religions
Article
The Logical Problem of the Trinity: A New Solution
Joshua Reginald Sijuwade
London School of Theology, Northwood HA6 2UW, UK;
[email protected]
Abstract: This article aims to introduce a new solution to the Logical Problem of the Trinity. This
solution is provided by utilising a number of theses within the field of contemporary metaphysics
in order to establish a conceptual basis for a novel account and model of the doctrine of the Trinity
termed Monarchical Aspectivalism, which will provide the means for proposing an alternative
reading of the Athanasian Creed that is free from any consistency problems.
Keywords: Trinity; identity; location; aspects; first-person perspective; O-Roles
1. Introduction
Citation: Sijuwade, Joshua Reginald.
2022. The Logical Problem of the
Trinity: A New Solution. Religions 13:
809. https://doi.org/10.3390/
rel13090809
θεός
θεός
According to the doctrine of the Trinity, there exists one ‘God’
(θεóς) and three distinct
’ (ὑ(ὑπόστασις
πόστασις the Father, the Son and the Spirit, each of whom is of one ‘ousia’
‘hypostases’
πóστασις):
’ (ο
σία
σία These hypostases are identified as ‘persons’ that are ‘relationally’ distinct—in
(oοὐὐσία).
the sense that they are solely individuated by their relations to one another: the Father
is individuated by being ‘unbegotten’ (i.e., being uncaused), the Son is individuated by
being ‘begotten’ by the Father (i.e., being ‘caused’ to exist by the Father) and the Spirit is
individuated by being ‘spirated’ by the Father and/through the Son (i.e., being ‘caused’ to
exist by the Father and/through the Son).1 Moreover, each of the persons of the Trinity is
‘God’ by being (in some manner) related to the one divine ousia (i.e., one divine nature).
Yet, despite each of the persons being ‘God’, there is solely one ‘God’ within the Trinitarian
life. In contemporary analytic and historical theology, certain ‘models’ of the doctrine of
the Trinity have been proposed to further clarify the nature of the central tenets of this
teaching.2 One model is that of Monarchical Trinitarianism, which centres on two tenets:
Academic Editors: Brian Huffling
and Roberto Di Ceglie
Received: 8 February 2022
(1) (Monarchical Trinitarianism)
Accepted: 26 August 2022
Published: 31 August 2022
’’
Publisher’s Note: MDPI stays neutral
with regard to jurisdictional claims in
published maps and institutional affiliations.
Copyright:
© 2022 by the author.
Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland.
This article is an open access article
distributed under the terms and
conditions of the Creative Commons
Attribution (CC BY) license (https://
creativecommons.org/licenses/by/
4.0/).
(a) There are three relationally distinct persons within the
Trinity: the Father, the Son and the Spirit, each of whom
shares one divine nature, and thus are each equally termed
‘God’ (in the predicative sense).
(b) The one ‘God’ (in the nominal sense) is numerically
identical to one of the entities: the Father, who is the sole
ultimate source of the Son and the Spirit.
The Trinitarian model of Monarchical Trinitarianism—centred on the doctrine of the
‘monarchy of the Father’—has been most recently defended by John Behr (2004, 2018), in
the historical theological literature, as well as by Beau Branson (2022) and Joshua Sijuwade
(2021, 2022), in the analytic theological literature, and is primarily grounded upon the idea
that the Father is the sole ultimate (unsourced) source of everything else and thus possesses a
specific priority within the Trinity (and reality as a whole). This specific priority grounds
the fact of the Father being designated as ‘God’ in the primary (i.e., nominal) sense of the
word. That is, the Father is numerically identical to the one ‘God’. Whilst the Son and the
Spirit are each, with the Father, ‘God’ in a secondary (i.e., predicative) sense of the word (by
each of them sharing in the one divine nature). Therefore, this specific view of the Trinity
posits the existence of three entities: the Father, the Son and the Spirit, who are each ‘God’
in the secondary (predicative) sense. Yet, there is only one ‘God’ within the Trinity, as only
one of those entities: the Father, is ‘God’ in the primary (nominal) sense of the word.
Religions 2022, 13, 809. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel13090809
https://www.mdpi.com/journal/religions
Religions 2022, 13, 809
2 of 46
The authoritative sources for Monarchical Trinitarianism are the creedal declarations
made at the Council of Nicaea (325 CE) —termed the ‘Nicene Creed’—and the Council of
Constantinople (381 CE)—termed the ‘Niceno-Constantinopolitan Creed’. These specific
creedal declarations provide the standard for Trinitarian ‘orthodoxy’, which is evidenced
by their wide spread acceptance amongst distinct ecclesial communities within Christianity. Now, for the ‘Greek-speaking’ Trinitarian trajectory (hereafter, Greek Trajectory)—
influenced historically by that of the work of the Cappadocian Fathers (i.e., St. Basil of
Caesarea, St. Gregory of Nyssa and St. Gregory Nazianzus), and found, in a contemporary ecclesial context, in Eastern Orthodoxy—Monarchical Trinitarianism is the teaching
of these creedal declarations and expresses the ‘orthodox’ or ‘pro-Nicene’ conception of
Trinitarianism. Yet, this conception or model of the Trinity has not gained much traction
in the ‘Latin speaking’ Trinitarian trajectory (hereafter, Latin Trajectory)—that has been
influenced historically by that of the work of the St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas,
and is found, in a contemporary ecclesial context, in Roman Catholicism. However, what
will now be our central focus is to show how Monarchical Trinitarianism can indeed be
of great benefit in providing grounds for dealing with an important problem that plagues
the conception of the Trinity found within the Latin Trajectory, which we can begin to see
as follows: in addition to the Niceno-Constantinopolitan Creed (and Nicene Creed), the
‘Athanasian Creed’ (hereafter, AC) has played an important role in forming the conceptual
framework for the doctrine of the Trinity within the Latin Trajectory—with this specific
creed helping to shed light on issues such as the relation between the persons of the Trinity and ‘God’, the manner in which these persons are distinct from one another, and the
monotheistic foundation of the Trinity as a whole.3 Moreover, within the field of analytic
theology—which has been developed within an Anglo-American context that has ‘conceptual roots’ within the Latin Trajectory—this specific creedal declaration has often been
taken as a starting point for analysing the coherence and cogency of the central elements of
the doctrine of the Trinity—with the progenitors to this form of analysis within the field of
analytic theology being that of Richard Cartwright (1987)—with his identification of the
‘Logical Problem of the Trinity’,4 Richard Swinburne (1994)—with his ‘Social Trinitarianism’
account,5 Brian Leftow (2004)—with his ‘Latin Trinitarianism’ account,6 and Peter van
Inwagen (1995)—with his ‘Relative Identity Trinitarianism’ account.7 Hence, in proceeding
down the same path as these individuals, and thus assuming this creedal declaration as our
conceptual starting point, it is quite clear that (AC) uses specific terms that have a certain
level of ambiguity and thus are open to different forms of interpretation. Nonetheless,
the standard interpretation of (AC) is that of an ‘identity reading’ (IR), which we can state
succinctly alongside a summary statement of (AC) as follows:8
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
Athanasian Creed (AC)
The Father is God.
The Son is God.
The Spirit is God.
The Father is not the Son.
The Father is not the Spirit.
The Spirit is not the Son.
There is exactly one God.
Identity Reading (IR)9
1*. The Father = God.
2*. The Son = God.
3.* The Spirit = God.
4*. The Father 6= the Son.
5*. The Father 6= the Spirit.
6*. The Spirit 6= the Son.
7*. There is exactly one God.
The standard interpretation of (AC) provided by (IR) takes there to be, first, solely one
‘God’ within the Trinitarian life, and, second, the copula ‘is’ featured in (AC) is taken to
be that of a numerical identity relation (=), which results in each of the three hypostases:
the Father, the Son and the Spirit, being numerically identical to the one ‘God’. Given this
specific reading of (AC), it is quite clear that a proponent of this reading would face a logical
incoherence challenge, which has been termed the ‘Logical Problem of the Trinity’ (LPT).
Specifically, the (LPT) can be raised against the consistency of elements (1*)–(7*) of (IR) on
two fronts: first, by the ‘is’ featured in (1*)–(3*) being that of a numerical identity relation,
Religions 2022, 13, 809
3 of 46
then, by the transitivity of identity (i.e., if x = y and y = z, then x = z), the Father would be
identical to the Son (and the Father and the Son would also be identical to the Spirit), which
would thus render (4*), (5*) and (6*) as inconsistent—let us call this issue the distinction
issue. Second, as (1*)–(6*) takes each of the members of the Trinity to be numerically distinct
entities that are each God and as (7*) takes there to be only one ‘God’, there seems to be
an inconsistent affirmation of there being exactly one ‘God’ and also more than one ‘God’
within the Trinitarian life—let us call this issue the oneness issue. So, taking these two issues
together, it seems as if (1*)–(7*) are inconsistent statements and thus one (or more) of these
statements must go. However, as each of these statements, or ‘elements’, is required to be
held by a proponent of the doctrine of the Trinity, one cannot simply jettison any of these
statements. Rather, the task for one who holds to this specific reading of (AC) is either
for them to defend (IR)—by showing the distinction and oneness issues to not really be
problematic—or, for them to provide an alternative reading of (AC)—in a way that wards
off the distinction and oneness issues—without, however, transgressing the boundaries set
by (AC).
In taking the second option on the table, one can adopt the alternative reading of
(AC) that can be provided by Monarchical Trinitarianism, which will allow one to clearly
deal with the oneness issue. How this specific issue is dealt with within a Monarchical
Trinitarian context is simply through equivocating on the usage of the word ‘God’. As,
on the one hand, in (1)–(3) of (AC), it is used as a predicate in reference to each of the
entities who possess the one divine nature—each of the persons is ‘God’ (in the predicative
sense). Yet, on the other hand, in (7), it is also used as a name that solely designates the
Father, who is thus taken to be numerically identical to the one ‘God’ (in the nominal sense).
Moreover, this also provides a means for one to deal with the distinction issue as each of the
Trinitarian persons is taken to ‘possess’ the divine nature (hereafter, Divinity), rather than
being identical to it—as each is predicated the term ‘God’ by possessing Divinity. Hence,
there is no transitivity in play that requires one to identify each of the persons with one
another. We can thus state this Monarchical Trinitarian interpretation of (AC)—termed the
Monarchical Reading (MR), as follows (where ‘ins’ stands for ‘instantiates’):
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
Athanasian Creed (AC)
The Father is God.
The Son is God.
The Spirit is God.
The Father is not the Son.
The Father is not the Spirit.
The Spirit is not the Son.
There is exactly one God.
1*.
2*.
3*.
4*.
5*.
6*.
7*.
Monarchical Reading1 (MR1 )
The Father ins Divinity (Universal).
The Son ins Divinity (Universal).
The Spirit ins Divinity (Universal).
The Father 6= the Son.
The Father 6= the Spirit.
The Spirit 6= the Son.
There is exactly one God, the Father.
At the heart of the equivocation strategy that is offered by (MR1 ) is the conception
of Divinity as a universal that is instantiated by each of the members of the Trinity.10 More
specifically, Divinity is a numerically singular universal that renders the persons as homoousios (i.e., them ‘possessing’ or ‘being of’ one nature) due to each of them individually
instantiating this universal. Hence, by adopting this specific conception of the Trinity, one
is thus presented with a consistent reading of (AC). However, one is not entirely out of
the woods yet, as, by one adopting this reading, they are presented with another important issue. More specifically, the ‘instantiation-based’ position that grounds the solution
provided by (MR) faces a problem,11 termed the ‘multiple-natures problem’—namely, it
enables a proliferation of particular divine natures within the Trinitarian life. That is,
as Timothy Pawl (2020) has highlighted,12 an instantiation relation seems not to ‘fit the
bill’ for the task of tying the persons of the Trinity to the divine nature, due to the fact
that it will need to preserve the ontological unity on which the doctrine of the Trinity is
built upon—namely, the persons being homoousios.13 However, as the objection goes, the
relation of instantiation, unfortunately, allows a form of ontological disunity to creep into
the depths of the foundation of the Trinity, which an adherent of this doctrine would clearly
Religions 2022, 13, 809
4 of 46
find problematic. However, an adherent of Monarchical Trinitarianism can themselves now
ask the question of why does a construal of the model as an instantiation-based position
results in there being a multiplicity of instances of the divine nature within the Trinity? In
answering this type of question, Pawl (2020, p. 12) has given an interesting parity example,
which he states as follows:
When my daughters, Mary, Beatrice, Edith, and Agnes, each instantiate the
universal, Humanity, and each has proper characteristics such that we don’t
confuse them, what we have here are four humans, not a single human.
In other words, when we count human people, we count by individual instances
of humanity. Thus, if there are a multiplicity of instances of humanity, then there are
multiple humanity universals (i.e., humanity natures). The Trinitarian persons, in a similar
manner, can be taken as individual instances of a specific universal (i.e., Divinity). However,
understood in this way, it does not seem as if there is only one Divinity universal (i.e., one
nature) within the Trinity, which is surely problematic. More specifically, if we posit the
existence of an instantiation relation between the Trinitarian persons and the divine nature,
then it seems that when we are counting the number of natures within the Trinity, we are
also to count by individual instances of that specific universal. Since there are three instances
of this Divinity universal, each of the Father, the Son and the Spirit, we can take there to
be three particular natures (i.e., attributes) within the Trinity. Therefore, taking this issue
into account, instead of Monarchical Trinitarianism solely positing one nature—it appears
to allow a proliferation of particular natures that correspond to the number of instances
within the Trinitarian life.14 One would thus not want to adopt the conception of the
relation of possession that is posited by (MR). Given this, one can thus see that Monarchical
Trinitarianism can provide a way out of the oneness issue—namely, by identifying the
one God as the Father alone—yet, as it stands, it does seem to provide any progress in
dealing with the important distinction issue—which will be indeed problematic for a
proponent of a Latin Trinitarian conception of the Trinity, given an additional doctrine that
has played a formative role in this specific trajectory—namely, that of the doctrine of the
Divine Simplicity (hereafter, the DDS). From a historical standpoint, this specific doctrine
was a central component of the Latin Trajectory that provided the motivation for one to
adopt (IR), as Lewis Ayres (2004, p. 281) writes:
God is non-composite: God has no parts, is incapable of division, and is not
composed of a number of elements. In other words, God is simple . . . Thus,
in pro-Nicene texts, the primary function of discussing God’s simplicity is to
set the conditions for all talk of God as Trinity and of the relations between the
divine ‘persons’.
Within the Latin Trajectory, the DDS was not a doctrine that was accidentally linked
to the Trinity; rather, these two doctrines were ‘two sides of the same coin’. The DDS was
viewed as being a foundational teaching concerning the Christian doctrine of God, as it
was the means by which Trinitarianism could be spoken of as monotheistic—in a similar
manner to how the monarchy of the Father was for the Greek Trajectory. That is, alongside
the one God being identified as the Father—which was emphasised more prominently
within the Greek Trajectory—the DDS provided the Latin Trinitarian theologians with the
resources to securely ground the Trinity within a monotheistic framework—as the nature
shared by each of the members of the Trinity was taken to be one because it is simple and
thus numerically identical to each of the members. More specifically, the classical conception
of the DDS, in its most basic sense, posits the fact of Divinity not being composed of ‘parts’.
At a general level, a part is a portion of any given entity, and if a portion of a given entity is
less than the whole entity itself, then it is a ‘proper’ part, whereas if a portion of a given
entity is not less than the whole itself, then it is an ‘improper part’. The DDS negates
the compositional nature of Divinity in a proper sense, which allows one to understand
that Divinity is a metaphysically simple entity by it lacking any type of proper part (i.e.,
proper spatial, temporal or metaphysical parts). More precisely, according to the DDS,
Religions 2022, 13, 809
5 of 46
no portion of Divinity is numerically distinct from it. Hence, Divinity is a being that is
intrinsically within itself and does not have any division or ontological composition. That
is, Divinity must be such that it does not have any sort of complexity involving composition.
Rather, any intrinsic property attributable to Divinity must be numerically identical to it.
For example, if goodness is attributed to Divinity, then one is not properly attributing to it
an ontologically distinct property that it has. Moreover, given that Divinity is identical to
each of the entities that are predicated of it, one must also infer—given the transitivity of
identity—that these entities are identical to each other. Thus, in short, according to the DDS,
there is no numerical distinction between Divinity and anything that is related to it—as
this would render it as metaphysically complex. So, this is the position; however, one can
indeed see that the assumption of this specific doctrine within the Latin Trajectory provides
a further deepening of the problem that is provided by the distinction issue, as how can there
indeed be three (relationally) distinct entities within the Trinity—as is required by (MR)—
and yet there only be one, metaphysically simple nature within the Trinity: Divinity, that is
also numerically identical to each of these distinct entities? It seems, at least at a prima facie
level, that if we want to affirm (MR)—then one cannot do this within Latin Trajectory, given
the working of the DDS that requires one to identify each of the members of the Trinity
with Divinity itself. Hence, it seems to be the case, as was stated succinctly and sharply
by Christopher Hughes (1989, p. 240), that ‘the full-strength account of divine simplicity
. . . describes a God who could not possibly be triune’. Therefore, in taking this all into
account, one can see how Monarchical Trinitarianism provides grounds for dealing with an
important problem that plagues the Latin Trajectory: the (LPT); however, as it stands, it
can only serve the role of being a partial solution as it itself is plagued by some problems
that cause it to lack correspondence with some important elements of the Latin Trajectory.
The central question that is now presented to us is: how are we to proceed forward? How,
within the framework of the Latin Trajectory, is one to maintain the gains provided by (MR),
yet without one having to either adopt an instantiation-based position—and thus face the
multiple-natures problem—or face the problem raised by its assumption of an identitybased position and the DDS? I believe that the best way forward is for one to indeed not
abandon an ‘identification approach’,15 but simply re-configure it so as to ward off the
remaining issue presented by the (LPT) (i.e., the distinction issue).16 This re-configuration
will be made possible by utilising certain important theses that have been proposed within
the field of contemporary metaphysics. Specifically, this article will focus on utilising a
‘heavy duty’ metaphysic that includes various concepts such as: powerful tropes, multiple
location, aspects, first-person perspectives, onto-thematic roles and fundamentality/grounding
in order to introduce a new Monarchical account of the doctrine of the Trinity—termed
‘Monarchical Aspectival Trinitarianism’—Monarchical Aspectivalism for short, which will
provide us with an alternative reading of (AC) that is not plagued by the issues raised by
the (LPT). As introduced previously in our exposition of Monarchical Trinitarianism, at the
heart of the solution offered in this article to the (LPT) is an equivocation move. Specifically,
through the use of the metaphysical concepts that will be employed in this article, one
can ward off any form of the (LPT) and the issues raised by it by ‘biting the bullet’ and
taking each of the members of the Trinity to be numerically identical—which will allow
one to re-construe (4*)–(5*) in such a manner in Monarchical Aspectivalism so as to ward
off any charge of inconsistency, given that the members of the Trinity are not numerically
distinct, but only qualitatively distinct. That is, more fully, one can indeed affirm the
numerical identity of each of the members of the Trinity with Divinity and one another,
whilst being able to also maintain their distinctiveness—which is that of their qualitative
distinctiveness. Hence, according to the proposed account, one is able to affirm the fact
that each of the members of the Trinity is numerically identical to Divinity—the copula ‘is’
is one of numerical identity (i.e., the Father is (numerically identical) to Divinity, the Son is
(numerically identical) to Divinity, and the Spirit is (numerically identical) to Divinity), and one
can also affirm that the members of the Trinity are distinct from one another. However, there
is then an equivocation on the copula ‘is’ with it now being one of qualitative distinctiveness
Religions 2022, 13, 809
6 of 46
(i.e., the Father is not (qualitatively identical to) the Son, the Father is not (qualitatively identical
to) the Spirit and the Spirit is not (qualitatively identical to) the Son. Given that there is solely
a qualitative distinction between the members of the Trinity, and not that of a numerical
distinction, there thus can indeed be solely one Divinity that each of them is numerically
identical to. That is, one will also have a conception of the Trinity that allows one to
unproblematically affirm the existence of solely one, metaphysically simple particular object
within the Trinity: Divinity, yet there also being three (relationally) distinct entities that are
numerically identical to this object—and each other. Thus, this equivocation move—which
is underwritten by the metaphysical concepts that will be further unpacked in this article—
allows one to ward off the distinction issue—as the members of the Trinity are distinct
from one another—and the oneness issue—as, in addition to the monarchy of the Father,
there is only one (metaphysically simple) nature (i.e., Divinity) within the Trinitarian life.
Monarchical Aspectivalism provides a reading of (AC) that is not plagued by the issues
raised by the (LPT) and thus should be favoured over other accounts. To achieve this
goal, we will proceed in a step-wise manner over four stages that focus on philosophically
elucidating and re-construing each of the elements of (MR1 )—with elements (1*)–(3*) being
under focus in stage one and two, elements (4*)–(6*) being under focus in stage three and
element (7*) being under focus in stage four.
It will be important to further flesh out the proposal that has been briefly introduced
here; however, prior to doing this, it will be helpful to highlight two things: first, it is
important to highlight the fact that there is a linguistic assumption that will be made
throughout—namely, the term ‘God’ that is featured in (AC) will now be substituted for the
term ‘Divinity’, which will enable the present account to fit within the present Monarchical
context that holds to the term ‘God’ (in the nominal sense) being solely applicable to one
person within the Trinity: the Father. Thus, the dilemma to be faced is trying to show how
the members of the Trinity are numerically identical to Divinity (i.e., the one divine nature),
whilst retaining the simplicity and oneness of Divinity, the distinction of the members, and
the monarchy of the Father. Second, it will also be important to highlight the similarity, or
more specifically, the dissimilarity between that of Monarchical Aspectivalism and other
available models in the field of analytic theology. That is, Monarchical Aspectivalism—
which seeks to utilise a number of important concepts in contemporary metaphysics—might
seem to some to either be a version of J.P. Moreland and William Lane Craig’s (Moreland
and Craig 2003) ‘Trinity Monotheism’ or Peter van Inwagen’s (1995, 2003) ‘Relative Identity
Trinitarianism’. However, first, for the former model, Monarchical Aspectivalism is clearly
to be distinguished from Craig and Moreland’s Trinity Monotheism by the mere fact that
this model does not conceive of the persons of the Trinity to be ‘parts’ of Divinity, and
neither does it take the persons to lack divinity as the Trinity Monotheism account does.
In short, Monarchical Aspectivalism does not assume a compositional view of the Trinity
and affirms the divinity of each of the persons. Second, for the latter model, there are
two important distinctions between the proposed account and van Inwagen’s: first, the
metaphysical concepts utilised to formulate this Trinitarian account (such as location, tropes,
aspects, relations, etc.)—unlike van Inwagen’s account—are found within the broader field
of philosophy and thus, the charge of ad hocness (which is regularly raised against van
Inwagen’s account) cannot be raised against this account. Second, and most importantly,
the identity in play within the proposed account—unlike van Inwagen’s relative identity—
is not an ‘esoteric’ notion of identity, but the ordinary notion of identity that is taken to
conform to a ‘restricted’ form of Leibniz’s Law—which is not to be had by van Inwagen’s
account through it denying the absoluteness of identity and Leibniz’s Law in a restricted
or unrestricted sense. With that said, the proposed account might indeed be some type of
‘relative identity’ account—in that there is a distinction affirmed between numerical-identity
and qualitative-identity. Nonetheless, as it stands, it is clearly not one that is to be located
within the van Inwagian tradition, and thus does not face the objections raised against that
type of model.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
7 of 46
So, in taking all of these things into account, the plan of action is as follows: in
section two (‘Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage One’), I detail the first set
of metaphysical concepts—tropes and powerful qualities—and apply it to the task at
hand, which will provide the first part of our re-construal of elements (1*)–(3*) of (MR1 ).
Subsequent to this, in section three (‘Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage Two’),
I detail the second set of metaphysical concepts—multiple location and aspects—and apply
it to the task at hand, which will provide the second part of our re-construal of elements (1*)–
3*) of (MR1 ). Then, in section four (‘Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage Three’),
I detail the third set of metaphysical concepts—first-person perspectives and onto-thematic
roles—and apply it to the task at hand, which will provide a re-construal of elements (4*)–
(6*) of (MR1 ). After this, in section five (‘Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage
four’), I detail the fourth set of metaphysical concepts—fundamentality and grounding—
and, again, apply it to the task at hand, which will provide a re-construal of element (7*)
of (MR1 ). This will complete the construction of Monarchical Aspectivalism and provide
an alternative reading of (AC)—termed (MR2 )—which is not subject to any of the issues
raised by the (LPT) (i.e., the oneness issue and the distinction issue). In section six, there
will be a concluding section (‘Conclusion’) which will summarise the above results and
conclude the article.
2. Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage One
The first stage of our constructive tasks focuses on providing a philosophical elucidation and re-construal of elements (1*)–(3*) of (MR1 ). This element, in its standard reading,
posits the fact of the Father, the Son and the Spirit instantiating the divine nature (i.e.,
Divinity) that is conceived of as a universal. The standard and alternative readings of this
element are stated as follows:
Monarchical Reading1 (MR1 )
1*–3*. Divinity = Universal
Monarchical Reading2 (MR2 )
1’–3’. Divinity = Powerful Trope
In this re-construal of the nature of Divinity in (1*)–(3*) of (MR1 ), there is a utilisation of
the metaphysical notion of a ‘powerful trope’—which allows one to identify the Divinity as
a powerful trope—rather than as a universal (that is to be instantiated). It will be important
to now further unpack the nature of a powerful trope, and then apply it to the task at hand,
which will provide a further clarification of this specific element of (AC) and complete the
first stage of our constructive task.
2.1. The Nature of a Powerful Trope
In stage one of our constructive task, we introduce the notion of a powerful trope, the
nature of which is stated as follows:
(2)
(Powerful Trope): An abstract particular nature of a modifier or modular kind that can be
considered as a disposition or as a quality.
This concept of a powerful trope can be further divided into two sub-concepts: as
a module or modifier trope and as a powerful quality. These two sub-concepts will now be
unpacked in further detail.
Modifier and Module Tropes. A trope is an abstract particular nature of a modifier or
modular kind. Abstractness is a word, as A.R.J Fisher (2020, p. 44) notes, that ‘is vague,
imprecise, and ambiguous, like many other words in our philosophical theories and
ordinary language’. That is, there is not a single conception of the term ‘abstract’. However,
trope-theorists, in disambiguating this term, focus on the original and broadest sense of
the word, as D.C. Williams (1953, p. 186) writes: ‘At its broadest the ‘true’ meaning of
‘abstract’ is partial, incomplete, or fragmentary, the trait of what is less than it’s including
whole’. Thus, a trope is abstract in the sense that it does not exhaust its content or is, in some
sense, less than its content. This is in contrast, firstly, to the meaning of the word ‘concrete’,
which, according to Williams (1986, p. 3), is ‘if not the main thing which this means is that,
Religions 2022, 13, 809
8 of 46
however discontinuous the placetime, or ‘plime’, which just contains such an object, the
object exhausts or is the whole content of it’. Thus, as Williams (1986, p. 3) further adds,
‘abstract entities differ from concreta in that many of them can and do occupy the same
plime’. Thus, for example, a shape-trope that a table possesses is abstract because it does
not exhaust its content, as other tropes, such as a colour-trope and a mass-trope, are also
collocated with the shape-trope by occupying the same content. However, in contrast, the
table would be concrete by itself exhausting its content and thus not allowing another table
(or object) to also occupy this content—hence, this example also reveals that a trope needs
to be in some way predicable of the whole. The table would be a concrete entity, whilst the
shape of the table would be an abstract entity. Thus, in further emphasising this distinction,
Keith Campbell (1990, pp. 2–3) helpfully writes:
Abstract here contrasts with concrete: a concrete entity is the totality of the being
to be found where our colours, or temperatures or solidities are. The pea is
concrete; it monopolises its location. All the qualities to be found where the pea
is are qualities of that pea. But the pea’s quality instances are not themselves so
exclusive. Each of them shares its place with many others.17
This conception of ‘abstractness’ shows us that an entity is abstract, not because of its
relation (or lack thereof) to spatiotemporal reality—as is often held in areas of contemporary
metaphysics—but simply because it fails to exhaust the content of the region that is located
(or is a part of the content of that region).
In a similar vein to the abstractness of a trope, a trope’s particularity is defined in
a specific way within a trope-theoretic framework. In a general setting, universals are
regularly taken to be entities that can be wholly present in different locations simultaneously (Macbride 2004, pp. 181–94). In contrast, particulars are taken to not be able to be
wholly present in different locations simultaneously. However, Williams and other tropetheorists have proposed an alternative means of distinguishing properties as universals
from properties as particulars through Leibniz’s Law, which is taken here to be comprised of
two principles: the Identity of Indiscernibles and the Indiscernibility of Identicals, can be
formally defined as such:
(3) (Leibniz’s Law)
(a) Identity of Indiscernibles: ∀x∀y(x = y ↔ (ϕ(x) ↔ ϕ(y)).
(b) Indiscernibility of Identicals: ∀ϕ(ϕ(x) ↔ ϕ(y) → x = y).
In further elucidating this view, Williams (1986, p. 8) writes that:
Entities determined and named in the first principle, by definition not subject to the
identity of indiscernibles, are cases or particulars; entities determined in the second way,
by definition subject to the identity of indiscernibles, are ‘general’ entities, that is, kinds
or universals.
The central contention here is that of universals, but not particulars, conforming
to Leibniz’s Law (Ehring 2011, pp. 32–25). Thus, by not conforming to Leibniz’s Law,
particulars are entities, as Williams (1986, p. 3) further writes, which ‘may be exactly similar
and yet not only distinct but discrete’. For example, according to this account, a shapetrope is particular because it is possible that there is a duplicate of this shape, that is, an
entity that is exactly similar, but also distinct from this shape. If a property (or a given
entity) obeys Leibniz’s Law, then it is universal. If it does not obey this principle, then it
is particular. Thus, for properties as universals, the principle holds in that exactly similar
entities (universals) are identical (i.e., if universal x and universal y are indiscernible, then
x = y). Whereas for particulars (e.g., tropes), the principle does not hold, as exactly similar
entities can be distinct (i.e., if trope x and trope y are indiscernible, then x 6= y). Given this
conception of particularity, a trope is thus particular if it can have a duplicate.
Closely related to the concepts of abstractness and particularity is the primitive nature
of a trope. That is, the concept of a nature within this theoretical framework is taken to
be an unanalysable notion (i.e., a primitive) that directly applies to a given trope (Fisher
2018, p. 154). A trope is thus a (qualitative) nature in that it does not have, or possess, a
Religions 2022, 13, 809
9 of 46
nature of its own; rather, the nature of a trope is intrinsic to it. A helpful way to construe
intrinsicality, as noted by James Alvarado (2019), is through Rae Langton and David Lewis’
(1998, pp. 334–37) Independence Account of Intrinsicality—where a property P, according
to Alvarado (2019, pp. 53–54)18 , following Langton and Lewis (1998), is ‘combinatorially
intrinsic if and only if the instantiation of P by an object x is indifferent to the fact that x is
alone or accompanied in a possible world’. An object x is alone in a possible world w if and
only if there is no other object besides x in w. An object that is not alone is accompanied.
Thus, the nature of a trope is combinatorially intrinsic if and only if this nature of the
trope is invariant under the scenarios in which the given trope is alone or accompanied
(Alvarado 2019, p. 554). However, the modal invariance of a trope, unlike other entities,
is not grounded upon the possession of an intrinsic nature, but that of it being its intrinsic
nature. There is nothing more to a trope than its nature and thus, as noted by Anna-Sofia
Maurin (2018, §2.2), tropes, at a general level, ‘have no constituents, in the sense that they
are not ‘made up’ or ‘built’ from entities belonging to some other category’. Tropes are thus
primitively qualitative and irreducible entities—they are, in a sense, metaphysically simple
(i.e., they lack proper parts). However, a trope can be conceptualised in two ways: as a
‘trope’ or as a ‘troper’. Michael Loux (2015, p. 31) introduces this distinction as such:
Whereas tropes are particular properties—things like this redness, this triangularity, this pallor, tropers are thin individuals—things like this individual red thing,
this individual triangular thing, and this individual pale thing. The claim would be
that familiar objects are bundles of compresent tropers. So the view would again
dispense with properties and insist that the ultimate constituents of familiar
particulars are intrinsically characterised or natured, but would construe those
constituents as particulars rather than universals. Such intrinsically characterised
particulars would be the ultimate or underived sources of character: a familiar
particular would be, say, pale because it has a pale troper as a constituent.
The central difference between a trope and troper is that of the former being a singly
(or minimally) characterising property, whilst the latter is a singly (or minimally) charactered
property in a ‘stretched’ (or analogical) sense—it is a ‘propertied thing or object’—where an
object is a countable, property-bearing particular that has determinate existence and identity
conditions and is not borne or possessed by anything else.19 Thus, there is an ontological
difference between tropes that are ‘tropes’ and tropes that are ‘tropers’. However, off of this
distinction, Robert K. Garcia (2015a, 2015b) notes that Loux’s division between a trope and
a troper is not a novel suggestion, but is, in fact, the prevalent view of tropes found within
the literature (Garcia 2015a). According to Garcia, Loux’s distinction between a ‘trope’ and
a ‘troper’ is thus best described as a distinction between two different concepts of a trope.
Hence, Garcia sees that the two terms ‘trope’ and ‘troper’ are potentially misleading, and
thus he introduces the more helpful terms of a ‘modifier trope’ (for Loux’s ‘trope’) and a
‘module trope’ (for Loux’s ‘troper’). At a general level, modifier tropes and module tropes
are both taken to be non-shareable, maximally thin (i.e., singly charactered) charactergrounders (Garcia 2015b). The central difference between these two types of tropes is
that of a modifier trope being a property that does not exemplify this character, but simply
bestows it upon (i.e., ‘makes’) something else to be charactered in that specific way. Thus,
for example, a particular object is spherical in virtue of its modifier trope, which ‘spherises’
that object by simply making it spherical, without it sharing in that character as well. The
character grounding provided by a modifier trope is thus de novo (or sui generis) (Garcia
2015b), whilst a module trope is an object that exemplifies the character that it grounds
(i.e., is self-exemplifying). Thus, for example, a particular (thickly charactered) object is
spherical and red in virtue of its module tropes, which are themselves spherical and red (i.e.,
exemplify sphericity and redness), and together (compresently) are parts (or constituents)
of that object. A module tropes’ character grounding, rather than being de novo, can thus
be taken to be some type of parthood (or constitution) relation (Garcia 2015a). Furthermore,
an additional distinction between modifier and module tropes is the role played by these
types of tropes in causation. As Maurin (2018, §4.1, emphasis in text) writes,
Religions 2022, 13, 809
10 of 46
According to a majority of the trope theorists, tropes have an important role
to play in causation. It is, after all, not the whole stove that burns you, it is its
temperature that does the damage. And it is not any temperature, nor temperature
in general, which leaves a red mark. That mark is left by the particular temperature had by this particular stove now or, in other words, it is left by the stove’s
temperature-trope.
At a more specific level, it is solely module tropes, rather than modifier tropes, that can
play any direct role in causation. As in Maurin’s example, a modifier hotness trope cannot
fulfil the role of being the direct cause of the burn mark, as it is not itself hot—something
else must thus be the direct cause of the burn mark. Yet, this is not a unique problem for
the modifier view, as Garcia notes, ‘mass tropes are not massive, charge tropes are not
charged, and so on. Thus, unlike module tropes, modifier tropes seem ineligible to play
a direct role in causation’ (Garcia 2015a, p. 643). Modifier tropes, in a similar manner to
universals, are thus causally inert. However, the modular view does not have this issue,
given that module tropes are self-exemplifying entities, resulting, in our example above, in
a modular hotness trope being the direct cause of the burn mark. Thus, again, at a more
specific level, it is module tropes, and not modifier tropes, that are uniquely suited to be the
basic terms of causation (Garcia 2015a). Thus, a trope, identified as an abstract particular
nature, can either be a modifier—and thus be a maximally thinly charactered property that
is not self-exemplifying (i.e., does not exemplify the character that it bestows)—or, it can be
modular, and thus be a maximally thinly charactered property* that is self-exemplifying
(i.e., exemplifies the character that it bestows). We can now turn our attention onto the
second sub-concept noted above: a powerful quality.
Powerful Qualities. As a modular or modifier trope, a trope is a powerful quality.
More specifically, according to Charlie B. Martin (2008) and John Heil (2012),20 every trope
possesses a dual-nature (or character),21 where, as Martin and Heil (1999, p. 45) note, it is in
‘in virtue of possessing a property [a trope], an object possesses both a particular dispositionality and a particular qualitative character’ (Martin and Heil 1999). The dispositionality
of a trope conveys, upon the object that possesses it, specific powers to behave in certain
ways, in certain circumstances. More fully, a trope’s dispositionality, following Molnar
(2003), can be understood in at least five ways: it is, first, directed—in that a trope is directed
towards some characteristic and distinctive manifestation.22 Second, it is independent—in
that a trope is ontologically independent of its manifestations; that is, it can exist when it is
not being manifested. Third, it is actual—in that a trope is an occurrent feature of the object
that possesses it. Fourth, it is intrinsic—in that a trope is intrinsic to its bearer.23 Fifth, it is
objective—in that the existence of a trope is not dependent on the existence of any conscious,
observing minds. In addition to these five characteristics of the dispositionality, one can
also conceive of a trope as ‘multi-track’—which is that of it being capable of bringing
about distinct ‘manifestation types’ (i.e., different types of effects), and it often does this in
conjunction with other powerful tropes. One way to understand the outworking of this
is through the notion of a threshold that has been introduced by Stephen Mumford and
Rani Lill Anjum (2010)—where a given effect occurs when certain powers have accumulated to reach the requisite threshold.24 This accumulation can then be plotted as vectors
which, according to Mumford and Anjum (2010, p. 145), ‘is a useful way of modelling
powers because, like powers, they have a direction—the possible manifestation the power
is for—and they have a strength or intensity, indicated by the length of the vector’. This
would thus be depicted on a one-dimensional quality space with F and G representing
two possible manifestation types of some accumulated dispositions. For example, F could
be the property of being cold, and G could be the property of being hot, as illustrated by
Mumford and Anjum (2010, p. 146) in Figure 1. as follows (where ‘T’ is the threshold and
‘R’ is the resultant effect):
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
‐
11 of 46
Figure 1. Powers Modelled as Vectors (Mumford and Anjum 2010, p. 145).
In this illustration, for one to calculate the final effect, one has to take into account the
strength and direction of each individual vector with the resultant vector R, representing the
‐
fact that an effect is caused when the dispositions under question have accumulated to reach
‐
a certain point in which that effect is triggered (Mumford and Anjum 2010). Taking this all
into account, a trope, of a modifier or modular kind, is thus dispositional in that it fulfils
the roles of directedness, independence, actuality, intrinsicality and objectivity. Additionally,
one can understand the effects of a multi-track powerful trope, in a ‘fine-grained’ manner,
‐
‐
through the utilisation of the notion of a threshold and plotting vectors.
Now, the qualitativity of a trope—which is a less developed concept than the concept
of dispositionality in the Powerful Qualities view—is that of the trope being a ‘real’ or
‘actual’ feature of the object that possesses it. That is, as Heil (2012, p. 59) writes, qualities
are ‘here and now, actual, not merely potential, features of the objects which they are
qualities’. Thus, the qualitativity of a trope essentially contributes to the overall makeup of its
bearer—in the here and now (Taylor 2013).25 In other words, the trope provides a qualitative
‐
contribution to its bearer, where, as Joaquim Giannotti writes, ‘a bearer is in some way or
other by virtue of having a property [a trope]’ (Giannotti 2019, p. 81, square parenthesis
‐
added). It is thus a matter of how the bearer is actually like by having that specific quality.
Therefore, taking the dispositional trope of fragility as an example, one would rightly say
that this trope is an actual or occurrent feature of the vase, in that it is really present within
the vase in a ‘here and now’ fashion, and thus contributes to the way that it is, or the overall
make up of it.26
Dispositionality and qualitativity, as Martin and Heil write, must thus be ‘thought of as
unrealizable limits for different ways of being of that property [trope]’ (Martin and Heil 1999,
pp. 46–47, square parenthesis added). Where the ways of being a trope can be conceived,
‐
as John Levinson (1978) has noted, as the ways that a trope is. More specifically, as Levinson
(1978, p. 2) writes, they are ‘the varied fashions in which it goes about the complicated
business of existing’. There is thus a correspondence between the dispositional and the
qualitative in such a way that they are to be taken as inseparable and correlative ‘traits’
or ‘ways’ of any given trope.27 They are ‘built into a trope’ in such a manner, as Martin
and Heil note, that they are that trope, and thus, because of this, a trope’s dispositionality
or qualitativity ‘cannot be abstracted as entirely distinct or separable ingredients’ (Martin
and Heil 1999, p. 46). There is thus no ‘real’ distinction between the dispositionality and
qualitativity of a given trope.28 That is, within the Powerful Qualities view, there is, in
fact, a ‘surprising identity’ between the dispositional and the qualitative (Martin and Heil
1999). A trope’s dispositionality is not grounded upon its qualitative nature and thus is,
in some sense, separable from it. Instead, a trope’s dispositionality is its qualitativity and
vice versa (see note 22). (Martin and Heil 1999).Thus, whilst it might seem that the terms
‘dispositionality’ and ‘qualitativity’ are referring to two distinct and separable types of
tropes, it is, in fact, that the dispositional and qualitative are identical to each other, and that
‐
‐
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
12 of 46
‐
‐
each is also identical to the single unitary trope itself (Taylor 2013).29 Importantly, however,
there is no ontological priority between the dispositional and the qualitative; rather, they
‐
equi-fundamental. Moreover,
there is, in fact, a deflation between the dispositional and
qualitative, where the same trope can simply be regarded, or considered, as a disposition or‐ a
quality. Dispositionality and qualitativity are thus not parts or sides of a given trope, but
the one trope itself, just differently considered. They are, as Martin and Heil write, ‘different
ways of representing the self-same property [trope]’‐ (Martin and Heil 1999, p. 47, square
parenthesis added). For example, in illustrating this, we can turn our attention to the
case of a ball and an inclined slope in Figure 2. (with the black arrows representing the
dispositionality of the ball and the circular object representing the geometrical shape had
‐
by the object):
Figure 2. Ball and Slope Illustration.
In this specific example,30 if we consider a rubber ball that possesses a spherical-trope,
‐
this trope can be considered qualitatively when we regard it as the distinctive and actual
geometrical shape that contributes to the overall makeup of the ball (i.e., it provides it
with its shape). However, we can also consider the spherical-trope dispositionally when we
‐
regard it as the power that the ball has to roll in a certain way when placed in a certain
circumstance (e.g., on an inclined slope) (Giannotti 2019). Thus, we can see here that
there is no demarcation of a numerical distinction in reality between the dispositional and
‐
qualitative, but instead, the dispositionality that conveys upon a ball the certain powers
that it has is indeed identical to the qualitativity that gives that ball a certain shape and both
of these are identical with the single unitary spherical-trope itself that is possessed by the
‐
ball (Taylor 2013).31 Thus, at a more general level, when one considers a trope as qualitative
or as dispositional, they are considering the whole trope—and not a part of it—in a certain
way, at a given time. Thus, in other words, when we are dispositionally considering a trope
at a given time, we consider that trope as bestowing upon its bearer certain dispositional
powers. Additionally, when we are qualitatively considering the same trope at another given
time, we are simply considering it as contributing to the overall ‘real’ or ‘actual’ make up
of its bearer.
In summary: a trope is an abstract particular nature that either can be modular—a
self-exemplifying, maximally thinly charactered property* (i.e., an object)—or, it can be a
modifier—a non-self-exemplifying, maximally thinly characterising property—with a dualcharacter: a dispositionality and a qualitativity, that are identical to the trope itself. This is
the philosophical framework within which we will be operating. However, one can raise
an objection against the cogency of this powerful trope theoretic framework. Specifically,
one can raise an issue against the dual-character that is identical to a given trope. As, given
Leibniz’s Law, how could the dispositionality of a trope be identical to its qualitativity
and the trope itself when each bears different qualities? That is, the dispositionality of
a trope is its ability to empower its bearer to behave in a certain way, the qualitativity
of a trope is what contributes to making the trope what it is, and a trope possesses this
dispositionality and qualitativity, without, however, its dispositionality and qualitativity
having this dual characteristic as well—dispositionality does not have a dispositional and a
qualitative character; qualitativity does not have a qualitative and a dispositional character.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
13 of 46
Thus, what is true of the dispositionality of a trope is not also true of its qualitativity and
of the trope itself (and vice versa). Hence, we have a transgression of Leibniz’s Law here,
which indicates that the dispositional and the qualitative are not identical to each other,
nor with the trope itself. Thus, an important question to be faced is: is there a way to
re-construe the powerful nature of a trope in order not to transgress Leibniz’s Law? I
believe that there is, once we have introduced the notion of an aspect.32 We will thus leave
this question unanswered until the penultimate section and focus on applying the above
set of concepts to the task at hand.
2.2. Divinity as a Powerful Trope
In this stage of our constructive task, we are utilising a powerful trope-theoretic
framework, and thus we take Divinity to be a powerful module trope—an abstract particular nature of a modular kind that can be considered as a disposition or as a quality.
More specifically, Divinity is, first, abstract because it has the trait of being ‘less than the
including whole’—Divinity does not exhaust its ‘content’ or ‘plime’ (or is less than its
‘content’ or ‘plime’)—where, in assuming Christian theism, we take this content or plime
to be the Trinity, which would include three ‘reiterations’ of Divinity (identified as the
Father, the Son and the Spirit)—resulting in it not exhausting either of these things.33
Second, Divinity is particular by it failing to abide by Leibniz’s Law, and thus permitting
the possibility of the existence of an entity (i.e., a duplicate) that is exactly similar in its
intrinsic properties (i.e., its nature) to it—specifically, Divinity, as will be shown below,
can have certain ‘region-specific’ reiterations of itself (i.e., Divinity reiterated as the Father,
the Son and the Spirit). Third, Divinity is the specific character that it bestows, which is
that of it being divine. In other words, Divinity’s nature is intrinsic to it—not in the sense
of it possessing a further intrinsic ‘property’, but simply by that of it being numerically
identical to this nature. Furthermore, it is plausible to take Divinity as a module trope,
rather than as a modifier trope, in the sense of it being a maximally thinly charactered
object—a property in an analogous sense (i.e., a property*)—that is self-exemplifying and
serves the role of bestowing this characteristic upon another object: the Trinity, which it
constitutes. Moreover, since Divinity is a trope of a modular kind, it plays a direct role in
causation and is thus a basic term of a causal relation.34 Fourth, Divinity is a powerful quality
in the sense of it being dual-charactered—it has a particular dispositional and qualitative
character. The dispositionality of Divinity is the disposition for it to behave in a certain
way (which empowers the Trinity to behave in a certain way). That is, as a module trope,
Divinity is powerful in five ways: it is, firstly, directed—in that Divinity (or its action) is
directed towards some characteristic and distinctive manifestations, such as that of creating
or sustaining the universe. Secondly, it is independent—in that Divinity is ontologically
independent of its manifestations; that is, it exists when its power is not manifested.35
Thirdly, it is actual—in that Divinity is an occurrent feature of the object that possesses it:
the Trinity. Fourthly, it is intrinsic—Divinity is intrinsic to its bearer, which is, again, the
Trinity.36 Fifthly, it is objective— in that the existence of Divinity is not dependent upon the
existence of any conscious, observing minds. Divinity, as a module trope, is thus powerful
in that it fulfils the roles of directedness, independence, actuality, intrinsicality and objectivity.
However, it does this without any of the limitations that certain other powerful module
tropes may have. In short, Divinity is a maximal power trope (i.e., an omnipotence-trope), in
that it is multi-track—it is cable of producing distinct manifestation types—yet it can do this
without any limitation except for logic—and thus is able to act in different scenarios without
limitation (i.e., being maximally powerful/omnipotent) and being able to know all things
without limitation (i.e., being maximally knowledgeable/omniscient), or being present at
all points of space (i.e., being maximally present/omnipresent), etc. One way in which one
can further understand the limitlessness of the dispositionality of Divinity is through the
utilisation of the notion of a threshold and a vector depicted on a one-dimensional quality
space with F and G representing two possible effects of Divinity. For example, F could be
the property of resting on the ground, and G could be the property of being suspended in
‐
‐
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
14 of 46
the air, which can be illustrated in Figure 3. as follows (where ‘T’ is the threshold and ‘R’ is
the resultant effect):
Figure 3. Divinity’s Power Modelled as a Vector.
In this illustration, for one to understand the effect brought about by Divinity—which,
in this case, is to cause something to be suspended in the air—is not produced by an aggregation of operative dispositions that have reached a certain threshold for the effect. Rather,
‐
Divinity, in all cases when it exercises its power, is unopposed and does not require other dispositions to reach a threshold. In short, Divinity can bring about any effect—and thus reach
‐
the needed threshold for the occurrence of an effect—without limitations from anything—
‐
aside from logic. In all, limitless dispositionality (i.e., maximal power/omnipotence) is thus
a ‘trait’ of Divinity—it is ‘built’ into it, whereas the qualitativity of Divinity is what makes
‐
it a ‘real’ or ‘actual’ entity. The qualitative character of Divinity thus essentially contributes
to the overall makeup of Divinity, which is that of it having various theoretical roles that it
fulfils and thus provides a qualitative contribution to Divinity, such that Divinity is what
it is because of it. Qualitativity is thus another ‘trait’ of Divinity—it is also ‘built’ into
it. Furthermore, there is a ‘surprising identity’ between this dispositionality, qualitativity,
and Divinity itself—in that Divinity’s dispositionality is just its qualitativity, and these
both are Divinity. In other words, the dispositional and qualitative characters of Divinity are numerically identical with one another and with Divinity itself. Thus, Divinity’s
‐
dispositionality—which disposes it to act in a certain way—is not really distinct from Divinity’s qualitativity—which bestows upon it the qualitative characteristic of being a certain
way. This dispositionality and qualitativity are the single and unitary powerful trope itself,
and the distinction between these ‘traits’ or ‘ways’ of Divinity, and Divinity itself, do not
demarcate a distinction in reality—rather, they are one and the same thing—namely, the
unitary, metaphysically simple Divinity itself. Thus, the dispositionality and qualitativity of
Divinity are not to be taken as parts, sides or additional properties possessed by Divinity,
but the one self-same trope, just differently considered. We can illustrate in Figure 4. this
‐ representing a numerical
‘surprising identity’ as such (with the double-headed arrows
‐
identity relation):
Figure 4. Theistic Powerful Trope.
‐
‐
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
15 of 46
Thus, Divinity can be regarded, or considered, as a disposition or as a quality, which
are simply equi-fundamental, identical ‘traits’ or ‘ways’ of Divinity. Thus, despite the
dispositional and qualitative distinctions that can be made of it, there is only one trope:
Divinity, which is not composed of any proper parts—given the fact that there is an identity
between Divinity and its qualitativity and dispositionality.
In summary: Divinity is a powerful trope, that is, it is an abstract particular nature
that is modular—it is a self-exemplifying, maximally thinly charactered property* (i.e., an
object)—with a dual character: a dispositionality and a qualitativity, that are identical to
the one, metaphysically simple Divinity itself. This is the conceptualisation of Divinity that
we will be working with. However, as in the mundane case, more indeed is required to be
said concerning how the dual character of Divinity can, on the one hand, be identical in the
manner stated above, whilst, on the other hand, each ‘character’ being able to differ to a
certain extent. This task will be taken up in the next section once the notion of an aspect
is on the table. However, what we have established, within the Trinitarian framework
in which we are operating within, is that there is exactly one particular object posited by
this account, which has been identified as one powerful divinity trope: Divinity. This
account thus does not posit, in line with certain other Trinitarian accounts (such as Richard
Swinburne’s (1994) ‘Functional Monotheism’ account), the existence of multiple ‘tropes
of divinity’ within the Trinitarian life—each of which is related (in some manner) to the
members of the Trinity. Rather, as we will see below, there is solely one (powerful module)
trope of divinity that grounds the oneness and distinction of the members of the Trinity.
Thus, on the basis of this conceptualisation of the nature of Divinity, we can now proceed
onto the second stage of our constructive task, which focuses on explicating and applying
the metaphysical notions of multiple location and aspects to the task at hand.
3. Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage Two
The second stage of our constructive task focuses on providing a philosophical elucidation and re-construal of elements (1*)–(3*) of (MR1 ). This element, in its standard
reading, posits the fact of the Father, the Son and the Spirit instantiating the one universal
of ‘Divinity’. The standard and alternative readings of this element are stated as follows:
Monarchical Reading1 (MR1 )
1*. The Father ins Divinity (Universal).
2*. The Son ins Divinity (Universal).
3*. The Spirit ins Divinity (Universal).
Monarchical Reading2 (MR2 )
1’. Father-Aspect = Divinity (Trope).
2’. Son-Aspect = Divinity (Trope).
3’. Spirit-Aspect = Divinity (Trope).
In this re-construal of (1*)–(3*) of (MR1 ), there is an assumption made concerning the
cogency of the metaphysical notions of ‘multiple location’ and ‘aspects’, which allows one
to, first, take Divinity to be a multiply located object and, second, to identify the Father,
the Son and the Spirit as ‘aspects’ that are numerically identical to the one Divinity. It
will be important to now further unpack the nature of multiple location and aspects, and
then apply it to the task at hand, which will provide a further clarification of this specific
element of (AC) and complete the second stage of our constructive task.
3.1. The Nature of Multiple Location and Aspects
In stage two of our constructive task, we introduce the notion of aspectival multiple
location, the nature of which is stated as follows:
(4)
(Aspectival Multiple Location): A particular object having more than one (disjoint) exact
location and bearing different aspects at those locations.
This notion of aspectival multiple location can also be further divided into two sub-concepts:
multiple location and aspects. These two sub-concepts will now be unpacked in further detail.
Multiple Location. A ‘chorological system’ is a system concerning location. Following
Cody Gilmore (2018, §2), we can utilise a specific chorological system that takes the relation
of ‘exact location’ as basic and construes it as such:
Religions 2022, 13, 809
16 of 46
(5)
(Exact Location): An entity x is exactly located at a region y if and only if x has (or has-at-y)
exactly the same shape and size as y and stands (or stands-at-y) in all the same spatial or
spatiotemporal relations to other entities as does y (see note 27).
At the heart of this conceptualisation of the chorological relation of exact location is
the fact of objects inheriting the same properties and relations of the regions that they are
exactly located at—for example, small spheres are exactly located at small spherical regions
and share all of the spatial properties and relations of these regions; large cubes are exactly
located at large cubical regions and share all of the spatial properties and relations of these
regions, etc. (Gilmore 2018). More precisely, following Nikk Effingham (2015a, p. 846), we
can, first, state the chorological relation of exact location as such: ‘__ is exactly located at
spatial region __ (at time __)’,37 and, second, express the inner workings of this relation
through the following paradigm examples:
(6)
(7)
(8)
The cube is exactly located at just one cube-shaped region.
The Kuiper Belt is exactly located at a scattered region composed of lots of disjoint asteroid
shaped regions.
A sphere is exactly located at some region with a volume equal to 4π/3 multiplied by the
radius (of the sphere) cubed.
On the basis of the conceptualisation of the relation of exact location that is expressed
by these types of paradigm examples, we can now—again following Effingham (2015a,
p. 848)—define the chorological term of multiple location as such:
(9)
(Multiple Location) An entity x is multi-located if there are two or more distinct regions that
x is exactly located at.
According to this construal of the notion of multiple location, to say that a given
object is multiply located is simply to say that it possesses more than one (disjoint) exact
location—it has the exact same shape/size as, and stands in the same relations of, more
than one (disjoint) spatial region. Following Gilmore (2018, §6), we can illustrate in Figure 5.
the inner workings of this notion through the following paradigm example (with the left
image representing a scattered, single-located object and the right image presenting a
non-scattered, multiply located object):
Figure 5. Multiple Location.
In this paradigm example, object o1 is a scattered entity due to its shape being that of
the sum of the two disjoint circles (Gilmore 2018). This type of entity is thus not multiply
located as it has one exact location: the scattered region r3 . However, object o2 is, in fact,
multiply located as it has (solely) two exact locations—it is exactly located at region r3
and at the (disjoint) region r4 , and thus—in assuming the construal of exact location noted
above—as o2 is exactly located at r3 and at r4 , which are both circular in shape, o2 must
also be circular (at least whilst it is exactly located at r3 and r4 ) (Gilmore 2018). Given all of
this, exact location is thus not a one-one relation, but a many-one relation, where a single
‐
‐
‐
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
17 of 46
object can be (exactly) located in more than one (disjoint) region at the same time. On the
basis of this clarification of the notion of multiple location, we can now turn our attention
towards the second sub-concept: ‘aspects’, which was noted above.
Aspects. The concept of an ‘aspect’ provides a coherent conceptual foundation for
the notion of qualitative self-differing (hereafter, self-differing). Self-differing, according
to Donald Baxter (1999, 2016, 2018a, 2018b), is the qualitative differing of some entity in
one way (or respect) from itself in another.38 Self-differing is thus the qualitative differing
of numerically identical aspects possessed by an individual (Baxter 1999). That is, the
same individual can possess qualitatively differing aspects that are nevertheless numerically
identical with the individual, and thus, given the transitivity of identity, with each other.
To help motivate the existence of aspects within this context, we can consider two
different cases in which an individual is torn about what to do (or how to feel) in a
certain situation:
The Case of David
David is an ardent philosophy professor and is also a
loving and faithful father of two children, Jacob and
Melissa. Now suppose that, firstly, David has an
upcoming philosophy conference in which he is the
keynote speaker and, due to other work commitments,
has not prepared his speech yet. Secondly, suppose that
David had previously promised that he would reward
his children with a camping trip this upcoming weekend
if they achieved A* grades in their A-Level results. And,
thirdly, suppose that Jacob and Mellissa have both, in
fact, recently achieved A* grades in their A-Level results.
The Case of Jane
Jane is an ambitious lawyer and a
(volunteer) senior staff member of
Humanists UK. Now, suppose Jane is
on her way to an important meeting
at her law firm. However, when she is
walking, she observes an assault
taking place in an alley. An inner
struggle now ensues between her
conscience, to stop and call for help,
and her career ambitions, which tell
her she cannot miss this meeting.
In these two specific scenarios, David and Jane are in situations of self-differing as,
first, in the Case of David, he knows that he has an important keynote speech that he needs
to prepare—and being an ardent philosophy professor, he wants to fulfil this commitment
and thus complete his speech. So, the following proposition would be true: David ‘does not
want to take his children on a camping trip this upcoming weekend’. However, having promised
his children that he would reward them for their academic achievement, and being a loving
and faithful father, he wants to fulfil his promise to them. So, the following conflicting
proposition would also be true: David ‘wants to take his children on a camping trip this weekend’.
David is torn. He is in conflict with himself. He thus differs from himself. David’s struggle
is between two aspects of him: David insofar as he is a philosopher versus David insofar as he is
a father. Now, second, in the Case of Jane, she knows that she has an important meeting
that will lead to her becoming partner at her law firm—and has career ambitions that result
in her wanting to go to her meeting to secure the promotion. So, the following proposition
would be true: Jane ‘does not want to stop and call for help for the stranger’. However, being
an ethically minded humanist—who thus tries to live a life of empathy and compassion
towards her fellow human beings—she wants to help the individual who has been attacked.
So, the following conflicting proposition would also be true: Jane ‘wants to stop and call
for help for the stranger’. Jane, like David, is torn. She is in conflict with herself. She thus
differs from herself. Jane’s struggle is between two aspects of her: Jane insofar as she is a
lawyer versus Jane insofar as she is a humanist. These cases, and other cases of internal
conflict, are cases of self-differing, where the subjects of what differs are the aspects of
the individual that self-differs. Thus, for the case to be one of differing, one aspect must
possess a quality that another aspect lacks. Additionally, for it to be a case of self-differing,
the aspects must be numerically identical to the individual that bears them (Baxter 2018a,
p. 907). The notion of an aspect can be further elucidated at two levels: the semantic level
and the ontological level.
At the semantic level, aspects are expressed through ‘nominal qualifiers’ such as
‘insofar as’ (or ‘in some respect’ and to a lesser extent ‘as’ and ‘qua’). Nominal qualifiers
serve a special role of referring to aspects—they are specifically present within self-differing
Religions 2022, 13, 809
18 of 46
cases, where the same entity can be discernible from itself. Furthermore, following Jason
Turner (2014, p. 227), the use of a nominal qualifier in these cases (and other cases like
them) can be further precisified via formalisation—where one takes ‘α’ as a regular term
and ‘ϕ(y)’ as any formula open in y, and thus we can introduce a term to refer to aspects,
namely an aspect term, written as such: ‘αy [ϕ(y)]’. From this semantic basis, and with the
notion of an aspect term to hand, we can now progress onto the ontological level, which
will allow us to further elucidate the nature of an aspect.
At the ontological level, according to Baxter, aspects are difficult to distinguish from
other entities.39 However, we can begin to acquire an understanding of their nature by
describing their functional role and the relationship to the individuals that bear them.
Primarily, the aspects of an individual function as the particular ways of being of that
individual. A way of being is a conceptually primitive notion that, as noted previously,
can be glossed in part by taking it to be the way or manner in which an entity exists. Thus,
aspects function as the particular ways in which individuals are. However, as ways of being
of an individual, aspects are not qualities (or properties) as they can, themselves, possess
qualities (or properties) due to their numerical identity to the individuals that bear them.40
Aspects, however, do not possess all of the qualities that the particular individuals that
they are aspects of have. Moreover, in a similar manner to their bearers, they are particular
entities, rather than universals, through Leibniz’s Law (in an unrestricted sense) failing to
hold for them.41 Secondly, despite the numerical identity between individuals and their
aspects, aspects are not ‘complete individuals’ due to the fact that complete individuals are
entities that can exist independently. Instead, according to Baxter, aspects are ‘incomplete
entities’ due to them ‘having fewer properties than it takes to exist on one’s own’ (Baxter
2018a, p. 916). Aspects are thus incomplete in the sense of them being dependent upon
the complete individuals that they are numerically identical to.42 The nature of a complete
individual determines the aspects that they have, in that they depend entirely upon how
that individual entity is—once we have the individual, we also have its ways of being
(Giannotti 2019).43 Thirdly, aspects are not mereological parts of the individuals that they
are aspects of, as, again, they are numerically identical to, rather than a ‘part’ of, these
individuals (Baxter 2018a). Lastly, aspects are not mental abstractions. That is, even though
a complete individual’s aspects are abstract entities (through them failing to exhaust the
content or plime that they are aspects of),44 that can be considered by means of abstraction
(where one abstracts a way that an individual is), it is important to note, as Baxter writes,
that the difference between a complete individual and their aspects is ‘a less-than-numerical
distinction but more than a mere distinction of reason’ (Baxter 2016, p. 99). Baxter terms
this distinction, an aspectival distinction, which results in the aspects of an individual only
ever being two (or more) in a ‘loose’ sense—when they are counted based on qualitative
distinction. However, in a ‘strict’ sense—when the aspects are counted based on a numerical
distinction—they are only ever one. Thus, aspects, as Baxter notes, provide a ‘complexity to
the simple, i.e., a qualitative complexity to the quantitatively simple’ (Baxter 2016, p. 178).
Taking this explanation of the semantic and ontological features of aspects into account, for
further clarity, we can construe the concept of an aspect as such:
(a)
(b)
(10) (Aspect)
(c)
(d)
An aspect is a qualitatively differing, incomplete abstract particular entity
that is numerically identical to the complete individual that bears it (and any
other aspect possessed by that individual).
It functions as a particular way that a complete individual is and is
determined by that individual’s nature.
It is expressed through a nominal qualifier such as ‘insofar as’, which, at a precise
level, can be captured through the use of an aspect term (such as αy [ϕ(y)]).
It is distinguishable through an aspectival distinction, rather than a
numerical or conceptual distinction.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
19 of 46
On the basis of this basic construal of an aspect, we can now re-construe the notion of
self-differing as that of the qualitative differing of numerically identical aspects possessed
by an individual. Therefore, in having motivated and clarified the notion of an aspect and
aspectival self-differing it will be helpful now to turn our attention away from psychological
cases, and apply this notion to the case of a multi-located object, which will show how such
an object can differ from itself (without entailing a contradiction). We can state this case
succinctly as follows:
The Case of a Multilocated Object
There is a particular object that is located at two (disjoint) spatial regions. As an entity inherits the
properties (‘qualities’) and relations of the specific region that it is exactly located at, this
particular object bears different properties (‘qualities’) and relations at each of the specific spatial
regions that it is exactly located at.
In unpacking this case and example further: let the spherical region r1 and the cubical
region r2 be disjoint regions in space. Let there exist a multiply located object O that is
exactly located at r1 and r2 , and bears the properties of sphericity S and cubicity C at its
respective regions. Additionally, let ‘@’ stand for the chorological relation ‘__ is exactly
located at spatial region __ (at time __)’. Then, we take the following aspects to exist and
bear differing properties:
(11)
Oy [y@r1 ] is S
and
(12)
Oy [y@r2 ] is C
‘Oy [y@r1 ]’ (i.e., O insofar as it is exactly located at spatial region r1 ) refers to one,
numerically identical aspect of O, which bears the property of sphericity, and ‘Oy [y@r2 ]’ (i.e.,
O insofar as it is exactly located at spatial region r2 ) refers to another, numerically identical
aspect of O, which bears the property of cubicity. These region-specific aspects thus differ in
the properties that are possessed at the regions in which they are exactly located—which,
for some, would be problematic as it seems to be the case that45 :
(13)
Oy [y@r1 ] is S
and
(14)
Oy [y@r2 ] is S
is contradictory, as assuming that it is not possible for an object to be both spherical and
cubical at the same time, then the fact that Oy [y@r1 ] is spherical in r1 implies that it is not
shaped in any other way in any other region in space (including r2 ). Additionally, due to
Leibniz’s Law (i.e., the Indiscernibility of Identicals), which was previously defined above,
it follows that:
(15)
(Oy [y@r1 ]) = (Oy [y@r2 ]) → ∀O [((Oy [y@r1 ]) is F)
↔ ((Oy [y@r2 ]) is F].
This results in Oy [y@r1 ] possessing all of the properties that Oy [y@r2 ] has. More
specifically, as Oy [y@r1 ] is spherical in r1 , then so must (Oy [y@r2 ]) be spherical in r2 .
However, according to (12) Oy [y@r2 ] is not spherical in r2 (through it being cubical in r2 ).
Hence, contradiction. However, a way for one to deal with this apparent contradiction
is to posit the existence of aspects. As, by doing just this, we can see that it is the aspects
possessed by the multiply located object at the different regions in which it is exactly located
that possess these properties and not the object itself. Thus, there is no entailment of a
contradiction here. That is, through the use of nominal qualifiers such as ‘insofar as’ (i.e.,
formally αy [ϕ(y)]), it removes any explicit contradiction, as the above case does not say that
O, unqualified, is and is not spherical shaped. Rather, it is simply Oy [y@r1 ] (i.e., O insofar
Religions 2022, 13, 809
20 of 46
as it is located at a spherical region) that is spherical and Oy [y@r2 ] (i.e., O insofar as it is
located at a cubical region) that is not spherical. The negation, in these types of cases, as
Baxter writes, ‘is internal, that is, has short-scope relative to the nominal qualifier and so
there is no contradiction’ (Baxter 2018b, p. 104). Aspects of O have these qualities, but not
O (unqualified). Yet, Oy [y@r1 ] and Oy [y@r2 ]—as aspects of O—are identical to it, which
indicates, as Turner (2014, p. 239) notes, that the following principle holds:
(Aspect Identity) ∀x(∃z(z = xy [ϕ(y)]) → x =
xy [ϕ(y)]).
Informally: Every aspect is numerically
identical with a complete individual x.
(16)
In reality, O is Oy [y@r1 ], and O is Oy [y@r2 ]—O insofar as it is in a particular region (i.e.,
at r1 or at r2 ) is still O. Additionally, taking into account the transitivity of identity, this
would result in:
(17)
Oy [y@r1 ] = Oy [y@r2 ]
which is that of O’s qualitatively differing aspects each being numerically identical to one
another, yet without the resultant differences between them indicating that these aspects,
and the object that bears them, are numerically distinct entities. That is, one can block the
secundum quid ad simpliciter inference, which, following Baxter (2018a, p. 913), can be written
formally as such:
(18)
(Block) ∼(∀x)(F(xy [ϕ(y)]) → Fx).
Informally: It does not follow from the fact that
an aspect of a complete individual x is F that x
is F.
Thus, in this context, the same thing can be abstractedly considered in two ways,
and in this discernment, it can differ from itself, whilst still being that same thing. O
is numerically identical to the two above aspects (and a near-infinite number of other
aspects), and these aspects are all numerically identical to each other. The same individual
can possess qualitatively differing aspects that are nevertheless numerically identical to the
individual that bears them and also with each other. This all seems to be conceptually
coherent. However, a pertinent issue appears to be in sight. That is, at a prima facie level,
Leibniz’s Law seems to be transgressed within an aspectival framework, as the existence
of aspects allows for there to be numerically identical entities that do not share the same
qualities. Any violation of Leibniz’s Law will certainly be problematic for most individuals.
However, once this issue is further investigated, we can, in fact, see that there is no violation
of Leibniz’s Law within an aspectival framework—as, according to Baxter (2016, p. 172,
emphasis added), aspects allow ‘contradictories to be predicated of the same thing in a
way that Leibniz’s Law is silent about’. We can begin to notice this ‘silence’ by asking the
question of why Leibniz’s Law should be taken to apply to all entities, without restriction?
Baxter sees that the issue might revolve around the frequently raised worry that a relation
that is not characterised by Leibniz’s Law is not identity.46 However, Baxter (2018a, p. 908)
sees that the only reason for this attitude is that the principle seems to express the truth
that no entity both possesses and lacks a property—that contradictions cannot exist in
reality. Thus, as Baxter writes, ‘It may seem that the original Indiscernibility of Identicals
[Leibniz’s Law] is just another way of saying that nothing both has and lacks a property,
which is just another way of saying that no contradictions are true’ (Baxter 2018a, p. 907,
square parenthesis added). It thus seems that individuals regularly accord Leibniz’s Law
(the Indiscernibility of Identicals) the same unassailable status that is regularly given to the
Principle of Non-Contradiction (Baxter 2018a, p. 908). However, following Aristotle, Baxter
sees that what is central to the latter principle is solely that of nothing both possessing
and lacking a property in the same respect at the same time. Thus, this formulation leaves
room to maneuver as it opens up the possibility that, as Baxter writes, ‘something in one
Religions 2022, 13, 809
21 of 46
respect has a property that it in another respect lacks’ (Baxter 2018b, p. 105). However,
that claim is not contradictory, as a contradictory claim here would be for one to say that
some individual in one respect possesses a property that in no respect it possesses. Baxter’s
non-contradictory claim is thus simply that something in one respect is numerically identical
with itself in another respect.47 Thus, based on this claim, some numerically identical things
can qualitatively differ without an entailment of a contradiction. Baxter thus believes that
we lack any substantial reason to believe that Leibniz’s Law applies to every entity without
question, and states that ‘Leibniz’s Law should not be thought of as applying absolutely
generally to anything that can be talked about; the argument that it must apply so generally,
fails’ (Baxter 2018a, p. 907). Rather it is important to consider the domain of quantification for
Leibniz’s Law. That is, according to Baxter (2018a, pp. 907–8), Leibniz’s Law solely applies
to individuals (i.e., complete/independent entities) and thus does not generalise over to
aspects, (i.e., incomplete/dependent entities).
The non-applicability of Leibniz’s Law here leads Baxter (2018a, p. 911) to propose a
further distinction within Leibniz’s Law between the Indiscernibility of Identical Individuals—
which is an iteration of the original principle (i.e., the Indiscernibility of Identicals)—and
the Indiscernibility of Identical Aspects—both of which we can construe formally as follows
(where (II) stands for the Indiscernibility of Identical Individuals and (IA) stands for the
Indiscernibility of Identical Aspects):
(19) (Indiscernibility)
(II):
(IA):
∀x∀y(x = y→(F(x) ↔ F(y)).
Informally: For any things x
and y, if x is numerically
identical with y, then for any
quality F, F is had by x if and
only if F is had by y
∀x∀y(x = y→(∀F)(F(zk[Xk])↔
F(wk[Yk]))) Informally: For
any things x and y, if x is
numerically identical with y,
then, for any property, any
aspect numerically identical
with x has it if and only if any
aspect numerically identical
with y has.
With this distinction in place, Baxter believes that the notion of an aspect does not
present a counterexample to the Indiscernibility of Identical Individuals—as this principle is taken to be silent on aspects.Instead, the issue that we have here is that of there
being problems with the Indiscernibility of Identical Aspects—as an individual might be
numerically identical with an aspect that differs from an aspect that another individual
is numerically identical with, even in the situation in which the first and second individuals are identical (Baxter 2018a). That is, an individual can differ from itself by having
aspects that differ, yet without this requiring that the individuals are numerically distinct.
Identicals that are considered unqualifiedly are indiscernible. However, identicals that are
considered qualifiedly may be discernible—that is, something may qualitatively differ from
itself (Baxter 1999). The non-contradictory internal negation in specific self-differing claims,
such as O’s above, seems to suggest that Leibniz’s Law, properly so-called, does not apply
to aspects. Thus, there are certain cases in which identicals are discernible, yet do not falsify
the principle, namely, when an individual possesses aspects that are numerically identical
to it (and each other). The same thing cannot be true and false of the same individual, in
the same respect, without entailing a contradiction. Yet, phrases such as ‘O insofar as it is
located in a cubical shaped region’ refer to aspects, which are incomplete entities, and not
the complete individual that the aspect is numerically identical with. Thus, as Baxter (2018a,
p. 907) notes, it is vital that one is sensitive to ‘aspectival reference’, which refers to aspects
and is distinguishable from singular reference, which refers to complete entities. Singular
Religions 2022, 13, 809
22 of 46
reference, according to Baxter, is not sensitive to the aspectival distinction, whilst the former
is. Additionally, once we are sensitive to this distinction, we can realise that the domain
of quantification for Leibniz’s Law, in its original sense, as Baxter writes, ‘includes all the
complete entities, but does not include the incomplete entities numerically identical to
some of them’ (Baxter 2018b, p. 104). Thus, it follows that Leibniz’s Law does not preclude
the numerically identical aspects of an individual from being qualitatively different from
each other and the individual themselves.48 Assuming the reality of aspects thus does not
lead to a complete denial of Leibniz’s Law. Instead, there is only a denial of an unrestricted
understanding of Leibniz’s Law that includes all complete and incomplete entities within
its domain. That is, more precisely, there is only a denial of an unrestricted understanding
of Leibniz’s Law—which includes the two principles of the Indiscernibility of Identical
Aspects and the Indiscernibility of Identical Individuals.49 In other words, Baxter is not
seeking to provide counterexamples to Leibniz’s Law, when it is simply understood as
a principle concerning objects of singular reference
(i.e., the Indiscernibility of Identical
‐
Individuals), instead he is proposing counterexamples solely to the principle that ranges
over aspects (i.e., Indiscernibility of Identical Aspects), and so to the Indiscernibility of
Identicals, when it is taken as the conjunction of the former and the Indiscernibility of Identical Individuals (i.e., unrestricted Leibniz’s Law). More can indeed be said here. However,
for the task at hand, we can conclude that Leibniz’s Law does not apply to aspects, and
thus it is coherent to posit the existence of qualitatively differing, yet numerically identical
aspects.
In summary: an object (such as a module trope) can be multiply located in the sense of
it being exactly located at more than one (disjoint) region—it has the exact same shape, size
as, and stands in the same relations of, more than one (disjoint) spatial region. At each of
these regions, a given object can bear (region-specific) aspects—qualitatively differing, yet
numerically identical abstract particular entities that function as ways in which that object
is—which enable it to bear a range of incompatible qualities, without an entailment of a
contradiction. We can now focus on applying the above set of concepts to the task at hand.
‐
3.2. Divinity as a Multiply Located Aspect Bearer
‐
In this stage of our constructive task, we take Divinity to be a multiply located particular
object that possesses aspects.50 Divinity is multiply located in the sense that it is exactly
located at more than one disjoint region—it is exactly located at three (disjoint) spatial
‐
regions. More specifically, within the present chorological system, we take the chorological
‐
relation of exact location: ‘__ is exactly located at spatial region __ (at time __)’, as basic,
and thus state the multiple (exact) locations of Divinity as such:
‐
(20) (Divinity Multiple Location)
(a)
(b)
(c)
Divinity is exactly located at spatial region r1 .
Divinity is exactly located at spatial region r2 .
Divinity is exactly located at spatial region r3 .
Divinity has three exact locations, and it inherits the ‘qualities’ and ‘relations’ of each
of the regions that it is exactly located at. For a visual heuristic, we can illustrate in Figure 6.
this case of multiple location as such:
Figure 6. Theistic Multiple Location.
‐
‐
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
23 of 46
Divinity, which is exactly located at r1 , r2 and r3 , is now taken to bear different
characteristics at each of its different regions. One can ask, however, how could this be so,
given that it is the same single object that is exactly located in three (disjoint) regions at
the same time? Well, how this can indeed be so is by Divinity possessing (region-specific)
aspects. More precisely, Divinity possesses three aspects—termed ‘Divinity-Aspects’—that
correspond to its exact locations, which, utilising the notion of an aspect term, we can
succinctly state as such:51
(21) (Divinity-Aspects)
(a)
(b)
(c)
Divinityy [y@r1 ] (i.e., Divinity insofar as it is exactly located at r1 ).
Divinityy [y@r2 ] (i.e., Divinity insofar as it is exactly located at r2 ).
Divinityy [y@r3 ] (i.e., Divinity insofar as it is exactly located at r3 ).
The nature of these Divinity-Aspects can be further elucidated by focusing on their
specific functional roles and the relationship that they have to Divinity, which allows
us to say that these aspects are not properties, complete entities, or mereological parts.
Rather, they are incomplete abstract particular entities that are numerically identical to
a specific complete individual: Divinity, and function as its ways of being. More fully,
each of the Divinity-Aspects is numerically identical to Divinity, yet they do not possess
the same characteristics as it—they are not the characteristic of being divine. Lacking this
characteristic, the Divinity-Aspects are thus incomplete entities, in that they are dependent
on Divinity, which exists as a complete entity (i.e., an independently existing entity). These
Divinity-Aspects do not exhaust the content or plime that they are aspects of (i.e., they each
do not exhaust Divinity), and they each function as ways that Divinity exists—which we
can consider through a process of abstraction.
At a more specific level, these Divinity-Aspects are focused on the different particular
ways in which the Divinity is. That is, by this module trope having (or, more specifically,
being) the singular-character of Divinity, it would exist in a particular manner and have
certain limitless abilities that enable it to fulfil different roles. This functional role fulfilled
by Divinity allows one to establish an aspectival distinction that takes these differing ways to
be aspects of this specific trope. More precisely, the subjects of this differing would be the
Divinity-Aspects, with each aspect possessing a quality that each of the other aspects lacks.
For instance, focusing on the qualitative differing of Divinityy [y@r2 ] and Divinityy [y@r3 ]
from Divinityy [y@r1 ], we have the following example:
(22)
(23)
(24)
Divinityy [y@r1 ] has the qualities and/or relations of r1 .
~Divinityy [y@r2 ] has the qualities and/or relations of r1 .
~Divinityy [y@r3 ] has the qualities and/or relations of r1 .
In this particular case, we have a case of differing, as there is a qualitative difference
between the aspects of the Divinity. Additionally, importantly, it is a case of self -differing,
as the aspects are numerically identical to Divinity itself. In other words, Divinity insofar as
it is located at a certain region (i.e., r1 , r2 or r3 ) is still Divinity:
(25)
Divinity = Divinityy [y@r1 ]; Divinityy [y@r2 ]; Divinityy [y@r3 ].
Additionally, due to the transitivity of identity, each of the Divinity-Aspects is also
numerically identical to another:
(26)
(27)
(28)
Divinityy [y@r1 ] = Divinityy [y@r2 ],
Divinityy [y@r2 ] = Divinityy [y@r3 ],
Divinityy [y@r3 ] = Divinityy [y@r1 ].
So, in making an aspectival distinction here, in a ‘loose’ sense—focused on qualitative
distinctiveness—we can indeed count a multiplicity of aspects that correspond to the
different spatial regions that Divinity is exactly located at. Yet, in a ‘strict’ sense—focused
on numerical distinctiveness—there is solely one self-same particular object (i.e., property*):
Religions 2022, 13, 809
24 of 46
Divinity, which is differently considered at each of those regions. Taking all of these things
into account, we can now proceed to rename the Divinity-Aspects as such:
(29)
(30)
(31)
The Father = Father-Aspect (i.e., Divinityy [y@r1 ]).
The Son = Son-Aspect (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]).
The Spirit = Spirit-Aspect (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ]).
Each of the members of the Trinity is thus to be identified as Divinity insofar as it is
exactly located at a certain spatial region. The members of the Trinity are Divinity-Aspects
‐
and thus are numerically identical to Divinity and each other—without, however, this
resulting in them having the same qualities as each other—which will keep any issue of
‘Patripassianism’ at bay.52 That is, the Father is a qualitatively differing aspect of Divinity,
the Son is a qualitatively differing aspect of Divinity, and the Spirit is a qualitatively‐
differing aspect of Divinity. Yet, at the bottom level, they are each simply Divinity, despite
there being a qualitative distinction between them. So, again for heuristic purposes, we can
illustrate in Figure 7. this aspectival distinction as such (with ‘D’ standing for ‘Divinity’,‐
‘r1 ’, ‘r2 ’ and ‘r3 ’, standing for distinct spatial regions, ‘A’ standing for an ‘aspect’):
‐
Figure 7. Divinity-Aspects
(i).
Notably, however, there is no Leibniz’s Law (i.e., the Indiscernibility of Identical‐
Individuals) failure here as this law solely applies to complete individuals and thus does
not generalise over to the Divinity-Aspects,
which exist as incomplete/dependent entities.
‐
Thus, within an aspectival context, the same thing: Divinity, is discerned in different ways
in each of the spatial regions that it is located at. Additionally, in this discernment, it differs‐
from itself, whilst still being that same thing. That is, within this aspectival framework,
there is one particular object (i.e., property*): Divinity, that is located at more than one
exact location. Additionally, within each of those locations, Divinity has a corresponding
(region-specific)
aspect, which it is identical to—with each of these aspects being identical
‐
to each other. In short: Divinity is the qualitatively differing Divinity-Aspects,
and the
‐
qualitatively differing Divinity-Aspects
are
one
another.
The
Divinity-Aspects
provide
a
‐
‐
certain ‘complexity to the simple’—a qualitative complexity to the quantitatively simple
(powerful) trope of Divinity. Divinity is thus a multiply located particular object that‐
possesses aspects at its multiple (disjoint) regions—it is exactly located at three (disjoint)
‐
spatial regions, and it bears qualitatively differing, yet numerically identical aspects at
those regions. Counting ‘strictly’, there is only Divinity, but counting in a ‘loose’ manner—a
manner that takes into account qualities—then there are indeed three qualitied entities
present. The numerical identity of the members of the Trinity with Divinity is indeed
‐
secured here—and thus there being an affirmation of the metaphysical simplicity and
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
25 of 46
‘oneness’ of Divinity. However, given that members of the Trinity are to be construed not
simply as aspects of Divinity, but also as relationally distinct persons, what is the nature
of personhood and relationality that is now in play here that enables them to actually be
qualitatively distinct (yet numerically identical) to Divinity and each other? To answer this
question, we will now proceed to the penultimate stage of our constructive task.
4. Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage Three
The third stage of our constructive task focuses on providing a philosophical elucidation and re-construal of element (4*)–(6*) of (MR1 ). This element, in its standard reading,
posits the fact of the Father, the Son and the Spirit being numerically distinct from one
another. The standard and alternative readings of this element are stated as follows:
Monarchical Reading1 (MR1 )
4*. The Father 6= the Son.
5*. The Father 6= the Spirit.
6*. The Spirit 6= the Son.
Monarchical Reading2 (MR2 )
4’. Father-Aspect 6= Son-Aspect.
5’. Father-Aspect 6= Spirit-Aspect.
6’. Spirit-Aspect 6= Son-Aspect.
As was pre-empted at the end of the previous section, in this re-construal of (4*)–(6*)
of (MR1 ), there is an equivocation on the notion of identity that is denied of the members
of the Trinity. Specifically, the 6= symbol is not to be taken as the denial of a relation of
numerical identity between the Divinity-Aspects (which could not be the case given the
fact that the aspects of an individual are numerically identical to that individual and one
another). Rather, it is the denial of a qualitative identity (i.e., sameness) between these
aspects. In other words, the Divinity-Aspects are qualitatively differing, yet numerically
identical aspects of Divinity—and so the present (identity) reading of (AC), unlike that
of (IR), allows one to affirm the numerical identity of the Father, the Son and the Spirit.
This does not, however, lead one to affirm a form of ‘Patripassianism’—the notion that the
Father suffered and underwent the Son’s other human experiences (Kelly 1968, p. 120)—as
each of the members of the Trinity, conceived of as Divinity-Aspects, do not share the
same qualities, and thus, at a qualitative level, are indeed distinct entities—and so, despite
their numerical identity, the qualities (derivable from the experiences) that the Father (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r1 ]) has are not (necessarily) the qualities (derivable from the experiences)
that the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ]) have. That is, in
other words, on the basis of (18), one can block the secundum quid ad simpliciter inference
within an aspectival framework by the qualities of a qualitatively distinct aspect not being
required to be shared by its bearer or by the other aspects of the bearer as well—which
would’ve potentially led to this issue arising. Moreover, neither does it require one to affirm
a form of ‘modalistic Monarchianism’ (i.e., ‘modalism’)—the notion that the Son and the
Spirit were not distinct ‘persons’ from the Father (Kelly 1968, p. 119)—as the qualitative
distinction between the members of the Trinity is a real (i.e., mind-independent) and eternal
distinction between them, such that each of the members of the Trinity is a person—through
each meeting the necessary and sufficient conditions for being one—and are distinct from
one another by a relational distinction. It will be important to now detail the nature of
this qualitative distinction—focused on the metaphysical notions of ‘personhood’ and
‘relations’—that play a part in grounding the distinction of the members of the Trinity, and
then apply it to the task at hand, which will provide a further clarification of this specific
element of (AC) and complete the third, and penultimate, stage of our constructive task.
4.1. Personhood and Relations
In stage three of our constructive task, we introduce the notion of relational personhood,
the nature of which is stated as follows:
(32)
(Relational Personhood): A multiply located particular object that has (region-specific)
aspects, each of whom has a first-person perspective and stands in a non-symmetric relation
that enables it to fulfil certain onto-thematic roles.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
26 of 46
As in stages one and two, this concept of relational Personhood can be further divided
into two sub-concepts: personhood and relationality. These two sub-concepts will now be
unpacked in further detail.
Personhood. The term ‘person’ can plausibly be taken to designate a primary kind. A
primary kind determines what an entity fundamentally is, and thus a given entity could
not exist without being of its primary kind. Specifically, for Lynne Rudder Baker (2005,
2007, 2013), what makes an entity of the primary kind person is that they have a first-person
perspective essentially. As Baker (2007, p. 335) writes, ‘to be a person—whether a divine
person, an angel, a human person, or a Martian person—one must have a first-person
perspective’. ‘Person’ is thus a fundamental kind of which there are many instances:
human, divine, bionic and Martian, etc.; however, despite the numerous instances of
this specific kind, there is a shared, fundamental trait between them: their first-person
perspective—where it is in virtue of an entity having a first-person perspective that it is a
person and falls within this fundamental kind. A first-person perspective is thus the specific
essential property that makes a person fundamentally what they are—it serves as the
defining characteristic of all persons. Hence, a first-person perspective is thus necessary and
sufficient for being a person—it is fundamental in grounding the personhood of an entity—
and it comes in two stages: a rudimentary stage and a robust stage, which corresponds to the
distinction between consciousness and self-consciousness (Baker 2013, p. 62). Following
Baker (2013, pp. 41–42), and focusing firstly on a rudimentary first-person perspective,
we can understand that this type of first-person perspective is, first, a perspective—it is a
disposition to perceive the world from a particular location. Second, it is personal—not in
a manner that it refers to a subject—but one that simply provides the default location in
which the conscious subject perceives the environment that she is interacting with. Third,
it is independent of linguistic or conceptual abilities, which enables entities such as human
infants or non-infants—each of whom lacks concepts—to be able to have this basic form of
a first-person perspective. Turning now to a robust first-person perspective, this type of
first-person perspective is one that has the former features; however, it also includes the
ability for an entity to conceive of oneself as oneself, in the first-person (Baker 2013, p. 108).
Additionally, the specific means by which one conceives of oneself as oneself from the
first-person is through a ‘self-concept’—a concept of oneself from one’s own point of view.
Thus, a self-concept, such as ‘I’m glad that I am a father’, manifests an individual’s robust
first-person perspective—it attributes to oneself a first-person reference—where the second
occurrence of ‘I’ in the above statement directs one’s attention to the person, without, as
Baker writes, any ‘name, description, or other third-person referential device to identify
who is being thought about’ (Baker 2007, p. 334). Thus, the possibility to conceive of as
oneself in the first-person through the use of a self-concept is the primary dividing line
between a rudimentary and a robust first-person perspective.
Nonetheless, in both cases, a first-person perspective is an exemplification of the
dispositional property (‘quality’) first-person perspective, which, in the human case, is an
essential property (‘quality’) of any human being. That is, an animal can only have a
rudimentary first-person perspective that it possesses contingently, whereas a person
comes into existence, according to Baker (2005), at the specific point in which a human
organism develops to the point of supporting a rudimentary first-person perspective.53
Specifically, a human organism firstly acquires a rudimentary first-person perspective
and then proceeds, if uninhibited, to acquire a robust first-person perspective when they
learn enough of a natural language to be able to conceive of themselves as themselves in the
first-person. Thus, a first-person perspective establishes a distinction between thinking of
oneself in the first-person and thinking of oneself in the third person. Once someone, as
Baker writes, can ‘make this distinction, she can think of herself as a subject in a world
of things different from herself’ (Baker 2007, p. 334). Hence, when a person comes into
existence, her first-person perspective determines her persistence conditions: she exists as
long as her first-person perspective is exemplified (Baker 2005, p. 28). Additionally, what
makes a person that specific person is the state of affairs of them exemplifying a first-person
Religions 2022, 13, 809
27 of 46
perspective. Therefore, since a person has a first-person perspective essentially, the state
of affairs of them exemplifying a first-person perspective is the same state of affairs at all
times of their existence—at any time t and in any possible world w, a person exists at t in
w if and only if their first-person perspective is exemplified at t in w (Baker 2013, p. 150).
Thus, given this role that a first-person perspective fulfils, it is a dispositional property
(‘quality’) that cannot be shared. That is, as Baker notes, it is one whose ‘instances cannot be
divided or duplicated. So, a molecule-for-molecule replica of our body would not have
your first-person perspective’ (Baker 2013, p. 65). A first-person perspective is thus a
dispositional property (‘quality’) that is uniquely had by its bearer, specifically because the
particular ‘default’ location, in which the entity perceives the environment, is not shareable,
and thus a duplicate of this entity would not have the same disposition expressed by the
former entity’s first-person perspective, but would instead perceive the world through a
different perspective within the particular default location in which it resides in.
Hence, what we have here is that of an entity being a person—that is, they fall into
the primary kind Person—if, and when, they possess a unique (i.e., non-shareable or divided) first-person perspective (rudimentary or robust), which is an essential dispositional
property (‘quality’) of the person. From this unpacking of the ‘dispositional’ notion of
personhood, we can now turn our attention onto detailing the second notion noted above:
onto-thematic roles.
Relational Onto-Thematic Roles. Relations are certain entities whose nature and ontological status have produced a proliferation of views from the medieval to the contemporary
period. According to Heil (2009, 2012), a helpful taxonomy of views is as follows:
(a)
(33) (Relations)
(b)
(c)
(d)
Hyper-Realism: Relations are ontologically fundamental; truthmakers for
relational judgements are relations.
Projectivism: Relations are creatures of reason, mental comparisons.
Reductionism: Relations are ‘reducible to’ non-relational features of relata.
Moderate Realism: Truthmakers for relational judgements are
non-relational features of the universe.
Focusing on (a): Hyper-Realism, which is the default position within contemporary
metaphysics today,54 relations are real and serve as the ontological counterparts of the
relational predicates that feature in statements such as the following:
(34)
Dante loves Beatrice.
At a more specific level, within the Hyper-Realist framework, the term ‘relation’, as
David Armstrong (1997, p. 87) notes, covers all types of polyadic properties ‘dyadic, triadic
. . . n-adic’. That is, relations can firstly be distinguished by their ‘adicity’: relations (unlike
properties that are ‘monadic’ and thus exemplified by a particular entity alone) are ‘n-adic’
(i.e., n > 1) in that they can hold between a particular and other particulars. So, a ‘dyadic’
relation, such as that which features in (34), holds between one particular and exactly one
other particular, whereas a ‘triadic’ relation is one that holds between one particular and
exactly two other particulars (Macbride 2020, §1).
Secondly, relations can be distinguished by the manner in which they hold between
their relata: as an internal relation or as an external relation. An internal relation is one in
which the existence of the relata entails the existence of the relation. Thus, external relations
are those relations that are not internal. So, focusing on the former type of relation, the
truthmakers for internal relations are nothing more than the terms of the relation—the
identity of a given internal relation is determined by the identity (or the difference) of
their truthmakers. Thus, an internal relation supervenes on the existence of the terms—
where an entity Q supervenes upon another entity P if, and only if, as Armstrong (1997,
p. 12) writes, ‘it is impossible that P should exist and Q not exist, where P is possible’. In
other words, as Armstrong further notes, supervenience ‘in my sense amounts to entity P
entailing the existence of entity Q’ (Armstrong 1997, p. 12). Thus, given this conception
Religions 2022, 13, 809
28 of 46
of supervenience, whatever supervenes in this manner is not something ontologically
additional to the subvenient—it is ‘no addition of being’ or an ‘ontological free lunch’. The
supervenient is ontologically nothing more than its base, and thus, as Armstrong adds, ‘you
get the supervenient for free, but you do not really get an extra entity’ (Armstrong 1997,
p. 13). Internal relations—as entities that supervene upon their terms—are thus not things
that are ontologically more than their subvenient terms—as simply given the existence
of their terms, internal relations ‘are not an addition to the world’s furniture’ (Armstrong
1997, p. 87).
Thirdly, relations can also be distinguished by their direction: a symmetrical relation
or a non-symmetrical relation. A relation is symmetrical if it is the case that whenever an
entity Q stands in a relation R to another entity S, then S also stands in R to Q. Thus, in
contrast to this, a relation is non-symmetrical if it fails to be symmetric in this sense—Q
standing in R to S, does not imply that S also stands in R to Q. So, for example, the marriage
relation, under normal circumstances, would be asymmetrical relation, as if Q stands in
the marriage relation to S, then S also stands in that same relation to Q, whereas the love
relation, which featured in (34), is a non-symmetric relation, as Dante standing in the loving
relation with Beatrice does not imply that Beatrice also stands in this same relation with
Dante—namely, that she loves him as well.
So, focusing now on non-symmetrical relations, Kit Fine (2000) has identified a specific
problem plaguing non-symmetrical relations: the Problem of Relational Order. Specifically,
taking (34) as an example, the issue is that of non-symmetrical relations having a certain
order that stems from the first relatum in a relational fact—Dante—to the second relatum
in that fact— Beatrice. However, there also seems to be different relational order that
goes from the second relatum in that relational fact—Beatrice—to the first relatum in that
fact—Dante. Yet, the question is, how can this be so? Given that within this relational
fact, there are exactly the same relata: Dante and Beatrice, that are standing in the exact
same relation: loving. In response to this issue, Francesco Orilia (2008, 2011, 2014), who
argues from a positionalist framework55 , has introduced the notion of ‘onto-thematic roles’
(O-Roles). O-Roles are introduced by Orilia (2014, p. 283) in order to deal with the Problem
of Relational Order, and are best understood as ‘the ontological counterparts of thematic
roles such as agent, patient, beneficiary, instrument and the like, introduced by linguists in
their syntactic and semantic analyses of verbs and prepositions’. O-Roles such as *agent*,
*patient* *instrument* and *beneficiary*, etc., according to Orilia (2014), are sui generis
properties (‘qualities’) that function as specific roles that relata fulfil in a given relation,
with a requirement within this theory that a relation must always occur with a certain
O-Role attached to it. This notion of an O-Role ultimately provides a plausible solution
to the Problem of Relational Order, due to the fact that within a given relation, the relata
have different relational orders based upon the O-Roles that they fulfil. Order is thus,
as Orilia (2008, p. 172) writes, ‘nothing but the occurrence in a fact of arguments with
different o-roles’. For example, focusing on the relational fact of (31) again, if one assumes
the existence of the O-Roles of *agent* and *patient*, we have the case of Dante fulfilling the
O-Role *agent* in the statement Dante loves Beatrice, whilst we have Beatrice not fulfilling
that specific O-Role—instead, she fulfils the O-Role *patient* in that exact same relation.
This relational fact has a different relational order from Beatrice loving Dante, as in this fact,
it is Beatrice that fulfils the O-Role *agent* and not Dante—where, instead, Dante fulfils the
O-Role *patient* in this specific relation. So, even though there are exactly the same relata
that stand in the exact same relation, there is a relational order within these facts due to the
different O-Roles that are fulfilled by the relata—in other words, order is established in a
relation by it always being accompanied by a specific O-Role that can be fulfilled by the
distinct relata that stand in that particular relation.
In summary: a given object is classed as a person if it bears a first-person perspective,
which is best conceived of as a dispositional property (‘quality’)—that is tied to the ‘region’
(or ‘location’) that the entity resides within. Furthermore, relations can be distinguished
by their adicity, form and direction, with the latter requiring the existence of O-Roles—
Religions 2022, 13, 809
29 of 46
ontological counterparts of thematic roles that play a part in establishing order within a
specific relation. We can now, again, focus on applying the above set of concepts to the task
at hand.
4.2. Divinity as Onto-Thematic Persons
In this stage of our constructive task, we take Divinity to possess a robust first-person
perspective and fulfil a certain O-Role in each of the spatial regions that it is exactly located
at. As noted previously, Divinity is a multiply located particular object, in that it is exactly
located at three (disjoint) regions of space. At each of these regions, Divinity has a robust
first-person perspective essentially. That is, Divinity insofar as it is exactly located at a certain
region—Divinityy [y@r1 ] (i.e., the Father), Divinityy [y@r2 ] (i.e., the Son) and Divinityy [y@
r3 ] (i.e., the Spirit)—has a personal perspective—a disposition to perceive and interact with
the world and surrounding environment from a particular default spatial region. Secondly,
this personal perspective is robust in the sense that Divinity has the ability to conceive of
itself as itself, in the first-person, which is expressible through a ‘self-concept’—a concept
of Divinity from its’ own point of view. Now, given that Divinity bears the dispositional
quality of a robust first-person perspective, it falls into the primary kind Person and thus
can be classed as a person. More specifically, as Divinity is a multiply located particular
object, what we have here is that of Divinity insofar as it is exactly located at a specific spatial
region bearing this particular dispositional quality and thus is a person. We can state this
more precisely as such:
(35)
(36)
(37)
The Father (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) is a person (i.e., has a robust first-person perspective).
The Son (Divinityy [y@r2 ]) is a person (i.e., has a robust first-person perspective).
The Spirit (Divinityy [y@ r3 ]) is a person (i.e., has a robust first-person perspective).
The persons that are Divinity insofar as it is exactly located at r1, r2 and r3 (i.e., the
Father, the Son and the Spirit) are not the same persons, given the fact that, first, it is
the qualitatively differing Divinity-Aspects that bear these ‘dispositional qualities’ and,
second, as noted above, an instance of a first-person perspective cannot be duplicated nor
divided in any sense. Thus, the Father, even though he is an aspect of Divinity—and
thus is numerically identical to it—does not have the first-person perspective of the Son
and the Spirit (and so on for the Son and the Spirit as well). This is specifically the case
here due to the fact that the particular ‘default’ location, in which, for example, the Father
(Divinityy [y@r1 ]) perceives his environment, will not be shareable—that is, r1 is solely
occupiable by the Father, with r2 being solely occupiable by the Son and r3 solely occupiable
by the Spirit—and thus the Son and the Spirit (who are simply Divinity insofar as it is located
in other (disjoint) regions) would not have the same disposition expressed by the Father’s
first-person perspective. Rather, given that Divinity is a multiply located object, it would
instead perceive the world through different perspectives within the particular ‘default’
locations in which it resides in—namely, r1 , r2 and r3 .56 Hence, each of the members
of the Trinity has a different robust first-person perspective—they each bear a different
‘dispositional quality’—and thus are distinct persons—and are ‘eternally’ so, given the
essential nature of a first-person perspective. That is, as a first-person perspective plays
a key role in the persistence conditions of an entity, the members of the Trinity—each of
whom are eternally existing entities—would thus bear their distinct and unique first-person
perspective essentially for as long as they exist, which is thus eternally. In short, contra
modalism, the members of the Trinity are essentially and eternally distinct persons.
On the basis of this, we can now further elucidate the relational distinction between
the members of the Trinity within this framework by focusing on the particular relation
in which they stand to one another. Specifically, we posit that there is an internal, nonsymmetrical relation that serves as an ontological counterpart to the relational predicates of
the following statements:
Religions 2022, 13, 809
30 of 46
(38)
(39)
The Father generates the Son.
The Father generates the Spirit through the Son.
Within the framework in which we are operating within, we can take this generation
relation, which is expressed by (38) and (39), to be best conceptualised as a relation of
‘grounding’ that holds between the Father, the Son and the Spirit, due to the Father (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r1 ]) setting the ‘location relations’ in both cases—such that Divinity is then
exactly located at two other (disjoint) spatial regions (i.e., r2 and r3) as well—which (nontemporally) results in the existence of the Son and the Spirit. The Son and the Spirit (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r2 ] and Divinityy [y@r3 ])) exist in the specific regions that they do in virtue of the
Father (i.e., Divinityy [y@r1 ]).57 In regard to the nature of these generation (i.e., grounding)
relations, we can understand that, firstly, the generation relation that holds between the
Father and the Son in (38) is a ‘dyadic’ relation, as it holds between two qualitatively
distinct things: the Father and the Son. Whereas the relation of ‘generation’ that holds
between the Father, the Son and the Spirit in (39) is a ‘triadic’ relation, as it holds between
three qualitatively distinct things: the Father, the Son and the Spirit. Secondly, this relation
of generation in both cases is an internal relation—the existence of the Father, the Son
and the Spirit entails the existence of this relation—in short, they serve as its truthmakers.
Additionally, thus, the generation relation is supervenient upon the existence of the Father,
the Son and the Spirit (i.e., it’s supervenient upon the existence of the Divinity, which
serves as its subvenient base)—in other words, the generation relation is not ontologically
additional to them—it is ‘no addition of being’ and an ‘ontological free lunch’. Thirdly, this
relation of generation is non-symmetrical in the sense that the Son and the Spirit standing in
a generation relation with respect to the Father does not imply that the Father also stands
in the same relation with the Son and the Spirit—the Father is not generated by the Son, nor
by the Spirit. Additionally, thus, given the non-symmetrical nature of this relation, there is a
relational order present within it that stems from the Father to the Son and the Spirit, which
is grounded upon the O-Roles that the Father, the Son and the Spirit fulfil in this relation.
Specifically, we have three O-Roles present in the relational facts of (35) and (36)—*agent*,
*instrument* and *patient*—which we can distribute amongst the persons as follows: first,
as the Father is the generator of the Son and the Spirit, he fulfils the O-Role *agent*. Second,
as the Son is generated by the Father, and is the means by which the Spirit is generated, he
fulfils the O-Roles *patient* and *instrument*. Additionally, third, as the Spirit is generated
by the Father (through the Son), he solely fulfils the O-Role of *patient*. The relational order
that is present in (38) and (39) is thus founded upon the different O-Roles that are fulfilled
by the Father, the Son and the Spirit, which is simply that of Divinity insofar as it is exactly
located at r1 , r2 and r3 fulling these specific roles. Taking this all into account, we can now
re-state (35)–(37) as that of there being three relationally distinct persons, the nature of which
is to be understood as such:
(40)
(41)
(42)
The Father (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) is a person (i.e., has a robust first-person perspective) and fulfils
the O-Role of *agent*.
The Son (Divinityy [y@r2 ]) is a person (i.e., has a robust first-person perspective) and fulfils the
O-Roles of *patient* and *instrument*.
The Spirit (Divinityy [y@ r3 ]) is a person (i.e., has a robust first-person perspective) and fulfils
the O-Role of *patient*.
The Father, the Son and the Spirit are thus each Divinity insofar as it is exactly located
at a particular region of space, with a robust first-person perspective and the fulfilment
of a certain O-Role at that region. However, as noted previously, the Father, the Son and
the Spirit are Divinity-Aspects and thus are each numerical identical to Divinity and one
another, yet can (and do) qualitatively differ by their possession of distinct robust firstperson perspectives and the fulfilment of distinct O-Roles. So, we can see here that there is a
basis for the present account dealing with the distinction issue. However, before we further
explain how this is to be done, it will be important to now answer the further question of:
what is the ontological nature of the first-person perspective and O-Roles that are fulfilled
‐
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
31 of 46
‐
‐
by Divinity in its specific spatial regions? Unlike in the more mundane cases, a first-person
‐
perspective
and O-Role cannot be‐ a dispositional or sui generis property of Divinity, if it is
to continue to be conceived of as a metaphysically simple trope—as any property borne by
it would not be numerically identical to it—resulting in Divinity not being identical to its
nature through its possession of dispositional and sui generis proper metaphysical parts.
‐ and O-Roles must
So, the Father, the Son and the Spirit’s robust first-person perspectives
‐
be construed in a different way, which we can do by combining together two previously‐
adduced concepts: powerful qualities and aspects, and introduce the notion of an aspectival
powerful quality.
More specifically, we can answer this question by utilising a reformulation of the
powerful qualities concept that was previously introduced. As noted above, Divinity is a
‐
dual-charactered
property* that has a dispositional character—conveying upon it a power
to act in a certain way—and a qualitative character—contributing to the overall makeup of
it. The dispositional and qualitative character of Divinity, as in the more mundane cases,
are identical to each other and Divinity itself. So, on the basis of this identity between
them, and in answer to the question concerning the nature of them that was also previously‐
raised, we can now take the dispositional and qualitative character of Divinity to be
dispositional and qualitative aspects of it. Within this reformulated framework, we are thus
to perform a conversion of the dispositional and onto-thematic
‐ properties into dispositional‐
and qualitative (onto-thematic)
‐ aspects, which will also result in the instantiation relation in
the former case being converted into a relation of numerical identity. We can illustrate in
Figure 8. this conversion for heuristic purposes as such:
Figure 8. Aspects and Relation Conversions.
This conversion allows us to construe the first-person
perspectives and O-Roles
fea-‐
‐
‐
tured here in an aspectival manner. More precisely, the robust first-person
perspective
had,
‐
and the O-Roles
fulfilled by, Divinity insofar as it is in a certain spatial region, are dispo-‐
‐
sitional and qualitative sub-aspects
of it—dispositional and qualitative aspects of aspects.
‐
Divinity insofar as it is exactly located in one spatial region has the dispositional and quali-‐
tative sub-aspects
that Divinity insofar as it is exactly located in another spatial region lacks.
‐
The Divinity-Aspects
‐ differ in their sub-aspects.‐For each of the Divinity-Aspects, identified
‐
as the Father, the Son and the Spirit, they have a dispositional first-person perspective
aspect‐
‐
and a qualitative O-Role aspect. We
can
state
this
succinctly
as
such:
‐
‐
‐
(a)
(b)
(43) (Divinity-Aspects (ii))
(c)
The Father (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) is: Dispositional Sub-Aspect: A
Robust First-Person Perspective Qualitative Sub-Aspect: The
‐
‐
O Role *agent*.
‐
The Son (Divinityy [y@r2 ]) is: Dispositional Sub-Aspect: A
Robust First-Person Perspective Qualitative Sub-Aspect: The
‐
O-Role‐*patient* and *instrument*.
The Spirit
(Divinityy [y@r
‐
‐ 3 ]) is: Dispositional Sub-Aspect: A
Robust First-Person Perspective Qualitative Sub-Aspect: The
O Role *patient*.
‐
‐
‐
Within an aspectival framework, a ‘sub-aspect’ is an aspect of an aspect. Hence, the
dispositional first-person perspective sub-aspect (i.e., Divinityy [y@rn ] insofar as they have a
first-person perspective), which is had by Divinity in each of its (disjoint) spatial regions,
endows the Father, the Son and the Spirit with the power to—amongst other things—think
of themselves as themselves in their respective regions, whereas the qualitative O-Role
sub-aspect, which is fulfilled by Divinity in each of its (disjoint) spatial regions, contributes
to making each of the Divinity-Aspects what they are—for the Father, by him bearing the
qualitative O-Role sub-aspect of *agent* (i.e., Divinityy [y@r1 ] insofar as it is the O-Role
‐
‐
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
‐
‐
‐
‐
32 of 46
‐
‐
‐
‐
‐
‐
*agent*), he is the Father. For the Son, by him bearing the qualitative O-Role sub-aspect
of *patient* and *instrument* (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ] insofar as it is the O-Role *patient* and
‐
‐ he is the Son. Additionally, for the Spirit, by him bearing
‐ the qualitative
*instrument*),
‐ O-Role *patient*), he is‐
O-Role sub-aspect of *patient* (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ] insofar as it is the
the Spirit. Yet, each of these dispositional and qualitative sub-aspects of the Divinity-Aspects
‐
is not a numerically
distinct entity but, in fact, are one and the same thing—the DivinityAspects, which are themselves numerically identical to Divinity. For heuristic purposes, we
can illustrate in Figure 9. this as such (with all of the letters remaining as before with the
addition being that of ‘D’ in the smaller
circle standing for ‘dispositional aspect’ (with ‘F’‐
‐
standing for ‘first-person perspective’) and ‘Q’ in the smaller circle standing for ‘qualitative
aspect’ (with ‘A’ standing for ‘agent’, ‘IP’ for ‘instrument and patient’ and ‘P’ for ‘patient’)):
‐
Figure 9. Divinity-Aspects
(ii).
So, as noted previously, there is no Leibniz’s Law failure, as was found within the original Powerful Qualities framework introduced above. Rather, we have a cogent proposal‐
that enables one to establish the metaphysical simplicity and oneness of Divinity, whilst
continuing to maintain the relational distinction of the persons. As for a given Divinity‐
Aspect—let us take the Father as an example—one can make an aspectival distinction by‐
dispositionally regarding, or considering it in one way, through its first-person‐perspective‐
that renders it as a person (i.e., as the person of Father), or one can also make another
aspectival distinction by qualitatively regarding, or considering it in another way—through
the specific O-Role that it fulfils
‐ (i.e., as *agent*), which together allows one to distinguish
the Father from the Son and the Spirit (and vice versa). Nonetheless, it is the self-same,
simple,‐ powerful trope: Divinity, which is located at multiple (disjoint) spatial regions‐
—at r1 and r2 and r3 . Divinity, as a multiply located powerful module trope, is thus one
metaphysically simple entity despite the relational and personhood distinctions that have
been made, which allows there to only be one Divinity (i.e., divine nature) posited here.
5. Constructing Monarchical Aspectivalism: Stage Four
The fourth stage of our constructive task focuses on providing a philosophical elucidation and re-construal of element (7*) of (MR1 ). This element, in its standard reading, posits
the existence of one God in the Trinitarian life who is numerically identical to the Father.
The standard and alternative readings of this element are stated as follows:
Monarchical Reading1 (MR1 )
7*. There is exactly one God, the Father.
Monarchical Reading2 (MR2 )
7’. There is exactly one fundamental
Divinity-Aspect, the Father-Aspect.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
33 of 46
In this re-construal of (7*) of (MR1 ), there is a utilisation of the metaphysical notion
of ‘fundamentality’—which allows one to further understand the notion of ‘God’ (in the
nominal sense) as centring on the metaphysical concept of ‘fundamentality’, and thus one
can identify the one ‘God’—taken as the Father—to be the fundamental Divinity-Aspect
within the Trinity. It will be important to now further unpack the nature of fundamentality,
and then apply it to the task at hand, which will provide a further clarification of this
specific element of (AC) and complete the final stage of our constructive task.
5.1. The Nature of Fundamentality
In stage four of our constructive task, we introduce the notion of fundamentality, the
nature of which is stated as follows:
(44)
(Fundamentality) An entity is fundamental if it is independent (i.e., unbuilt/ungrounded)
and complete (i.e., the builder/ground of everything else).
This concept of fundamentality can be further divided into two sub-concepts: independence/completeness and grounding. These two sub-concepts will now be unpacked in
further detail.
Independence and Completeness. In contemporary metaphysics, the notion of fundamentality is used in reference to an entity (or entities) that is (or are) basic, primitive or
rock-bottom in the hierarchical structure of reality. Two central aspects of the notion of
fundamentality, according to Karen Bennett (2017), are those of independence and completeness (with the former being more central to the notion than the latter).58 In Bennett’s
thought, fundamentality, construed as independence and completeness, is intimately tied
to the further notion of building. Building is a technical term that ties together the following
type of relations: composition, constitution, set-formation, realisation, micro-based determination, grounding and causation. These various relations are not intended by Bennett to be
exhaustive but are instead relatively central notions that intuitively fit the mold of being a
building-relation. How these paradigm relations fit this building mold is through them
fulfilling the three necessary and jointly sufficient conditions of directedness, necessitation
and generation. Firstly, the condition of directedness takes a building-relation to be antisymmetric, irreflexive and thus asymmetric. Secondly, the condition of necessitation
takes builders to necessitate, in some sense, what they build. Thirdly, the condition of
generation takes the built entities to exist in virtue of their builders, and thus the latter back
an explanation for the former existing as they do (Bennett 2017, p. 32). These necessary
and sufficient conditions distinguish building-relations from other types of relations and
provide a basis for the claim that building-relations form a unified family (i.e., a natural
resemblance class) despite the differences amongst them (Bennett 2017, p. 20). Off the basis
of this further explication of the notion of building, we can now construe the independence
aspect of fundamentality as such:
(45)
(Independence) x is independent if nothing builds x (Bennett 2017).
Additionally, we can now also construe the completeness aspect of fundamentality
as such:
(46)
(Completeness) The set of the xxs is (or the xxs plurally are, or a non-set-like x is) complete
at a world w just in case its members build ( . . . ) everything else at w (Bennett 2017, p. 109).
According to (Independence), absolutely fundamental entities are independent in
the sense that they are unbuilt and thus do not depend on anything else. Moreover, for
(Completeness), a certain set of absolutely fundamental entities are complete at a specific
world in the sense that they build everything else in that world. That is, they are the things
that ultimately account for everything else that does exist in that specific world. Fundamentality, as expressed by (44) and further elucidated by (45) and (46), reflects, as Bennett (2017,
p. 111) notes, two halves of the familiar phrase ‘unexplained explainers’, the ‘unexplained’
Religions 2022, 13, 809
34 of 46
part reflecting independence which says that nothing ‘presses upwards’ on them and the
‘explainers’ part reflecting completeness which says that a certain set of entities ‘presses
upwards’ on everything else in a specific world. Furthermore, and more importantly, these
two aspects are reducible to and defined by the notion of building. That is, within the
building-fundamentality framework, there is thus a deflationism (or reductionism) about
fundamentality, where the fundamentality facts are simply the building facts (Bennett 2017).
Therefore, as Bennett notes, for certain fundamentality relations to obtain is simply ‘for
certain complex patterns of building to obtain’ (Bennett 2017, p. 139). In short, there is an
identification of fundamentality with building. Thus, the state of affairs of an entity being
absolutely fundamental is that of them being independent and complete, which is reducible
to the entity being, on the one hand, unbuilt and, on the other hand, part of a set at a world
whose members build everything else in that specific world. However, it is important to
remember that there is not a single, general relation of building. Rather there are a different
number of building-relations that form a unified family. Thus, when the term ‘building’ is
used in a singular sense, it is simply a generalisation about a class of relations (Bennett 2017,
p. 3). Therefore, fundamentality, construed as independence and completeness, is to be
indexed to particular building-relations. Hence, in indexing fundamentality to particular
building-relations, to be absolutely fundamental is to be independent and complete, which,
for the former, is ultimately reducible to either not being composed, or constituted, or
realised, or determined, or grounded, or caused, by anything else—an absolutely fundamental entity does not feature as an output of a particular building-relation (Bennett 2017,
p. 112), whereas for the latter, it is ultimately reducible to being a member of a set of entities
at a world whose members compose, or constitute, or realise, or determine, or ground, or
cause everything else, in that specific world—the set of absolutely fundamental entities
builds, in one of the above ways, everything else (Bennett 2017, p. 112). Thus, there are
various real distinctions between the indexed versions of fundamentality. We can focus
attention now on one particular building-relation: grounding.
Grounding. This notion is one that is regularly characterised as a primitive expression
of dependence, determination or explanation. This expression has been championed by
‘grounders’ (i.e., grounding theorists) such as Kit Fine (2012), Jonathan Schaffer (2009, 2016)
and Gideon Rosen (2010), amongst others.59 For some of these grounders, such as that of
Schaffer, grounding is best construed as follows:
(47)
(Grounding) An asymmetric, necessitating dependence relation that links the more
fundamental entities to the less fundamental entities, and is best conceptualised as a type of
causation: metaphysical causation.
As an asymmetric, necessitating directed-dependence relation, grounding is associated
with the notion of ontological priority—this directed-dependency relation takes in terms
from any arbitrary ontological category and links a more fundamental input to a less fundamental output (Schaffer 2016).60 Thus, according to Schaffer (2009), there is an ontological
ordering within reality, in that some entities are derivative of other, more fundamental
entities. The fundamental entities of reality ontologically undergird the derivative entities,
and grounding is the relation that connects the undergirding entity to entities that are at a
higher level in the structure of reality. Thus, within this perspective, there is a hierarchical
view of reality that is ordered by priority in nature. Once one distinguishes more from
less fundamental entities, it is natural to posit a relation linking certain more fundamental
entities to certain less fundamental entities which derive their existence from them (Schaffer
2016, p. 145). Grounding is thus the name of this direct ‘linkage’ which is governed by the
above formal and modal principles, connects the more to the less fundamental entities and
thereby imposes a hierarchical structure over what there is (Schaffer 2009).
Now, closely related to ground’s ability to structure reality are two further roles that it
serves: its explanatory and generative roles. That is, firstly, explanation tracks grounding,
and grounding, in some sense, backs explanation. Grounding entails the explicability of
the grounded on the basis of its grounds and thus serves the role of providing a synchronic
Religions 2022, 13, 809
35 of 46
metaphysical explanation for the nature and/or existence of a less fundamental entity on the
basis of the nature and/or existence of another, more fundamental entity (Schaffer 2016).
Thus, for example, if one is seeking an explanation for the existence of Singleton-Socrates
(i.e., the set with Socrates as its sole member), a synchronic metaphysical explanation for
this particular case would simply cite the relevant metaphysical laws (i.e., the principles of
grounding) and the fact that Socrates exists. More fully, in this example, Socrates grounds
Singleton-Socrates and thus a synchronic metaphysical explanation for the existence of the
less fundamental entity: Singleton-Socrates, would cite the more fundamental source(s) of
that entity, which is that of Socrates, as mediated through the principles of grounding. Thus,
in this case, and others like it, the grounds provide an explanation for the grounded—grounding
is thus a relation that is intimately tied to explanation. Secondly, grounding is super-internal
in the sense that the existence and intrinsic nature of one of the relatum ensure, firstly, that
the grounding relation obtains and, secondly, that the other relatum (or relata) exists with
the intrinsic nature that it has (Schaffer 2016).61 So, for example, it is Socrates, and the
intrinsic nature that he possesses, which makes it the case that Singleton-Socrates exists
and has the nature that it does (namely, being the singleton set that includes Socrates as a
member). Thus, as there is a generation of the grounded from the grounds, once there is a fixing
of the intrinsic nature of the grounds, there is also a fixing of the intrinsic nature of what is
grounded. This emphasises the fact that the existence of the grounds is sufficient to account
for the grounded—grounding is thus a relation that is generative by nature.
Consequently, given the fulfilment of these explanatory and generative roles, grounding thus provides the direction and linkage needed for metaphysical explanation and
generation in a similar manner in which causation provides the direction and linkage
needed for causal explanation and generation. This leads one to infer that the best explanation of this striking similarity is that of grounding being identical to metaphysical
causation—which is to be held in distinction from nomological causation. Specifically, following Alastair Wilson (2018),62 , we can take the grounding relation to be a special case of
the causal relation where, as Wilson (2018, p. 724) notes, ‘whenever A grounds B, A is a
(metaphysical) cause of B and B is a (metaphysical) effect of A’. Metaphysical causation and
nomological causation, are thus different species of the same genus: causation, such that,
for the former, once one distinguishes the more from the less fundamental, it is quite natural
to posit an explanatorily-backing, generative relation of metaphysical causation. Thus, the
similarity between grounding (i.e., metaphysical causation) and causation (i.e., nomological
causation) centres on the manner in which the causal sufficiency relation is mediated within a
causal and grounding context. More precisely, if laws of nature mediate a given instance
of the causal sufficiency relation, then it is a case of nomological causation—for example,
the throwing of a stone is a sufficient nomological cause of the breaking of a window, as
this causal relation is mediated by laws of nature. Whereas if the (law-like) principles of
grounding fulfil the role of mediating a given instance of the causal sufficiency relation,
then it is a case of metaphysical causation—for example, the existence of Socrates is a
sufficient metaphysical cause of the existence of Socrates’ singleton set, as this causal relation
is mediated by the (law-like) principles of grounding.63 Grounding (i.e., metaphysical
causation) and nomological causation are thus simply different ways for the causal relation
to be mediated and thus obtain (Wilson 2018).64 With this notion of grounding to hand, we
can now further elucidate the notion of fundamentality in light of grounding, and re-state
(44) in its indexed format as such:
(48)
(FundamentalG ): x is fundamental if x is independentG and completeG .
In unpacking this, we, firstly, can state the indexed version of (45) as such:
(49)
(IndependenceG ): x is independent if nothing grounds x.
Additionally, secondly, we can state the indexed version of (46) also as such:
Religions 2022, 13, 809
36 of 46
(50)
(CompletenessG ): The set of the xxs is (or the xxs plurally are, or a non-set-like x is)
complete at a world w just in case its members ground everything else at w.
According to (48), as further elucidated by (49) and (50), an entity is fundamental if it
is ungrounded (i.e., not grounded by any other entity) and is a member of a set of entities at
a world whose members ground everything else in that specific world. Whereas an entity
is derivative, that is non-fundamental (i.e., dependent and non-complete), if something
grounds it and/or it is not a member of a set of entities at a world whose members ground
everything else in that specific world.65 In further precisifying this connection between
fundamentality and grounding, we can apply the various grounding principles within this
framework resulting in the nature of a fundamental entity being as expressed by Table 1:
Table 1. Fundamentality Grounding Principles.
Grounding Principles
IndependentG (Ungrounded)
CompleteG (Ground)
Directed
This entity does not rank below any other
entity in the hierarchical structure of reality.
This entity is part of a set that ranks higher than any
other entity in the hierarchical structure of reality
within the specific world in which this set exists.
Necessitating
The existence of another entity does not
necessitate the existence of this entity.
This entity is part of a set that necessitates the
existence of every other entity within the specific
world in which this set exists.
Generative
This entity’s existence and intrinsic nature are
not fixed by the existence and intrinsic nature
of any other entity.
This entity is part of a set whose existence fixes the
existence and intrinsic nature of every other entity
within the specific world in which this set exists.
Explanatory
This entity’s existence, at a specific time, is not
explained by the existence of any other entity.
This entity is part of a set that, at a specific time,
explains the existence of all other entities within the
specific world in which this set exists.
Causal
This entity is not a grounded effect of any
other entity.
This entity is part of a set that is the metaphysical
cause of other entities, which are grounded effects
within the specific world in which this set exists.
A fundamental entity is thus one that is not an output of a grounding relation, rather, it
ultimately serves as the ground of everything else. For a fundamental entity, nothing presses
upwards on it, instead, it serves the role of pressing upwards on all other (non-fundamental)
entities—it is a basic feature of the hierarchical structure of reality (Bennett 2017, p. 111).
We thus have a clear, and indexed precisification of the notion of fundamentality with a
clarification here of how the building-relation of grounding fits neatly into this picture. We
can now utilise these notions and apply them to the task at hand.
5.2. ‘God’ as the Fundamental Aspect
In this stage of our constructive task, we take the Father (i.e., Divinityy [y@r1 ])—unlike
the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ])—to exist of himself, be
the ultimate source of everything and thus be the one true ‘God’.66 More specifically, the
Father is the ‘unexplained explainer’, in that he is, on the one hand, independent, which is
to say that he is unbuilt and, on the other hand, he is complete, which is to say that he is a
member of a set of entities at a world whose members build everything else.67 However,
as noted above, the notions of independence and completeness are ambiguous as they
stand. In that, we must index each of the notions to particular building-relations. Thus,
focusing on the specific building-relation of grounding, the Father being independent is
reducible to him being ungrounded and him being complete is reducible to him being a
member of a set of entities at a world whose members ground everything else. In short,
the Father is the ungrounded ground of everything else. Hence, in the reading of (AC)
provided by Monarchical Trinitarianism—where the one ‘God’ is numerically identical to
the Father—is now to be understood as him—in Monarchical Aspectivalism—being ‘God’
in a ‘fundamentality-sense’. The Father, as the fundamental Divinity-Aspect—in that this
Religions 2022, 13, 809
37 of 46
specific aspect of Divinity (i.e., Divinityy [y@r1 ]) is ontologically prior to all other things
in the hierarchical structure of reality. He is independent of all things and exists as the
complete entity within this structure, due to him—in the region in which he is located
within—being ungrounded (i.e., unbuilt) and fulfilling the role of grounding (i.e., building)
the Son, the Spirit and all other features of reality—with the former being done by setting
their specific ‘location relations’. The Father (i.e., Divinityy [y@r1 ]) is thus fundamental by
not being the output of any grounding relation, in that nothing ‘presses upwards’ on him;
rather, he presses upwards on all other (non-fundamental) entities.
We can thus further elucidate the nature of the Father’s role as the fundamental aspect
of Divinity—that is, the fundamental Divinity-Aspect within the Trinity—by applying the
grounding principles, expressed by Table 2., to this specific case as well:
Table 2. Trinitarian Fundamentality Grounding Principles.
Grounding Principles
IndependentG (Ungrounded)
CompleteG (Ground)
Directed
The Father (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) does not rank
below the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the
Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ]) or any other entity
in the hierarchical structure of reality.
The Father (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) ranks higher than the Son
(i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ])
and any other entity in the hierarchical structure of
reality within the specific world in which he exists.
Necessitating
The existence of the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ])
and the Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ]) or any
other entity does not necessitate the existence
of the Father.
The Father’s (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) existence necessitates
the existence of the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the
Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ])and every other entity
within the specific world in which he exists.
Generative
The Father’s (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) existence and
intrinsic nature are not fixed by the existence
and intrinsic nature of the Son (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r3 ]) or any other entity.
The Father’s (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) existence and intrinsic
nature fix the existence and intrinsic nature of the Son
(i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r3 ]) and every other entity within the
specific world in which he exists.
Explanatory
The Father’s (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) existence, at a
specific time, is not explained by the existence
of the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit
(i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ]) or any other entity.
The Father’s (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) existence, at a specific
time, explains the existence of the Son (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ])
and all other entities within the specific world in which
he exists.
Causal
The Father (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) is not a grounded
effect of the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the
Spirit (i.e., Divinityy [y@r3 ]) or any other entity.
The Father (Divinityy [y@r1 ]) is the metaphysical cause
of the Son (i.e., Divinityy [y@r2 ]) and the Spirit (i.e.,
Divinityy [y@r3 ]), and all other entities that are grounded
effects within the specific world in which he exists.
Grounding, conceived as a relation of directed-dependence, plays the needed role of a
necessary explanation-backing link that stems from the Father to Son and the Spirit, and is
mediated by the principles of grounding. The Son and Spirit—as Divinity Aspects— are
dependent for their existence as aspects of Divinity upon the (eternal and necessitating)
action of Divinity insofar as it is located at a different location—namely, r1 —fulfilling a
certain role—namely, the O-Role *agent*. Hence, the Son and the Spirit do not exist as
independent aspects but are grounded (or built) aspects. Thus, as the Son and the Spirit
are the less fundamental result within this grounding relationship, they are subordinate
aspects of Divinity. Therefore, there is a distinct ordering and status distinction between
the Divinity Aspects within the Trinitarian life, where the Father as the independent and
complete aspect (i.e., the ungrounded ground of everything else), is fundamental, and the
Son and the Spirit, who, as dependent and non-complete aspects (i.e., grounded entities
that are not the ground of everything else), are thus derivative, non-fundamental aspects.
We can now illustrate in Figure 10. for heuristic purposes this status distinction
through the following fundamentality (hierarchical) structure (with (‘Ground’ standing for
a ‘relation of grounding’, ‘LS’ standing for ‘location setting action’ and ‘CLS’ standing for
‘cooperative location setting action’):
‐
Religions 2022, 13, 809
‐
38 of 46
Figure 10. Trinitarian Fundamentality Structure.
There is a hierarchical structure within the Trinity as we have the case here of there
being one entity: Divinity, which insofar as it is located in one region (having a perspective
and fulfilling a certain role) is fundamental and undergirds itself in insofar as it is located
in two other regions (having two perspectives and fulfilling two other roles) with the
grounding relation connecting the latter aspects to the former aspect that is at a higher
level in the structure of reality. Thus, the Son and the Spirit (i.e., the undergirded aspects)
are linked by the grounding relation as less fundamental output, to a more fundamental
input (i.e., undergirding aspect), the Father.68 Within this hierarchical structure, as noted
previously, the Father is thus the fundamental and most ‘basic’ aspect in all of reality
who serves as the ultimate (synchronic metaphysical) explanation for the nature and/or
existence of the Son and the Spirit (and all other reality). He (i.e., (Divinityy [y@r1 ])) is thus
the one ‘God’ (i.e., the fundamental Divinity-Aspect). Yet, the Son and the Spirit, are not
rightly called ‘God’ (in the nominal sense), through them being aspects of Divinity that
lack this fundamentality.
Given all of this, we can now, first, re-construe conditions (a) and (b) of (Monarchical
Trinitarianism) as follows:
(a)
(51) (Monarchical
Aspectivalism)
(b)
There are three relationally distinct persons (i.e., three bearers of a
first-person perspective that fulfil an onto-thematic role at their
respective spatial regions) within the Trinity: the Father, the Son and
the Spirit, each of whom is a (region-specific) aspect that is numerically
identical to the one, multiply located, powerful trope: Divinity.
The one ‘God’ (in the nominal sense), who is the fundamental (i.e.,
independent and complete) Divinity-Aspect, is identified as one of the
aspects: the Father, who is the sole ground (i.e., builder) of the Son and
the Spirit.
Second, within the framework established by this account, we thus have a basis
for providing a re-interpretation of the Athanasian Creed (AC) through an alternative
Monarchical reading (MR2 ), which was previously constructed in a step-wise manner but
now can be brought together as follows:69
Religions 2022, 13, 809
39 of 46
Athanasian Creed (AC)
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
The Father is God
The Son is God
The Spirit is God
The Father is not the Son
The Father is not the Spirit
The Spirit is not the Son
There is exactly one God.
Monarchical Reading2 (MR2 )
1’. Father-Aspect = Divinity (Trope).
2’. Son-Aspect = Divinity (Trope).
3’. Spirit-Aspect = Divinity (Trope).
4’. Father-Aspect 6= Son-Aspect
5’. Father-Aspect 6= Spirit-Aspect
6’. Spirit-Aspect 6= Son-Aspect
7’. There is exactly one fundamental
Divinity-Aspect, the Father-Aspect.
Thus, according to (MR2 ), in line with element (7), there is one ‘God’—identified as
the Father, who is the fundamental Divinity-Aspect. However, in line with elements (1)–
(3), The Father, construed as an aspect—termed ‘Father-Aspect’—is numerically identical
to Divinity (i.e., a powerful trope); the Son, construed as another aspect—termed ‘sonAspect’—is numerically identical to Divinity (i.e., the same powerful trope as the former
aspect); and the Spirit, construed as another aspect—termed Spirit-Aspect’—is numerically
identical to Divinity (i.e., the same powerful trope as both former aspects). Yet, and most
importantly, given their relational personhood (i.e., the distinct first-person perspectives
and onto-thematic roles) had by each of the Divinity-Aspects, we (fortunately) in this
account, do not face the distinction issue (i.e., (4), (5), (6) being transgressed), and neither—
given the metaphysical and Monarchical element of this reading—do we face the oneness
issue, (i.e., (7) being transgressed)—as, for the former issue, the Father (i.e., Father-Aspect),
the Son (i.e., Son-Aspect) and the Spirit (i.e., Spirit-Aspect), are qualitatively distinct, yet
numerically identical to one another (and Divinity), which thus grounds their distinction
from one another. Additionally, for the latter issue, there is only one entity who is identified
as the one God (in the nominal sense) and the sole fundamental Divinity-Aspect: the Father,
which preserves the oneness of ‘God’ within the Trinitarian life. Monarchical Aspectivalism
thus provides a means for one to affirm the doctrine of the Trinity whilst also upholding a
numerical identity of the Father, the Son and the Spirit with Divinity, and thus maintaining
the metaphysical simplicity of the Divinity by forgoing relational and personal properties,
for ‘personal’, ‘relationally determined’ aspects. Additionally, given the metaphysical
framework that has been developed here, one can uphold all of these things without,
however, falling into absurdity. Thus, the (LPT) does not, in fact, plague the reading of the
Athanasian Creed (i.e., (MR2 )) that is provided by this Trinitarian account. The doctrine of
the Trinity, as construed in an Aspectival manner, does not face the Logical Problem of the
Trinity, and thus one can indeed proceed to adopt a Monarchical Trinitarian position, even
within the Latin Trajectory as well.
6. Conclusions
In conclusion, a solution has been provided to the Logical Problem of the Trinity
by introducing a new account of the doctrine of the Trinity: Monarchical Aspectivalism,
and an alternative reading of the Athanasian Creed: the Monarchical Reading, in light
of certain central theses within the field of contemporary metaphysics. In utilising these
theses, one is able, in a coherent manner, to affirm the existence of three relationally
distinct persons within the Trinity, with the Father being the one ‘God’ and each of the
persons being numerically identical to one, metaphysically simple divine nature—whilst
still being distinct from one another (in the most important sense of the word). Monarchical
Aspectivalism thus allows a certain reading of the Athanasian Creed to be a viable option
for future Trinitarian theorising.70
Funding: This research received no external funding.
Institutional Review Board Statement: Not applicable.
Informed Consent Statement: Not applicable.
Data Availability Statement: Not applicable.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
40 of 46
Conflicts of Interest: The author declares no conflict of interest.
Notes
1
The veracity of the filioque is assumed in this conception of the Trinity.
2
By a model, following Alvin Platinga (2000), I mean a collection of propositions that shows how it could be so that another
collection of target propositions is true or actual. In light of this, certain models of the doctrine of the Trinity seek to provide a
possible means in which the doctrine could, in fact, be true.
3
The Latin Trajectory includes Latin-speaking theologians such as Hilary of Poitiers, Ambrose of Milan and Augustine of Hippo.
However, the origin of the Athanasian Creed post-dates the writing of these authors, yet its language and concepts are firmly
grounded within the Latin (Augustinian) tradition. For a detailed exposition of the historical development of the Athanasian
Creed within the trajectory, see (Kelly 1964).
4
Cartwright appears to be the first individual to have introduced into the literature what has come to be known as the ‘Logical
Problem of the Trinity’. There are other terms used in reference to this problem, such as the ‘Inconsistent Septad Problem’ and the
‘Fundamental Problem’. However, due to the ambiguity of some of these terms, I will continue to refer to this problem through
the more generic term of the ‘Logical Problem of the Trinity’ (LPT). More on the nature of this problem below.
5
Swinburne’s ‘social Trinitarianism’ account of the Trinity provides a ‘three-self’ answer to the Logical Problem of the Trinity.
6
Leftow’s ‘Latin Trinitarianism’ account of the Trinity provides a ‘one-self’ answer to the Logical Problem of the Trinity.
7
van Inwagen’s ‘Relative Identity’ account of the Trinity provides an answer to the Logical Problem of the Trinity by questioning
the ‘absoluteness’ of identity—and proposing a relativisation of identity.
8
For further clarity, (IR) can be translated into predicate logic and reduced to three premises as follows (where f stands for the
Father, s for the Son, h for the Spirit and G for God).
9
1*. Gf & Gs & Gh.2*. f 6= s & f 6= h & s 6= h.3*. ∃x (Gx & ∀y(Gy → x = y).
10
(Sijuwade 2021) is the first to propose this type of account within a Monarchical Trinitarian context.
11
For a helpful explanation of this issue within a detailed historical context—namely that of the notion of a universal within the
Cappadocians and the tri-theistic theology of John Philoponus, see (Erismann 2008).
12
Pawl (2020) did not fully explicate the critique of the development of the model featured in this article. Thus, the ‘multiple-natures’
problem should be seen as a further development of his critique.
13
We can further understand the term to mean that each of the persons is extensively equal such that they possess numerically the
same essential property of Divinity. For a further explanation of this construal of the notion of the homoousion, see: (Mullins 2020,
p. 2).
14
For a response to this issue within an instantiation-based framework, see (Sijuwade 2021).
15
Which has been done frequently within the analytic theology literature to deal with the distinction issue by taking the ‘is’ of
(1)–(3) as one of predication rather than that of identity. For this, see (Swinburne 1994), (Wierenga 2004), (Hasker 2013) and (Davis
2006).
With the oneness issue now being held at bay by one utilising a Monarchical framework.
16
17
This use of the term ‘abstract’ (and concrete) also contrasts with the prevalent understanding of the term, which sees an abstract
entity as something that has, for concrete entities, or lacks, for abstract entities, spatiotemporal location or causal efficacy (Fisher
2020). Thus, as Campbell (1990, p. 3) further writes, focusing on abstract entities:
Abstract does not imply indefinite, or purely theoretical. Most importantly, it does not imply that what is abstract is
non-spatiotemporal. The solidity of this bell is a definite, experienceable and locatable reality. It is so definite, experienceable
and locatable and that it can knock your head off, if you are not careful.
18
Given the complexity and space required to unpack Langton and Lewis’ account, the brief explanation here will be based on
Alvarado’s interpretation of it.
19
20
I leave the account of analogy here undefined. Furthermore, I do not assume here that the ‘properties’ borne by this particular
have to be properties in an ‘ontologically robust sense’—as other entities could be borne by this particular, such as ‘sub-aspects’,
which are introduced below.
Further philosophers who have defended and developed the Powerful Qualities view are: Alexander Carruth (2015), J. Henry
Taylor (2013, 2017, 2019), William Jaworski (2016) and Joaquim Giannotti (2019), Galen Strawson (2008), Jonathan D. Jacobs (2011),
Kristina Engelhard (2010) and Rognvaldur Ingthorsson (2013).
21
Character language will be favoured over that of nature language.
22
An assumption is made here concerning a powerful trope being multi-track, rather than single-track.
23
We can assume the notion of intrinsicality noted above.
24
In contradistinction to this, one could hold (as some philosophers do) to the conception of the dispositionality of a trope as
‘single-track’—which is that of a given trope only having one manifestation type.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
41 of 46
25
Construing qualitativeness in this specific way, rather than as a term that is synonymous with the term ‘non-dispositional’—as it
regularly has been done—enables the proponents of the Powerful Qualities view to ward off the charge of inconsistency that has
been raised by David Armstrong (1997) and Stephen Baker (2013), amongst others. For an extended and informative examination
of the notion of qualitativeness within the literature, see (Taylor 2019).
26
This example is adapted from (Taylor 2017).
27
The proponents of the Powerful Qualities view do not use the term ‘traits’ to refer to the dispositionality and qualitativeness of a
trope. However, I feel that it is less metaphysically loaded than the terms ‘parts’ or ‘sides’, and thus I will continue to utilise this
term here.
This distinction is usually drawn by the proponents of the positions of Dispositionalism—all properties are purely dispositional,
Categoricalism—all properties are solely non-dispositional, and a ‘mixed view’—some properties are solely dispositional, whilst
other properties are held to be solely categorical/qualitative. For a defense of Dispositionalism, see Sydney Shoemaker (1980)
and Alexander Bird (2007). For a defense of Categoricalism, see David Lewis (1983) and David Armstrong (1997). Additionally,
for a defense of a mixed view, see George Molnar (2003) and Brian Ellis (2001).
28
29
This can be termed the canonical conception of the Powerful Qualities view, given that this specific version is the one proposed by
the formulators of the Powerful Qualities view: Martin and Heil. However, there are other versions of the Powerful Qualities view,
such as that provided by Giannotti (2019) and Taylor (2013), that do not adhere to a ‘surprising identity’ between a property’s
dispositionality and its qualitativity.
30
Another example of a general case of a powerful quality is that of the mass or charge of a particle: we can consider a particle
quantitatively when we consider it to have a certain mass or for it to have a certain quantity of charge that can be measured in
Coulombs—with each of these being ‘here and now’ features that a particle has. However, at the same time, we can consider
a particle dispositionally when we regard it to have a disposition to generate gravitational force or a disposition to produce an
electromagnetic force. In this example, it is in virtue of a particle having a certain mass or quantity of charge (both qualities of
this particle) that it has the dispositions that it does.
31
An objection that can be faced here—as was raised by an anonymous reviewer—is that of one getting the physics wrong with
this example. That is, it seems to be the case that whether the ball is disposed to roll down the slope depends on much more
than the shape of the ball. For example. if the ball and slope are in zero gravity, the ball is not disposed to roll down the slope.
If the ball and slope are appropriately magnetised, then the ball is not disposed to roll down the slope. If the ball is made
from a super-adhesive substance, then the ball is not disposed to roll down the slope. If—perhaps per impossible—the ball is
massless, then the ball is not disposed to roll down the slope. Thus, it seems to be a mistake in taking the ability of a ball to roll
down a slope to be a paradigm example of a powerful quality. However, in response to this, one can—in following Heil (2012,
p. 129)—understand that the case of a ball rolling down a slope to be a mutual manifestation of dispositions of the ball/slope and
the dispositions present in the environment. Hence, if the ball and the slope are in zero gravity, or are magnetised, or the ball is
massless, or made from a super-adhesive substance, then these additional things simply inhibit this manifestation. However,
this inhibition is simply a matter of the dispositional system that includes dispositions of the magnetic field, the super-adhesive
substance, and the absence of gravity and mass, yielding a different sort of mutual manifestation—namely, the manifestation of
the ball to remain still on the slope. Hence, in these cases, it is a matter of certain dispositions of the ball and the slope manifesting
themselves with various other mutual manifestation partners that results in a different effect than if the ball and slope were
manifesting their dispositions without the interference of these other dispositional partners. For more on this issue, see (Heil
2012, pp. 126–30).
32
Importantly, the notion of an aspect that will be introduced below is not the same as that of Giannotti’s (2019), which he introduced
to deal with a similar problem with the Powerful Qualities view.
33
More on the nature of location below.
We can also say that Divinity is in some sense a personal agent, as to exercise its maximal power/omnipotence, it must be an
entity that has a rich form of consciousness that enables it to perform a range of actions that are solely limited by logic. Thus,
taking Divinity to be a trope does not rob it of this personhood, given that it is a trope of a modular kind. More on the notion of
personhood below.
34
35
Though in the Father’s ‘grounding’ of the Son and the Spirit—as will be detailed below—Divinity’s power will not move from
inactivity to activity but, instead, would always be manifested, given that its grounding act will be a necessary action that stems
from Divinity’s perfect goodness. More on this below.
36
As Christian Theism is being assumed here, Divinity is taken to be a ‘part’ of the Trinity and thus is borne by, and works through,
the Trinity (i.e., in cooperation with the Son and the Spirit). This conception of the Trinity assumes the notion of the ‘monarchy of
the Father’—the teaching that Divinity is numerically identical to the Father alone—which is contrary to the common position
that holds to Divinity being numerically identical to the Trinity. As noted in the main text, the difference between these positions
is more than a linguistic issue as proponents of the monarchy of the Father will take the existence of the Father to be the basis
for Christian Theism being monotheistic—as there is ‘one Father’, there is ‘one Divinity’—whereas proponents of the common
position would take the existence of the Trinity to be the basis for Christian Theism being monotheistic—the ‘unified collective’
(i.e., the Trinity) is the ‘one Divinity’.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
42 of 46
37
With the temporal relativisation being kept implicit.
38
Aspects are also further developed by Baxter in the different context of clarifying the instantiation relation between a particular
and a universal. For this, see (Baxter 2001).
As Baxter writes, ‘aspects should not be confused with Casteneda’s guises (1975), or Fine’s qua-objects (1982), or other such
attenuated entities’ (Baxter 2018b, p. 103).
39
40
In reference to aspects, there will be an interchanging of the term ‘qualities’ with the term ‘properties’. However, the former term
is preferable over the latter term, as it helps us to ward off mistaking the entities that are born by aspects needing always to be
further entities that are ontologically different from them—as aspects can bear qualitied ‘sub-aspects’.
41
More on this below.
In motivating aspects, Baxter believes that the clearest cases, as in the example in the main text, are those of the internal
psychological conflict of a person. However, self-differing, according to Baxter, is not only confined to these psychological
conflicts but, as Baxter writes, cases ‘of being torn give us the experiences by which we know that there are numerically identical,
qualitatively differing aspects. We feel them’ (Baxter 2016, p. 99). Self-differing is present in any case where an entity has a
property and lacks it at the same time, in the virtue of playing different roles (Baxter 1999).
42
43
One can ask the question of if aspects can vary over time? I believe that they can, and do, given that the paradigm examples of
aspects—as noted above—are had in self-differing cases. Given the modal variance of aspects, how could they be numerically
identical to their bearers? I believe that one way in which one can hold to the numerical identity of an aspect with their bearer,
despite their modal variance, is by assuming an account of ‘temporary identity’ (or ‘occasional identity’)—such as that found in
the work of André Gallois (1998), and which has been endorsed by Baxter (2018c)—in which something identical with itself at
one time is at that time distinct from itself at another. That is, any case of identity is identity at a time, which, following (Baxter
2018c, p. 767) allows one to formalize temporary identity as follows:
(Temporary) (∃x)(∃y)(∃t)(∃t’)(at t: x=y & at t’: ~(x = y))
Informally: For something x and something y and for some times t and t’, x is numerically identical with y at t and x is
numerically distinct from y at t’.
A good reason that motivates adopting this view of identity (as ‘temporary’ or ‘occasional’) is explained well by McDaniel (2014,
p. 16) and thus deserves to be quoted in full:
One reason to embrace ‘temporary’ identity is that it solves puzzles arising from fission and fusion. The left half of a worm
is crushed by a boot. The worm is mutilated but endures. So a worm can survive the loss of half of its body. What if it had
been the right half that had been crushed? The worm would have been mutilated but would have endured. Again, the
worm can survive the loss of half of its body. Suppose we bisect a worm with a surgical knife. Two non-identical worms,
Lefty and Righty, are the result. Which is the original worm? Let t′ be the time of bisection, and t some time shortly prior. It
seems that, at t, Lefty is identical with the original worm, but so is Righty. Therefore, at t, Lefty is identical with Righty.
However, it seems that at t′ , Lefty is not identical with Righty. According to the doctrine of temporary identity, things are
exactly as they seem. (It is worthwhile to remember that many of our students find this response initially very attractive
when they first consider the puzzle of fission.) Similar remarks apply to puzzles in which two things fuse into one.
Now, in adopting this view of identity, one is indeed required to make further restrictions to Leibniz’s Law (i.e., there being a
temporal analogue of Leibniz’s Law)—which might indeed have some pushback. Nevertheless, for good reasons to make these
further restrictions (and for a method on how to do this), see: (Baxter 2018c, pp. 769–79) and (McDaniel 2014, pp. 17–19).
44
45
Thus, the abstractness and particularity of an aspect fit neatly with that of a trope’s abstractness and particularity that was
noted above.
Region-specific in the sense that an aspect borne by a particular object in the specific region in which it is located is not borne in
any other region in which that object is also exactly located at.
46
As noted by Ted Sider (2007, p. 57), ‘Defenders of strong composition as identity must accept this version of Leibniz’s Law; to
deny it would arouse suspicion that their use of ‘is identical to’ does not really express identity’. Likewise, as noted by Einar
Bohn (2021, p. 4597, square parenthesis added), [Leibniz’s Law] is simply conceptually rock bottom of what I mean by identity.
So, violating it amounts to, at best, changing the subject’. Furthermore, one might still comment that it is inconceivable to define
numerical identity without utilising Leibniz’s Law, and thus Baxter’s approach should be rejected. However, Baxter (2018a,
p. 908) notes that he is not defining identity; but instead, is taking it as primitive—for one to be numerically identical is to be one
single individual and to be numerically distinct is simply to be two single individuals (Baxter 2018a). It is the connection with
cardinality, rather than qualitative sameness, which is essential to numerical identity.
47
A single individual differs from itself by having two or more aspects. An important question that can be raised here is if the
two-ness of the aspect entails a numerical distinctness between the aspects? Baxter (2018a, p. 908) believes not, as counting
aspects is only a loose way of counting individuals—aspects possessed by a single individual are counted as more than one in
virtue of their qualitative difference; however, this does not entail a numerical difference that would result in the individual being
more than one individual. More on this below.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
43 of 46
48
Baxter notes that Leibniz’s Law does not entail Indiscernibility of Identical Aspects, given that it could only do this if aspects
were included within the domain of quantification for the principle, but as it is not, there is no entailment and the variables thus
instead range only over individuals alone (Baxter 2018a).
49
Baxter (2018a, p. 909) sees Leibniz’s Law as being closely related to the further principle that co-referential terms are substitutable
salva veritate. However, he notes that this specific principle concerns only singular reference, and thus the substitution of
expressions only refers to single individuals. One would thus need to provide an argument for why it should be generalised
to aspects.
50
An objection that can be raised here concerns the importance of location relations to the current proposal, as one could argue
that, even if the proposal works, it is not applicable within a theological context, given that the Trinitarian persons are usually
taken to not stand in any location relation. Or, at least, the Trinitarian persons stand in a location relation in a derivative sense,
such as that found within the accounts of divine omnipresence featured in: (Swinburne 2016) and (Wierenga 2010). However, a
possible way to deal with this issue is to adopt Hud Hudson’s (2009) and Alexander Pruss’ (2013) ubiquitous entension account
of location, which takes Divinity to stand in location relations in a fundamental sense—by entending the region in which it is
located. Additionally, thus, within this account, Divinity does indeed have an exact location in the manner that the proposal
requires it to have—it entends three specific spatial regions. For a further discussion and historical modification of this position
in light of the ‘materialist’ implications of the account, see (Inman 2017). However, another issue that one could raise is that,
given the further assumption that Divinity entends the entirety of space (as it is omnipresent), it is hard to see how the Trinitarian
persons could have distinct regions of space in which they are located within—that is, they, too, will entend the entirety of space.
Additionally, thus, to suggest otherwise would be to suggest that the three persons are subject to arbitrary limitations. However,
one can respond to this issue by questioning the assumption that Divinity entends the entirety of space. Rather one can assume
the derivative view of omnipresence such that Divinity is related to the entirety of space in a derivative sense and thus does not
entend it. More specifically, this derivative form of omnipresence would take ‘Being present at’ relation in a non-basic sense,
which means, as Georg Gasser (2019, p. 45) ‘that any locative facts about an object’s presence in a region in space are constituted
by facts about another entity (or entities) bearing a ‘present at’-relation in a basic sense and to which the object in question stands
in a particular relation’. Being present at thus means being present at in a derivative sense, and thus Divinity, being omnipresent,
would be present to all of space in this specific sense of the terms. Hence, Divinity is to be taken to be an entity that only entends
the three disjoint spatial regions of r1 , r2 and r3 —and is then, from these regions, related to the rest of the spatial regions in a
derivative sense.
The following proposal seeks to further develop the interesting work of Effingham (2015b).
51
52
53
More on this issue below.
Thus, human infants are persons in virtue of them having a rudimentary first-person perspective and developing, over time, a
robust first-person perspective as they mature and learn a language (Baker 2013).
54
Heil (2009, 2012) himself affirms Moderate Realism. However, for a further explanation of the role played by Hyper-Realism
within the field of contemporary metaphysics, see (Macbride 2020).
55
Positionalism is a specific conception of the nature of relations which takes there to be certain ‘positions’ in a relation that are
‘occupied’ by the relata. For a further explanation of positionalism, see (Macbride 2020, §4). Furthermore, Mario Paoletti (2016)
has also developed Orilia’s theory by providing a reformulation of the nature of O-Roles through a utilisation of E.J. Lowe’s and
John Heil’s notion of a mode. Paoletti (2019) then applied this reformulated theory of O-Roles to certain logical issues concerning
the Trinity. Despite the plausibility of Paloletti’s proposal, this development cannot affirm the numerical identity (yet qualitative
distinctiveness) of the members of the Trinity—as a mode is not identical to its bearer— and thus, given this, I will stick with
Orilia’s position that O-Roles are simply sui generis properties (which, however, provides ‘conceptual room’ to conceive of them
as aspects within a theistic context).
56
I leave it open here whether the argument for the distinctiveness of the first-person perspectives had by the members of the
Trinity that has been put forward here is sufficient to ground the distinctiveness of a robust first-person perspective or only
a rudimentary one. If not, then one can modify (32)–(34) by taking them to bear rudimentary rather than robust first-person
perspectives—which is sufficient for them being persons.
57
The ‘in virtue’ clause here indicates that this is a metaphysical grounding relation. More on the nature of grounding below.
58
For the reasons for privileging independence over completeness, see (Bennett 2017, pp. 122–23).
59
For a historical explanation of these individuals’ roles in developing the notion of ground, see (Raven 2020).
60
For a different, but highly influential conception of ground, that does not take it to be a relation, but a sentential operator that has
facts within its purview, see: (Fine 2012).
61
That grounding is super-internal was first posited by (Bennett 2011, pp. 32–33). Furthermore, grounding’s super-internality is not
to be confused with the internality of other relations. As the former type of internality, and not the latter, requires that only one of
the relatum exists in order for the relation to hold between the relata.
In following Wilson in taking grounding to be identical to causation—metaphysical causation—we are not taking grounding to be
analogous to, but distinct from, causation as Schaffer (2016) does. For the reasons why Schaffer does not make this identification,
62
Religions 2022, 13, 809
44 of 46
see (Schaffer 2016, pp. 94–96). Additionally, for a summary of reasons why someone should make this identification, see (Wilson
2018, p. 748).
63
Wilson (2018) is more instructive than Schaffer (2016) in highlighting the importance of the different ways that the causal
sufficiency relation is mediated. Furthermore, Schaffer (2016, p. 57) uses the terms ‘laws of metaphysics’ rather than ‘principles of
grounding’, which feature in a later article (Schaffer 2021). We can thus take both of these terms to be synonymous and continue
using the latter.
64
For a further explication of the notion of grounding within a Trinitarian context, see (Sijuwade 2022).
65
For brevity, the additional clause ‘in that specific world’ will now be an unwritten assumption.
66
For ease of writing, in this specific constructive stage, the sub-aspects of each of the Divinity-Aspects will be suppressed.
67
Specifically, the Father would be the sole member of this set.
68
However, by the Son and the Spirit being ‘derivative’, it does not mean that they are created, which, assuming the doctrine of
creatio-ex-nihilo (i.e., creation out of nothing), would require the Son and the Spirit to be brought from non-being into being at
some point in time. However, as the Son and the Spirit are backwardly everlasting, this is clearly not the case.
69
For further clarity, (MR2 ) can also be translated into predicate logic and reduced to three premises as follows (where f stands for
the Father, s for the Son, h for the Spirit and G for God):
1’. Gf & Gs & Gh.
2’. f = s & f = h & s = h.
3’. ∃x (Gx & ∀y(Gy → x = y).
With this alternative reading, in comparison to (IR), we have a numerical identity relation being retained in (MR2 ), with solely the
negation of a relation of a qualitative identity (sameness) between them—which is brought out in the main text by stating in
(4’)–(6’) that each of the Divinity-Aspects is not identical (i.e., 6=) to another. Importantly, however, this is not a form of relative
identity, as identity is not assumed to be relative in this specific account.
70
I am grateful to the editors and publishers of the International Journal for Philosophy of Religion and the European Journal for
Philosophy of Religion for allowing me to reuse certain material from previously published work.
References
Alvarado, José. T. 2019. Are Tropes Simple? Teorema 38: 53–54.
Armstrong, David. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ayres, L. 2004. Nicaea and Its Legacy: An Approach to Fourth-Century Trinitarian Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Baker, Lynne R. 2005. When Does a Person Begin? Social Philosophy and Policy 22: 25–48. [CrossRef] [PubMed]
Baker, Lynne R. 2007. Persons and the metaphysics of resurrection. Religious Studies 43: 333–48. [CrossRef]
Baker, Lynne R. 2013. Naturalism and the First-Person Perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Baxter, Donald L. M. 1999. The Discernibility of Identicals. Journal of Philosophical Research 24: 37–55. [CrossRef]
Baxter, Donald L. M. 2001. Instantiation as partial identity. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 79: 449–64.
Baxter, Donald L. M. 2016. Aspects and the Alteration of Temporal Simples. Manuscrito 39: 169–81. [CrossRef]
Baxter, Donald L. M. 2018a. Self-Differing, Aspects, and Leibniz’s Law. Noûs 52: 900–20. [CrossRef]
Baxter, Donald L. M. 2018b. Oneness, Aspects, and the Neo-Confucians. In The Oneness Hypothesis: Beyond the Boundary of Self. Edited
by Philip J. Ivanhoe, Owen Flanagan, Victoria S. Harrison, Hagop Sarkissian and Eric Schwitzgebel. New York: Columbia
University Press, pp. 90–105.
Baxter, Donald L. M. 2018c. Temporary and Contingent Instantiation as Partial Identity. International Journal for Philosophical Studies 26:
763–80. [CrossRef]
Behr, John. 2004. The Nicene Faith Part 1 & Part 2. New York: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press.
Behr, John. 2018. One God Father Almighty. Modern Theology 34: 320–30. [CrossRef]
Bennett, Karen. 2011. By Our Bootsraps. Philosophical Perspectives 25: 27. [CrossRef]
Bennett, Karen. 2017. Making Things Up. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bohn, Einar. 2021. Composition as identity: Pushing forward. Synthese 198: 4595–607. [CrossRef]
Bird, Alexander. 2007. Nature’s Metaphysics: Laws And Properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Branson, Beau. 2022. One God, the Father. TheoLogica: An International Journal for Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology 6: 1–53.
[CrossRef]
Campbell, Keith. 1990. Abstract Particulars. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cartwright, Richard. 1987. On the Logical Problem of the Trinity. In Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 187–200.
Carruth, Alexander. 2015. Powerful Qualities, Zombies and Inconceivability. The Philosophical Quarterly 66: 25–46. [CrossRef]
Davis, Stephen T. 2006. Christian Philosophical Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Effingham, Nikk. 2015a. The Location of Properties. Noûs 49: 25–44. [CrossRef]
Effingham, Nikk. 2015b. Multiple Location and Christian Philosophical Theology. Faith and Philosophy 32: 25–44. [CrossRef]
Ehring, Douglas. 2011. Tropes: Properties, Objects and Mental Causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ellis, Brian. 2001. Scientific Essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Religions 2022, 13, 809
45 of 46
Engelhard, Kristina. 2010. Categories and the Ontology of Powers: A Vindication of the Identity Theory of Properties. In The
Metaphysics of Powers: Their Grounding and Their Manifestations. Edited by Anna Marmodoro. New York: Routledge, pp. 41–58.
Erismann, Christophe. 2008. The Trinity, Universals, and Particular Substances: Philoponus and Roscelin. Traditio 53: 277–305.
[CrossRef]
Fine, Kit. 2000. Neutral Relations. Philosophical Review 199: 1–33. [CrossRef]
Fine, Kit. 2012. Guide to Ground. In Metaphysical Grounding: Understanding the Structure of Reality. Edited by Fabrice Correia and B.
Schnieder. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 37–80.
Fisher, Anthony. R. J. 2018. Instantiation in Trope Theory. American Philosophical Quarterly 55: 153–64. [CrossRef]
Fisher, Anthony. R. J. 2020. Abstracta and Abstraction in Trope Theory. Philosophical Papers 49: 41–67. [CrossRef]
Gallois, André. 1998. Occasions of Identity: A Study in the Metaphysics of Persistence, Change, and Sameness. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Garcia, Robert K. 2015a. Two Ways to Particularize a Property. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1: 635–52. [CrossRef]
Garcia, Robert K. 2015b. Is Trope Theory a Divided House? In The Problem of Universals in Contemporary Philosophy. Edited by Gabriele
Galluzzo and Michael Loux. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 133–55.
Gasser, Georg. 2019. God’s omnipresence in the world: On possible meanings of ‘en’ in panentheism. International Journal for Philosophy
of Religion 85: 43–62. [CrossRef]
Giannotti, Joaquim. 2019. The Identity Theory of Powers Revised. Erkenntnis 86: 603–21. [CrossRef]
Gilmore, Cody. 2018. Location and Mereology. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved March 2021. Available online:
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/location-mereology/ (accessed on 1 October 2021).
Hasker, William. 2013. Metaphysics And The Tri-Personal Divinity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Heil, John. 2009. Relations. In The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics. Edited by Robin. L. Poidevin. New York: Routledge.
Heil, John. 2012. The Universe As We Find It. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hudson, Hud. 2009. Omnipresence. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Edited by Thomas Flint and Michael Rea. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, pp. 199–216.
Hughes, Christopher. 1989. On a Complex Theory of a Simple God: An Investigation in Aquinas’ Philosophical Theology. Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Ingthorsson, Rögnvaldur. 2013. Properties: Qualities, Powers, or Both? Dialectica 67: 55–80. [CrossRef]
Inman, Ross. 2017. Omnipresence and the Location of the Immaterial. In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, 8th ed. Edited by
Jonathan Kvanvig. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 168–206.
Jacobs, Jonathan. 2011. Powerful Qualities, Not Pure Powers. Monist 94: 81–102. [CrossRef]
Jaworski, William. 2016. Structure And The Metaphysics Of Mind: How Hylomorphism Solves The Mind-Body Problem. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Kelly, John N. D. 1964. Athanasian Creed. Manhattan: Harper and Row.
Kelly, John N. D. 1968. Early Christian Doctrine, 4th ed. London: Adam & Charles Black.
Langton, Rae, and David Lewis. 1998. Defining ‘Intrinsic’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58: 333–45. [CrossRef]
Leftow, Brian. 2004. A Latin Trinity. Faith and Philosophy 21: 304–33. [CrossRef]
Levinson, Jerrold. 1978. Properties and Related Entities. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 39: 1–22. [CrossRef]
Lewis, David. 1983. New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343–77. [CrossRef]
Loux, Michael. 2015. An exercise in constituent ontology. In The Problem of Universals in Contemporary Philosophy. Edited by Gabriele
Galluzzo and Michael Loux. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 9–45.
Macbride, Fraser. 2004. Whence the Particular-Universal Distinction? Grazer Philosophische Studien 67: 181–94. [CrossRef]
Macbride, Fraser. 2020. Relations. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved March 2021. Available online: https://plato.stanford.
edu/entries/relations/ (accessed on 1 November 2020).
Martin, Charlie B. 2008. The Mind in Nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Martin, Charlie B., and John Heil. 1999. The Ontological Turn. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23: 34–60. [CrossRef]
Maurin, Anna-S. 2018. Tropes. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved March 2021. Available online: https://plato.stanford.
edu/entries/tropes/ (accessed on 1 November 2020).
McDaniel, Kris. 2014. Parthood is identity. In Mereology and Location. Edited by S. Kleinschmidt. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp.
13–32.
Molnar, George. 2003. Powers: A Study in Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Moreland, James P., and William Lane Craig. 2003. Philosophical Foundations For A Christian Worldview, 1st ed. Westmont: InterVarsity Press.
Mumford, Stephen, and Rani L. Anjum. 2010. A Powerful Theory of Causation. In The Metaphysics of Powers: Their Grounding and Their
Manifestations. Edited by Anna Marmadoro. New York: Routledge, pp. 143–59.
Mullins, Ryan T. 2020. Trinity, Subordination, and Heresy: A Reply to Mark Edwards. TheoLogica: An International Journal for Philosophy
of Religion and Philosophical Theology 4: 1–15. [CrossRef]
Orilia, Francesco. 2008. The Problem of Order in Relational States of Affairs: A Leibnizian View. In Fostering the Ontological Turn: Essays
on Gustav Bergmann. Edited by Guido Bonino and Rosaria Egidi. Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag, pp. 161–86.
Orilia, Francesco. 2011. Relational Order and Onto-Thematic Roles. Metaphysica 12: 1–18. [CrossRef]
Orilia, Francesco. 2014. Positions, ordering relations and o-roles. Dialectica 68: 283–303. [CrossRef]
Religions 2022, 13, 809
46 of 46
Paoletti, Michele. 2016. Non-Symmetrical Relations, O-Roles and Modes. Acta Analytica 31: 373–95. [CrossRef]
Paoletti, Michele. 2019. The Holy Trinity and the Ontology of Relations. Sophia 60: 173–91. [CrossRef]
Pawl, Timothy. 2020. Conciliar Trinitarianism, Divine Identity Claims, and Subordination. TheoLogica: An International Journal for
Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology 4: 102–28. [CrossRef]
Platinga, Alvin. 2000. Warrented Christian Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pruss, Alexander. 2013. Omnipresence, Multilocation, the Real Presence and Time Travel. Journal of Analytic Theology 1: 60–72.
Raven, Michael. 2020. (Re)discovering Ground. In The Cambridge History of Philosophy, 1945–2015. Edited by Kelly Becker and Iain D.
Thomson. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 147–59.
Rosen, Gideon. 2010. Metaphysical Dependence: Grounding and Reduction. In Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology. Edited
by Bob Hale and Aviv Hoffmann. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 109–36.
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2009. On what Grounds what. In Metametaphysics: New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Edited by David
Manley, David J. Chalmers and Ryan Wasserman. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 347–83.
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2016. Grounding in the Image of Causation. Philosophical Studies 173: 49–100. [CrossRef]
Schaffer, Jonathan. 2021. Ground Functionalism. In Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Mind 1. Edited by U. Kriegel. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, pp. 171–207.
Shoemaker, Sydney. 1980. Causality and properties. In Time and Cause. Edited by Peter van Inwagen. Kufstein: Reidel, pp. 109–35.
Sider, Theodore. 2007. Parthood. Philosophical Review 116: 51–91.
Strawson, Galen. 2008. The identity of the categorical and the dispositional. Analysis 68: 271–82. [CrossRef]
Sijuwade, Joshua. 2021. Monarchical Trinitarianism: A Metaphysical Proposal. TheoLogica: An International Journal for Philosophy of
Religion and Philosophical Theology 5: 41–80. [CrossRef]
Sijuwade, Joshua. 2022. Building the monarchy of the Father. Religious Studies 58: 436–55. [CrossRef]
Swinburne, Richard. 1994. The Christian Divinity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Swinburne, Richard. 2016. The Coherence of Theism: Second Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Taylor, John H. 2013. In Defence of Powerful Qualities. Metaphysica 14: 93–107. [CrossRef]
Taylor, John H. 2017. Powerful qualities and pure powers. Philosophical Studies 175: 1423–40. [CrossRef]
Taylor, John H. 2019. Powerful Problems for Powerful Qualities. Erkenntnis 87: 425–33. [CrossRef]
Turner, John. 2014. Donald Baxter’s Composition as Identity. In Composition as Identity. Edited by D. Baxter and A. Cotnoir. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, pp. 225–43.
van Inwagen, Peter. 1995. And Yet They Are Not Three Divinitys But One Divinity. In Divinity, Knowledge & Mystery: Essays in
Philosophical Theology. Edited by Peter van Inwagen. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 241–78.
van Inwagen, Peter. 2003. Three Persons in One Being: On Attempts to Show That the Doctrine of the Trinity is Self-Contradictory. In
The Trinity: East/West Dialogue. Edited by Melville Y. Stewart. Boston: Kluwer, pp. 83–97.
Wierenga, Edward. 2004. Trinity and Polytheism. Faith and Philosophy 21: 281–94. [CrossRef]
Wierenga, Edward. 2010. Omnipresence. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Charles Taliaferro, Paul Draper and
Philip Quinn. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 258–62.
Williams, Donald C. 1953. On the Elements of Being II. Review of Metaphysics 7: 171–92.
Williams, Donald C. 1986. Universals and Existents. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64: 1–14. [CrossRef]
Wilson, Alastair. 2018. Metaphysical Causation. Noûs 52: 723–51. [CrossRef]