feature
Decision-making in
betting markets
The placing of a bet is a classic example of decision-making under
uncertainty. A betting market is also an example of a simple financial
market, but one which possesses the advantage that each bet is
characterised by a well-defined end point at which it possesses
a definite value, i.e. the amount won or lost. Leighton Vaughan
Williams explains the implications for our understanding of
economic decision-making of the observed tendency for the expected
returns on bets to differ markedly at different odds levels.
The favourite–longshot bias
In recent years there has developed a rapidly growing
economics literature which has focused on the nature
and behaviour of betting markets. This literature has
been published in some of the foremost international
academic journals, and has increasingly influenced
mainstream economic enquiry.
The most significant focus of the published literature to date has been the issue of information efficiency,
i.e. the way in which and the degree to which a market incorporates available relevant information. In the
strictest sense, a market is informationally efficient if
it incorporates all available information. No consumer
or investor operating in such a market could, therefore,
know more than the market. In the particular context of
a betting market, this means in one sense that no bettor
could make a profit except by chance.
Numerous studies have sought to investigate
whether betting markets are indeed informationally efficient, and if so to identify the extent to which this is so.
If betting markets are efficient, one might expect
that the average return to a bet at any given odds level will be the same as that at any other odds level. By
odds level we mean the net amount gained by a winning bet to a given stake. For example, odds of 5 to 1
against would imply that a £1 bet on a horse would, if
successful, return a net amount of £5, i.e. £5 and the £1
returned to the bettor. A losing bet would lose the stake.
In fact, there is significant published evidence to suggest
that the expected return differs markedly at different
odds levels. This phenomenon has come to be known
as the “favourite–longshot bias”, and can be traced to a
seminal piece of work published in 1949 by Richard M.
Griffith, a psychologist based at the Veterans Administration Hospital, Lexington, Kentucky1.
In his paper, Griffith produced evidence, derived
from the US racetrack, that, the shorter the odds about
a horse, the better on average the value. In other words,
those who systematically bet on the favourite (the horse
with the shortest odds) would over the long term win
more, or at least lose less, than those backing any other
horse or horses in the field.
This was a startling discovery because it suggested
that it was possible to earn above-average returns by following a simple system which required no knowledge of
anything other than the available odds.
This was significant not only for horse race bettors
but also for economists interested in the operation of
markets, and in particular financial markets. After all, if
markets were efficient, in the sense of incorporating all
available information, how could betting markets leave
open this loophole?
The answer has fascinated economists ever since,
and some interesting explanations have been teased out.
Attitudes to risk
The most obvious explanation is that those who bet at the
racetrack simply like risk, and so don’t want to back favourites. Favourites are, after all, the least risky option of
all the choices available to the bettor because they win, on
september2004
“There is significant
evidence that the
expected return differs
markedly at different
odds levels”
109
Charles Trevelyan
average, more often than any other available option. Those who like the thrill of the chase would
therefore, according to this explanation, steer
away from these relatively safe bets, and tend to
favour alternatives (“longshots”) which pay out
less often but which pay out more when they do
come in. This is the “lottery effect”, the observed
tendency of people to flock to the opportunity
of winning a large sum of money in one go even
though the probability of doing so is small.
The problem with this interpretation of
the evidence of a “favourite–longshot bias” is
that it conflicts with the tenets of all conventional economic theory. Such theory dictates
that people are, in general, risk averse, which
means that they need to be compensated for
taking on extra risk. For example, an investor
would require a higher expected return for
venturing £1000 into an exploratory oil venture in South America than for investing the
same £1000 in a savings account at the local
high street bank.
One explanation for the different attitude
to risk exhibited by bettors and investors is
that money spent in a betting context is treated
differently from money spent in an investment
context. This is the idea that people employ
“mental accounts” into which they file different
sorts of expenditure.
110
september2004
Such an explanation is convenient, of
course, because it allows us to explain away any
observed anomalies as simply a special case. On
this basis, however, it is possible to construct
as many special cases as there are anomalies;
a solution which is anathema to most scientists, and no less so to traditional mainstream
economists.
“If you know nothing else about
football, your best bet is to back the
shorter-priced team”
An integrated approach
For this reason, economists have more recently
addressed the issue of the “favourite–longshot”
bias within a more broad-based framework.
Such approaches seek to explain the bias as a
natural consequence of established economic
principles, avoiding the need to consider the
betting market and/or bettors as in any way
special or different.
One such approach is to regard the bookmaker as somebody facing the problem of setting odds in the face of a number of individuals,
of uncertain identity, who may know more than
they do. These individuals are usually called
“insiders”. In such an environment, the bookmakers may seek to contract those odds which
expose them to the greatest potential liabilities,
i.e. longer odds. This does not, however, explain
the existence of a bias (albeit of less extent) in
so-called “share-of-the-pool” (parimutuel) markets, where winning bettors share the pool of
all bets. After all, there is no bookmaker in such
markets to take fright at the informed insiders.
Another explanation is that bettors may
overlook some fraction of their losses, but
not their winnings. If so, it can be shown that
bettors will tend to bet too much, relative to
the objective chance of success, and will do so
increasingly as the odds lengthen. In my own
work, I have sought to distinguish between
these competing explanations by examining
whether the bias against longshots is particularly strong where insiders have the greatest
potential to operate2. The evidence indicates
that this is indeed the case, which suggests that
the shortening of odds at the longer end of the
spectrum in response to the threat of insider
activity is at least a partial explanation of the
established favourite–longshot bias. It does
not, of course, explain the bias in US betting
markets, which operate on a parimutuel basis.
Perhaps surprisingly, the well-established
phenomenon of a favourite–longshot bias,
apparent in most studies of the US, UK, Ireland, Australia, New Zealand and elsewhere,
is absent in studies of racing in Hong Kong
and Japan3,4. Perhaps the difference can be explained by the motivation of bettors at Asian
racetracks. At those tracks, where the pools
and rewards are particularly large, it may be
that bettors are operating more like investors
than punters.
Favourites appear also to offer no special
advantage in the US baseball betting market5.
Unlike racetrack markets in the US, which are
parimutuel only, the American baseball market is conducted at fixed odds, i.e. the odds
are given at the time that the bet is struck.
One explanation for this has been couched in
terms of the type of bettor (relatively sophisticated) inhabiting the baseball betting scene,
in an environment characterised by relatively
low costs.
A recently published analysis of English
Premier League football, however, confirms the
existence of the traditional favourite–longshot
bias for football, i.e. the odds available with
fixed-odds bookmakers about the favourite of
two teams is better value on average than the
odds available about the underdog6. In other
words, if you know nothing else about football, your best bet is to back the shorter-priced
team. Among correct score odds, incidentally,
the best value, according to the study, seems to
lie in backing very strong favourites to win by
1–0, 2–0, 2–1 or 3–2.
Spread betting—less biased?
Even so, this bias seems to be limited to fixedodds betting, at least on the basis of my own
research into football “spread” betting markets.
Just to clarify, in spread betting, bettors are
not offered odds but are instead invited to buy
or sell notional assets associated with an event
(for example, goals in a football match or the
price of gold), based on a “spread” set by market-makers (bookmakers). If the market-maker, for example, expects a team to score 3 goals,
a typical spread may be set between 2.9 and
3.2. Bettors who expect the number of goals to
exceed the top end of the spread (3.2) are invited to buy at this level. Similarly, bettors who
expect the number of goals to fall short of the
bottom end of the spread (2.9) are invited to
sell at this level. The spread may move upwards
or downwards before or during the course of
the game until the value of the asset is known
with certainty (at the end of the game). At this
point a bettor who bought (sold) the asset will
win or lose the difference between the ex-post
value of the asset and the bid price, multiplied
by their original stake. The bettor may “close”
the trade at any time.
Spread betting markets have historically
been characterised by a low level of transaction
costs, at least relative to traditional betting markets, partly because of their relatively favourable tax treatment. They have therefore offered
an attractive option both to small traders, motivated primarily by wealth considerations, and
to larger traders using financial spread betting
markets as part of a more general risk management strategy. In particular, spread trading
is often used to hedge against, for example, a
potential short-term fall in the market. The
low transaction costs also make it possible for
potential arbitrageurs to profit from relatively
small mispricings in the market.
The absence of a favourite–longshot bias
in these markets may, therefore, be explained
by the relatively low transaction costs, or perhaps because these markets are inhabited (like
the baseball markets examined earlier) by relatively sophisticated bettors.
In truth, we still do not know for sure why
some markets are apparently more efficient in
processing information than others, or why biases which exist in some betting markets are
absent from others.
september2004
111
Charles Trevelyan
The Quarb strategy
This is the bad news. The good news, at least
for those of a more practical turn of mind
where betting markets are concerned, is the
evidence I have found that those who seek to
exploit price differentials offered by different
market-makers (what I have termed a “Quarb”
strategy7) have historically been able to earn
significant profits in spread betting markets, at
least in the market available about the number
of disciplinary cards issued in Premiership
football matches in the UK, i.e. the “bookings”
market8. In this market, 10 points are awarded
for a yellow card and 25 for a red card.
The logic behind the Quarb strategy goes
like this. In the absence of other information,
the mid-point of all spreads provides us with
an obvious point estimate of the expected value
of the asset. On this basis, we can expect positive returns as long as this value is greater (less)
than the price at which we buy (sell). Take the
case of the bookings market, for example, in a
game between Arsenal and Manchester United. Suppose three of the market-makers offer
a spread of 46–50 bookings points, while the
fourth market-maker offers a spread of 50–54
bookings points. Now, the mean mid-point of
112
september2004
all spreads in the market is (48+48+48+52)/4,
i.e. 49, which is below the spread offered by the
“maverick” market-maker, of 50–54. The strategy would be to sell bookings with this outlying
market-maker at 50. If the outlying spread was
40–48, with a mean of 49, on the other hand,
the strategy would be to buy bookings at 48. If
no market-maker offered a spread everywhere
outside the mean of the mid-points of all the
spreads, this would imply no trade. As I stated
above, there is supporting evidence of significant profits to be made, at least historically,
from following this trading strategy.
Does the opportunity still exist? Why not
try it and see! After all, it’s only money.
References
1. Griffith, R. M. (1949) Odds adjustment
by American horse-race bettors. American Journal
of Psychology, 62, 290–294.
2. Vaughan Williams, L. and Paton, D.
(1997) Why is there a favourite-longshot bias in
British racetrack betting markets? Economic Journal, 107, 150–158.
3. Busche, K. (1994) Efficient market results
in an Asian setting. In Efficiency of Racetrack Betting Markets (eds D. B. Hausch, S. Y. Lo and W. T.
Zeimba), pp. 615–616. London: Academic Press.
4. Busche, K. and Hall, C. (1988) An excep-
tion to the risk preference anomaly. Journal of Business, 61, 337–346.
5. Woodland, L. and Woodland, B. (1994)
Market efficiency and the favourite-longshot bias:
the baseball betting market. Journal of Finance, 49,
269–279.
6. Cain, M., Law, D. and Peel, D. (2000)
The favourite-longshot bias and market efficiency
in UK football betting. Scottish Journal of Political
Economy, 47, 25–36.
7. Vaughan Williams, L. (2000) Markets
and information efficiency: evidence from the UK.
In Global Business and Economics Review—Anthology 2000, pp. 24–29.
8. Paton, D. and Vaughan Williams, L.
(2004) Forecasting outcomes in spread betting
markets: can bettors use ‘Quarbs’ to beat the book?
Journal of Forecasting, to be published.
Further reading
Paton, D. and Vaughan Williams, L. (1998)
Do betting costs explain betting biases? Applied
Economics Letters, May, 333–335.
Leighton Vaughan Williams is Professor of Economics
and Finance, Director of the Betting Research Unit, and
Head of Economics Research at the Nottingham Trent
University. He has written and published extensively in
the area of betting research, and acts widely in a consultative capacity on betting and gaming issues.