TITLE: Citizenship Education in the UK and the Adult Migrant
Author: Qasir Shah
Affiliation: University College London Institute of Education
Contact:
[email protected]
ABSTRACT
This paper explores the policy reasons behind Adult ESOL Citizenship Education
(AECE) in the UK and then examines whether AECE adequately prepares
migrants for active citizenship in T. H. McLaughlin’s ‘maximal’ sense: involving
active political participation premised upon a shared concept of democratic
culture underpinned by rights and obligations. It argues that AECE, as envisaged
by Bernard Crick and Terence McLaughlin, has fallen short of its maximal
conceptualisation due to the watering down of CE and AECE in preference to
Fundamental British Values, and the Crick reports’ ‘light touch’ to their
implementation. The paper calls for a need to reassert the reality of the modern
nation as pluralistic and reject the current drive toward monism. It also argues
that AECE is unlikely to deliver social cohesion and integration, or an actively
participatory citizenry, unless issues of social justice and equity are addressed.
Word Count (abstract) : 142
1
Word Count (paper) : 6930
Key words: ESOL, citizenship education, civic republican, liberal, T. H.
McLaughlin
2
TITLE: Citizenship Education in the UK and the Adult Migrant
Introduction
What does it mean to be a citizen? Is it possible for various ethnic communities
to do more than simply exist? Moreover, for Mouffe (1992), ‘the interpellation
“citizen” to be able to fulfil that role, what conditions must it meet?’ ((1992, p.
70). This question is of vital significance and its response depends on one’s
philosophical leanings. ‘The way we define citizenship is intimately linked to the
kind of society and political community we want.’ (ibid. (1992, p. 70). Should it
be conceived purely in terms of the ‘minimal/liberal’ citizenship-as-legal-status:
full membership in a particular society, or the ‘maximal/civic republican’
citizenship-as-desirable-activity: where the extent and quality of citizenship
depends on one’s participation. I have been a teacher of ESOL (English as a
Second Language) to adults since 2003 in various contexts, from the private
sector to Local Authorities and Further Education college, yet not once in any of
these sectors have I been offered/encouraged, or had Citizenship Education (CE)
training made accessible to me, nor have colleagues with whom I have worked.
What are the consequences of this? Further, what does this reveal in the context
of CE becoming a legal requirement in compulsory education in September
2002? This legal requirement came about following the Crick report (Crick and
Advisory Group on Citizenship, 1998). The two subsequent reports, from Crickchaired committees, concerned the CE needs of 16-19 year olds (Crick, 2000),
and migrants to Britain (Crick, 2003) which affected the teaching of ESOL
courses by making it a requirement to have CE components in the ESOL
curriculum. The provision of CE was seen as a means to combat the perceived
3
democratic deficit – with declining political participation of the polity, and in the
context of community cohesion for migrants. This paper will explore the context
of Adult ESOL Citizenship Education (AECE) to answer the above questions, and
consider to what extent Bernard Crick’s desire ‘to change the political culture of
this country both nationally and locally’ (Crick, 1998, para. 1.5) has come about.
The paper begins by briefly articulating the main conceptualisations of
citizenship to gain some perspective of what the aims of AECE should be, in
order to understand its current philosophical underpinnings in the UK. Then the
current policy and legislation with regards to AECE will be articulated. Next, the
policy motives behind AECE will be investigated - particularly the assertion that
the learning of English is of paramount importance to stimulating integration
and civic participation. This should reveal where AECE stands vis-à-vis the
different conceptualisations of citizenship and the wider discourse surrounding
lifelong learning. Finally, using T.H. McLaughlin’s maximal civic republican
conceptualisation, I argue that AECE does not equip migrants for such a
citizenship.
The concept of citizenship
The Western concept of citizenship is complex and contested; it has run along
the civic republican approach (whose roots can be traced back to Sparta,
Athens and Aristotle, through Harrington, Rousseau, Machiavelli, Cicero and
Tacitus), which emphasises a direct relationship between citizenship and
active political participation in Aristotelian terms as defined in his Politics of
a citizen who is both able to rule and to be ruled in turn;
liberal models founded upon legal rights having a Universalist vocation
4
(whose racines can be traced to the Roman Empire of the mid-5th century BC,
through Rawls, Dahl, Marshall, Adam Smith, Locke and Hobbes);
to
communitarian
approaches
emphasising
cultural
belonging
and
community (Walzer, 1983; Kymlicka, 1996) and finally
to radical pluralistic approaches in which any identity can find its place
(Young, 1989).
Arguably, Crick’s intention was toward the civic republican conceptualization of
citizenship. His reports drew strongly on the work of T.H. Marshall (Marshall and
Bottomore, 1992) who had argued that citizenship comprised three distinct albeit related - dimensions: the civil, the political and the social, which were
transformed into three strands: social and moral responsibility; political literacy;
and community involvement. The Crick report (1998), referring to an earlier
report Encouraging Citizenship (1990), emphasized that greater import be paid
to ‘the reciprocity between rights and duties; and, more than Marshall, on
welfare being not just provision by the state but also what people can do for each
other in voluntary groups and organisations, whether local or national’ (para.
2.3). Concerning political citizenship, it reiterated that it should not be taken for
granted, and that: ‘Civic spirit, citizens’ charters and voluntary activity in the
community are of crucial importance, but individuals must be helped and
prepared to shape the terms of such engagements by political understanding and
action. (para. 2.3). I will however use a contemporaneous conceptualisation of
maximal citizenship articulated by T.H. McLaughlin (1992), which has
considerable overlap with Marshall, and Crick’s ‘maximal’ conceptualisation of
citizenship.
McLaughlin
proposes
the
5
conceptualisation
of
contrasting
interpretations of citizenship (and democracy itself) along a continuum ‘rather
than in terms of discrete conceptions’, which can be illustrated with reference to
‘four aspects of citizenship’ (236).
the extent of the political involvement of the individual
identity: a dynamic membership of a shared democratic culture, involving
rights, responsibilities and obligations
virtues that enable justice and empowerment of one’s fellow citizens
the social prerequisites necessary for effective citizenship – consideration
of social disadvantages as barriers to full citizenship participation.
The four aspects are conceived in social, cultural and psychological terms, which
address the heart of a citizen’s identity that such a citizenship confers.
McLaughlin’s conceptualisation is particularly appealing because it looks at
the virtues of the citizen that are required, the extent of the political involvement on the
part of the individual that is thought to follow, and the social prerequisites seen as
necessary for effective citizenship (1992, p.236).
McLaughlin’s reinterpretation helps us locate policy and AECE provision for
migrants in a more nuanced way than ‘distinct conceptions’ of citizenship; it
helps us to go beyond the assumption that 'minimal' conceptions are more free
than their 'maximal' counterparts of ideological content or significance’ (ibid., p.
237). For example, liberals stress the importance of personal autonomy as being
part of public virtues to be promoted, but this requires living an examined life
6
that is critical of perceived wisdom., However, philosophers such as Galston
(1989, 1991) argue against living an examined life, as it may lead to the
questioning of one’s private beliefs. McLaughlin’s interpretation ‘merely insists
that questions relating to substantial identity, to virtues of general focus, to
significant participation and to the problem of social disadvantage’ be
considered relevant in questions of citizenship’, without requiring a specific
answer (237). But, before I address whether the current AECE for migrants
allows them to function fully as citizens in McLaughlin’s ‘maximal’ sense, or as
envisaged by Crick,1 it is worth outlining the current state of play in AECE in the
UK in terms of policy, legislation and their origins, to discern their intent.
AECE discourse, policy and legislation in the UK
The UK strategy for the integration of migrants was formulated primarily by the
work of the Community Cohesion Review (2001) led by Ted Cantle, the reports by
Denham et al. (2001) and Crick ‘The New and The Old’ (2003) chaired by Bernard
Crick. The changes in British Law that proceeded the Denham Report were part
of a greater change in the debate on citizenship, which led in September 2002 to
citizenship becoming a statutory foundation subject in the national curriculum
as recommended in the first Crick report (Crick and Advisory Group on
Citizenship, 1998); the subsequent two reports, from Crick-chaired committees,
concerned the CE needs of 16-19 year olds (Crick, 2000) and migrants to Britain
(Crick, 2003).
The report’s primary concern according to Crick was ‘to change the political
1
It is worth highlighting that the maximal form of CE advocated by Crick is not uncontroversial
and contested as being a minority view (Miller 2000) of leftwing anti-capitalist bias (Tooley,
2000) and undermining of private beliefs and practices (Galston, 1989) cf. Kymlicka (1999).
7
culture of this country. Such language ‘sees citizenship as process rather than
status, as activity rather than nationality, as enabling rather than behavioural’
and consequently ‘seeks to address a variety of agendas: the democratic deficit,
community cohesion, social inclusion, and civic renewal’ (Breslin, 2005).
Regarding adult migrants, the Crick report (2003) recommended that something
similar to what was being taught in CE in schools should be extended to
migrants, with the proviso that a Programme of Studies should be tailored to fit
the ‘different attainments and different skills’ of those seeking naturalisation’
(p15).
The Crick report also considered English language competency as being ‘the
most important means of diverse communities participating in a common
culture with key values in common’ (Crick, 2003, p. 11). English competency was
seen as being essential in the process of integration and therefore the report
recommended unified ‘language-with-civic-content programmes’ (ibid, p. 14).
Section 1 of the Nationality, Immigration and Asylum Act 2002 amended the
requirements for citizenship in the British Nationality Act 1981, to include
language requirements and knowledge of UK life, for people seeking
naturalisation. The recommendations of Crick’s 2003 report were enacted by
subsequent changes to the legislation concerning the acquisition of UK
citizenship. Since 2004 those with ESOL Entry 3 English skills have been
expected to demonstrate knowledge of the official publication on citizenship
(Home Office., 2013) by answering multiple-choice questions about life in the
UK. Those less capable in English could take an ESOL course containing elements
of citizenship and, by progressing a level (evidenced by passing a speaking and
listening exam), would be eligible for settlement or naturalisation without
8
having to undertake the Life in the UK test. In April 2007, the UK Immigration
Rules were amended so that the aforementioned requirements were extended to
people seeking indefinite leave to remain (ILR). And from October 2013 an
additional English language test may be required for some applicants subject to
10 caveats (Brooks, 2013, p. 5).
The discourse on AECE and its subsequent enactment in statute can be traced
to the British government’s underlying concern about social unrest which took
place in three towns and cities2 - with large ethnic minority populations - in the
north of England in 2001. The riots led to the formation of The Community
Cohesion Review led by Cantle who noted that ‘community cohesion
fundamentally depend[ed] on people and their values’, and recommended
strategies that would make migrant settlements feel “at home”, including an
agreement on ‘some common elements of “nationhood” ’ (Cantle, 2001, p. 18).3
Following these reports the White Paper on immigration, asylum and nationality
stated that: ‘We need to develop a sense of civic identity and shared values, and
knowledge of the English language … can undoubtedly support this objective’
(Home Office, 2002, p. 32). Thus English fluency viewed through such lens, is
seen as a British value by which to judge the willingness and ability of the
immigrant to integrate. Consequently, ESOL classes are considered a front line in
government policy on national cohesion and homeland security policy.
However, another important underlying motive of AECE policy has been
influenced by the learning economy discourse in the UK, premised upon the
economic imperative (OECD, 1996; Kocanova, Bourgeois and de Almeida
Coutinho, 2015), which sees learners as human capital who must improve their
2
3
Leeds, Oldham and Bradford.
(see also Denham, 2001).
9
economic skills;4 for migrants this means mastery of English is for employment;
as such ESOL was partly conceived in economic terms.
From the preceding policy narrative, there appears to be a conflict between
the initial intent of the Crick reports’ civic republican – maximal - model of
citizenship, and successive governments’ economic imperative of the learning
economy - improving skills for employment - rather than on an emancipatory
agenda of social justice. To highlight this, I will use McLaughlin’s four aspects of
citizenship to compare policy intent and its delivery with respect to AECE
provision and ask the question: does AECE encourage political involvement or
political literacy?
Political involvement
For McLaughlin, political involvement needs to go beyond the minimal views of
loyalties and responsibilities, which are viewed ‘primarily as local and
immediate in character’ (McLaughlin, 1992, p. 236) - that is to say a citizen
should be law-abiding and 'public spirited', for example helping neighbours via
voluntary activity. This contrasts with McLaughlin’s maximal view, which
regards citizens as possessing ‘a responsibility to actively question and extend
their local and immediate horizons [to greater] considerations such as those of
justice, and to work for the sort of social conditions that will lead to the
empowerment of all citizens.’ This concurs with Crick’s transformative maximal
aims: to see the citizen as having the potential to participate actively in
democratic and political processes in the widest possible manner, rather than
the narrow (minimal) sense of a citizen merely upholding democratic ideals and
Rather than education’s emancipatory social justice that was advocated prior to the 1980s. See
Faure et al., (1972; UNESCO, 1997).
4
10
participating to the limited degree of voting in local and national elections.
However, one could argue as Benjamin Constant (1819) did that the scale and
complexity of grands États modernes precludes the kind of civic engagement
envisaged by Aristotle (and Crick). The present-day citizen, unlike the
Aristotelian, does not see herself as a zoon politikon with politics being central to
her identity; politics is now just one of her many interests. An individual should
be free to choose her level of engagment: whether maximally or minimally. But
to exercise this choice, she must first know that such a choice exists and to have
sufficient knowledge to make this choice: she needs to be informed.
With regard to new citizens and migrants, arguably the learning of English is
motivated mainly by integrationist needs: to gain employment and survive in
their daily lives in their communities (Han, Starkey and Green 2010). This
concurs with my anecdotal evidence from 15 years’ teaching. It fits with
Maslow’s hierarchy of needs (1954): many ESOL students are pre-occupied with
the need to survive rather than the contemplation and/or actualisation of
citizenship in a maximal sense. But as Ralph Miliband argued (1994, in Martin,
2003, p. 575) ‘the practice and the habit of democracy’ needs to be understood,
experienced, and practiced as part of the texture of our everyday lives. For all
citizens ‘to make themselves effective in public life’ (Crick, 1998, para. 2.12), they
need first of all to possess political knowledge in addition to simply learning the
language - only by becoming so informed, will they come to realise the
importance of becoming active citizens in order to secure their freedoms and
rights, as well as understand their obligations.
But unfortunately, as Keating and Kerr (2013) state, the initial emphasis on
political literacy by Crick et al. (1998) has been weakened due to a greater
11
emphasis being placed on promoting community cohesion and integration as one
of the fundamentals of the Citizenship curriculum, and this I contend also holds
true of AECE. This emphasis on community cohesion was made a legal
requirement by the Department for Children, Schools and Families in 2007
following the Diversity and Citizenship Curriculum Review 2007. The National
Curriculum was then updated in 2008 to include a fourth thematic strand to be
attached to CE, that of Identity and diversity: living together in the UK (QCA 2007,
in Keating and Kerr, 2013, p. 8). As a consequence, political literacy had to be
deferred in favour of discussions on diversity, community and social cohesion. In
a similar vein, CE was further watered down with the coming into effect in 2015
of a legal duty to promote Fundamental British Values (FBV) in schools:
democracy, the rule of law, individual liberty, mutual respect for and tolerance of
those with different faiths and beliefs and for those without faith, as part of the
prevent policy (HM Government, 2011) aimed at children at risk of being drawn
to terrorism. The teaching of FBV has filtered through to AECE.
For me maximal political participation could not have been the intent of
government policy in the UK regarding AECE. Even if this were the case, one
could ‘question as to whether language and citizenship tests and courses are a
genuine contribution to preparation for [adult] citizenship’ (Han, Starkey and
Green, 2010). The status of CE (and AECE) was undermined at its inception by
policy design flaws and implementation. The 1998 (and 2003) Crick reports
applied a ‘light touch’ to its implementation in the school curriculum by not
requiring a more prescriptive curriculum. The fear was of a) being accused of
political interference in subject content (McLaughlin, 2000, p. 546); b) a need to
recognise teachers’ professional abilities by trusting them to engage learners by
12
localising and personalising the content and format(s) (Halliday 1999, in Keating
and Kerr, 2013, p. 8); and c) understanding the different levels of linguistic
attainment of migrants (2003, p.15). These intentions were laudable; however,
this pragmatic approach has led to the main aims envisaged by the 1998 report,
such as political literacy, being delivered patchily, with some schools developing
good Citizenship practices while others squeeze Citizenship into cracks in the
timetable (this is also true of AECE).
Compounding the variations in provision, as little guidance was provided to
implement CE concerning its format, content, teaching qualifications or
resources, Benton (2008) identified a gap between the policy and what was
being taught in practice due to a lack of subject specific knowledge: one fifth of
the teachers lacked confidence in teaching about the EU, parliament and
government and the global community, with nearly 20% not at all confident in
delivering about voting rights. Additionally, a survey of teachers found 50% of
the teachers reported they had received no training on Citizenship, and two
thirds believed they required more training (Keating et al., 2010, pp. 39–41).
Jerome (2012, p. 117) estimated a shortfall of 1160 qualified Citizenship
teachers in England. The problem of a shortage of CE specialists in AECE is even
more acute. Teachers are the most important and final link in the delivery of
AECE; the wish that it be taught in its maximal sense is undermined by the fact
that it is often delivered by ESOL tutors with little CE knowledge. In my 14 years
of teaching ESOL at various institutions, I have yet to be offered any training on
CE. This state of affairs hinders the migrant attaining political knowledge and
therefore becoming politically literate for a maximal understanding, and or
engagement.
13
Thus the problems that surfaced in CE in schools are being mirrored in
AECE: a mismatch of policy intent and implementation. This situation is further
compounded by the fact that most ESOL students are below Level 1, and
therefore do not possess the linguistic capacity for a maximal understanding of
citizenship.5 This could in part explain the finding of Han, Starkey and Green’s
(2010) study that the ESOL learners interviewed had very little understanding of
the maximal concept of citizenship. Another explanation for this could be a lack
of subject-specific knowledge on the part of the ESOL teachers themselves.
However, even if one were to have subject specialists teaching CE to ESOL adults
of Levels 1 and 2, it is questionable whether they would gain sufficient political
literacy that would prepare them for maximal political participation. The reason
for this is to be found in the Adult ESOL Curriculum and the CE handbook: Life in
the UK, which singularly fails to provide an in-depth understanding of citizenship
and British culture in its profound sense; the Test contains some trivial
knowledge questions (Brooks, 2013; 2015). It is not fit-for-purpose - it would fail
the validity, reliability and fairness test as it contains outdated information,
meaning the respondents need answer incorrectly to gain a correct mark
(Brooks, 2013; 2015). Thus, simply passing a language test and the Citizenship
Test, which is not fit for purpose, does not ensure that those who pass will have
skills sufficient to engage actively in civic life. This is especially so when one
considers that:
Maximal conceptions require a considerable degree of explicit understanding of
democratic principles, values and procedures on the part of the citizen, together with
5
This is not to say that they do not possess the intellectual capacity for such an understanding in
their native tongues.
14
the dispositions and capacities required for participation in democratic citizenship
generously conceived (McLaughlin 1992, p. 237).
The next section addresses the importance of identity, and what it means to be a
citizen in McLaughlin’s conceptualisation. It examines the contention that
language proficiency with (AE)CE is sufficient in promoting a shared identity of
the migrant into the host nation in a maximal sense.
Identity and language competence
In the minimal concept of identity; citizenship is seen through the lens of the
formal, the legal, and the juridical. Such a status confers on the citizen a certain
civil status, with its associated rights. In contrast, identity in maximal terms
should be considered in dynamic rather than static terms, requiring the citizen to
have
a consciousness of him or herself as a member of a living community with a shared
democratic culture involving obligations and responsibilities as well as rights, a sense of
the common good, fraternity and so on. [This dynamic interpretation of identity] is seen
as a matter for continuing debate and redefinition. It also gives rise to the question of
the extent to which social disadvantage in its various forms can undermine citizenship,
especially when a sense of effective personal agency is seen as a necessary ingredient of
what is at stake (McLaughlin, 1992, p. 236).
This issue of social disadvantage will be considered below in the later section on
social prerequisites. Government policy (Home office, 2002; QCA, 2007) and the
FBV narrative of social integration and promotion of a shared culture and values
15
appear to go some way to align with McLaughlin’s maximal conceptualisaton of
identity. To this end one can argue that the mastering of English language is a
‘strong enabler of integration’ (Casey, 2016), as is the Citizenship Test, for its
purpose is to help the migrant understand British culture and history. Such
knowledge and language competency are an important step toward enabling the
new citizen to eventually bond with her host nation. Creating a bond between
citizenship and nationality goes back to Aristotle, who stated that ‘[t]he citizens
of a state should always be educated to suit the constitution of their state’
(Heater, 1999, p. 171). The reconstruction of the migrant's identity in the new
society is essential and enriches it, and makes it more complex (Griswold, 2011,
p. 618); identity reconstruction enables a deeper understanding of the host
nation’s history, customs, culture, and legal and political systems. Learning the
language of a country is inextricably linked to accessing civil freedom and
understanding its culture and society. As such, it is not unreasonable to believe
that greater knowledge of the host country would facilitate social integration and
acceptance in the host nation.
But what evidence is there for the above suppositions? One would find few
newcomers to any new country who do not understand the importance of
acquiring linguistic competency in order to ‘flourish’ and gain personal agency;
most also understand that learning about the host culture, people and history
can be beneficial. This may explain the persistence of the belief that citizenship
and social integration are not possible without language proficiency in the host
country, however, there is little empirical support for this (Etzioni, 2007). This
idea persists because research on the discourse on citizenship suggests that
language proficiency signifies one as legitimately belonging to a particular
16
community, whether ethnic or national (Griswold, 2011, p. 407). This discourse,
which purports to promote inclusivity and social integration is in fact premised
upon the fact that those speaking other than the dominant national language are
perceived as being outsiders and not truly belonging to the nation (Blackledge,
2003; Bjornson, 2007). This association has led to the targeting of new migrants
with ESOL and CE, instead of tackling failures of integration amongst longstanding minorities. Consequently, it ignores that fact that evidence for the
assumption ‘that speaking languages other than English leads to a breakdown of
social cohesion is hard to come by’ (Simpson and Whiteside, 2012, p. 6). For
example those minorities who participated in the 2001 riots spoke English as
their first language. To conflate ‘the presence of long-standing minority citizens
with newer migrants and refugees’ (Tomlinson, 2008, p. 135), ignores the root
causes of the riots which were not to be found in values and language but instead
in racism, discrimination, poverty, housing, unemployment, education policies,
and class as the root cause of the social unrest (Tomlinson, 2008).6
Nevertheless, this link is constantly alluded to in political discourse; for
example David Blunkett in 2002 wrote about the ‘schizophrenia which bedevils
generational relationships’ in bilingual families (in ibid). Underpinning the
desire for English fluency is an anxiety about ‘incursions’ of foreign cultures and
terrorism (former Prime Minister David Cameron in Mason, 2016) into the
national domestic space; of neighbourhoods (Fortier, 2010), or homes (Byrne,
2013) where English is not spoken. Mandatory language classes and/or tests in
the national language(s) for immigrants are seen as a way to facilitate – or
compel – such integration (Bjornson, 2007). The current narrative of the failure
6
In a recent poll on bias in Britain (The Guardian, 2018), half of ethnic minority respondents felt
treated differently due to their ethnicity. See also The Race Disparity Audit (Cabinet Office, 2017).
17
of multiculturalism and the drive toward assimilation under the guise of
integration through the targeting of specific minorities such as Muslims,
conflates ‘language as an instrument of communication with language as a
symbol of social identification and wholesale cultural identity. There is no room
here for the multilingual speaker who might have multilocal or transnational
attachments and identifications, including in Britain’ (Fortier, 2017). This
narrative is contrary to McLaughlin’s conceptualization of an identity that is
dynamic, changing and open to redefinition via debate. Current discourse denies
the composite nature of identities and that suppressing one aspect of one’s
identity – in terms of one’s nationality, race, religion, gender, profession, class,
political ideology, family, and so on – is akin to cutting/erasing one part of what
makes a person a whole. Consequently, one feels unwelcomed and attacked, and
then begins to identify more with that part of one’s identity which is attacked
(Maalouf, 2000: 26). As Hannah Arendt says, ‘If one is attacked as a Jew, one
must defend oneself as a Jew’ (in Cassin and Brault, 2016, p. 42). But this Arendt
suggests is a political response, ‘purely political.’ ‘There is no essentialization, no
naturalization, no substance, just a simple predicate’ (ibid. Cassin and Brault,
2016, pp. 42–43).
Moreover, the current form of identity construction is predicated upon the
weakening notion of citizenship as being attached to a particular nation, and
ignores the transnational nature of citizenship with the increasing prominence of
international law and supra-national agglomerations such as the EU. Research
conducted by Yuval-Davis (1999) for example emphasises that migrants’ legal
status as citizens of one nation does not preclude their political participation in
another, and Hanauer (2008) argues that such transnational individuals
18
belonging to communities such as the EU would be more interested in the
functional nature of citizenship, i.e. what Stokes (2004) deems the liberal
perspective on citizenship – concerned mainly with the legal status and the
rights of individuals - rather than the republican one. This whole scenario calls
into question the assertion that without language proficiency in the host country,
the new migrant would be unable to participate in civic life or to integrate
socially or culturally (Bjornson, 2007).
The importance of language competency, and knowledge of the host
country’s history, culture, customs and values (through AECE if it is taught
maximally), are undoubtedly an important step toward enabling the new citizen
to eventually bond with her host nation. However, language competency and
AECE alone are insufficient, if it means being forced to give up some of one’s
previous identities. In the present climate, with the rise of nationalism and
hostility toward migrants and ethnic minorities, as exemplified in Brexit, and the
election of people like Trump and Viktor Orban in Hungary, whether any new
citizen would feel a greater bond to their host culture, and inclined to active
citizenship engagement, is questionable. It is discomfiting that a recent Yougov
survey (Smith, 2017) suggests half of Brexit supporters state that gaining
citizenship through naturalisation does not make you British – for these
individuals notions of national identity are inextricably tied to ideas of blood and
soil.7
In the following section I will examine to what extent AECE can encourage
those public virtues that lead to engagement in struggles for social justice and
the empowering of all citizens.
7
For more on this idea, see Bauman (1992)
19
Public virtues and the importance of language competency
In the context of a pluralistic democratic society, the public virtues CE promotes
are not without controversy. Liberal governments have to balance legitimate
unifying influence on society without promoting ‘monism or homogeneity of
public virtues, that lay it open to the charge of indoctrination. Conversely, not
promoting a set of shared public values, may contribute to the disintegration of
society itself.8 As McLaughlin (1992, p. 241) argued, these are not abstract
notions but vital to the kind of society that we wish to inhabit and maintain; their
articulation through CE are crucial in a pluralistic democratic society. For
McLaughlin virtues maximally conceived imply engagement in struggles for
justice ‘and to work for the sort of social conditions that will lead to the
empowerment of all citizens’ (1992, p. 237), whereas minimally conceived imply
being law-abiding and helping one’s neighbour. This point as McLaughlin states
is of course linked to the level of political participation that is deemed
appropriate for citizens, and this in turn is dependent upon whether one holds to
the maximal, or minimal conceptualisation of citizenship.
Should one conceive of AECE in maximal terms (Crick’s intent) then I would
argue that the AECE on offer is unlikely to empower, liberate or lead to the
political and social agency of the migrant. The idea of needing to learn English
(AECE) in order to access one’s rights, to become a fully participatory citizen and
avoid marginalisation is a simplistic notion if the underlying discriminations and
structural inequalities are not addressed. Initially, the need to speak English was
couched under the liberal terminology of social cohesion, but has now given way
8
For more on this see Callan (1997)
20
to a ‘[s]ustained rhetoric insisting that migrants have an obligation (rather than a
right) to learn English, which grew in pitch under Prime Minister Blair’s Labour
Government in the UK, [and] has continued under the Coalition’ (Simpson and
Whiteside, 2012, p. 6), and subsequent governments. Thus there is a deep
suspicion of some communities, especially of Muslims, as not desiring to
integrate.
There is a ‘European-wide moral panic about “difference”’ (Grillo 2007 in
Byrne, 2017, p. 324). There is a worry that fostering and celebrating too much
difference leads to the weakening of national unity and national culture which
needs to be preserved. Many minorities are perceived as living separate lives
without having a sense of ‘Britishness’ to foster national sentiment. This
perception contradicts the report on The Impacts of Migration on Social
Cohesion’s (2012, p. 2) analysis that regarding a sense of belonging to Britain,
migrants score more highly than native-born, native-heritage Britons. There is
an undoubted tension between promoting diversity and unity, but by denying
the idea of multiculturalism, we are trying to erase an important element in the
identity of many migrants and minorities. To deal with this tension is a necessity,
especially as this tension has heightened post-Brexit, and the rise in nationalism
in Britain and Europe has helped the far right and populists to propagate a
narrative of Europe as ‘a besieged fortress … forever threatened by trespassing
of enemies, dilution, slackening of vigilance’ (Bauman, 1992, pp. 678–79) –
swamped by antithetical cultures. For McLaughlin, the way to deal with this
tension was to advocate a public debate to define shared values within a diverse
society, suggesting that we need to reach agreement on public virtues and the
common good.
21
To blame multicultural tolerance and celebration of diversity as being
responsible for too much separation, and of preventing a more forceful response
toward those who are perceived to be hostile to Christianity and Western
culture, is to deny the pluralistic nature of modern societies. The reality of
transnationalism and super-diversity (Vertovec, 2007), the existence of supraidentities such as EU citizenship, and powerful multinational corporations means
‘[m]embership is more fluid and transcends national or regional borders’
(Abowitz and Harnish, 2006, p. 675), and makes the idea of fostering national
identity seem rather parochial. It is wrong to view diversity as ‘disintegrative or
a fault to be overcome’ (Figueroa, 2000, p. 54) but should be seen as an ideal. For
Figueroa, encounter with the other is natural to human experience, and
consequently citizenship should promote commitment to the society in its
diversity; openness to, solidarity with, and respect for the different other;
acceptance of the basic worth of all people; rejection of any form of exploitation,
inequitable treatment or racism is important (Figueroa, 2000, p. 57).
Social prerequisites
For McLaughlin, a maximal concept of social prerequisites for citizenship has to
go beyond the minimal approaches, which merely grant the formal legal status
described earlier; it must take into consideration social disadvantage, and
acknowledge the diverse nature of Britain society, and the imposition of monism
to be rejected. This requires a real debate as to the social prerequisites needed to
give recognition to the plural nature of British society. The Parekh Report
(Runnymede 2000: 105, 107) carrying forward McLaughlin’s debate advocated
the reimagining of multicultural Britain as a ‘community of communities’,
22
predicated upon a combination of five tasks:
(a) reimagining Britain's past story and present identity,
(b) balancing equality and difference, liberty and cohesion, . . .
(c) confronting and eliminating racisms . . .
(d) reducing material inequalities and
(e) building a human rights culture.
The Report sought to disentangle Britishness from Englishness, viewing
Britain as a shared nation rather than one dominated by or belonging to any
particular group. However, as the rhetoric of scapegoating multiculturalism for
the disintegration of society (due to a perceived lack of shared public virtues)
has gained momentum, the suspicion and targeting of minorities and difference,
has resulted in the conflation of native ethnic minorities with new migrants. Such
suspicion and targeting of certain communities has alienated them, and is
unlikely to make them feel ‘at home’, as envisaged by Cantle (2001). But, to
impose monism or homogeneity of belief, practice and values in such a diverse
society such as England’s, borders on a new form of imperialism; the dominant
culture (invariably Western) deems itself progressive, and the rest as archaic.
More insidious yet, the narrative of English for integration devalorises the
subject who speaks other languages, sometimes several other (Fortier, 2017). Or
as Sneja Gunew says (Fortier, 2017), the first language of some migrants is
‘rendered alien, shameful, transgressive, particularly if it is outside the
acceptable repertoire of “foreign languages”’. In the current post-Brexit and post9/11 securitised politics of language, speaking other languages whether at home
23
or in the streets has ‘become associated with non-assimilable alterity and
danger’ (Fortier, 2017).
The superficial perception by some policymakers and media is of ethnic
minorities’ reluctance to integrate and learn the language, rather than looking
deeper, to discrimination, poverty, housing, unemployment, and so forth. Instead
of addressing such issues, successive governments under the learning economy
hegemony have viewed adult learning as an important lever for economic
growth and global competitiveness. Language skills are equated with economic
success, with the onus on the individual to make good the literacy deficit to
improve her economic lot. The current problem with lifelong learning (including
AECE) is that ‘it converts deep-seated economic problems into short-lived
educational projects’ (Coffield, 1999).
Conclusion
Any answer to my preliminary questions: ‘what does it mean to be a citizen?’ and
‘is it possible for various ethnic communities to do more than simply exist?’,
depends on one’s conception of the citizen and that depends on your
philosophical leaning: whether you hold her in liberal terms as citizenship-aslegal-status, or the civic republican citizenship-as-desirable-activity. Crick’s
intention was ‘maximal’: in order to transform the political culture of Britain, he
wanted existing citizens to become more politically literate and active in civic
engagement, and this he also intended for migrants and new citizens. So how has
his vision faired? It is undeniable that linguistic competency is vital for accessing
one’s civil freedoms: exercising political power both as a citizen and as an
informed elector, and for social integration, sharing ‘the social heritage in its
24
wholeness and to live … according to the standards prevailing in society’
(Marshall and Bottomore, 1992, p. 59). However, in order for the new citizen to
fully participate as an active member, it is not sufficient for her to master the
language of the host country, for that in itself does not make her fully conversant
with her civil, political and social rights, as well as her obligations as a citizen.
What makes a difference is having proper knowledge and understanding of the
social, legal and political systems of the host country and being equipped with
the skills and aptitudes to make full use of this knowledge and understanding.
This was the purpose of CE and AECE as articulated in the Crick report (2003).
Unfortunately, the teaching of AECE (and CE) has been undermined. AECE
can be instrumental in addressing issues of social cohesion and integration, but
for this to happen, AECE needs to be given more prominence in the ESOL Adult
Curriculum, and neither diluted nor superseded as it is currently by
Fundamental British Values. AECE also needs greater focus and definition to
develop in teachers a ‘shared sense of what the subject is for if they are to teach
it well and not merely follow prescribed procedures (Tate, in Mclaughlin 2000, p.
560). It should be taught by subject specialists, or by ESOL teachers trained
adequately to deliver the citizenship components of the curriculum.
However, even if these elements were in place, there remains a fundamental
problem: citizenship is being taught to two groups: those in compulsory
education, and migrants from non-EU countries; this has resulted in 43% of
migrants (i.e. those from the EU) being exempt from CE (ONS, 2013). Moreover,
let us suppose that AECE were to deliver a comprehensive and effective
understanding as well as the desire to live a life of active citizenship. How does
this enhance the migrant’s integration into British society, communities and
25
workplaces when the majority of the adults with whom they will interact have
had not one single lesson in their entire lives about concepts of citizenship?
For CE (and AECE) to change the culture of this country, as Crick envisaged to foster greater social cohesion, rather than simply coexisting, and to reduce the
democratic deficit by having a politically active polity - it is essential that CE be
taught to all migrants, and all native adults, for it makes no sense to have the
majority native adult population of the UK ignorant of what citizenship means.
Alternatively, if the true intent of AECE was to promote a ‘minimal’
conceptualisation of citizenship, then competency in English language is a
prerequisite for the migrants’ economic prosperity, and provides an interface
with the wider British society.
However, contrary to political rhetoric, language fluency and AECE are
insufficient in themselves to foster integration, engender greater civic
participation and prevent social exclusion. AECE should not be seen as being the
panacea for such deficiencies as the democratic deficit and all-pervasive social
inequalities - it is not a fix-it-all (Halsey, 1972; Martin, 2003). If we are serious
about promoting an active democratic citizenry with its concomitants of social
inclusion and equity, then we must also look at what is ‘being done to close the
yawning gap between those citizens at the top and those at the bottom of our
social and economic system?’ (Martin, 2003, p. 572). We must ‘ask some hard …
questions about the relationship between the social, political and cultural axes of
citizenship’ in order to prevent citizenship becoming a mechanism of exclusion
(in ibid, p. 574). Without this, CE will perpetually reflect and reinforce the major
social divisions of power vis-à-vis class, gender and ‘race’, and systematically
exclude many ‘others’ (ibid). However, if taught in a maximal way that
26
encourages the reimagining of multicultural Britain as a ‘community of
communities’ predicated upon a combination of the five elements recommended
by the Parekh Report, AECE can be a stepping stone to greater social and political
emancipation, and activism as envisaged by Crick.
Word Count : 6930 (excluding references)
27
References
Abowitz, K. K. and Harnish, J. (2006) ‘Contemporary Discourses of Citizenship’,
Review of Educational Research. SAGE Publications, 76(4), pp. 653–690. doi:
10.3102/00346543076004653.
Bauman, Z. (1992) ‘Soil, Blood and Identity’, The Sociological Review. London,
England: SAGE Publications, 40(4), pp. 675–701. doi: 10.1111/j.1467954X.1992.tb00407.x.
Benton, T. et al. (2008) [CELS] Citizenship Educational Longitudinal Study 6th
report. Young People’s Civic Participation In and Beyond School: Attitudes,
Intentions and Influences (DCSF Research Report 052). London: DCSF.
Bjornson, M. (2007) ‘Speaking of citizenship: Language ideologies in Dutch
citizenship regimes’, Focaal. Berghahn Journals, 2007(49), pp. 65–80. doi:
10.3167/foc.2007.490106.
Blackledge, A. (2003) ‘Imagining a Monocultural Community: Racialization of
Cultural Practice in Educational Discourse’, Journal of Language, Identity
and Education, 2(4), pp. 331–347. doi: 10.1207/S15327701JLIE0204_7.
Breslin, T. (2005) ‘Education for citizenship: towards a new literacy for all?’,
Reflect: the magazine of NRDC. London: NRDC, 3, p. 21.
Brooks, T. (2013) The ‘Life in the United Kingdom’ Citizenship Test: Is It Unfit for
Purpose? Durham: Durham University.
Byrne, B. (2013) Neurotic Britishness: why are we threatened by the multi-lingual
home?, OpenDemocracyUK. Available at:
https://www.opendemocracy.net/ourkingdom/bridget-byrne/neuroticbritishness-why-are-we-threatened-by-multi-lingual-home (Accessed: 27
28
March 2018).
Byrne, B. (2017) ‘Testing Times: The Place of the Citizenship Test in the UK
Immigration Regime and New Citizens’ Responses to it’, Sociology. SAGE
Publications, 51(2), pp. 323–338. doi: 10.1177/0038038515622908.
Cabinet Office (2017) Race Disparity Audit: Summary Findings from the Ethnicity
Facts and Figures website. London.
Callan, E. (1997) Creating citizens: Political education and liberal democracy.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Cantle, T. (2001) Community Cohesion: a Report of the Independent Review Team.
London: Home Office.
Casey, L. (2016) The Casey Review A review into opportunity and integration.
London.
Cassin, B. and Brault, P.-A. (2016) Nostalgia : when are we ever at home? 1st ed.
New York: Fordham University Press.
Coffield, F. (1999) ‘Breaking the Consensus: lifelong learning as social control’,
British Educational Research Journal. Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 25(4), pp.
479–499. doi: 10.1080/0141192990250405.
Constant, B. (1819) The Liberty of Ancients Compared with that of Moderns, Online
Library of Liberty. Available at: http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/constantthe-liberty-of-ancients-compared-with-that-of-moderns-1819 (Accessed: 9
July 2017).
Crick, B. (2000) Citizenship for 16-19 year olds in education and training: report of
the Advisory Group to the Secretary of State for Education and Employment.
London: Home Office.
Crick, B. (2003) The New and the Old: The Report of the ‘Life in the United
29
Kingdom’ Advisory Group. Translated by G. E. Bevan. London: Home Office.
Crick, B. and Advisory Group on Citizenship (1998) Education for citizenship and
the teaching of democracy in schools. Final report, 22 September 1998.
London: Qualifications and Curriculum Authority.
Denham, J. (2001) Building cohesive communities, report of the ministerial group
on public order and community cohesion. London: Home Office.
Etzioni, A. (2007) ‘Citizenship Tests: A Comparative, Communitarian
Perspective’, The Political Quarterly. Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 78(3), pp.
353–363. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-923X.2007.00864.x.
Faure, E. et al. (1972) Learning to Be: The World of Education Today and
Tomorrow. Paris: UNESCO.
Figueroa, P. (2000) ‘Citizenship education for a plural society’, in Osler, A. (ed.)
Citizenship and democracy in schools : diversity, identity, equality. Stoke-onTrent: Trentham, pp. 47–62.
Fortier, A.-M. (2010) ‘Proximity by design? Affective citizenship and the
management of unease’, Citizenship Studies. Taylor & Francis Group, 14(1),
pp. 17–30. doi: 10.1080/13621020903466258.
Fortier, A.-M. (2017) ‘On (Not) Speaking English: Colonial Legacies in Language
Requirements for British Citizenship’, Sociology. SAGE Publications. doi:
10.1177/0038038517742854.
Galston, W. A. (1989) ‘Civic Education in the Liberal State’, in Rosenblum, N. L.
(ed.) Liberalism and the Moral Life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, pp. 89--101.
Galston, W. A. (1991) Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal
State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
30
Griswold, O. V. (2011) ‘The English you need to know: Language ideology in a
citizenship classroom’, Linguistics and Education, 22(4), pp. 406–418. doi:
10.1016/j.linged.2011.08.001.
Halsey, A. H. (1972) Educational Priority: EPA Problems And Policies: Report of a
Research Project Sponsored by the Department of Education and Science and
The Social Science Research Council Volume 1. London: HMSO.
Han, C., Starkey, H. and Green, A. (2010) ‘The politics of ESOL (English for
speakers of other languages): implications for citizenship and social
justice’, International Journal of Lifelong Education. Routledge, 29(1), pp.
63–76. doi: 10.1080/02601370903471304.
Hanauer, D. I. (2008) ‘Non-Place Identity: Britain’s Response to Migration in the
Age of Supermodernity’, in Delanty, G., Wodak, R., and Jones, P. (eds)
Identity, Belonging and Migration. Liverpool: Liverpool University Press, pp.
198–218.
Heater, D. B. (1999) What is citizenship? Polity Press.
HM Government (2011) Prevent strategy. Cm 8092. London: The Stationery
Office.
Home Office. (2013) Life in the United Kingdom : A Guide for New Residents.
London: TSO.
Home Office (2002) Secure borders, safe haven : integration with diversity in
modern Britain. Norwich: Stationery Office.
Jerome, L. (2012) England’s Citizenship Education Experiment: State, School and
Student Perspectives. London: Bloomsbury.
Keating, A. et al. (2010) Citizenship education in England 2001-2010: young
people’s practices and prospects for the future: The eighth and final report
31
from the Citizenship Education Longitudinal Study (CELS). London: DfE.
Keating, A. and Kerr, D. (2013) ‘Putting participation into practice: re-evaluating
the implementation of the Citizenship curriculum in England’, in Hedtke, R.
and Zimenkova, T. (eds) Education for Civic and Political Participation: A
Critical Approach. London: Routledge.
Kocanova, D., Bourgeois, A. and de Almeida Coutinho, A. S. (2015) Adult
Education and Training in Europe: Widening Access to Learning
Opportunities - Eurydice Report. Education, Audiovisual and Culture
Executive Agency, European Commission.
Kymlicka, W. (1996) Multicultural citizenship : A Liberal Theory of Minority
Rights. Oxford: OUP.
Kymlicka, W. (1999) ‘Education for citizenship’, in Halstead, J. M. and
McLaughlin, T. H. (eds) Education in morality. Routledge, pp. 86–111.
Maalouf, A. (2000) On Identity. Translated by B. Bray. London: The Harvill Press.
Marshall, T. H. and Bottomore, T. (1992) Citizenship and social class. London:
Pluto Press.
Martin, I. (2003) ‘Adult education, lifelong learning and citizenship: some ifs and
buts’, International Journal of Lifelong Education. Taylor & Francis Ltd,
22(6), pp. 566–579. doi: 10.1080/0260137032000138130.
Maslow, A. H. (1954) Motivation and personality. Oxford: Harper.
Mason, R. (2016) ‘Migrant spouses who fail English test may have to leave UK,
says Cameron’, The Guardian, 18 January.
McLaughlin, T. H. (1992) ‘Citizenship, Diversity and Education: a philosophical
perspective’, Journal of Moral Education, 21(3), pp. 235–250. doi:
10.1080/0305724920210307.
32
McLaughlin, T. H. (2000) ‘Citizenship Education in England: The Crick Report
and Beyond’, Journal of the Philosophy of Education, 34(4), pp. 541–570.
doi: 10.1111/1467-9752.00194.
Mouffe, C. (1992) ‘Democratic citizenship and the political community’, in
Dimensions of radical democracy: Pluralism, citizenship, community, pp.
225–239.
OECD (1996) Lifelong Learning for All. Paris: OECD.
ONS (2013) Provisional Long Term International Migration (LTIM) estimates Jun
2013.
Potter, J. (2002) ‘The challenge of education for active citizenship’, Education +
Training, 44(2), pp. 57–66. doi: 10.1108/00400910210419955.
Saggar, S. et al. (2012) Impact of migration on social cohesion and integration.
Final report to the Migration Advisory Committee, January 2012. London:
Home Office.
Simpson, J. and Whiteside, A. (2012) ‘Politics, policy and practice: ESOL in the UK
and the USA’, King’s College London Working Papers in Urban Language &
Literacies. London, WP87.
Smith, M. (2017) Half of Leave voters say getting British citizenship doesn’t make
you British, YouGov. Available at:
https://yougov.co.uk/news/2017/11/10/getting-british-citizenshipdoesnt-make-you-britis/ (Accessed: 8 March 2018).
Stokes, G. (2004) ‘Transnational Citizenship: Problems of Definition, Culture and
Democracy’, Cambridge Review of International Affairs, 17(1), pp. 119–135.
doi: 10.1080/0955757042000203687.
The Guardian (2018) Bias in Britain: explore the poll results, The Guardian.
33
Available at: https://www.theguardian.com/uk-news/nginteractive/2018/dec/02/bias-in-britain-explore-the-poll-results
(Accessed: 5 December 2018).
Tomlinson, S. (2008) Race and Education: Policy and Politics in Britain. McGrawHill Education (UK).
Tooley, J. (2000) Reclaiming education. London: Cassell.
UIE (1997) Adult Education: The Hamburg Declaration – The Agenda for the
future. Fifth International Conference on Adult Education 14 - 18 July.
Available at: http://uil.unesco.org/adult-education/confintea/adulteducation-hamburg-declaration-agenda-future.
Vertovec, S. (2007) ‘Super-diversity and its implications’, Ethnic and Racial
Studies. Taylor & Francis Group, 30(6), pp. 1024–1054. doi:
10.1080/01419870701599465.
Walzer, M. (1983) Spheres Of Justice: A Defense Of Pluralism And Equality. New
York: Basic Books.
Young, I. M. (1989) ‘Polity and Group Difference: A Critique of the Ideal of
Universal Citizenship’, Ethics. University of Chicago Press, 99(2), pp. 250–
274. doi: 10.1086/293065.
Yuval-Davis, N. (1999) ‘The “Multi-Layered Citizen”’, International Feminist
Journal of Politics. Taylor & Francis, 1(1), pp. 119–136. doi:
10.1080/146167499360068.
34