·
]
T M
Ambiguous Lever
SIANNE NGAI is Andrew W. Mellon Professor of English at the University of Chicago
and a recently elected member of the
American Academy of Arts and Sciences.
She is the author of Ugly Feelings (Harvard
UP, 2005), Our Aesthetic Categories: Zany,
Cute, Interesting (Harvard UP, 2012), and
Theory of the Gimmick: Aesthetic Judgment and Capitalist Form (Harvard UP,
2020).
In History and Class Consciousness, Georg Lukács describes mediation as “a lever with which to overcome the mere immediacy of the
empirical world,” stressing that “as such it is not something (subjective) foisted on to . . . objects from outside” but “rather the manifestation of their authentic objective structure” (162).1 As Fredric Jameson
notes, Lukács is thinking of reification—the central concept of
History and Class Consciousness—and also of Max Weber’s closely
related concept of rationalization; both are processes that apply equally
to “social relations in late capitalism” and to “formal relations and verbal structures within the latter’s cultural and literary products”
(Political Unconscious 27 [42]).2 Lukács makes a tacit distinction
between good or useful mediations and bad or obscuring ones, the latter being “confusing categories of reflection,” the “mediations of metaphysics and myth” (History 166, 190).
Jameson follows Lukács in The Political Unconscious, while making what is implicit in the latter’s argument more explicit. Similarly
describing mediation as “a device of the analyst, whereby the fragmentation . . . of social life . . . is at least locally overcome,” Jameson
dedicates the bulk of his introduction to singling out a list of interpretative wrong turns or dubious analytic moves (including many
favored by Marxist critics) that are essentially bad mediations, while
offering the more detailed account Lukács does not himself offer
(focused as the latter is on defining reification) of why they are dissatisfying (Political Unconscious 25 [40]). At the same time, Jameson
clarifies that all mediations, bad or good, involve “transcoding,” or
“mak[ing] connections among the seemingly disparate phenomena
of social life”—which boils down to identifying a likeness or pattern
of recursion across social levels (25 [40]). Reification in modernist
artworks, for example, particularly in their fragmentation and autonomization of the senses, replicates, while remaining ultimately distinct
© The Author(s). Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Modern
Language Association of America
PMLA . (), doi:./S
https://doi.org/10.1632/S0030812922000372 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Ambiguous Lever
from, the reification of commodities and rationalization of labor in capitalist production.
So let’s recap: (1) mediations are analytic
devices for counteracting false immediacies (such
as how the capitalist world necessarily appears to
us, through the senses, as fragmented and subdivided); (2) not all these devices are equally effective;
(3) a theory of literary interpretation should offer
insight on how to distinguish effective mediations
from ineffective ones; and especially since (4) both
strategies for combatting the given involve pointing
out some sort of resemblance, likeness, repetition, or
familiarity. If the distinction between good and bad
mediations makes a difference, what we are facing is
the challenge of distinguishing between modes of
sameness that are alike but, ultimately, not the same.
Does the distinction between good and bad mediations make a difference? Certainly the introduction
to The Political Unconscious makes it clear that it
should? Jameson’s list of the problematic moves
made by left-liberal critics—economisms that reduce
everything about capitalist life to “the market” (and
all of capitalist ideology to “liberalism”); “contemplative” attitudes that in presuming the gulf between
object and subject, end up widening it; the historicist errors Louis Althusser castigates as “mechanical
causality” and “expressive causality”; and merely
formalist homologies—demonstrates how difficult
it is for “reified minds” to grasp the unity of unity
and difference in capitalist social life. That is, to
see two things as part of the same process, different
branchings of the same unity, without conflating
them or assuming that one must be the “cause” or
“result” of the other.
These ways of thinking are so automatic, so
entrenched in everyday activity, are so much a part
of what counts as common sense, that even for local
and transient traction on a total social process rendered empirically inaccessible by capitalism’s abstractions (including labor’s abstraction in the valorization
of commodities), the analyst will need an “invention”:
a “lever” or “device.” And given the criticisms of bad
mediations with which The Political Unconscious
begins, it seems like only the right one will do.
Now of all the unsatisfactory “interpretative
mechanism[s]” discussed at the beginning of The
https://doi.org/10.1632/S0030812922000372 Published online by Cambridge University Press
[
P M L A
Political Unconscious, the one singled out most is
homology. (It is also singled out, it should be noted,
in the concluding chapter on dialectical thinking in
Marxism and Form [1971]). Interestingly, this spotlighting of homology—its coming to the fore as the
poorest of mediations—is occasioned almost accidentally: at the end, and as a by-product, of Jameson’s
much lengthier discussion of another dubious mediation—“expressive causality”—in which the discussion of homology is embedded but that homology
ultimately displaces.
Expressive causality is Althusser’s main antagonist in Reading Capital, his overarching example of
his problem with “mediation” (and Hegel) in general. But Jameson suggests that expressive causality
(i.e., Hegelian mediation) isn’t ultimately as dangerous as Althusser makes it out to be: “The true target
of the Althusserian critique would seem to me not
the practice of mediation, but something else,
which presents superficial similarities to it but is
in reality a very different kind of concept, namely
the structural notion of homology (or isomorphism,
or structural parallelism)—a term currently in wide
use in a variety of literary and cultural analyses”
(Political Unconscious 28 [43]).
In Marxism and Form, Jameson’s example is
the historicism of Hippolyte Taine and Oswald
Spengler, who, in their efforts “at giving an account
of the total style of a culture,” try to illustrate “the
unity of [that] cultural style as it envelops everything
from engineering techniques and mathematical
thinking to religious dogma and literary convention” (324, 325). (In this manner, as René Wellek
notes about Taine, “classicism” is regarded as a
“style or mode which mediates ‘between a hedge at
Versailles, a philosophical and theological argument
of Malebranche, a prosodic rule prescribed by
Boileau, a law of Colbert on mortgages, a compliment in the waiting room of the king at Marly, a
statement of Bossuet about the kingship of God’”
(qtd. in Jameson, Marxism 324–25). In The Political
Unconscious, the example is Lucien Goldmann’s
study of Jansenism, The Hidden God, which constructs parallels between class situations, worldviews,
and artistic forms, in order to argue, unconvincingly,
that “at some level of abstraction the ‘structure’ of the
·
]
three quite different realities . . . [is] ‘the same’” (28
[43–44]).
Coming to the fore as the poster child of bad
mediation at the end of a discussion of expressive
causality, in which it effectively displaces it from
this undesirable role, homologies are unambiguously problematic in The Political Unconscious.
They are “static,” “misguided,” “comfortable,” and
above all “abstract” (29, 30, 30, 51).
But when we turn, almost thirty years later, to
Valences of the Dialectic (2009), we encounter something more neutrally presented as “the ideological
replication of . . . form—what leaves its imprint on
the organization of the various superstructures,
whether theoretical, political or artistic” (360).
Now this “replication” by which we track the same
pattern across different social “levels” may not be
the same as homology. But it certainly looks a lot
like homology—at the very least, it seems isomorphic or analogous to it. In his chapter “Ideological
Analysis,” Jameson’s main example is what Marx
calls “cooperation”: that politically ambiguous organization of labor power (at once intensifying exploitation, yet essential for any future “association of
free men”) that “can be observed in the structure
of the nineteenth-century novel, with its immense
increase in personnel and their reorganization
around protagonists and levels of secondary or
minor characters, organized into a kind of proletariat, anonymous background” (Valences 360). If the
mode of similarity being discussed here—the recurrence of a form or pattern across social realities as
different as the novel, the industrial workplace,
and an analytic text by Marx—is essentially the
same as the mode of similarity highlighted in The
Political Unconscious, it is interestingly no longer
repudiated.
Similarly, in Representing Capital (2011) we
encounter “dialectical synonymity,” “the process
whereby a critique is waged on several levels of
implication at once” (17). The example offered is
taken again from Marx in Capital, volume 1:
Marx’s singling out of the principle of equivalence,
which we see primarily played out in economic
exchange, but also in the realms of mathematics, political theory (legal rights), contract law, and psychology
https://doi.org/10.1632/S0030812922000372 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Sianne Ngai
(“reflexionist” theories of self-consciousness). Like the
cultural replication of the social form of cooperation
discussed in Valences, this mode of similarity is also
presented neutrally, perhaps even admiringly, qua
Marxian mediation, a lever used to disclose “the patterns and the functions or operations of the system as
it is replicated in all the multitudinous subsystems that
make up [capitalist] life today everywhere” (Valences
359).
What is the relation, then, between “replication,” “synonymity,” and what was called homology
in The Political Unconscious? Are these three modes
of similarity, all enlisted as devices or mediations for
ideological analysis, the same mode of similarity?
Or are they (meaningfully) different ones?
In a sense this is the overarching question asked
across all of Jameson’s work from Marxism and
Form onward, insofar as all of it is an exploration
of the future of dialectical thinking. Consider this
moment from Representing Capital (2011), in which
Jameson offers
a hypothesis about the very origins of the dialectic
itself. For I believe that the dialectic came into
being to handle a strange and unparalleled historical
situation, namely one in which everything is different
and yet remains the same: in which the discovery (or
invention) of history reveals the enormous structural
disparities, not only between anciens and modernes,
but between all the different historical modes of production! And yet in another sense, they are all the
same thing, namely modes of production. By the
same token, history reveals the immense variety
of groups which exercise dominion over other
groups—castes, feudal orders, clans, families, hordes
and, finally, unique to our mode of production,
social classes; and yet in another sense they are all
social classes, all somehow the same, a ruling class
extracting its surplus value from a laboring class.
(133–34; emphases added; see also Valences 17–19)
Dialectic, Jameson concludes, is “a mode of thinking
able to combine the singular and the general in a
unique way, or better still, to shift gears from the one
to the other and back again, to identify them in such
a way that they remain different” (134). Dialectic and
its “lever,” mediation, are thus isomorphic things.
Ambiguous Lever
Both enable us to “shift gears” between the singular
and the general, the individual and the collective.3
Both, in a way that is maybe insufficiently acknowledged, rely on similarity, which, as Jonathan Flatley
suggests with startling lucidity, is itself dialectical: the
unity-in-difference of sameness and difference:
[B]eing alike . . . is both experientially and conceptually distinct from being equal or identical. As
Jean-Luc Nancy concisely observes, “The like is not
the same [le semblable n’est pas le pareil].” Indeed,
when something is like something else, it means precisely that it is not the same as it. Things that are
alike or similar are neither incommensurate nor
identical; they are related and resembling, yet distinct. Similarity is thus a discrete concept aside
from the same-different opposition.
(5; emphases added)
Valences of the Dialectic’s “replication of form[s],”
Representing Capital’s “dialectical synonymity,” The
Political Unconscious’s “homology”: if similarity
lies at the core of these analytic mechanisms—concepts of similarity that are in themselves similar
(that is, “neither incommensurate nor identical”)—
it is a concept that cannot be purged from the theory
of mediation. For, in the end, mediations are similarities. And we have nothing else to rely on for tracking
the relation between (static) antinomies and (moving) contradictions, or expressive and structural causalities, or homologies and dialectical synonymities.
If, more dynamically, we want to see the first terms in
these series as “proto-narratives,” as naive or “prephilosophical” versions of the more developed or
properly philosophical terms, we will need to rely
on similarity as well.
But if homology, as similarity, is in this manner
retroactively “forgiven” by Jameson’s work as a
whole (by way of the eventual accrual of multiple
similar mediations—i.e., modes of similarity, in
his analytic tool chest), it is not because it is immune
to error. Similarity—or mediation—remains susceptible to error. But it is so, in Jameson, in the
context of his significant reevaluation of error’s role
in interpretation overall. This shift is already visible
or “proto-narrativized” in The Political Unconscious,
where, as we move through the three readings of
https://doi.org/10.1632/S0030812922000372 Published online by Cambridge University Press
[
P M L A
Honoré de Balzac, George Gissing, and Joseph
Conrad, we notice the book’s opening tone of warning
or caution (Don’t make homologies! Avoid expressive
causality!) modulate into something gentler, culminating in the conclusion’s argument for the inextricable coupling of ideology and utopia. But it is also
possible to see this change played out across
Jameson’s books over the decades. And here it also
becomes possible to argue, I think, that the shift in
Jameson’s attitude toward error is specifically
facilitated by Hegel.
In Valences of the Dialectic, for example, the
static binaries, contemplative abstractions, and onesided reflections of Verstand (understanding) in
Hegel’s Science of Logic are read as necessary
crutches—contrivances that can’t be abandoned
even if we try, because they are part of everyday
thinking. “[E]rror is always a stage in truth and
remains part of the latter” (Valences 98).4 As
Jameson suggests, reading Verstand as the Science
of Logic’s “villain”—a term with a curiously comic
undertone—involves tracking how this incarnation
of reification moves and develops, as it creatively
adjusts and adapts itself first to the realm of Being,
then Essence, and Notion (while always remaining
the same Verstand across these changing levels).5
The idea that even error is capable of dialectical
movement recalls a thesis, already laid out for us
in The Political Unconscious (and in a way that
directly anticipates the culminating chapter on the
unity of ideology and utopia, or the unity of replication [sameness] and The New [difference]), that
reifying thought is not itself reified but astonishingly
productive. For what are our culture’s most symbolically powerful artifacts if not products of (as well as
enactments of, or meditations on) rationalization
and fragmentation (of the senses, in the case of
modernism)? How do the very concepts we use to
interpret culture emerge, if not through abstraction
and autonomization? Jameson’s examples are, significantly, “desire” and “value.” Desire can only
become a semi-autonomous object of study, or
“independent sign system,” when sexuality is set
apart from embodied existence and social life—
isolated, compartmentalized, specialized (Political
Unconscious 49 [64]). But this separation enables
·
]
the abstraction to take on a special charge that it
would not have otherwise. Similarly, “value” only
acquires its vast symbolic extension when it disappears from the social field—that is, “at the moment
of . . . the virtual obliteration of all value by a universal process of instrumentalization” (240 [251]).6
This brings me to an argument in The Political
Unconscious that I have always found strangely hard
to absorb, even though it is one of the book’s central
and most plainly stated claims: ideology is less “false
consciousness,” or even an “imaginary resolution of
a real contradiction” (245n42 [256n42]; see also 65
[79]), than a containment strategy—a shutting down
of possibilities generated by, if never fully realized
in, the text itself. But it is now easy to see why this
explicit definition of ideology is hard to remember.
Like Verstand in The Science of Logic, or Lukácsian
reification, a text’s ideological strategy of containment
can be so creative and energetic that what comes
across to the reader will seem like the opposite of
“containment”—rather much more like an opening
or multiplication of possibilities than their narrowing
down. This very contradiction—brought to the fore in
the remarkable chapter on Lord Jim, and in more
recent reinterpretations of Jameson’s semiotic squares
by Phillip Wegner—helps us grasp how these two
actions might be one.
Horror tropes abound across Jameson’s writings.
Connoisseurs of the genre may especially delight in
these moments in the characterization of dialectic in
Marxism and Form, which seem to deliberately activate our squeamishness so it can in turn be enjoyed:
“dialectical thought comes as a brutal rupture, as a
cutting of the knots that restores us suddenly to the
grossest truths, to facts as unpleasantly common as
common sense itself” (309); “[t]here is a breathlessness
about this shift from the normal object-oriented activity of the mind to such dialectical self-consciousness—
something of the sickening shudder we feel in an elevator’s fall or in the sudden dip in an airliner. That
recalls us to our bodies much as this recalls us to
our mental positions as thinkers and observers”
(308). And my favorite:
The peculiar difficulty of dialectical writing lies
indeed in its holistic, “totalizing” character: as though
https://doi.org/10.1632/S0030812922000372 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Sianne Ngai
you could not say any one thing until you had first
said everything; as though with each new idea you
were bound to recapitulate the entire system. So it
is that the attempt to do justice to the most random
observation of Hegel ends up drawing the whole tangled, dripping mass of the Hegelian sequence of
forms out into the light with it.
(306)
But what we might call The Political Unconscious’s
affective arc from gothic to comedy—how it opens
by inculcating our anxious vigilance against X, but
then, in homeopathically absorbing X, turns that anxiety into an object of play—ultimately shows us how to
become less fearful in our interpretative practices.
NOTES
I am grateful to Andrew Cole for his comments on this essay.
1. Lever itself is an ambiguous word. As a tool for maneuvering
a stolid or resisting object by applying force in a clever way, it is a
device that can easily veer in the equivocal directions of stratagem
or ruse. As Andrew Cole has pointed out to me, it doesn’t seem like
an especially intuitive metaphor for dialectical thinking—and certainly not a metaphor one would think its own practitioners would
choose, given its dubious invocation of a flippable switch. Yet Lukács
does in fact choose lever (methodischer Hebel) as his image for “mediation” (Vermittlung) and moreover in the same text in which he cites
Marx on how the working class, instead of becoming absorbed by
“economic ‘trade-union’” struggles, might use “their organised forces
as a lever for the final emancipation of the working class, that is to
say, the ultimate abolition of the wages system” (qtd. in History
73). This said, in a way underscoring the term’s political ambiguity, the “levers” in Capital, volume 1, are nearly all stratagems for
capital. A few examples: the piece-wage “served as a lever for the
lengthening of the working day and the lowering of wages”
(698); at a certain point in the development of capitalism, the “productivity of social labour” becomes the “most powerful lever of
accumulation” (772); “[t]he masses of capital welded together
overnight by centralization . . . become new and powerful levers
of social accumulation” (780); “[c]ommensurately . . . there also
takes place a development of the two most powerful levers of centralization—competition and credit” (778–79); “[b]ut if a surplus
population of workers is a necessary product of accumulation or of
the development of wealth on a capitalist basis, this surplus population also becomes, conversely, the lever of capitalist accumulation” (784).
2. Numbers in square brackets refer to pages in the first edition
of The Political Unconscious, published by Cornell University
Press in 1981.
3. If this is the case, there is an utterly everyday event that offers
a crude model of what happens in, and maybe even assists us to
[
Ambiguous Lever
practice, dialectical thought or mediation: aesthetic judgment, as
theorized by Kant. Strange as it sounds—for isn’t the aesthetic,
in its affective immediacy, the very cauldron of ideology?—aesthetic judgment in general might be thought of as a prototype or
rough draft or primitive mimesis of mediation’s way of coordinating the singular with the general. For it involves an irreducibly
individual experience of pleasure or displeasure—an experience
no one else can have for me—that, as revealed in the strange verbal
compulsion to share it, nonetheless cannot be private. Here spontaneous feeling signals the inextricable coupling of discursive
judgment to the perception of form—the seam that joins a way
of speaking, a way of facing or addressing others, to a way of seeing.
How we talk to each other—how we verbally share or make
our feelings of pleasure and displeasure public—is immanent to
aesthetic experience. It is not an auxiliary matter. As such, it
reveals the content of any aesthetic experience to be less about a
subject’s relation to an object—flower, poem, pop song, vacuum
cleaner—than about a relation of subjects to subjects. A relation
among subjects that deceptively looks, on the surface, like a relation to a thing: doesn’t this sound like a Marxist account of the
commodity’s logic, or how its form ends up reverberating
throughout society once that logic becomes universalized (with
the commodification of labor-power)? So here it is a case, not of
applying the same terms across different levels of social reality,
but of a recursive pattern or structure. “Looks like a thing—is really
a relation” coordinates two levels of social reality that are in truth
part of a single process but that for “objective” reasons appear not
to be.
4. Jameson writes, “Hegel’s analysis of Verstand—so subtle
and wide-ranging—thereby proves to be his most fundamental
contribution to some more properly Marxian theory of reification.
We have indeed had many studies—negative and positive alike—of
Marx’s Hegelianism; but this particular transmission does not
seem to me to bring more grist to a mill still very much in business,
however antiquated its technology. I would rather propose for current purposes a more unusual version, namely Hegel’s Marxism.
This virtually unexplored continent would certainly include the
dialectic itself” (Valences 100).
5. “Verstand, although omnipresent, and the very thinking of
daily life itself, is the villain of the piece,” Jameson writes in
Valences. “We cannot say that throughout the Logic, Hegel tracks
down the truth like a detective, but we can certainly say that he
tracks error, and that error always and everywhere takes the
form of Verstand. The Logic is therefore not a Bildungsroman,
where the little Notion grows up and learns about the world,
and eventually reaches maturity and autonomy: that could be, perhaps, the narrative schema of the Philosophy of History, and can
still be detected in its alleged teleology. Rather, Verstand is the
great magician, the Archimago, of the work, the primal source
of error itself, and of all the temptations—to persist in one
moment, for example, and to make one’s home there. Unlike the
Faerie Queene, however, if there is a villain, there are no heroes:
none of the knights, not the Dialectic, not Reason (Vernunft),
not Truth, nor Speculative Thinking, nor even the Notion itself,
goes forth to do battle with this baleful force (although it might
perhaps be argued that Philosophy is itself such a heroic
https://doi.org/10.1632/S0030812922000372 Published online by Cambridge University Press
P M L A
contender, a word which, besides meaning Hegel, also means all
those other positive things just mentioned). And this may have
something to do with the fact that Verstand also has its place, as
we have suggested, and cannot only not be done away with for
good: it would be undesirable to do so, it is the taming and proper
use of this mode rather than its eradication, which is wanted” (82).
As we see here, Jameson does not explicitly describe Verstand’s villainy as comic. The phrase “comic villain” does appear later in
Valences, however, in a gloss on comedy, as genre (Valences
586). The indestructibility of Verstand in the Logic moreover
recalls the indestructability of Geist in the Phenomenology, as
famously described by Judith Butler in slapstick terms: “[For]
Hegel, tragic events are never decisive. . . . What seems like tragic
blindness turns out to be more like the comic myopia of Mr.
Magoo whose automobile careening through the neighbor’s
chicken coop always seems to land on all four wheels. Like such
miraculously resilient characters of the Saturday morning cartoon,
Hegel’s protagonists always reassemble themselves, prepare a new
scene, enter the stage armed with a new set of ontological
insights—and fail again” (21).
6. This passage is worth quoting at length: “What we are here
concerned to stress is the paradox of the very notion of value itself,
which becomes visible as abstraction and as a strange afterimage
on the retina, only at the moment in which it has ceased to exist
as such. The characteristic form of rationalization is indeed the
reorganization of operations in terms of the binary system of
means and ends; indeed, the means/ends opposition, although it
seems to retain the term and to make a specific place for value,
has the objective result of abolishing value as such, bracketing
the ‘end’ or drawing it back into the system of pure means in
such a way that the end is merely the empty aim of realizing
these particular means. . . . [Because] rationalization involves the
transformation of everything into sheer means (hence the traditional formula of a Marxist humanism, that capitalism is a wholly
rationalized and indeed rational system of means in the service of
irrational ends).
“Thus, the study of value, the very idea of value, comes into
being at the moment of its own disappearance and of the virtual
obliteration of all value by a universal process of instrumentalization: which is to say that—as again in the emblematic case of
Nietzsche—the study of value is at one with nihilism, or the experience of its absence. What is paradoxical about such an experience
is obviously that it is contemporaneous with one of the most active
periods in human history. . . . We must ponder the anomaly that it
is only in the most completely humanized environment, the one
most fully and obviously the end product of human labor, production, and transformation, that life becomes meaningless” (Political
Unconscious 239–40 [250–51]).
WORKS CITED
Butler, Judith. Subjects of Desire: Hegelian Reflections in
Twentieth-Century France. Columbia UP, 1987.
Flatley, Jonathan. Like Andy Warhol. U of Chicago P, 2017.
·
]
Jameson, Fredric. Marxism and Form: Twentieth-Century
Dialectical Theories of Literature. Princeton UP, 1974.
———. The Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic
Act. Routledge, 2002.
———. Representing Capital: A Commentary on Volume One.
Verso, 2011.
———. Valences of the Dialectic. Verso, 2009.
https://doi.org/10.1632/S0030812922000372 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Sianne Ngai
Lukács, Georg. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in
Marxist Dialectics. Translated by Rodney Livingstone, MIT
Press, 1971.
Marx, Karl. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Vol. 1, translated by Ben Fowkes, Penguin Books, 1976.
Wegner, Phillip E. Invoking Hope: Theory and Utopia in Dark
Times. Minnesota UP, 2020.