Comparative Civilizations Review
Volume 77
Number 77 Fall 2017
Article 4
11-8-2017
A Reply to Johann Arnason
Toby Huff
[email protected]
Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/ccr
Part of the Comparative Literature Commons, History Commons, International and Area
Studies Commons, Political Science Commons, and the Sociology Commons
Recommended Citation
Huff, Toby (2017) "A Reply to Johann Arnason," Comparative Civilizations Review: Vol. 77 : No. 77 , Article 4.
Available at: https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/ccr/vol77/iss77/4
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the All Journals at BYU ScholarsArchive. It has been accepted for inclusion in Comparative
Civilizations Review by an authorized editor of BYU ScholarsArchive. For more information, please contact
[email protected],
[email protected].
Huff: A Reply to Johann Arnason
12
Number 77, Fall 2017
Reply to Johann Arnason’s Comments
Toby Huff
It is an honor to have the comments of Johann Arnason on my paper. He has raised
many issues and important questions. No doubt we will disagree of some minor issues
but agree on major ones and I appreciate this opportunity to discuss matters vital to
civilizational analysis. There are more issues here than I can address in our limited
space, so I shall confine my reply to what I see as the most important of the questions
raised.
I agree with Arnason’s comments on Max Weber’s legacy and his overlooking of
imperialist consequences of Europe’s ascendancy. Likewise, his comments on
Eurocentric issues and the now excessive attacks on Weber seem to me justly put. No
doubt Weber’s understanding of Japan was deficient and given his sparse comments on
Japan and his extraordinary knowledge of many other cultures and civilizations, his
missteps on Japan seem forgivable.
I shall return, however, to his reference to “normative projections” that most likely refer
to Weber’s notion of “world-historical” consequences. I will also return to the question
of why I put so much stress on the unfolding of the European legal revolution in the late
medieval period.
A basic difference between us is the role of evidence versus theory in doing
civilizational analysis. I believe one should start with a reasonably clear problem and
then dig into the empirical/historical evidence. Eisenstadt’s approach seems to start at
the other pole. His paper cited by Arnason is an entirely theoretical and vast survey,
impressive as it is, that covers huge sweeps of time and space (from 500 BC to about
100 AD, and even later “modern” developments), suggesting all sorts of
developments, structurations and “crystallizations.” But the paper does not cite a
single historical or sociological study that could support his many generalizations
during the Axial Age.13 So it should not be surprising that my comparison of three
civilizational encounters (the West, Islam, China), based as it is on decades of trying
to find and master the best historical sources, finds little help in what Eisenstadt has
written.
Shmuel Eisenstadt,” The Civilizational Dimension in Sociological Analysis,” Thesis Eleven 62
(2000): pp. 1-21.
13
Published by BYU ScholarsArchive, 2017
1
Comparative Civilizations Review, Vol. 77 [2017], No. 77, Art. 4
Comparative Civilizations Review
13
A perplexing feature of the Eisenstadt discussion is the fact that it proceeds with an
unclear conception of civilizational analysis that constantly verges back-and-forth
between the putative civilizational complexes (ancient Greece, Israel, China,
Buddhism, Hinduism, etc.) and references to “societies.” It is pretty much agreed
among sociologist that “societies” are social groups with distinct boundaries established
by their governments and economies. Having a formal governmental structure is the
defining characteristic of societies in this sense. In my understanding civilizations are
much larger units of two or more societies (or peoples) as articulated by
Durkheim/Mauss and Nelson14. This concept is a breakthrough in thinking about
civilizations as trans-national complexes. Such entities often have unclear boundaries
because they generally are voluntary entities, not empires or coercive entities (though
this could happen). This gets us to what it is that allows cultural phenomena to grow
and transcend national boundaries. The Durkheim/Mauss problematic asks: what is the
nature of this “coefficient of expansion”15 that some cultural phenomena have that
allows them to become translocal if not universal? Eisenstadt does not at all address
this question of how and why civilizational phenomena are trans-societal.
Eisenstadt does make an interesting suggestion that the “core” idea behind the concept
of “civilization” is an “ontological or cosmological vision.”16 He suggests that such
visions generally involve sacred, cosmological references and often entail tensions with
the mundane world. But does this help us understand the fundamental differences in
orientation between the Greek/Hellenic complex, Islamic civilization, Western and
Chinese civilizations?
Of course, one could improve on my description of the three encounters (between the
West, Islam, and China) but for the purpose of why the three took such different
approaches to naturalistic inquiry, it is far more useful to consider their alternative
philosophies of nature (which may have ontological references). These somewhat
metaphysical notions are more easily described and there is considerable literature on
the subject.
Thus, the ancient Greeks created a philosophy of nature (later adopted by Europeans)
that suggested that the natural world is a lawful, autonomous order, probably made up
of small particles, and a natural world that human beings can know and explain with
the aid of reason and logic.17
Emile Durkheim and Marcel Mauss, "Note on the Notion of Civilization,” Social Research vol. 38,
no. 4 (1971): 809-813; translated by Benjamin Nelson.
15
Ibid.., p. 811.
16
Eisenstadt, ibid., p. 2.
17
This and the following paragraphs draw from the third revised edition of my book, The Rise of Early
Modern Science: Islam, China and the West (Cambridge University Press, third edition, forthcoming,
2017)
14
https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/ccr/vol77/iss77/4
2
Huff: A Reply to Johann Arnason
14
Number 77, Fall 2017
In contrast, the Islamic philosophy of nature denied such rational-causal principles,
insisting instead that God is always in control, and that humankind can only know what
God enables or permits one to know.18 This is, of course, only one part of the story, as
my paper shows. Moreover, even with the aid of all the Greek-into-Arabic translations
of the core Greek scientific and philosophical texts, the Muslims did not institutionalize
the Greek modes of inquiry. Consequently, there was early success that soon dissipated.
The classic Chinese philosophy of nature entailed the polarities of yang/yin, the five
elements (water, wood, fire, earth, and metal) and the elusive energy called Chi. Here
no causal laws operate, there is no push-pull mechanism(s) operative. There is also a
notion of cyclical change over long periods of yang and then yin domination in timeless
cycles. In the long run (from ancient times to the 20th Century) no group of scholars
emerged who could or would overthrow that Confucian worldview (even with the help
of the European missionaries and thousands of translated books19). In a word, we can
understand these three intercivilizational encounters without resorting to Eisenstadt’s
loftier locutions such as “world-articulating meanings” and so on. From my limited
reading on the subject, I do not know of useful discussions of “multiple modernities”
that also take into account what I see as the fundamental grounding of European
civilization and its “modernity,” to which I shall return.20
Although I have difficulty with Chris Wickham’s precise time-line in the long citation
from his work, it strikes me that the general thrust of his statement endorses the multiple
factor and historical approach that I set out in the Epilogue to Intellectual Curiosity and
the Scientific Revolution.
Moreover, whatever point one wants to make with regard to the Holy Roman Empire
and its role in Central and Eastern Europe, the fact is that like all the other territorial
entities in Europe of the time, it adopted and operated with the aid of the ius commune,
the common law of Europe.21 This was the new and revised legal system that the
canonists and Romanists fashioned as one part of what I have called the legal revolution
of the long 12th century.
This is the well-known Islamic philosophy of occasionalism also discussed in The Rise of Early
Modern Science.
19
This I discussed in some detail in Intellectual Curiosity and the Scientific Revolution. A Global
Perspective (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011), chapter 4.
20
This idea was advanced by S N. Eisenstadt: “Multiple Modernities,” Daedalus 129 #1 (2000): 1-29.
Eisenstadt deserves credit for advancing this idea, but by claiming that the new modernity was an 18th
century phenomenon with its “first expansion” in the Americas (p. 13) seems to me off the mark. I shall
return to this.
21
Peter Stein, Roman Law in European History (New York; Cambridge University Press, 1999);
Michael Hoeltlich and Jasonne M. Grabler, "The Establishment of Normative Legal texts. The
Beginning of the Ius Commune," pp. 1-21 in The History of Medieval Canon Law in the Classical
Period, 1140- 1234, edited by William Hartmann (Washington, D.C: Catholic University of American
Press, 2008).
18
Published by BYU ScholarsArchive, 2017
3
Comparative Civilizations Review, Vol. 77 [2017], No. 77, Art. 4
Comparative Civilizations Review
15
Moreover, this new Romano-canonical system was taught in universities across Europe.
As a result, advocates across the Continent (and England) had to know both the
Ecclesiastical and civilian version of canon law, both based on the same legal principles.
This they had to do because they might have to try a case in an Ecclesiastical court.
This new legal system, above all other cultural factors, is what gave “Europe as a
civilization” its center and “framework of interacting” in all sorts of encounters and
transactions, that is, its modus operandi. In this sense, I am not “isolating” a single
factor but pointing to the multiple revolutions in institutional arrangements that gave
Europe an entirely new footing for virtually every aspect of political, economic, and
educational life. As I stressed in the first part of my Plenary paper, the European legal
revolution of the twelfth and thirteenth centuries laid the foundations for what we now
recognize as modern political institutions.22 These include due process of law, the
notion of elective representation in all forms of corporate bodies, the very idea of legally
autonomous organizations, and not least of all, legally autonomous professional
associations (of doctors and lawyers), charitable organizations, universities, as well as
cities and towns. All of these innovations, including the rise of parliamentary
governance, arose out of medieval canon law and contributed to the stability of
economic enterprises and made local self-government possible. Each of these
developments was part of the emergence of constitutionalism as understood in the
Western world.
Of course, the emergence of the universities created an institutional space for relatively
undisturbed public discourse on all sorts of subjects, most importantly by
institutionalizing the study of the (Greek-fashioned) natural sciences and incubating
modern science. There were further discussions within the universities and no doubt
they reverberated back on other political, economic, and political issues.
If, à la Eisenstadt, one would prefer to call this a “new civilization,” I would not greatly
object. I would insist, however, that this crystallization occurred long before the 17th
century and the Reformation, and that it produced the first real fusion of Greek
philosophy, Roman law, and Christianity, a position articulated by Ben Nelson and
many other historically minded scholars.23 That would also, in my view, place the title,
the “Axial” shift in the “long 12th century,” whether one wants to call it a “new”
Christian civilization or plainly, European civilization. That fusion was unique and was
soon exported to the U.S and “Europe overseas.”
Huff, “Europe as a Civilization: The Revolution of the Middle Ages and the Rise of the
Universities,” CCR #69 (2013); 65-86.
23
Nelson, On the Roads to Modernity. Conscience and Civilizations, edited by Toby E. Huff (Lanham,
Md: 1981; reprinted 2012), pp. 99-101; and, among others, Edward Grant, God and Reason in the
Middle Ages (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001).
22
https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/ccr/vol77/iss77/4
4
Huff: A Reply to Johann Arnason
16
Number 77, Fall 2017
Furthermore, that spiritual, legal, scientific complex is in my mind, at the heart of the
raging debates today about the rise or “decline” of “the West.” Whatever its fate, that
cluster of revolutions centered on the legal domain suggested above has no counterpart
in Islamic or Chinese civilization.24
One can explore the early history of Islam and influences on its formation as much as
one would like (as Patricia Crone25 and others have done), but the fact remains that the
canonical texts centered on the Quran and the hadith collections came to be the central
core of Islamic civilization, and there was no influence of the Roman Civil law. The
religious scholars (the ulama) worked assiduously to preserve and protect that central
legacy, rooted in faith, with the result that there were no revolutions (or reformations)
in religious thought, and no breakthroughs in theology or law. There is no Islamic Peter
Abelard, Thomas Aquinas or other intellectual innovators equivalent to those in
Western philosophy or theology. There were no innovative legal scholars parallel to
Gratian, Tancred, or Durand in Western Europe. Beyond that, and with more details
provided in Intellectual Curiosity, the fact remains that there was no Copernicus,
Galileo, Tycho Brahe, or Kepler in the history of Arabic-Islamic science.
Arnason also raises the question of how significant law and legal structures were in
China, so I offer this short account. Commentators on China who accent the “Chinese
bureaucracy” often forget to note that throughout the empire from before the Sung
dynasty (960-1279) throughout the Qing dynasty (1644-1911), the whole regime was
based on a legal code borrowed from earlier dynasties. The earlier Tang and Ming
codes were simply restated with additions and put in place without basic
modification.26 That code was based on a complex set of punishments and mitigations
and many hidden assumptions. The Code lacked a section detailing due process so
that the actions of the magistrates and all others followed their own whim, with no
effort to compile formal case records in order to achieve uniformity of outcome. This
also meant that there were no zones of autonomy, no independent associations of
doctors or lawyers (lawyers did not exist), nor were there any independent scholars
who could decide philosophical and educational issues as European scholars did. All
that was controlled by a small elite of official officeholders.
I have explored these comparative questions in several chapters in the third edition of my Rise of
Early Modern Science. Whether we could say that Japan experienced such revolutions of thought and
institutional arrangement, I leave to specialists on Japan to determine.
25
Patricia Crone, God’s Rule: Government and Islam. Six Centuries of Medieval Political Thought.
(New York. Columbia University Press, 2005).
26
The Great Ming Code, translated by Jiang Yonglin (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 2013).
24
Published by BYU ScholarsArchive, 2017
5
Comparative Civilizations Review, Vol. 77 [2017], No. 77, Art. 4
Comparative Civilizations Review
17
During various periods of time it was unlawful (and hence backed by punishments) to
own books on mathematics or astronomy while astronomical observation was strictly
controlled and forbidden outside the royal aegis. Likewise owning or using a telescope
was regulated by royal decree when the devices arrived in the 17th century.
Given that there were no law schools and there was no independent body of legal
scholars, there was little chance for legal evolution or for advanced legal thought. With
this background in mind, it would be an exaggeration to suggest that the Chinese had
anything like the Western legal system of due process that I mentioned earlier (and have
discussed in more detail elsewhere). There were no rights for legal challenge, no strict
procedures for getting a case heard by the magistrate who was in effect a person with
only “on-the-job training.” Moreover, he had a variety of options that would allow him
to ignore any petition that he did not want to deal with, or simply send it back to the
lineage elders for resolution.27
Because of this state of affairs in which the Emperor’s decree was law (on top of the
official legal code), and with the total absence of a notion of legal autonomy, all sorts
of activities were proscribed. Here I shall just mention the innocuous practice of official
examination of deceased bodies that were suspected of foul play. Postmortems as such
were conducted “by the book” by two novices: the magistrate who had no medical
training, and the ostensor, a lowly self-trained, often illiterate person who might have
been a barber. The book was called the Washing Away of Wrongs, dating from the 12th
century and by decree could not be changed in any detail all the way to the early 19th
century. The book contains diagrams of mortal and non-mortal places of wounds on
the body and which had to be identified by the two officials as they examined the corpse.
This was not a proper autopsy (such as Europeans had been carrying out since the 13th
century) and in this case without the aid of a properly trained physician, simply followed
the book with the ostensor calling out information that he extracted from observing the
body to the magistrate who recorded it on the form. It has been observed, however, that
even when more informed medical examiners discovered anomalies in the corpses they
studied, they were not allowed to make any changes to the official manual.28
Among many others, see Melissa Macauley, “Civil and Uncivil Disputes in Southeastern Coastal
China, 1728- 1820,” in Civil Justice in Qing and Republican China, edited by Kathryn Bernhardt and
Philip Huang, pp. 85-121 (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994); and idem,
Social Power and Legal Culture. Litigation Masters in Late Imperial China (Stanford: Stanford
University Press,1998). I discuss the issues further in Chapter 7 in the new edition The Rise of Early
Modern Science.
28
Pierre-étienne Will, “Developing Forensic Knowledge Through Cases in the Qing Dynasty,” in
Thinking with Cases, In Thinking with Cases, edited by Charlotte Furth, Judith T. Zeitlin, Judith T., and
Ping-chen Hsiung, pp. 62-100. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 2007.
27
https://scholarsarchive.byu.edu/ccr/vol77/iss77/4
6
Huff: A Reply to Johann Arnason
18
Number 77, Fall 2017
In this way the rigidities of the Ming and Qing legal codes prevented learning in this
area of human anatomy, which, one would think, had no political implications, but
significant benefits for human well-being if subordinates had any leeway to speak and
record their new findings. Clearly there were many inhibitive effects of the Chinese
legal code on the advance of science and economic activity.
Perhaps there are alternative “modernities” that might be designated as modernity1,
modernity2, and so on. There is a problem, however, if we are following Eisenstadt’s
model. That is, just like the sociologists against whom he is arguing as he attempts to
forge the idea of multiple modernities, Eisenstadt adopts a socio-psychological
approach which means that he looks at personality characteristics not societal
characteristics.29 He talks about conceptions of “human agency,” and “reflexivity”
instead of identifying societal (and/or civilizational) structures and institutions. If,
however, one thinks about the deep roots of Western culture and civilization and the
unique institutions it invented, then one arrives the following suggestion.
In the first type of modernity I would place the presence of a public sphere (including
the right to assembly), the unfettered pursuit of science, a free press, a clear sense of
due process of law buttressed by articulated rules (not just conventions), the presence
of an independent legal profession, parliamentary democracy and constitutionalism,
along with legally autonomous commercial enterprises buttressed by secure property
rights. The seeds of all these ideas and institutions were planted long before the
Reformation, the Enlightenment and the Americas.
These I think are the likely “normative” implications that would flow from a
Weberian civilizational analytic. It would be most fascinating to see how a denizen of
another culture or civilization would construct an alternative modernity (modernity2).
And what kind of Westerners would choose it?
The examples of supposed unilinear development on the roads to modernity that Eisenstadt cites are:
Daniel Lerner, The Passing of Traditional Society (Glencoe, Ill: Free Press, 1958); and Alex Inkeles,
Becoming Modern: Individual Changes in Six Developing Countries (Cambridge, Ma: Harvard
University Press,1974). As much as I admire the work of Lerner and Inkeles, it has to be said that their
work is entirely ahistorical insofar as it does not reflect upon the cultural and historical foundations of
Western modernity as it unfolded far earlier than the Enlightenment. But that was not their problematic.
Ben Nelson was well-aware of this problem in Inkeles’ work
29
Published by BYU ScholarsArchive, 2017
7