Quantum mechanics: ontology and
information
Gennaro Auletta
Volume 6
Winter 2014
journal homepage
Pontifical Gregorian University, Piazza della Pilotta 4 - 00187 Rome, Italy
[email protected]
www.euresisjournal.org
Abstract
Quantum theory shows that natural laws cannot be understood as ruling single events since the latter
occur randomly. Nevertheless, the physical world shows everywhere order whose source cannot be
represented by the latter. It is shown that this order is due to the presence of quantum correlations.
Since their effect is to reduce the space of the possible events, they can be considered as causal factors.
However, being correlations, they do not display the dynamic character that would be required in
order to produce a determinate effect. This is why they need additional local factors in order to
concur to the production of a certain event. If not so, this would even imply a violation of Einstein’s
locality since correlations could be used by themselves to transmit superluminal signals. Due to such a
character of correlation, they can be understood as kind of potential reality needing actual (and local)
context to be effective. This allows also a distinction that is classically unknown between locality and
globality. Such a distinction solves the important problem of measurement showing that ultimately
we have irreversible local processes while globally everything is still reversible. In particular, it is a
shift of information that can explain this local phenomenon. In fact, quantum systems are essentially
information and also the measurement process is ultimately a dealing with information: information
processing (preparing a system), information sharing (coupling a system with an apparatus) and
information selection (detecting). State, observable and property appear as equivalence classes of
these three procedures, respectively. Finally, the distinction between interpreted and uninterpreted
ontology is considered in a Kantian perspective, but it is also shown that the approach supported
here is rather a critical realism.
1. Random events
The most revolutionary aspect of quantum theory is the acknowledgment that in the physical
world there is an irreducible randomness [4]. In other words, there is no law allowing us to
predict certain events with certainty. We may compare this astonishing result with the
idea that the majority of physicists had at the end of the 19th century about the power of
classical laws. It is indeed well known that Lord Kelvin, in his 1900 address to the British
Association for the Advancement of Sciences, seemed to assume that physics was essentially
accomplished as a scientific discipline, since he affirmed that “there is nothing new to be
discovered in physics now. All that remains is more and more precise measurements”. What
Lord Kelvin meant was that classical laws covered potentially every phenomenon and that
7
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
everything could be in principle perfectly measured, so that our ability to determine with
exactitude any physical phenomenon was only an issue of technical power.
Two examples will clarify the difference between the classical and quantum-mechanical approach [4]. Consider an apparatus known as a Mach-Zehnder interferometer. The incoming
beam of light (that is pumped by a laser) is split (by a first beam splitter) into two components along two main paths and then (by a second beam splitter) these components are
recombined and sent to the final detectors (two, in the basic arrangement). Until the second
beam splitter the description could be to a certain extent in accordance with classical laws,
since the light behaves wave-like and produces typical interference phenomena in accordance
with classical predictions. However, when impinging the detectors, the beam seems composed of small particles (photons) since we have discrete clicks. Moreover, we can arrange
the apparatus in such a way that a single photon can be sent at a time through the first
beam splitter. In this case, we have a phenomenon that is fully unknown classically: the
photon makes interference with itself, which means that we have no longer a superposition of
distinct waves but a new, classically unknown state of superposition of the two possible final
detection events. Precisely this circumstance determines the randomness of those events.
Consider now a different experimental context: a beam of light prepared in a polarization
state, say with light oscillating along the 45◦ direction. Suppose that we set a polarization
filter along the vertical direction. Classically, we would expect that the beam will behave
uniformly across time, since any classical system or object prepared in the same state (polarization at 45 degrees) and subjected to the same experimental conditions (vertical filter)
behave in the same way (produces the same outcome). This is also what seems to happen
since we see that the beam will uniformly pass the filter with a reduced intensity (by one
half). However, when we perform a finer analysis thanks to quantum mechanics, we shall
discover that the beam can be understood as “composed” of photons each of which in a
superposition state of vertical and horizontal polarization. In such a state, each of them has
a probability of one half to pass the filter or be blocked by it, what implies that in the mean
one half will pass the test and the other half will be blocked. This is quite extraordinary,
since it means that systems prepared in the same state will behave differently. Moreover,
since they have been prepared in the same state and there is therefore nothing that allows us
to discriminate among them, we cannot predict which singular photon will pass the test and
which not. This is why we have irreducible events when dealing with quantum-mechanical
systems.
This situation determines a new understanding of the relations between events and laws as
well as of the issue of causal relations. I shall deal with the latter issue below and focus here
on the relation between laws and events [6]. According to the classical view as expressed
by the words of Lord Kelvin quoted above, natural laws are thought to rule single events
and properties. At the opposite side, if we take the above quantum-mechanical description
8
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
seriously, we are obliged to admit that any law will at most allow us to predict, at a general level, the behavior of quantum systems but not what a quantum system will do at a
particular or individual level. Indeed, we can say that half of the photons will pass the test
represented by a vertical polarization filter but we cannot predict which one will do it. In
other words, laws have only a general significance. Here we need to immediately overcome
a possible misunderstanding. We could interpret this situation as meaning that quantum
laws have a statistical character as it happens for statistical mechanics. There is a long and
honored tradition that considered this to be the case [4]. However, subsequent experimental
tests have clearly shown that quantum laws are as deterministic as classical ones are but that
they rule the general features of any single system and not the particular behavior that it
will assume. Indeed, the so-called Schrödinger equation [4] rules the probability amplitudes
(whose square moduli allow us to compute the relative probabilities) to get certain experimental outcomes when the object system undergoes determinate experimental procedures
(preparation and premeasurement). In the case of the interferometry experiment above, the
Schrödinger equation will tell us the probability of a single photon to be detected by a certain
detector but will not ensure us that it will in fact impinge the latter. In other words, quantum
systems are intrinsically probabilistic, which means that probability does not represent (as
it is the case for classical mechanics) a subjective ignorance of the actual state of a system
but expresses an objective uncertainty affecting the system.
2. Correlations and information
A world ruled only by chance events could never produce any kind of order or regularity.
More specifically, reality would consist of unrelated pieces of matter and any connection or
relation would simply be an illusion or addiction of the mind. Should the world be a random
collection of particles in Brownian motion, whose sizes, masses, speed, and so on are totally
arbitrary, my guess is that no single configuration of things would emerge at all. Indeed,
as soon as one ordered configuration could form by chance, it would be rapidly destroyed
by the random motion of the other particles and following interactions [6]. It is well known
that L. Boltzmann accounted for the macroscopic phenomenon of gas pressure in terms of
the random motion of the gas molecules. This could be interpreted in the sense that a pure
random motion could give rise to some sort of ordered effects (and macroscopic property).
However, without confining those particles into a closed space, e.g. in a piston, such an effect
would never be produced. This shows that, without a confining constraint, the disordered
motion alone would again be insufficient for producing any ordered effect.
As a matter of fact, we observe order everywhere in our universe. Moreover, quantummechanical laws allow probabilistic predictions, which imply a certain regularity. Since probability amplitudes evolve deterministically, we are also able to compute probabilities at later
stages of the dynamic evolution of a system if the initial state is known. So, the question is:
how is this order generated if the world consists in quantum random events? The problem
9
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
here is also the solution. When the state of a quantum system changes and therefore the
probabilities of obtaining certain events also change, a prediction about the latter would
be strictly impossible if the probability amplitudes computable at any moment were independent of each other. This is not the case because, as a manifestation of superposition,
in the state of any quantum system, constraining correlations relating all probability amplitudes are somehow nested, thus allowing us to formulate deterministic predictions about
all outcome probabilities. In a recent paper [5], I have called such interdependences quantum “features” because they are those characters of the system that, not being properties in
themselves, nevertheless determine the probabilities to get certain outcomes and therefore to
assign properties to a system. Indeed, true properties are local by definition, while features,
being interconnections among components of the system, are non-local by their very nature.
Let us consider the following example: suppose that the state of two particles is a singlet
state. In such a case, they show a spin-correlation such that when one of the two particles
is found to be in a spin-up state along an experimentally chosen direction, the other one
will be necessarily in a spin-down state along the same direction and vice versa. In other
words, we expect to obtain either up-down or down-up but never up-up or down-down. If the
world consisted of random events only, we would expect to obtain any of these four possible
outcomes with equiprobability. The fact that we can obtain only two (either up-down or
down-up) out of four cases represents a reduction of the space of possible events. In other
words, quantum mechanical correlations act as constraints limiting the space of what we can
obtain. For the example of the singlet state such correlations are called entanglement. Entanglement is a correlation among several subsystems. However, also correlations in a single
system can show this behavior. For instance, in a Mach-Zehnder interferometry experiment,
if we choose the relative phase between the two components to be either 0 or 180 one of the
two detectors never clicks, which is due to the self-interference of the photon. However, if we
block one of the two paths both detectors can click.
3. Information
There is a natural question that now arises: what is the kind of reality that the correlations
in our universe consist of? We indeed live in a world that is physical, but correlations are by
definition formal [7]. The problem is that correlations and ordinary physical quantities are
tightly connected: it suffices to say that correlations are instantiated in physical systems and
enter into interactions involving exchanges of physical magnitudes. Now, how is it possible to
put together something formal with something else that is not? We need a sort of quantity
that is both formal and nevertheless linked to the material dimension. Let us come back
to the example of entanglement that we have proposed above. We have shown that, in an
entangled state, the outcome statistics are more ordered (two out of four possible cases) than
when there is no entanglement (four out of four cases). There is a language for dealing in
the most general way with such kinds of problems: the language of information. Indeed,
10
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
information (and its connected quantity, the so-called Shannon entropy):
• Is concerned with the issue of singling out a subset of elements (the message or the
information we like to acquire) from a larger set (the set of all possible messages or at
least the set of elementary units out of which any message can be composed, like the
alphabet);
• Measures the unlikeliness of performing such an extrapolation, which is expressed by
the probability that the latter does not occur or is not chosen. Obviously, if there is no
(syntactical) order among the units and the sequence of the latter is random, to acquire
or to guess the right message will be much more difficult than in the case in which there
is some rule (for instance, in some cases, we can understand that an encrypted message
represents an English sentence because of the higher or lower frequency of some letters).
Therefore, we may say that information and entropy are concerned with the amount of order
and disorder of a system. The more correlations there are in a system, the more the system is
to be considered ordered and the easier the guess is about its state. Indeed, the way in which
entanglement can be mathematically described is with the so-called mutual information, that
is, the information shared by several systems or components of a system that makes them
interdependent.
4. Potentiality and information
An important concept is the following: entanglement is an information resource (consisting
in mutual information) called ebit that rather displays potential characters. Indeed, when
two particles are entangled we can exchange information in ways that are not allowed in
any classical protocol although we need an additional classical resource for doing this. This
exchange is called teleportation: if two partners conventionally called Alice and Bob have
each a particle of an entangled pair, and if Alice desires to communicate to Bob a bit of
information represented by a third particle, she lets her entangled particle interact with
the latter and classically communicates the result to Bob, who is now able to recover the
information contained in the third particle in the state of his own entangled particle [4]. This
shows that an ebit is a potential information resource that can be made effective or active
at a later time when some experimental conditions and a classical information transmission
are also present.
Potentiality is a concept that has been much devaluated in modern times. Among the reasons
of this devaluation there is the assumption that potential realities are a sort of ontological
genus different from actual realities. In fact, potentiality only consists in the relation that
a certain actual thing entertains with certain contexts or possible actions. It makes perfect
sense, even in classical physics, to say that a certain disposition of trees in a forest canalizes
the action of the wind in a forest. What is active here is the wind as a physical agent.
11
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
Nevertheless, such an effect (wind canalization along a certain direction) would have never
happened without such a disposition of trees. Therefore, although such a disposition is
perfectly actual in itself, its capacity to concur to a certain action (canalization of the wind)
can be said to be only potential to the extent to which it cannot happen (be made actually
active) without the wind being itself active. Obviously, the concept of potentiality is not
very interesting when dealing with classical-mechanical idealized systems but is far more
interesting when dealing with quantum-mechanical systems, as it was clear to Heisenberg,
but also with complex realities like living beings [6].
The interesting point now is that quantum mechanics sets very precise bonds on information exchange and therefore on causal interconnections (since we can speak of causal relation
only when at least a signal is exchanged). Although quantum-mechanical systems violate
the so-called Bell inequalities, which set classical-mechanical limits on information exchange,
they do not violate Einstein locality (they do not allow for superluminal or even instantaneous information exchange). Actually, the classical-mechanical limits forbid the kind of
interdependencies that are characteristic of quantum entanglement (they assume that physical systems need to be considered either as causally connected, in the sense of efficient or
mechanical causation, or as separated). However, quantum mechanics sets a bound that is
stricter than Einsteins locality. This is called Tsirelson bound. The reason why it is so was
unknown until recent times: it was shown that this bound must be satisfied in order to do
not violate the principle of information causality that tells us that we cannot acquire more
information than it was actually sent. What is the deep meaning of this principle that to
many can sound obvious? The meaning is that quantum correlations (entanglement) are
among possible events and therefore outcomes of a measurement procedure. At the opposite
side, if the Tsireslon bond were violated, we would have an interdependency, not among
events, but among experimental settings or premeasurement procedures [7]. In such a case,
we would be able to guess the whole code used by the sender even if it was not sent to us,
violating in this way the principle of information causality. This point allows us to define
information in all its generality as a relation among possible events,1 which also explains its
potential character when not actually acquired.
5. Causality
Therefore, quantum mechanics does not violate at all the requirements of classical causality.
However, it suggests the necessity to deeply reconsider the issue of causality since there are
situations in which there is a causal contribution of factors (like entanglement) that are
not local by definition, whilst efficient causality need to be always local (implying actually
exchange of dynamical physical magnitudes like energy or momentum).
My first suggestion would be to consider quantum systems as instantiating essentially infor1
First suggested by A. Zeilinger, personal communication.
12
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
mation [4]. I am fully aware that we cannot reduce a system like an atom or an electron
to information only, since here also other quantities like mass, energy, spin and so on are
relevant. I am also aware that many of these quantities do not present the typical characters
of information codification and that information is a non-dimensional quantity. However, my
modest suggestion would be the following: to consider all the relevant physical quantities as
crucial when quantum systems interact (showing dynamical and efficient-causality features)
and much less when quantum systems are considered in their isolation or as simply correlated
but not as actually interacting. My guess is that, in such a case, information is a more basic
quantity (and the definition of information in terms of relation among possible events perfectly describes this situation). This would help us to explain the issue of causality. Indeed,
if we admit that quantum systems represent informational resources that are not necessarily
active or accessible (I recall that the whole potential information contained in a quantum
system is never accessible as such), then they represent possible sources from which we can
extract information at a later time when certain experimental or spontaneous contexts are
activated. They can then be conceived as the sources of the whole information that is present
in our universe but not necessarily as efficient causes of any information acquisition.
One of the biggest misunderstandings brought by some interpretations of the theory of information communication is that information propagates causally as it would be a kind of
medium or substance. Actually, information never propagates in this sense and we can never
say that a certain source causes certain information to be received elsewhere. This can only
be a metaphoric way of speaking but does not describe how things go on. Actually, an information source only need to be a source of variety and not an already preselected message that
need to be transmitted as a kind of momentum or energy. Actually, what currently happens
when information is exchanged is that any initial potential information is never acquired in
its totality, since additional factors at the reception are relevant to this acquisition.
Therefore, I think that we should consider quantum information (and correlations) as a kind
of formal cause that, when certain actual experimental conditions are made active, can concur
to give rise to certain effects. With the term formal cause I mean a kind of constraint able
to canalize certain dynamical processes (and therefore they are only potential, according to
what has been said before). Also formal causes were dismissed in modern ages. However,
today, when we deal with network theory – and every time we deal with sufficiently complex
contexts – we need to take advantage of the notion of constraints [3]. This examination also
shows that it is likely that there are two main ways to deal with information at a very basic
level: either when we share it, or when we select it (during actual information acquiring)
apart from information processing. The crucial point is that such a selection only happens
when the receiver receives in fact information and not when this information is at the source
or is only shared. To understand this, let us consider “the measurement process.”
13
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
6. Dynamics and measurement
Quantum systems, when considered in their isolation, show potential features, but when they
interact they give rise to actual events. We may take measurement as a model of dynamics
from which extracting some general notions. When we measure a quantum system, we do it
along three major steps [7]:
• First, we prepare the system in a certain state. This is necessary, since quantum systems
are very elusive and we are not able even to start a measurement procedure if we are
not able to ensure that the system is ready to undergo certain further operations.
• Then we pre-measure the system: we couple (entangle) it with a certain apparatus
(setting). In this way, we select a specific experimental context and therefore single
out a certain observable that we wish to measure. Until this step, measurement is fully
reversible and we only have determined certain information sharing between the object
system and the apparatus.
• The third step is the measurement properly or strictly understood, i.e. detection, an act
of information selection since we single out (in a way that is not controllable, as previously explained) a single outcome among many possible ones. It is here that we assign
an actual property (like to be localized in one of the two paths of an interferometer) to
the system.
What is important here is that the whole dynamics establishes a sort of trade-off between
potential and actual aspects (if any) of quantum systems. Therefore, dynamics has a sort of
ontological primacy in quantum mechanics.
Another important issue is the following: although very elementary, quantum systems show
a certain shift along their dynamical evolution. In other words, when cycling along a certain
circuit they never go back precisely to the same state. This phenomenon is called geometric
phase.
7. Global and local
The reader may be astonished by the fact that during the measurement we start with a
quantum system showing a certain potentiality and end with certain actual events. How is
it possible? This appears even more puzzling because, if we assume that a quantum system
has been prepared (as it is often the case) in a certain superposition of possible measurement
outcomes, to get a single outcome out of that superposition would violate the laws of quantum
dynamics (the Schrödinger equation), which are linear and therefore forbid such a result. The
solution of this problem is to consider that quantum systems are open to the environment.
Therefore, when we measure them, most of the information (which consists, as previously
stressed, in a relation among possible outcomes) goes lost into the environment while we get
14
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
only a single outcome. This is even necessary, since such correlations can never be acquired
or measured as such. This phenomenon is called decoherence and essentially tells us that the
apparent violation of quantum dynamics only happens from our local perspective [4].
However, when we consider the global evolution of the whole universe, this still happens in
perfect accordance with quantum-mechanical laws. Therefore, the apparent local violation
is only due to a local shift in the amount of order and disorder. Indeed, entanglement
(and mutual information) is a source of order and in fact most entangled systems show
a zero-entropy state (maximal order). However, to locally get a single outcome means a
sort of ”break” of this order (the result is a far less ordered state). Therefore, in the local
context of measurement, entropy (and disorder) grows. However, if the amount of order
of quantum systems is conserved (due to the necessity to preserve linearity), this means
that local measurements (or measurement-like interactions) “free” the source of order that
could be used elsewhere in our universe, contributing to explain the puzzling circumstance by
which, although the world is ruled by the second law of thermodynamics, it shows creation
and re-creation of order everywhere and at every scale [6].
The distinction (but also the entrenchment) between local and global is typical of quantum
mechanics and could be very fruitful for further scientific enquiry.
8. State-observable-property
As I have pointed out, a state can be prepared in the first step of measurement. Since different
procedures can lead to the preparation of the same state, it is suitable to operationally
consider the state as an equivalence class of preparations [5]. Since different premeasurements
can lead to a later measurement of the same observable, we can define an observable as an
equivalence class of premeasurements. Finally, since different detections can lead to the
attribution of the same property, a property can be considered as an equivalence class of
detection events. Let us consider the latter point a little: any event is in itself a pure
happening. It tells nothing about any system whatsoever. It is only thanks to the coupling
with the objective system (and therefore thanks to the previous two steps of the measurement
process) that we are able to make such an assignment.
This shows that a property (and also a state or an observable), although grounded in some
ontological reality, is not itself an ontological reality (being an equivalence class). It is
something that we are allowed to attribute given certain conditions. To misunderstand
properties (as well as states and observables) as ontological realities is one of the major flaws
of classical mechanics.
Let us call state, observable and property as pieces of an interpreted ontology (that is,
interpreted thanks to a theory: quantum mechanics). Then, the question naturally arises:
15
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
which is the ontological substrate of these classes? We have implicitly already mentioned it:
correlations, events, and their dynamic interplay [1]. Let us call these “objects” pieces of an
uninterpreted ontology.
The distinction between interpreted and uninterpreted ontology is somehow reminiscent of
the Kantian distinction between phenomenal knowledge, on the one hand, and world (or
thing) in itself, on the other, or at least I tried to take into account this lesson. However,
there is also a fundamental distinction. According to Kant, any form is due the productive
faculty of the subject and is therefore imposed on a reality that is perceived from the start
into the framework of such forms. For this reason, we can say nothing about it as such.
At the opposite, I assume that we interact with an independent reality that has the power
to correct our hypotheses and therefore allows us also to formulate moderate guesses about
its character in itself. In such a sense, the forms are not only due to the activity of the
subject, but are the result of such an interaction. This is why we can make distinctions (like
between events and correlations as pieces of uninterpreted ontology) that would be certainly
impossible on pure Kantian basis. Unfortunately, the transformation of Kant’s important
insight about the subject as source of productive activity into the sole source of activity has
given rise, as well known, to the idealistic approach. At the opposite, from an ontological
point of view, I support here a weak form of realism (acknowledging potential reality and
formal causes) as well as, from an epistemological point of view, a critical or fallibilist realism
(our knowledge is not a mirror of reality but reality corrects our hypotheses). On the latter
point, I am rather a follower of Peirce’s philosophy [7]
Bibliography
1 Auletta, G. and G. Tarozzi (2004). “Wavelike Correlations versus Path Detection: Another Form of Complementarity”, Foundations of Physics Letters 17: 88995.
2 Auletta, G., G. Ellis, and L. Jaeger (2008). “Top-Down Causation by Information Control:
From a Philosophical Problem to a Scientific Research Program”, Journal of the Royal
Society: Interface 5: 115972.
3 Auletta, G., M. Fortunato, and G. Parisi (2009). Quantum Mechanics (Cambridge, University Press).
4 Auletta, G. and L. Torcal (2011). “From Wave–Particle to Features-Event Complementarity”, International Journal of Theoretical Physics 50: 365468.
5 Auletta, G. (2011). Cognitive Biology: Dealing with Information from Bacteria to Minds
(Oxford, University Press).
6 Auletta, G. (2011). “Correlations and Hyper-Correlations”, Journal of Modern Physics
2: 95861.
7 Auletta, G. (2011). Integrated Cognitive Strategies in a Changing World (Rome, G and B
Press).
16
Volume 6
Ontology and information
Winter 2014
The previous list only comprehends some of my recent publications in which extensive references to further literature can be found.
17