Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader (review)
Patrick S. O'Donnell
Philosophy East and West, Volume 57, Number 3, July 2007, pp. 400-405 (Review)
Published by University of Hawai'i Press
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.2007.0036
For additional information about this article
https://muse.jhu.edu/article/217398
[ Access provided at 17 Mar 2022 19:48 GMT with no institutional affiliation ]
Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader. Edited by Martin D. Yaffe. Lanham,
MD: Lexington Books, 2001. Pp. ix þ 422. Paper.
Reviewed by Patrick S. O’Donnell
Santa Barbara City College
Judaism and Environmental Ethics: A Reader, edited by Martin D. Yaffe, is an anthology that endeavors to represent fairly the ‘‘state-of-the-art’’ on Judaism and environmental ethics in a philosophically respectable manner. In large measure, it succeeds.
The majority of its essays, first published in journals of Judaic studies and environmental ethics, are from the 1990s, while the earliest, from the forester and founder
of the Wilderness Society, Aldo Leopold (1887–1949), dates from 1920. Max Oelschlaeger rightly describes Leopold as ‘‘perhaps the most influential environmental
ethicist in American history’’ (1994, p. 3), an accolade owing principally to the
conclusion of his posthumously published book, A Sand County Almanac (1949).
However prescient and provocative, Leopold’s ‘‘land ethic’’ was never expressed in
anything close to a systematic ethical theory. The holistic environmental ethic that
did take shape drew sustenance from embryonic ecological sciences, reflections
on his wilderness experiences, and, interestingly, an English translation of Tertium
Organum (1912) by the Russian philosopher and mystic P. D. Ouspensky (1878–
1947). Oddly, the essay by Leopold selected for this reader, ‘‘The Forestry of the
Prophets,’’ was written some years prior to the full flowering of an ecological and
environmental ethic that envisioned species functioning, in one of ‘‘[his] favorite
metaphors, like parts of an engine’’ (Nash 1989, p. 64). Moreover, his ‘‘land
ethic’’—and here we detect the influence of Ouspensky—intimated something akin
to the Gaia hypothesis later formulated by the scientist James Lovelock, in which our
planet as a whole has the properties of a cybernetic-like self-correcting system and a
living organism. Given the anthology’s avowed aims, this essay has little to recommend it save the tongue-in-cheek appreciation by a modern forester of the of the biblical prophets’ practical knowledge of forestry.
The editor, Martin Yaffe, is Professor of Philosophy and Religion Studies at the
University of North Texas, now home to the Center for Environmental Philosophy
(publisher of the journal Environmental Ethics). Perhaps the essay by Leopold mentioned above was included to compensate for the drubbing Leopold suffers in Yaffe’s
rather long introductory survey to this anthology. Yaffe takes Leopold to task for venturing beyond ‘‘his own technical discipline forest ecology’’ in order ‘‘to criticize the
ethical principles he claims to find in the Hebrew Bible,’’ principles Leopold found
wanting in his imaginative (but not unprecedented) attempt to extend the compass of
urgent moral concern and ethical consideration to include animate and inanimate
(inorganic) objects and processes of the natural environment. To be sure, Leopold’s
writings display the virtues and vices that frequently attend the work of ‘‘public intellectuals’’ with little fealty to disciplinary expertise outside their own area(s) of specialization. Leopold wrote in the first instance neither as an ethicist nor as a biblical
scholar well-versed in hermeneutics; hence one is not surprised to learn that his ‘‘alltoo-hasty critique of what he takes to be the biblical view is highly selective and
dubious.’’
400
Philosophy East & West Volume 57, Number 3 July 2007 400–405
> 2007 by University of Hawai‘i Press
Impressionistic biblical interpretation is likewise found in the work of such historians as Arnold Toynbee and Lynn White, Jr., for they, too, have made, in Yaffe’s
words, ‘‘the same dubious charge that the Bible is ecologically unfriendly.’’ Well
known among ecologists and environmental ethicists, White’s 1967 Science article
‘‘The Historic Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis’’ argued that biblical rhetoric countenanced if not directly contributed to the development of Christianity ‘‘into the most
anthropocentric religion the world has ever seen’’ (White 1967, p. 25). Anthropomorphism is disturbing to environmentalists insofar as it is understood to encourage
an image of human beings as ‘‘masters’’ of the natural world, the products and
inhabitants of which are designed (merely) to serve our interests and needs—such
instrumentalist (i.e., non-intrinsic) valuation thought invariably to sanction ecological degradation, including the devastating exploitation of natural resources, as well
as the deeply troubling ill-treatment of (nonhuman) animals on a massive scale (on
this, see Singer 1990). And yet there are environmental ethicists who do not dismiss
certain species of anthropocentrism: ‘‘For example, strong reasons may exist to protect the environment out of obligations that we have to human future generations
to protect their welfare and not saddle them with environmental harms’’ (Light and
Rolston 2003, p. 9).
Just what is at stake in the question of anthropocentrism versus nonanthropocentrism can be gleaned from the following from Andrew Light and Avner de-Shalit:
The underlying assumption of almost all nonanthropocentrists is that nonanthropocentrism must be developed as an alternative worldview because most people are anthropocentrists. (This is in fact why many environmental philosophers feel there is a philosophical dimension to environmental problems: the history of Western philosophy has been
successful in developing the faulty worldviews that assert that only humans have the
kind of value that generates moral obligations.) Thus, the nonanthropocentrist advocating
the intrinsic value of nature cannot rest after making a persuasive case to other environmental philosophers of the truth of his or her views. The case must also be persuasive to
people who do not count themselves as nonanthropocentrists. It must be a case compelling enough to persuade anthropocentrists that they should accept the shift in burden of
proof (or burden of protection) that is made manifest through a claim to the nonanthropocentric intrinsic value of nature. But that is surely a higher hurdle of persuasion than starting with an acceptance of the anthropocentric terrain and arguing from within that framework that there are more values at stake in an environmental controversy than just pure
economic values in favor of development. (Light and de-Shalit 2003, pp. 6–7)
As Light and de-Shalit proceed to point out, environmental activists, lawyers, and
policy makers ‘‘must speak to the opposition in the opposition’s own largely anthropocentric terms or fail to be granted a hearing at all.’’
White was well aware that biblical verses were open to different, more nuanced
or sophisticated interpretations:
[White] was perfectly willing to concede that Christians [and presumably Jews as well]
of the 1960s might form a commitment to environmental responsibility from their reading of Genesis. He agreed that there was a biblical basis for environmentalism. But his
Book Reviews
401
point was that for nearly two thousand years the Christian tradition had not been so construed. Instead people used Scripture to justify the exploitation of nature in the same
way defenders of slavery used it to justify ownership and exploitation of certain classes
of humans. (Nash 1989, p. 89)
White’s argument remains plausible, although, at times, he appears to confuse
correlation with causation, if not committing the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy,
to wit: ‘‘modern science is an extrapolation of natural theology and . . . modern technology is at least partly to be explained as an Occidental, voluntarist realization of
the Christian dogma of man’s transcendence of, and rightful mastery over, nature’’
(White 1967, p. 27). Commenting on White’s interpretation of Genesis 1 : 28, Jeremy
Cohen’s essay contends that ‘‘premodern readers of the verse, Jews and Christians,
found in it relatively little bearing on the natural environment and its exploitation.’’
Apart from its anachronistic interpretation of biblical passages, White’s essay leaves
us in the dark as to the specific historical agents responsible for invoking and
entrenching the biblical passages under discussion. It becomes, in the end, impossible to ascertain precisely the burden of guilt that Christianity in general and the Hebrew Bible in particular must assume for the contemporary global ecological crisis,
including the effects of global warming, deforestation, shortages of fresh water supplies, soil erosion, a species extinction rate at its highest point in 65 million years
(hence a precipitous decline in biodiversity), and so forth and so on.
Illustrating the psychologist’s availability heuristic, Richard Lazarus observes that
‘‘in many respects, the quality of the natural environment in the United States is better on an absolute scale than it was over three decades ago, notwithstanding the tremendous increases in [economic] activity during the same period’’ (2004, p. xiv). In
other words, Lake Erie is not dead, smog levels have visibly declined in Los Angeles,
the Cuyahoga River is no longer burning, and, what is more, ‘‘the issues . . . of what
might be called the ‘second environmental crisis,’ are more genuinely global in
scope’’ (Goodin 1992, p. 4)—meaning, in effect, that the environmentalist’s case before the North American public regarding the urgency of the environmental crisis has
become immeasurably more difficult to make, a difficulty compounded by the fact
that the environmental consequences of current production practices and consumption activity are long-term and hard to calculate accurately.
Dale Jamieson (2002) has exquisitely captured the heart of the problem, one
in which the philosopher’s training becomes apposite if we believe the problem
amenable to reason: ‘‘Our moral psychology . . . is remarkably unresponsive to
large-scale issues, especially those that involve people and events that are not close
at hand’’ (p. 34). Media attention may mean that we respond to distant strangers
suffering from tsunamis, hurricanes, and earthquakes, but the public’s—and the
media’s—attention is notoriously short-lived: an entire generation has forgotten
Bhopal, Chernobyl, and the Exxon Valdez. Perhaps the lesson to be derived from
White’s essay, whatever the shortcomings of the actual argument, is simply that
Hebrew scripture and Christian dogma have to this point proven rhetorically and
practically impotent in the face of the Promethean conquest of nature. It thus
behooves Jews and Christians alike to redeem their traditions, to articulate a reli-
402
Philosophy East & West
giously grounded environmental ethic of stewardship or trusteeship that is ecologically sound and environmentally sustainable. Furthermore, Jews and Christians
might want to respond to the appropriation of dominion theology in an apocalyptic
key by the so-called Wise Use movement (see Hendricks 2005). New Christian Right
Reconstructionism is dominion theology with a vengeance, a pressing concern when
Time/CNN and Newsweek polls find that well over 50 percent of respondents subscribe, literally, to the apocalyptic prophecies of the Book of Revelation.
Yaffe’s introductory essay and assessment of the contributions to this volume is
quite thorough—indeed, to a fault, for what is best served as an appetizer or hors
d’oeuvre is more like the main course itself. That is to say, all but the most diligent
reader or academic specialist may finish the introduction wondering if there is any
need to peruse the individual contributions themselves. A less detailed analysis of
each essay might have been replaced by a discussion that locates the anthology
within the larger contexts of the ‘‘greening of religions,’’ recent developments in environmental ethics (and here I would include attempts to incorporate the array of
capital assets found in nature within economic reasoning; see, e.g., Partha Dasgupta’s Human Well-Being and the Natural Environment [2002]), and the variegated
worldviews and philosophies circulating in and around the environmental movement: ‘‘deep’’ and ‘‘reverential’’ ecologies, social ecology, red-green philosophies,
eco-feminism, eco-pragmatism, reformist (professional) environmentalism, postmodern bioregionalism, process theology, eco-fascism, and so forth (cf. Zimmerman
1994).
Eric Katz’ essay attempts to link genocide and ecocide with the concept of
‘‘domination’’ in a manner similar to the employment of this concept in Bookchin’s
Ecology of Freedom (Bookchin 1982) and some ecofeminist literature. Unfortunately,
the concept of domination is nowhere analyzed or clearly spelled out (much like the
concept of ‘‘exploitation’’ was for a time in the Marxist literature), and passages
such as the following are closer to an assertion than an argument: ‘‘Anthropocentrism [in which ‘‘human interests, satisfaction, goods, and happiness are the goals
of public policy and human action’’] as a worldview quite easily leads to the practices of domination, even when such domination is not articulated.’’ Insofar as one
can tease out the pertinent premises, they are of the tenuous, slippery-slope variety.
Katz even detects nefarious motives behind the practice of ecological restoration of
degraded ecosystems (restored to a semblance of their original states) as a result of its
permeation by ‘‘anthropocentric ideology’’: ‘‘we relieve our guilt for the earlier destruction of natural systems, and we demonstrate our power—the power of science
and technology—over the natural world.’’ Elsewhere, Katz has gone so far as to argue that ‘‘the practice of ecological restoration can only represent misguided faith in
the hegemony and infallibility of the human power to control the world’’ (quoted in
Light and Rolston 2003, p. 399). Andrew Light has elsewhere provided us with a lucid critique of Katz’ argument against both the idea that we can restore nature and
the practice of attempting to restore it (ibid., pp. 398–411).
Jeanne Kay’s ‘‘Concepts of Nature in the Hebrew Bible’’ suggests that any environmental ethic of Jewish pedigree will need to confront seemingly incontrovertible
Book Reviews
403
theological propositions found in the text: that creation is in a covenantal relation
with the Creator; that the biblical concept of nature is strongly anthropocentric; that
nature is God’s instrument of divine award and retribution, ‘‘and its beneficence
depends on human morality’’ (therefore, ‘‘humans indirectly bring about environmental destruction as the outcome of sin, or . . . directly through foolish arrogance’’);
that God manifests Himself in ‘‘natural theophanies’’; and, finally, that ‘‘nature in the
Bible may be loved for its beauty, its utility, or its unfathomable ways, but . . . it [is]
incapable in itself of sustaining life.’’ That said, and as evidenced in more than a few
of the essays, Jews can rely on their religious and philosophical traditions for the
conceptual resources with which to construct an environmental ethic. Among these
conceptual resources we count the halakhic principle of bal tashchit (‘‘you must
not destroy’’), extrapolated—rabbinically extended—so as to entail ‘‘the demand
for acute environmental sensitivity’’ (Jeremy Cohen); God’s ownership of the land,
meaning that we are stewards or trustees of the land and its bounty, ‘‘hence we discover that the care of the natural world . . . was an implicit part of [the] rabbinic
image of the good person’’ (David Ehrenfeld and Philip J. Bentley); the prohibition
against causing tza ‘ar ba’alei chayyim (the ‘‘pain of living things’’), which some
have interpreted to imply an abstention from killing animals, and thus an argument
for vegetarianism; and observance of the sabbatical (shevi’it) and jubilee years (in
Yaffe’s words, ‘‘correctly understood and applied’’).
Yaffe’s decision to include Steven Schwarzschild’s ‘‘The Unnatural Jew’’ is especially commendable, for it clearly goes against the current. According to Schwarzschild, ‘‘Jewish philosophy (in the exilic age) has paradigmatically defined Jewishness
as alienation from and confrontation with nature.’’ To the extent that this generalization may be true, it is further testament to the obstacles that must be overcome by
Jews committed to the greening of their religion. In one sense, Schwarzschild has
proffered an explanation for the fact that
the Jewish voice has joined the environmental movement relatively recently. Jews are not
among the leaders of the environmental movement, and environmental activists who are
Jews by birth have not developed their stance on the basis of Judaism. With the marked
exception of the Bible, the literary sources of Judaism have remained practically unknown to environmental thinkers, and Jewish values have only marginally inspired environmental thinking or policies. (Tirosh-Samuelson 2002)
In addition to the oft-cited ‘‘urban character’’ of diasporic Judaism, the dearth of
Jewish philosophical reflections on the natural world has been attributed to the intellectual and ethical attention given to the Holocaust; the nature of Zionism; the IsraeliArab conflict, and especially the Israeli-Palestinian conflict; the Jewish-Catholic
dialogue; and the meaning(s) of secular or cultural Judaism.
In conclusion, this anthology, alongside a volume generated from a series of
conferences on religions and ecology held from 1996 to 1998 at the Harvard Center
for the Study of World Religions (Tirosh-Samuelson 2002), convincingly demonstrates that Judaism is capable of formulating an ecological theology and environmental ethic relevant to the contemporary global environmental crisis, assuming
404
Philosophy East & West
here that the value systems of religions are essential to mobilizing people to care
for the environment (be it natural or unnatural) and to preserving environmental
resources, ecosystems, and biodiversity for future generations.
References
Bookchin, Murray. 1982. The Ecology of Freedom: The Emergence and Dissolution of Hierarchy. Palo Alto, CA: Cheshire Books.
Dasgupta, Partha. 2001. Human Well-Being and the Natural Environment. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Goodin, Robert E. 1992. Green Political Theory. Oxford, UK: Polity Press / Blackwell.
Hendricks, Stephenie. 2005. Divine Destruction: Wise Use, Dominion Theology, and the
Making of Environmental Policy. Hoboken, NJ: Melville House.
Jamieson, Dale. 2002. Morality’s Progress: Essays on Humans, Other Animals, and the Rest of
Nature. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
Lazarus, Richard J. 2004. The Making of Environmental Law. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Light, Andrew, and Avner de-Shalit. 2003. Moral and Political Reasoning in Environmental
Practice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Light, Andrew, and Holmes Rolston III, eds. 2003. Environmental Ethics: An Anthology.
Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Nash, Roderick. 1989. The Rights of Nature: A History of Environmental Ethics. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Oelschlaeger, Max. 1994. Caring for Creation: An Ecumenical Approach to the Environmental
Crisis. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Singer, Peter. 1990. Animal Liberation. New York: New York Review of Books.
Tirosh-Samuelson, Hava, ed. 2002. Judaism and Ecology: Created World and Revealed Word.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, for the Center for the Study of World Religions, Harvard Divinity School.
White, Lynn, Jr. 1967. ‘‘The Historic Roots of Our Ecologic Crisis,’’ Science 155 : 1203–1207.
Reprinted in Ian G. Barbour, ed., Western Man and Environmental Ethics. Reading, MA:
Addison-Wesley, 1973.
Zimmerman, Michael E. 1994. Contesting Earth’s Future: Radical Ecology and Postmodernity.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Book Reviews
405