Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
Vol. LXXXIX No. 3, November 2014
doi: 10.1111/phpr.12040
© 2013 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC
Against Doxastic Compatibilism
RIK PEELS
VU University Amsterdam
Abstract
William Alston has argued that the so-called deontological conception
of epistemic justification, on which epistemic justification is to be
spelled out in terms of blame, responsibility, and obligations, is untenable. The basic idea of the argument is that this conception is untenable because we lack voluntary control over our beliefs and, therefore,
cannot have any obligations to hold certain beliefs. If this is convincing, however, the argument threatens the very idea of doxastic responsibility. For, how can we ever be responsible for our beliefs if we
lack control over them? Several philosophers have argued that the
idea that we bear responsibility for our beliefs can be saved, because
absence of voluntary control over our beliefs is perfectly compatible
with having obligations to hold particular beliefs. With others, I call
this view ‘doxastic compatibilism’. It comes in two varieties. On the
first variety, doxastic obligations do not require any kind of doxastic
control whatsoever. I argue that this variety of doxastic compatibilism
fails because it confuses doxastic responsibility with other closely
related phenomena. On the second variety, doxastic obligations do not
require voluntary doxastic control, but only compatibilist doxastic
control (roughly, reason-responsiveness) and we do in fact have such
control. I grant that we have such control, but also argue that having
such control is insufficient for bearing doxastic responsibility. The
plausibility of the examples put forward by doxastic compatibilists in
support of the claim that it is sufficient for doxastic responsibility
derives from the fact that in these examples, the subjects have control
over factors that influence what they believe rather than control over
those beliefs themselves.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
679
1. Introduction
Several philosophers, most notably William Alston, have provided more or
less the same argument against the so-called deontological conception of
epistemic justification.1 On this conception, epistemic justification should be
understood in terms of obligations, permissions, requirements, responsibility,
praise, and blame. The idea is roughly that some person S justifiedly
believes that p iff in believing that p, S does not violate any obligations and
is, therefore, blameless for believing that p. And, of course, mutatis mutandis the same is taken to be true for other doxastic attitudes, such as disbelief
and withholding. Alston has argued that we lack voluntary control over our
beliefs, but that such control is necessary for having doxastic obligations. In
order to understand the thesis that we lack voluntary control over our
beliefs, let me say a few words on control. By ‘voluntary control’ Alston
means intentional and libertarian control. One has voluntary control over
something if and only if one can choose to do it and one can choose not do
it or, in other words, if one can decide to do it and one can decide not to
do it. Slightly more precisely, the idea seems to be that one has voluntary
control over u-ing if and only if one can u as the result of an intention to
u and one can ~u as the result of an intention to ~u.2 Thus, Alston would
say, in normal circumstances I have voluntary control over what I eat for
breakfast, what I say to my colleagues, how much time I spend on my
work, how I behave when I drive my car, and so on. For in all these cases
there is something which I can decide to do and decide not to do. According to Alston, it is clear that we lack this kind of control over the vast
majority of our beliefs: I cannot change my beliefs simply as the result of
an intention to do so in the way I can choose to say something to a colleague or in the way I can choose to spend an hour on writing a letter. I
believe that I had two slices of bread for breakfast, that I am now in my
study, that it is a sunny day, and so on, but I have no idea how I could
now abandon these beliefs. It seems that my beliefs are not under my voluntary control.
Furthermore, it seems that we can only have an obligation to believe
something if we have such control (‘ought’ implies ‘can’). Hence, we do
not have obligations to hold particular beliefs. But then being epistemically
justified in believing a proposition cannot be a matter of meeting or, at
least, not violating one’s doxastic obligations. Slightly more formally:
(1) We cannot have obligations to believe particular propositions
unless we have sufficient voluntary control over our beliefs.
1
See, for instance, Alston 1989, 115-152; 2005, 58-60.
2
Even more precisely, one can u and one can ~u as the result of an intention to u or ~u
via a non-deviant causal chain.
680
RIK PEELS
(2) We do not have sufficient voluntary control over our beliefs.
(3) Hence, we do not have doxastic obligations.3
Now, if epistemic justification should be understood in terms of obligations to believe and we do not have such obligations, then the deontological conception of epistemic justification is in trouble. Just to be
explicit, here is why. If being epistemically justified is supposed to be a
matter of meeting one’s doxastic obligations, then one would never be
epistemically justified, since there would not be any such obligations. If
being epistemically justified is supposed to be a matter of not violating
one’s doxastic obligations, there are two options. First, such a view
could presume that there are doxastic obligations. It would then follow
that we are never epistemically justified. Second, such a view could not
presume that there are doxastic obligations. We would then always be
epistemically justified. But any plausible theory of epistemic justification
should allow that sometimes we believe justifiedly and sometimes we do
not.
It is important for our purposes to note that this argument not only
threatens the deontological conception of epistemic justification, but also the
very idea that we can properly hold each other responsible for our beliefs.
We believe that—unless special conditions hold—the racist’s belief is
blameworthy. And we hold each other responsible for our moral and political beliefs.4 The whole philosophical discussion about a viable ethics of
belief—which we already find in the works of such philosophers as John
Locke and William Clifford—presumes that we are indeed responsible for
our beliefs. Sometimes we believe responsibly and sometimes we believe
blameworthily or culpably. In this paper, I will not consider whether the
deontological conception of epistemic justification is tenable. In fact, I will
not be explicitly concerned with epistemic justification at all and focus
entirely on responsibility for our beliefs.
Several strategies have been devised to save doxastic responsibility from
the above argument. Some philosophers have claimed that, surprisingly, we
do have some kind of voluntary control over our beliefs.5 Others have
argued that we lack control over our beliefs, but that we nonetheless influence them via our control over all sorts of factors that make a difference to
what we believe, factors such as evidence-gathering and working on our
3
For this argument, see Alston 1989, 115-136.
4
For linguistic evidence for this claim, see Van Woudenberg 2009.
5
That doxastic responsibility can at least partly be explained in terms of our indirect doxastic control has been claimed by Heil 1992, 51; Nottelmann 2007, 157-159; Price 1954,
16-21; Wolterstorff 2010, 62-85.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
681
intellectual virtues and vices.6 However, it seems that the major strategy has
been to grant that we lack voluntary control over our beliefs, but that we
nonetheless have doxastic obligations. In other words, the idea is that
having doxastic obligations and not having doxastic voluntary control are
perfectly compatible with each other. I, therefore, call this view, with others,
doxastic compatibilism. It turns out that doxastic compatibilism comes in
two varieties. Some doxastic compatibilists, such as Hilary Kornblith and
Matthew Chrisman, have argued that one can have doxastic obligations
even if one has no control over or influence on one’s beliefs whatsoever.
Other doxastic compatibilists, such as Sharon Ryan and Matthias Steup,
have argued that some kind of control is necessary for having doxastic obligations, but that compatibilist rather than voluntary control is enough for
having such obligations.7 The main aim of this paper is to argue that doxastic compatibilism is untenable. I discuss the first variety of doxastic compatibilism in section 3 and the second variety in section 4. Before that, in
section 2, I make a few preliminary remarks in order to get the crucial
notions of responsibility and blame sharper into focus.
2. A Word on Responsibility
Let me be explicit that by ‘responsibility’, I do not mean causal responsibility (roughly, bringing about or contributing to the occurrence of some state
of affairs), nor ministerial responsibility (one’s being accountable for the
professional actions and omissions of certain officials in one’s company or
department), nor legal responsibility (one’s being the proper object of legal
treatment in the form of pnishment or its absence), nor role responsibility
(we sometimes have certain tasks or duties in virtue of our role or profession),8 but normative responsibility, where I use the word ‘normative’ in a
narrower sense than it is often used. It is hard, if not impossible, to specify
this variety of responsibility in a theoretically neutral fashion—that is, in a
way that does not depend on a particular account of responsibility. Maybe
giving examples is the best I can do here. Florence Nightingale was normatively responsible for saving thousands of lives in the Crimean war, Adolf
Eichmann was normatively responsible for the deportation of millions of
Jews to concentration camps around Europe, I am normatively responsible
6
See, for instance, Clarke 1986; Dretske 2000; Kornblith 1983; Leon 2002; Stocker 1982.
This also seems to be the view of Alston himself. In a separate section of the paper, he
argues against the idea that epistemic justification can be understood in terms of influence on what we believe, but he does not deny that we can be doxastically responsible
in virtue of our influence on what we believe.
7
It is usually this second variety of doxastic compatibilism that philosophers have in mind
when they use the expression ‘doxastic compatibilism’.
8
Thus also Hart 1970, 211-230.
682
RIK PEELS
for the amount of work I do on an average day and for whether I take coffee or orange juice for breakfast, a racist is normatively responsible for his
heinous beliefs, and I am sometimes normatively responsible for believing
certain propositions upon insufficient evidence. Moral responsibility falls
under normative responsibility, but it is not the only kind of normative
responsibility: there also seem to be such things as prudential responsibility
and epistemic responsibility. In what follows, I am concerned solely with
normative responsibility.
To be responsible, it seems to me, is to be the proper object of one or
more of the reactive attitudes, such as praise and blame. But what are these
reactive attitudes? Reactive attitudes are affective attitudes that we adopt primarily towards people on the basis of their actions, desires, beliefs, virtues
and vices, and character. We adopt them towards other people, but also
towards ourselves. Thus, we can be angry at someone’s decision to remain
silent and I can feel remorse about what I said to my friend last night.
Reactive attitudes are as varied as blame, praise, resentment, outrage, gratitude, forgiveness, indignation, respect, compunction, and remorse. Reactive
attitudes are to be distinguished from another kind of attitude that we sometimes adopt, an attitude that I call the (merely) evaluative attitude.9 Varieties
of the evaluative attitude are pity, certain kinds of love, certain kinds of
shame, deeming inappropriate, considering harmful, and so forth. Some
evaluative attitudes are affective attitudes, whereas others are not. The crucial difference between reactive and evaluative attitudes is that in adopting
the former, we hold someone responsible, whereas in adopting the latter we
merely take it that the occurrence of some state of affairs was desirable,
undesirable, or of neutral worth. This is not to say that if we adopt an evaluative attitude towards someone, we do not hold that person responsible.
After all, we can adopt both a reactive and an evaluative attitude towards
someone for something. It is to say, however, that in adopting an evaluative
attitude, we do not thereby hold someone responsible, whereas we do if we
adopt a reactive attitude.
When I say that someone is the proper object of praise or blame for uing, I mean that that person deserves or merits praise or blame for u-ing. I
take this to be an objective notion: if someone deserves praise or blame,
then such appraisal will be the reactive attitude that would or could be
adopted by a physically, mentally, and emotionally well-functioning person
who is fully informed about the situation. This means that, contrary to what
some philosophers say,10 the notion of merit or desert is not to be spelled
9
10
I take it that Peter Strawson’s objective attitude is identical or similar to my evaluative
attitude (cf. Strawson 1974, 4-13). I prefer ‘evaluative’ to ‘objective’, for evaluations are
often highly subjective.
See, for instance, Eshleman 2004.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
683
out in terms of what a person with justified, rational, or warranted beliefs
about the situation would do. A person with merely justified beliefs may
mistakenly hold someone responsible, since justification and truth can come
apart. It also means that a fully informed and properly functioning human
being need not always actually adopt a reactive attitude towards some
person S for something for which S is responsible. For instance, in considering the Nazi crimes mentioned in Simon Wiesenthal’s monograph Justice,
not Vengeance, she may be so overwhelmed by their sheer number that she
will not have particular emotions towards each of them. However, being
fully informed and functioning properly, she could adopt such reactive
attitudes. Whether she will in fact adopt some reactive attitude or not
depends on all sorts of situational factors.
One might wonder how we should distinguish reactive from evaluative
attitudes. However, I do not think that providing such a criterion is necessary. In principle, we could provide an account of responsibility by including an exhaustive list of reactive attitudes. And if that list correctly picks
out those attitudes that we adopt in holding people responsible, then there is
no theoretical need to add a criterion to distinguish them from evaluative
attitudes. For instance, it seems intuitively obvious that in resenting or
blaming someone, we hold her responsible, whereas in pitying someone, we
do not. And it is contradictory to say that someone is blameworthy for her
bad situation but that she is not responsible for it, whereas it is not contradictory to say that someone is to pity for her bad situation but that she is
not responsible for it.
This account is similar to the widely influential account of Peter Strawson, who also defended an account of responsibility in terms of reactive
attitudes.11 My account differs from that of Strawson in that I have made
the additional claim that one is responsible only if one is the proper object
of reactive attitudes and I have spelled out when someone is a proper object
of reactive attitudes.
Of course, the literature also provides different accounts of responsibility. I think that, in so far as they are relevant to the issue under consideration in this paper, most of them are compatible with what I have said
here.12 However, there is one important alternative account, the behaviourist account, that delivers different and conflicting verdicts on certain cases
that are discussed in this paper, so let me say a few words about it. On the
behaviourist account, to be responsible is to be the proper object of punishment or reward. On this view, one is responsible to the extent that punishment and reward will increase the likelihood of good behaviour and
11
See Strawson 1974.
12
I am thinking, for instance, of accountability accounts (see Oshana 1997) and ledger
accounts (see Feinberg 1970, 30-31, and Glover 1970, 64-65).
684
RIK PEELS
decrease the likelihood of bad behaviour in the future. This account, which
has been advocated most famously by Moritz Schlick,13 seems to me incorrect for at least two reasons. First, we may punish and reward animals,
children, and people with limited mental abilities if we believe that we can
thereby train them to perform certain beneficial actions or not perform
certain harmful actions. Yet, we often do not hold them responsible.
Rather, we consider them as beings to be manipulated or treated in order
to bring about some good or to avoid some harm. Second, there are
circumstances in which we hold people responsible, but consider punishment or reward inappropriate. We hold our friends responsible for not
telling what they consider to be the truth, but only in judicial circumstances
are people punished for such a thing. Blame rather than punishment seems
to be the appropriate reaction in such cases.
It follows from the account that I have defended that to be responsible
for some belief is to be the proper object of such reactive attitudes as praise
and blame for that belief. This is crucial, for we often evaluate people’s
beliefs or people for holding certain beliefs without thereby holding those
people responsible. Consider the following sentences:
(a) “When asked what she sees, an adult and properly functioning
human being ought to believe that she is seeing a chair when she
is looking straight at one.”
(b) “If Judith is to win the quiz, she should believe that Jupiter is the
largest planet in our solar system.”
(c) “Since Hercule Poirot did not return to her house, he must have
believed that Mrs. Burgess was not culpable.”
(d) “If she knows that the polar bear was reclassified as a vulnerable
species in 2005, then she has to believe that.”
In most circumstances, these will not be judgements by which we hold
people responsible for some belief. Normally, (a) will be uttered to describe
proper doxastic functioning, (b) to say what belief is instrumentally useful
or necessary for attaining some social good, (c) to tell what belief someone
can reasonably be expected to have given certain available evidence, and
(d) to characterize the conceptual relation between knowledge and belief. In
uttering these sentences, we need not hold the cognitive subject in question
responsible for her belief, even if we use expressions like ‘should believe’,
‘ought to believe’, or maybe even ‘has an obligation to believe’. The
13
See Schlick 1962, 151-158.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
685
account of responsibility in terms of reactive attitudes that I gave above will
help us to distinguish situations in which we merely evaluate people for
holding certain beliefs from those in which we hold people responsible for
having certain beliefs.
3. Doxastic Obligations without Doxastic Control?
On the first variety of doxastic compatibilism, Alston’s argument does not
count against the idea that we bear doxastic responsibility, because premise
(1) is false: having doxastic obligations does not require any kind of doxastic control whatsoever. We can be praiseworthy if we meet our doxastic
obligations and we can be blameworthy if we violate our doxastic obligations, whether or not we can control our beliefs. In other words, we can be
responsible for our beliefs, even if we have no control over them whatsoever. Those who give this response to Alston’s argument have argued that
doxastic obligations or doxastic ‘oughts’ should be understood as role obligations, epistemic ideals, rules of criticism, or doxastic demands, and that
such obligations do not require any kind of control. In this section, I argue
that this response fails. There might be some sense of ‘ought’ or ‘obligation’ in which we ought to hold certain beliefs or even have an obligation
to hold certain beliefs, but such oughts and obligations have nothing to do
with responsibility, for in most cases they do not seem to imply blameworthiness in case one does not meet such oughts or obligations. To the extent
that they do, they do seem to require some kind of doxastic control and,
hence, are not convincing counter-examples to premise (1) of Alston’s
argument.
3.1. Doxastic Obligations as Role Obligations
First, according to Richard Feldman, doxastic obligations are role obligations. Parents ought to take care of their children, teachers ought to explain
things clearly, and cyclists ought to cycle well, whether they are able to do
so or not. Similarly, judgements on belief prescribe the right way to play
the role of a believer, even if one has no control over one’s belief.14
Feldman confines his account to epistemic doxastic obligations, that is,
“evaluations that have more to do with epistemologically central matters
such as knowledge and rationality”.15 The right way to play the role of a
believer, according to Feldman, is to believe in accordance with one’s
evidence. One might object that there is a crucial difference between the
role of believer on the one hand and the roles of, say, teacher and cyclist
on the other. For, in opposition to the former role, one has the latter roles
14
See Feldman 2000, 676-677.
15
Feldman 2008, 346.
686
RIK PEELS
voluntarily. Feldman agrees, but points out that there are many other roles
that are as involuntary as that of believer, such as the roles of eater and
breather. That these roles are involuntary does not imply that there are no
correct ways to eat or breathe.16
I think that, unfortunately, the analogy fails. We do have control over
the way we eat or breathe. To the extent that we do not, we are not the
proper object of praise or blame for eating or breathing. It seems unfair
to hold me responsible for the way I breathe if there is nothing I can
do to change it. Perhaps we can hold a teacher responsible for teaching
badly, even if he could not do any better. If so, however, that would be
because the role of teacher is a role he has voluntarily accepted. Thus,
to the extent that role obligations imply responsibility, they require some
kind of control. Such control is remarkably absent in the case of being a
believer: I have control neither over my beliefs nor over my being a
believer.
Feldman points out that we sometimes praise a person for things that are
not under her control, such as her beauty.17 I agree, but we should distinguish between praise as a reactive attitude from praise as an evaluative attitude. I might praise Miranda for her beauty or my recently bought
Chevrolet for its speed, but I do not thereby hold them responsible for these
qualities. We do not hold Miranda responsible for her beauty, in the same
way as we do not blame someone else for being ugly, unless, of course,
they had control over being beautiful or being ugly (but then, such praise
would not count against the idea that responsibility requires control). Such
merely evaluative praise ought to be clearly distinguished from praise as a
reactive attitude. If we adopt the reactive attitude of praise towards someone
for u-ing, we can in principle also, say, blame or resent that person for
u-ing.
3.2. Doxastic Obligations as Epistemic Ideals
Second, Hilary Kornblith construes doxastic obligations in terms of ideals
that take into account human limitations. More specifically, he says that
what he has in mind are epistemic ideals. Epistemic ideals take into account
what humans can believe, but they are not confined to what a particular
human can believe: sometimes one ought to believe a proposition that one
cannot believe. Epistemic ideals can be reached by at least some human
beings. Doxastic obligations, therefore, provide the middle ground between
epistemic ideals that are insensitive to human capacities and ideals that are
16
See Feldman 2008, 351. Feldman 2000, 674, distances himself from his earlier view on
which doxastic obligations are contractual obligations (see Feldman 1988, 240-243).
17
See Feldman 2000, 676.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
687
so constrained by a particular individual’s capacities that they are unworthy
of pursuit. Since being subject to epistemic ideals does not require control,
this approach could save doxastic obligations.18
It seems to me that this account is flawed. The problem with our
beliefs is that they seem under no one’s voluntary control. Thus, even if
we confine ourselves to epistemic ideals that can be reached only by
those who do epistemically well, there will not be any doxastic obligations. No matter what the ideal attitude is towards a proposition, if there
is no way I or anyone else can voluntarily acquire that attitude, it seems
clear that I have no obligation to acquire that attitude. Again, we may
very well be the proper object of evaluative attitudes for not reaching certain epistemic ideals. It follows neither that we are the proper object of
reactive attitudes nor that we have doxastic obligations. Of course, one
could say that we have an obligation to believe that p if and only if one
ought to believe that p and that one ought to believe that p if and only
if the epistemic ideal is to believe that p. Perhaps the word ‘obligation’
is sometimes used in this contrived sense. But then, it follows from what
I argued in the previous section that we will no longer be talking about
doxastic responsibility.
3.3. Doxastic Obligations as Rules of Criticism
Third, Matthew Chrisman argues that we should interpret doxastic obligations as what Wilfrid Sellars calls rules of criticism that materially imply
rules of action. Whereas rules of criticism (ought-to-be’s) concern ways of
being, rules of action (ought-to-do’s) concern actions. One can be subject to
a rule of criticism for u-ing, even if one has no control over u-ing, whereas
rules of action do require control. The material implication which Chrisman
has in mind can be spelled out as follows:
(4) If X ought to be in state Φ, then, other things being equal and
where possible, one ought to bring it about that X is in state Φ.
Now, as Chrisman rightly notices, (4)’s consequent can be interpreted in
three different ways: (i) on the conditional view, X herself ought to do what
she can to bring it about that X is in Φ, (ii) on the universal view, everyone
ought to do what she can to bring it about that X is in Φ, and (iii) on the
existential view, someone ought to do what she can to bring it about that X
18
688
See Kornblith 2001, 238-239. In a previous article (Kornblith 1983, 33), he distinguishes
between doxastic obligations as epistemic ideals and doxastic obligations that imply
responsibility. In an even earlier paper, he understands doxastic justification in terms of
the absence of epistemic culpability (Kornblith 1982, 243). Unfortunately, the distinction
between ideals and responsibility is absent from Kornblith 2001 and 2002, 137-161.
RIK PEELS
is in Φ. According to Chrisman, which view is correct depends on which
kind of ought is involved. For instance, the rules of criticism
(e) people ought to feel outrage about genocide;
(f) this child ought to be able to tie his shoes by age four;
materially imply respectively a universal and an existential rule of action:
(e’) everyone ought to do what she can to bring it about that people
feel outrage about genocide;
(f’) someone ought to do what she can to bring it about that this child
is able to tie his shoes by age four.19
According to Chrisman, the epistemic ideal for humans is to be good
information tracking and transmitting beings. Ought-to-do’s implied by doxastic ought-to-be’s are interpersonal and sometimes intrapersonal forwardlooking and backward-looking rules of action on the part of one’s epistemic
community, sometimes including oneself. Thus,
(g) you ought to disbelieve that the earth is flat;
is an ought-to-be that materially implies the following correlative existential
ought-to-do:
(g’) your parents and teachers ought to have taught you that the earth
is not flat.20
If this is correct, doxastic obligations do not require control on the cognitive
subject’s part. It seems to me, however, that this view is problematic. Chrisman rightly acknowledges that there are many situations in which S in some
sense ought to believe that p, without S’s herself being subject to a materially implied ought-to-do. But then it is incorrect to say that S herself is subject to an obligation to believe that p or that she is blameworthy if she fails
to meet that obligation. Assuming that there are such things as epistemic
obligations on the side of one’s epistemic community, one’s epistemic community may have an obligation to convince one of the truth of p and may
be blameworthy for failing to do so, but, clearly, that is something different.
The sense in which S ought to believe that p in such situations, then, will
not be normative, but merely evaluative.
19
See Chrisman 2008, 358-363.
20
See Chrisman 2008, 369-370.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
689
3.4. Doxastic Obligations as Doxastic Demands
Finally, according to Philippe Chuard and Nicholas Southwood, in expressing that we hold someone responsible for a belief, we make judgements that
are relevantly like judgements such as:
(h) Oscar ought to feel guilty for what he did to his sister, and
(i) Judy ought to understand what Nicole is going through,
in that these judgements make demands on us. They demand that we
respond in certain ways. But making a demand to u on some person S does
not presuppose that S has control over her u-ing, only that S can u. The
idea that S can u can be spelled out in terms of there being the logical possibility that S u-s, in terms of S’s having the alternate possibilities of u-ing
and ~u-ing, or in terms of S’s having the capacity to u. But none of these
implies that S has voluntary control over u-ing. Alston’s argument goes
wrong, then, in conflating the idea that S can u with the idea that S has
control over u-ing. Hence, doxastic obligations do not require control.21
It seems to me that this approach faces a serious difficulty. For it is not
clear what it is to be the proper object of a demand. If it does not have to
do with being responsible, then Chuard’s and Southwood’s strategy does
not even address the argument from lack of doxastic control that William
Alston and others give. If it has to do with being responsible, then it follows from what I argued in section 2 that if a demand is made on someone,
then that person is blameworthy if she fails to meet the demand (if she has
no good excuse). Chuard and Southwood, however, explicitly reject the idea
that doxastic obligations are in any way relevantly related to blameworthiness. They do so, because they do not find any plausible interpretation of
blame on which blameworthy belief requires doxastic control. As they see
it, blame can be interpreted in terms of being criticisable and in terms of
other people’s having certain legitimate expectations. As they rightly point
out, being criticisable does not require control. And someone else’s having
a legitimate expectation about what one will believe is an implausible way
of spelling out doxastic blame, for usually people have no expectations
about what we will believe.22
However, they overlook the option that I defended in section 2, namely
that one is blameworthy if and only if one is the proper object of a negative
reactive attitude, such as resentment or blame. I think that sentences (h) and
(i) can plausibly be understood along these lines, that is, as expressing reactive attitudes towards Oscar and Judy. But if they do, then it seems that a
21
See Chuard and Southwood 2009, 601, 614-619.
22
See Chuard and Southwood 2009, 620-623.
690
RIK PEELS
rational speaker would assume that there is something Oscar and Judy could
have done about respectively not feeling guilty and lacking understanding.
If there is nothing they could possibly do or have done to feel guilty or to
understand, then it is hard to see how we could properly blame them. How,
for instance, can we rightly blame Oscar for not feeling guilty for what he
did to his sister if he has tried everything he possibly could, but still fails to
feel guilty? Thus, a person is properly subject to some demand only if that
person has control over meeting that demand. However, as we saw, there is
good reason to think that we have no voluntary control over our beliefs.
3.5. Intermediate Conclusion
In this section, I have criticized four attempts to argue that doxastic obligations belong to a special kind of obligations that do not require control. For
each of the four kinds of obligations that I discussed—role obligations, epistemic ideals, rules of criticism, and doxastic demands—I agree that there
may be some sense of the word ‘obligation’ in which we have doxastic
obligations along these lines or at least that it can be true that we ought to
hold some belief. In all four cases, however, it turned out that such oughts
have nothing to do with responsibility. And that is because they have nothing to do with praise, blame, or any of the other reactive attitudes. To the
extent that they do have to do with these attitudes, they seem to require
some kind of control over or influence on our beliefs. Of course, this does
not establish that there is no way that one could plausibly argue that doxastic obligations are of a special kind that does not require control. But, as far
as I know, these four proposals are all the attempts that we find in the literature to argue that doxastic obligations do not require any kind of doxastic
control. I take it, though, that my criticisms of these four proposals provide
sufficient reason to seek an alternative solution to the problem formulated
by William Alston.
4. Doxastic Obligations in Virtue of Doxastic Compatibilist Control?
4.1. Compatibilist Doxastic Control
The second variety of doxastic compatibilism also denies premise (1), but
for a different reason. The idea is not that doxastic obligations do not
require any kind of control whatsoever, but that doxastic obligations do not
require voluntary control, as I defined ‘voluntary control’ earlier. Remember
that someone has voluntary control over u-ing if and only if one can u as
the result of an intention to u and one can ~u as the result of an intention
to ~u. Most doxastic compatibilists of this second variety grant that we
cannot form our beliefs as the result of an intention to do so, although, as
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
691
we shall see, Matthias Steup is an exception. All of them agree, though, that
it is not required that in exactly the same evidential circumstances, one
could have chosen to hold a different belief.
What does doxastic compatibilist control amount to? Doxastic compatibilists answer this question differently, although their accounts show important similarities. Let me briefly characterize the three main accounts that we
find in the literature. First, according to Mark Heller, people have an epistemic nature, that is, second-order desires to form beliefs in accordance with
certain dispositions rather than others. What is required for doxastic control
is that our beliefs reflect our epistemic nature, that is, that we form the
beliefs we form because of the epistemic nature we have. We are responsible in such cases because our beliefs manifest who we are from an epistemic point of view.23
Second, according to Sharon Ryan, what is required for doxastic responsibility is that we can appreciate evidence and form beliefs in accordance
with it, in the same way as we can weigh various practical considerations
and act in accordance with them. We are responsible for our beliefs if they
are unlike typical coerced actions and like actions such as typing the letters
that we type and moving our limbs when we have been running for a while.
These are actions that are responsive to reasons, but do not seem to involve
the formation of any intentions. It does not require an explicit intention to
perform them. It follows that intentional doxastic control is not required for
having a doxastic obligation.24
Third, according to Matthias Steup, some person is responsible for a
belief if that belief is the outcome of a process that is responsive to epistemic reasons, i.e. evidence, and if that person’s belief is weakly intentional.
Something is weakly intentional if it is non-accidental and if one has a proattitude towards it. Thus, my stepping on the clutch is weakly intentional if
it does not result from such things as a sudden cramp in my leg and if I
mean to step on the clutch. A belief is weakly intentional if it is not due to
cognitive malfunction and if one endorses it or if one is comfortable with it.
Beliefs, then, are like actions such as starting a car by inserting the ignition
key, engaging the clutch, shifting into reverse, and stepping on the gas.
These automatic, unthinking, and habitual actions are not performed as the
result of an explicit intention, but are nevertheless under one’s control.25
23
See Heller 2000, 132-137.
24
See Ryan 2003, 70-74. An account similar to that of Ryan is Owens 2000, 115-129. His
account is different in that he is not willing to describe reasons-responsiveness as control; he simply denies that doxastic responsibility requires any kind of control.
25
See Steup 2012. For other, less developed compatibilist accounts of doxastic control in
the same spirit, see Hieronymi 2008, 362-363; J€ager 2004, 217-227; Shah 2002, 443;
Smith 2000, 40-46; Smith 2005, 236-271; Weatherson 2008, 546.
692
RIK PEELS
One may object that these are not really instances of doxastic control.
But the doxastic compatibilist will simply disagree and will affirm that this
is all that is required for doxastic control. My criticism on this variety of
doxastic compatibilism that I provide in the following section will, therefore, not depend on whether or not compatibilist doxastic control can properly be called ‘control’. Rather, I will argue that compatibilist doxastic
control is insufficient for being responsible for one’s beliefs.
4.2. A Problem with Doxastic Compatibilist Control
I think the prospects for doxastic compatibilism of this second variety are
as bleak as those for the first variety. If, on the one hand, one has some
kind of control (whether intentional or otherwise) over or influence on one’s
higher-order beliefs or one’s reasons-responsive processes, then it seems
that in the scenarios sketched by doxastic compatibilists, one is responsible
for one’s beliefs not because one has some kind of doxastic compatibilist
control over them, but because one influences what one believes by having
control over such belief-influencing factors as higher-order beliefs and reasons-responsive processes. If, on the other hand, one lacks some kind of
control over or influence on one’s higher-order beliefs and reasons-responsive processes, then how can one be responsible for them and for the ensuing beliefs?
It seems to me that most, if not all doxastic compatibilists are aware that
the first horn of this dilemma is problematic and, therefore, opt for the second horn. This horn, however, is equally problematic. Imagine that Nagoni
is raised in a culturally isolated community. From an early age onward, she
is indoctrinated in the tradition of the tribe. She, therefore, believes that she
should believe anything that the tradition teaches and so she desires to
believe anything that is part of her tradition. Thus, upon considering the
proposition that humans are fallen angels, she immediately believes this
proposition, for this is one of the core teachings of her tribe. She believes
this as strongly as anything she could possibly believe. It is completely irresistible. Since she is convinced that this is what the tradition teaches, she
believes in accordance with her epistemic nature. But it is clear that she has
no control over her belief: she has been indoctrinated to such an extent that
her belief is genuinely irresistible. This shows that Heller’s account in terms
of epistemic natures is untenable. The reasons-responsiveness accounts of
Ryan and Steup do not face this problem, for Nagoni’s belief-forming
mechanism clearly is not reasons-responsive: she would hold that belief no
matter what her evidence were.
Ryan’s and Steup’s accounts face another problem, though. Imagine a
possible world in which there are creatures who are like us in that their
belief-forming mechanisms are largely functioning properly: upon having
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
693
the experiences and beliefs we have, they roughly form the same beliefs as
we do. Moreover, they are as responsive to evidential reasons as we are:
upon having (significantly) different evidence, they form different beliefs.
Once their evidence changes, their beliefs change accordingly. In one
regard, however, they are crucially different from us: they cannot influence
what they believe. Thus, they cannot gather evidence, work on their intellectual virtues and vices, improve the functioning of their cognitive mechanisms, and so forth. For instance, they cannot decide to gather further
evidence on a politically sensitive issue or decide to try to become more
open-minded. Nonetheless, their beliefs change every now and then,
because the doxastic mechanisms producing those beliefs are responsive to
changes in the evidential situation. In fact, they are caused in a paradigmatically good way: perceiving a tree causally leads to the belief that there is a
tree in front of them, tasting something sweet causally leads to the belief
that they are tasting something sweet and when that taste changes to something bitter, they come to believe that they are tasting something bitter.
Would we hold those creatures responsible for their beliefs in this scenario? It seems clear to me that we would not. Their belief-formation is
clearly not up to them. Their beliefs are simply the deliverances of their
cognitive mechanisms in combination with certain inputs. But, we have
assumed, neither the functioning of their cognitive mechanisms nor the
scope or quality of their evidence base is up to them. It seems clear that if
these are not up to them, the output is not up to them either and it would
be unfair to hold them responsible for their beliefs. I submit, then, that the
plausibility of Ryan’s and Steup’s doxastic compatibilism derives from the
fact that in the scenarios they sketch, people have control over all sorts of
factors that influence what the subjects believe. It is because we can intentionally perform such belief-influencing actions and not because our beliefforming mechanisms respond differently to different inputs (what they call
‘compatibilist doxastic control’) that we can be held responsible for our
beliefs in such cases. But, as I pointed out in section 1, that would count as
a different response to Alston’s argument, a response that denies that it follows from (3)—the thesis that we do not have doxastic obligations—that
we are not responsible for our beliefs. We would not be responsible in virtue of our presumed doxastic compatibilist control over our beliefs.
4.3. Three Arguments for Doxastic Compatibilism and Three Replies
The argument that I just gave against the second variety of doxastic compatibilism counts against any view on which we are responsible for our beliefs
in virtue of our compatibilist control over our beliefs. For, it seems that if
someone is merely reason-responsive without having the ability to influence
her beliefs, she is not at all responsible for her beliefs. Hence, compatibilist
694
RIK PEELS
control can never suffice for doxastic responsibility. However, we should
hold on to the idea that we cannot have obligations to believe particular
propositions unless we have sufficient voluntary control (as I defined it
earlier on) over our beliefs only if such a view does not face equally insurmountable difficulties. Let me, therefore, discuss the three main arguments
that compatibilists have levelled against the idea that doxastic obligations
require doxastic voluntary control rather than doxastic compatibilist control,
where ‘voluntary control’ should be understood as I defined it earlier,
namely implying that one has alternate possibilities.
First, one might think that what counts both when it comes to action and
when it comes to belief is reasons rather than intentions. Action and belief
are similar in that if one takes oneself to have sufficient reason to perform
act A or hold belief B, one will normally perform A or hold B. For instance,
if I have convincing reasons to slow down and stop when I approach an
intersection, I will stop, and if I have convincing reasons not to stick a knife
in my arm, I will not do so. Of course, I could decide to act differently if
I had an overriding reason to do so, but similarly I could believe differently
if my epistemic reasons were different.26 I find this reply unconvincing.
First, if I take myself to have good reasons to do A, I will not do A as long
as I do not also intend to do A (unless doing A is a habitual action; I return
to that momentarily). Reasons alone, then, will not suffice to explain action:
we also need intentions or, as I shall explain below, at least the ability to
do the thing in question intentionally.27 Second, there are many situations
in which my practical reasons for doing A and not doing A are balanced. In
such situations I can deliberate about whether to do A or not to do A and I
can consequently do A or not do A. For instance, I can choose to put cheese
or peanut butter on my bread.28 However, in all or most situations in which
my evidence for and against p is balanced, I cannot simply decide to
believe or disbelieve that p. Rather, I automatically find myself with a
particular doxastic attitude towards p, normally that of withholding (withholding both belief and disbelief).
Second, one could object that we are responsible for and have control
over actions such as my typing the letters that I type, my moving my legs
26
For this argument, see Russell 2001, 42-43; Ryan 2003, 63-64; Steup 2000, 46, 54;
2001, 17n.
27
According to Steup 2012, we can form our beliefs voluntarily. I return to this thesis
below.
28
Of course, if determinism is true, it is not the case that there are two options available to
one. Even if determinism is true, though, it will seem to the cognitive subject in question
that it is up to her whether she does A or she does not do A. When one’s evidence
regarding p is balanced, however, it will seem to one that one cannot believe that p and
that one cannot believe that ~p; it will seem to one that, given one’s evidence, one cannot but suspend judgement on p.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
695
when I have been running for a while, and my stepping on the clutch, even
though we often do not perform these actions as the result of a preceding
intention to do so. Hence, intentions are not crucial to control and responsibility.29 In response, let me point out that beliefs are crucially different from
such actions as moving my legs and typing the letters I type. I can type the
letters on my computer without explicitly intending to do so, only because I
once did intend to type these letters, and something similar applies to
actions like running. I do not think that this is true for all actions that are
under our control. I can exercise control over breathing or not breathing,
even if I have never intentionally done so. But breathing or not breathing—
or, at least, breathing or not breathing at some particular moment—is
something that I could in principle do intentionally. With belief, things are
different. I do not now unintentionally form certain beliefs because I once
intentionally formed them. Nor is it the case that I could in principle form a
belief as the result of an intention to do so. Rather, I have always found
myself with certain beliefs, given the evidence I had. Beliefs may be quite
different from compelled actions, but they are not very much like the
unintentional actions just mentioned either.
Third, one might object that the idea that control requires the ability to
form intentions becomes problematic if we apply this idea to control over
intentions themselves. Two problems have been identified here. First, we
lack intentional control over our intentions. We cannot form intentions to u
as a result of deciding to intend to u upon believing that intending to u
would be good. We can intend to u only if we believe that u-ing itself is
good. We are deluded into thinking that we have intentional control over
our intentions, because an intention is usually good to have just in case the
action intended is good to perform, but there are cases in which the goodness of intentions and that of the intended actions come apart.30 Second, the
idea that control requires the ability to form intentions leads to an infinite
regress. One’s intention to u is under one’s control only if one could form
an intention to intend to u. But that intention would be under one’s control
only if it could be formed by a further intention, and so on. In order to
avoid this infinite regress, we should deny that control over u-ing requires
the ability to u intentionally.31 And if these two points about intentions are
correct, then why would we not think that beliefs are like intentions in that
they are under our control but not in virtue of a presumed ability to form
an intention to have them?
Let me first address the final claim, that is, the assertion that beliefs are
like intentions. I think that this claim is false. If I have equally good reason
29
For this objection, see Steup 2008, 284-285; 2011, 154-155.
30
This point has been made by Owens 2000, 81; Hieronymi 2006, 56-57; 2008, 368-371.
31
For this line of reasoning, see Shah 2002, 440-442.
696
RIK PEELS
to do A as not to do A and equally good reason to intend to do A as to
intend not to do A, as is often the case, then I can equally well intend to do
A as intend not to do A. For example, if I do not mind whether I take coffee
or orange juice for breakfast, I can equally well intend to take coffee as I
can intend to take orange juice. Whether I intend to do some action A or
not to do A is in such cases up to me, in a way that it is not up to me what
doxastic attitude I take towards p if my evidence bearing on p is balanced.
Thus, it seems that I have a kind of control over my intentions that I lack
over my beliefs, however precisely this kind of control is to be spelled out.
As to the two points about intentions, I agree that one’s control over one’s
intentions is not to be spelled out in terms of one’s ability to form intentions to intend. I submit that some person S’s intention is under S’s control
simply if it is formed by S herself rather than anything else, such as an evil
neurosurgeon or a brain tumour. To form such an uncoerced intention is to
exercise one’s will. One might wonder why, if this is true, we should not
say that, similarly, to form a belief is to exercise one’s will. I answer that to
will something simply is to intend to do it, to choose to do it, to decide to
do it. To believe something is not to will something. Intentions seem to be
essential to exercising one’s will in a way that one’s beliefs seem not to be.
One may reply, as Steup does in his 2008 paper, by asking why we
should give pride of place to intentions. Actions are typically caused by
intentions and desires, whereas beliefs are typically caused by our evidence.
How is it supposed to follow that beliefs are not under our control? The
two domains of actions and beliefs have different criteria of control.32 To
say that control over u-ing requires the ability to form an intention to u is
to measure the two realms with the same yardstick, whereas they should be
measured with different yardsticks. In response, I would like to stress that
the intuition that I share with many philosophers that control over u-ing
requires the ability to intend to u is not an intuition about actions, but about
the very nature of control: one cannot have control over u-ing if one is
unable to form an intention to u.33 It seems implausible that control in one
realm is entirely different from control in another realm if, as Steup and
Ryan agree, to be responsible is to be the proper object of reactive attitudes
like praise and blame, and if we bear responsibility in virtue of having control. It seems that we should reject such a view unless we find a plausible
candidate of control in the doxastic realm that seems to render us doxastically responsible. As I argued above, doxastic compatibilists of the second
variety have not put forward any viable candidate.
Another option, which Steup defends in a more recent paper (Steup
2012), is to claim that we do form beliefs as the result of an intention to do
32
See Steup 2008, 387-390.
33
Thus also Booth 2009, 9-11.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
697
so. Thus, we form beliefs in a way that is not significantly different from
how we perform actions as the result of an intention to do so. According to
Steup, one can, in believing that p, carry out an intention to believe that p.
Consider the following case that Steup sketches:
having returned from a trip and taken a shuttle to the airport parking garage, I am now where I thought I left my car. To my surprise, it is no
longer there. I wonder whether it has been stolen. There is of course the
possibility that I don’t accurately remember where I parked it. So I retrieve
the paper slip which states the exact location of my parking spot. According to the slip, I am at the right spot. Considering my evidence—the parking slip and the absence of my car—I conclude that it was stolen.34
According to Steup, a situation like this is plausibly described by saying
that I come to believe that my car was stolen because, considering my evidence, I decided to believe that my car was stolen (and the causal relation
between this belief and the decision to hold it is non-deviant). The decision
to believe that my car was stolen is, according to Steup, analogous to deciding to take a walk: one considers one’s reasons for (not) taking a walk and
then decides to take a walk. Steup discusses and replies to two arguments
against this interpretation of the car theft scenario. Here, I will levy two
objections of my own against Steup’s interpretation. For, there are at least
two important differences between coming to believe that my car was stolen
and deciding to take a walk.
First, Steup is right that in both scenarios, before considering my reasons, it seems to me that there are two options; namely, respectively,
believing that p and not believing that p, and taking a walk and not taking
a walk. However, the scenarios are different once I have considered my
reasons. When I have considered my reasons for (not) believing that the
car was stolen and find myself with sufficient evidence for believing that
it was, I cannot but believe that the car was stolen. But when I have considered my reasons for (not) taking a walk and find myself with equally
good reasons to take a walk as to not take a walk—say, because the
weather is really nice, but I also do not have that much time left to prepare a lecture that I should deliver this evening—it seems it is up to me
whether or not I take a walk. This is confirmed by how we interpret such
scenarios afterwards. We think that, given the exact same practical reasons,
we could have decided not to take a walk. But we do not think that, given
the exact same evidential reasons, we could have failed to believe that the
car was stolen (or, at least, we would deem the absence of such a belief
irrational).
34
698
Steup 2012, 157.
RIK PEELS
We should notice that this remains true when we sketch two scenarios
that are even more analogous by coming up with a situation in which I have
to decide what to believe, but in which my evidential reasons for and
against p are balanced (in the same way as my reasons for and against taking a walk are balanced). Here, one could think of our evidence regarding
such propositions as that the number of stars is even or that the next time
I flip this coin, it will turn up heads. Once I have considered all my reasons,
I cannot but suspend judgement on the proposition that the number of stars
is even and on the proposition that the coin will turn up heads next time
I flip it. But, again, once I have considered all my reasons for and against
taking a walk, it seems that it is still up to me whether or not I take a walk.
Second, it is an important characteristic of voluntary actions that we can
decide when we perform the action in question. I can now decide to take a
walk in ten minutes, or in half an hour, or tomorrow. In deciding whether
or not to perform an action, I also decide when I will perform it or, at least,
whether or not I will perform it right now (I might decide to perform it at
some time in the future, without deciding on exactly when I am going to
perform it). When I decide to go to the library, to buy a car, or to raise my
arm, I thereby also decide whether to do it straight away or to do it later
and if the latter, we often decide when we will do it. If I decide to purchase a car tomorrow, then from that moment onwards—unless I change
my mind—I explicitly or implicitly intend to purchase a car tomorrow. All
this is absent in the case of belief. Once I have considered my evidence
regarding p, I find myself automatically and immediately believing that p,
disbelieving that p, or suspending judgement on p. I cannot decide to
believe that p later—in, say, ten minutes or tomorrow. Nor can I have the
intention for an extended period of time to believe that p (although I may
well have the intention to try to acquire the belief that p during a certain
period of time). This is a second, important difference between the process
of coming to believe that my car was stolen and deciding to take a walk. It
seems to me that, jointly, these two differences provide us with enough reason to say that, even though we decide to consider our evidence regarding
certain propositions and, therefore, decide to weigh our epistemic reasons,
we do not decide to form a belief or come to hold a belief as the (non-deviant) result of an intention to do so.35
5. Conclusion
In this paper, I have discussed doxastic compatibilism, which is one of the
major responses (or maybe the major response) that has been given to
35
In this section, I have argued that doxastic compatibilist control does not suffice for doxastic obligations. I have not provided a defence of the thesis that doxastic obligations
require the ability to believe otherwise. For a defence of that thesis, see Peels 2013.
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
699
Alston’s well-known argument against the deontological conception of epistemic justification but which also counts against the thesis that we are at
least sometimes responsible for our beliefs. Doxastic compatibilists claim
that we can have doxastic obligations, even if we have no voluntary control over our beliefs, and that we can be praiseworthy and blameworthy
for our beliefs in virtue of meeting and violating those obligations.
According to some doxastic compatibilists, having doxastic obligations
requires no doxastic control whatsoever. According to other doxastic compatibilists, having doxastic obligations does not require voluntary doxastic
control (the control one has when one can choose to do A and one can
choose not do A), but only compatibilist doxastic control (roughly, reasonresponsiveness). I have argued that the former confuse doxastic responsibility with closely related phenomena, whereas the latter use examples
which derive their plausibility from a view which turns out to be quite different from doxastic compatibilism, namely that we are responsible for our
beliefs in virtue of the fact that we can control factors that make a difference to what we believe, such as our evidence base. If my arguments are
convincing, then we have good reason to think that doxastic compatibilism
is untenable and that, in order to save the thesis that we are doxastically
responsible, we should argue that we can voluntarily choose our beliefs
after all or that we bear doxastic responsibility in virtue of our control
over factors that make a difference to what we believe, such as our evidence base and our intellectual virtues and vices, rather than over those
beliefs themselves.36
References
Alston, William P. (1989). “Concepts of Epistemic Justification”, in
Epistemic Justification: Essays in the Theory of Knowledge (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press), 81–114.
(2005). Beyond “Justification”: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation
(Ithaca: Cornell University Press).
Booth Anthony, R. (2009). “Compatibilism and Free Belief”, Philosophical
Papers 38.1, 1–12.
Chrisman, Matthew. (2008). “Ought to Believe”, The Journal of Philosophy
105.7, 346–370.
Chuard, Philippe and Nicholas Southwood. (2009). “Epistemic Norms
without Voluntary Control”, No^
us 43.4, 599–632.
36
700
For their helpful comments on presentations or earlier written versions of (sections of)
this paper, I would like to thank Anthony Booth, Jeroen de Ridder, Richard Feldman,
Hilary Kornblith, Conor McHugh, Philip Nickel, Herman Philipse, Michael Smith,
Nicholas Southwood, Ralph Wedgwood, Rene van Woudenberg, Nicholas Wolterstorff,
and an anonymous referee of this journal.
RIK PEELS
Clarke, Murray. (1986). “Doxastic Voluntarism and Forced Belief”,
Philosophical Studies 50.1, 39–51.
Dretske, Fred. (2000). “Entitlement: Epistemic Rights without Epistemic
Duties?”, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60.3, 591–606.
Eshleman, Andrew. (2004). “Moral Responsibility”, The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/, first published
January 6th 2001, substantive revision November 18th 2009, last
visited: November 7th 2012.
Feinberg, Joel. (1970). Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of
Responsibility (Princeton: Princeton University Press).
Feldman, Richard. (1988). “Epistemic Obligations”, in James E. Tomberlin
(ed.), Philosophical Perspectives 2: Epistemology (Atascadero, CA:
Ridgeview Publishers), 235–256.
. (2000). “The Ethics of Belief”, Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 60.3, 667–695.
. (2008). “Modest Deontologism in Epistemology”, Synthese 161.3,
339–355.
Glover, Jonathan. (1970). Responsibility (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul).
Hart, Herbert L.A. (1970). Punishment and Responsibility: Essays in the
Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Heil, John. (1992). “Believing Reasonably”, No^us 26.1, 47–61.
Heller, Mark. (2000). “Hobartian Voluntarism: Grounding a Deontological
Conception of Epistemic Justification”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
81.2, 130–141.
Hieronymi, Pamela. (2006). “Controlling Attitudes”, Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly 87.1, 45–74.
. (2008). “Responsibility for Believing”, Synthese 161.3, 357–373.
J€ager, Christoph. (2004). “Epistemic Deontology, Doxastic Voluntarism, and
the Principle of Alternate Possibilities”, in Winfried L€offler and Paul
Weingartner (eds.), Knowledge and Belief: Proceedings of the 26th
€
International Wittgenstein Symposium (Vienna: Obv&hpt
Verlagsgesellschaft), 217–227.
Kornblith, Hilary. (1982). “The Psychological Turn”, Australasian Journal
of Philosophy 60.3, 238–253.
. (1983). “Justified Belief and Epistemically Responsible Action”,
Philosophical Review 92.1, 33–48.
. (2001). “Epistemic Obligation and the Possibility of Internalism”, in
Abrol Fairweather and Linda Zagzebski (eds.), Virtue Epistemology:
Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford
University Press), 231–248.
. (2002). Knowledge and Its Place in Nature (Oxford: Clarendon
Press).
AGAINST DOXASTIC COMPATIBILISM
701
Leon, Mark. (2002). “Responsible Believers”, The Monist 85.3, 421–435.
Nottelmann, Nikolaj. (2007). Blameworthy Belief: A Study in Epistemic
Deontologism (Dordrecht: Springer).
Oshana, Marina A.L. (1997). “Ascriptions of Responsibility”, American
Philosophical Quarterly 34.1, 71–83.
Owens, David. (2000). Reason without Freedom: The Problem of Epistemic
Normativity (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).
Peels, Rik. (2013). “Does Doxastic Responsibility Entail the Ability to
Believe Otherwise?”, forthcoming in Synthese.
Price, Henry H. (1954). “Belief and the Will”, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 28, 1–26.
Russell, Bruce. (2001). “Epistemic and Moral Duty”, in Matthias Steup
(ed.), Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification,
Responsibility, and Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 34–48.
Ryan, Sharon. (2003). “Doxastic Compatibilism and the Ethics of Belief”,
Philosophical Studies 114.1–2, 47–79.
Schlick, Moritz. (1962). Problems of Ethics (New York: Dover
Publications).
Shah, Nishi. (2002). “Clearing Space for Doxastic Voluntarism”, The
Monist 85.3, 436–445.
Smith Angela, M. (2000). “Identification and Responsibility”, in Ton van
den Beld (ed.), Moral Responsibility and Ontology (Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers), 233–246.
. (2005). “Responsibility for Attitudes: Activity and Passivity in Mental
Life”, Ethics 115.2, 236–271.
Steup, Matthias. (2000). “Doxastic Voluntarism and Epistemic Deontology”,
Acta Analytica 15.1, 25–56.
. (2001). “Introduction”, in Matthias Steup (ed.), Knowledge, Truth,
and Duty: Essays on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue
(Oxford: Oxford University Press), 3–18.
. (2008). “Doxastic Freedom”, Synthese 161.3, 375–392.
. (2012). “Belief Control and Intentionality”, Synthese 188.2, 145–163.
Stocker, Michael. (1982). “Responsibility Especially for Beliefs”, Mind
91.363, 398–417.
Strawson Peter, F. (1974). “Freedom and Resentment”, in Freedom and
Resentment and Other Essays (London: Methuen), 1–25.
Van Woudenberg, Rene. (2009). “Responsible Belief and Our Social
Institutions”, Philosophy 84.327, 47–73.
Weatherson, Brian. (2008). “Deontology and Descartes’ Demon”, The
Journal of Philosophy 105.9, 540–569.
Wolterstorff, Nicholas. (2010). Practices of Belief, Selected Essays, Vol. 2,
ed. Terence Cuneo (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
702
RIK PEELS