, nole 13 at 5.
Ibid. at 89.
Ibid. at 4.
Sec, e.g., B. de Sousa Santos, "Law: A Map of Misreading: Toward a Postmodern Conception of
Law" (1987) 14 Journal of Law & Society 279; J. Griffilhs, "What is Legal Plurnlism"?'" (1986) 24
Journal of Legal Pluralism I.
FEMINISM, FOUCAULT AND LAW
841
Secondly, I would argue that Smart concedes too much to the law in her contentions
regarding the resilience of the law in the face of feminist discourses. In this respect she
herself may overinflate the law and its powers. Feminist and other critiques have affected
popular understandings of the law and undermined its self-image as impartial and
apolitical. Feminists have been successful in explicitly challenging the neutrality of
legislation which on its face docs not present formal discrimination. Indeed changing
definitions of equality have been legitimated by the courts in some jurisdictions. Further,
mediation techniques have been introduced into the legal system in part as a reaction
against the adversarial model as the optimal manner to resolve disputes for participants
in the legal system. The Jaw is not a static entity impervious to change, but a discourse
in a dialectical relationship with other discourses on which it relies and impacts. To treat
the law as particularly resilient to feminist demands is to prioritize the power of law's
excJusionary mechanisms over those of other discourse such as psychiatry, medicine, and
science.
Thirdly, her analysis of feminist jurisprudence seems to overlook other complementary
feminist strategies outside legal discourse. With little recognition of these non-judicial
strategies, feminist law reform can easily look very complicitous. Using the example of
rape, there are active rape shelter movements which work para11e1with strategies to
address the criminal law's deficiency in validating women's accounts of rape. Shelter
workers may have very different perspectives on the law and its utility for rape survivors
than the perspectives of legal advocates; these tensions are endemic to feminist politics.
I do not disagree with Smart's characterization of the law's power to delegitimize
women's accounts of rape and its celebration of this silencing; I take issue with the
presentation of feminist legal strategics operating in a vacuum and ignorant of the possible
injurious impact of law reform on women. I am not as convinced as Smart that all
feminists using the law have seen the law as an unproblematic tool and need to "resist the
temptation" to see solutions in the law. 63
FinaJly, Smart's advocacy of the creation of feminist discourses rather than feminist
legal policies in order to chaJlenge legal definitions and the power of the Jaw is a fine and
perhaps unproductive line to draw. There is also some problem in ascertaining exactly
what Smart means by her decentreing of the Jaw. She states, for example, that law reform
ought to continue in the area of rape because it is already in the domain of the law.CH
However, on her own analysis, the domain of law is ever-extending and, therefore, everincreasing the issues of concern to feminists. I would argue that law as a discourse ought
not to be given special treatment by feminists by ignoring possible strategies relevant to
women. To leave policies unexamined and static presents more risks than participating
in an exclusionary discourse. There can be deconstructive effects of such legal strategies,
if only small displacements of legal discourse. And law reform strategies can be
combined with other feminist movements outside the legal field. That does not mean that
feminist legal strategies should present themselves as without risks; on the contrary, these
strategies should imply their own contradictions and limitations.
b.l.
M.
S1111ra,
note 13 at 165.
Ibid. at 49.
842
ALBERTA LAW REVIEW
IVOL. XXX, NO. 3 1992]
Smart shows with precision and insight that the law, in a number of specific areas, has
excluded feminist knowledges and women's accounts.
This is a very valuable
contribution to feminist jurisprudence. However, because she does not explore how other
discourses such as psychiatry and psychology have similarly delegitimized feminist
knowledges, Smart's account leaves the reader with the sense that other discourses would
be more susceptible to feminist challenges. I am quite certain that Smart does not wish
to make this argument. Nonetheless it is important to highlight that feminists engaging
with any number of discursive realms in the ·modem episteme' will face obstacles in
legitimating alternative knowledges. The '"psy' professions" 65 are no exception in the
disqualifying of feminist discourses. Indeed feminist theorists are constantly dealing with
the contradictions of participating in discourses which exclude women's voices and of
risking complicity in these discourses. As Alan Hunt has argued in the context of rights
struggles; "there is no doubt co-optation is always a possibility. But this is only one of
the practical manifestations of the social consequences of the real world of hegemony.
What needs to be stressed is that all struggles commence on old ground. "66
In sum, I find ambiguities in both Foucault's writing on law and feminist engagement
with Foucauldian notions. It is more useful, I think, to apply his thesis of disciplinary
power in society to all discursive practices including the law and to challenge the claims
to truth that those discourses make. Feminist legal strategies, then, would attempt to
decentre the law from both within and beyond the discourse. This is the paradox of
working against a structure which has no equally legitimate counterpart. Until the time
that such competing structures arc put in place, multifarious modes of resistance ought to
be pursued.
IV. CONCLUSIONS
The critical process of evaluating Michel Foucault's work and feminist interpretations
and appropriations of his work is one dialogue within the feminist post-structuralist project
- one which I believe can lead to provocative results. Foucault's theories of power and
power/knowledge offer feminist theorists a way in which to conceptualize and contest
power relations in societies, including those local, minute and pervasive power relations
which characterize contemporary cultures. A Foucauldian approach seems particularly
adept at addressing the simultaneity of public and private aspects of women's oppression
which we see in such issues as abortion, rape and wife assault. Further, in such a
theoretical framework, law is a site of struggle, a discourse to be displaced, and a
mechanism of power to be challenged.
"'
/hid. at 15.
A. Hunt, supra, note 36 at 324.