Econ Journal Watch
Scholarly Comments on Academic Economics
Volume 9, Issue 2, May 2012
COMMENTS
Freedom Versus Coercion in Industrial Ecology: A Reply to Boons
Pierre Desrochers
78-99
Freedom Versus Coercion in Industrial Ecology: Mind the Gap!
Frank Boons
100-111
Fact Versus Conjecture in the History of Industrial Waste Utilization
Christine Meisner Rosen
112-121
Race, Ethnicity, and Baseball Card Prices: A Replication, Correction, and
Extension of Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver, and Regoli
122-140
David W. Findlay and John M. Santos
Supplement to “Race, Ethnicity, and Baseball Card Prices: A Replication,
Correction, and Extension of Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver, and Regoli”
David W. Findlay and John M. Santos
A1-A18
Beyond Race Cards in America’s Pastime: An Appreciative Reply to Findlay and
Santos
Robert Muñoz, Jr.
141-148
CHARACTER ISSUES
Characteristics of the Members of Twelve Economic Associations: Voting,
Policy Views, and Favorite Economists
Daniel B. Klein, William L. Davis, Bob G. Figgins, and David Hedengren
149-162
The Transmission of the Ideals of Economic Freedom
F. A. Hayek
163-169
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5757
ECON JOURNAL WATCH 9(2)
May 2012: 78-99
Freedom Versus Coercion
in Industrial Ecology:
A Reply to Boons
Pierre Desrochers1
LINK TO ABSTRACT
One of the signal advances made by this many-sided century has been in invention and
industry. In no way has this progress been more vividly shown than in its conquest of
waste. Nature, despite her marvellous prodigality, when closely studied, is seen to waste
nothing, to use and to re-use all things in unending cycles of activity. At the miraculous
feeding of the five thousand, when loaves and fishes were multiplied without sting, it
was commanded that the people should gather up the fragments that remained, that
nothing be lost. This lesson, carried out by Science as an instructive lesson in economy,
contains most interesting instances.
—William George Jordan (“Wonders of the World’s Waste,”
The Ladies’ Home Journal, October 1897, page 8)
“Industrial ecology” (IE) is an emerging interdisciplinary perspective whose
proponents have been based by and large in business and engineering schools.
Industrial ecologists adopt a systems approach to study material flows between
firms and industries and seek ways to reduce their effects on natural systems.
Common among the pioneers of IE was a belief that the institutional constraints of
market economies were not conducive to the development of “loop closing,” that
is, the development of by-product recycling linkages between firms operating in
1. University of Toronto Mississauga, Mississauga, ON L5L 1C6.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
78
DESROCHERS
different lines of work. One of their early goals was to devise various public policy
measures to correct this alleged market failure (Ayres and Ayres 2002).
Coming from a different academic background, I had independently
developed an interest in the history of loop closing and had reached the opposite
conclusion on the subject before coming across the IE literature in the late 1990s.
I submitted my alternative take on the issue to the Journal of Industrial Ecology and
its editors accepted two articles by me. I followed up with additional papers in
different outlets exploring other dimensions of the subject (Desrochers 2000;
2002a; 2002b; 2002c; 2004; 2005). In recent years I have explored the history of
by-product development in the coal gas, iron making (slag), and synthetic dyes
industries (Desrochers 2008b and 2009a), the source material available to
document past loop closing (Desrochers 2007; Desrochers and Lam 2007),
antecedents to the so-called “Porter Hypothesis” (Desrochers 2008a), the work of
Peter Lund Simmonds and Lyon Playfair in promoting by-product development
in Victorian England (Desrochers 2009b; 2011) and the history of industrial
symbiosis (i.e., geographically localized loop closing) in economic and geographical
thought (Desrochers and Leppälä, 2010).
In his “History’s Lessons: A Critical Assessment of the Desrochers Papers,”
Frank Boons2 (2008) criticizes several of my papers published during the years
2000 to 2005. Boons challenges my two main conclusions, namely: 1) loop closing
was widespread before 1900; 2) it was overwhelmingly the result of free-market
interactions. Boons also criticizes me for failing to incorporate structural, cultural,
and political considerations. My conclusions are “overly simple,” my policy prescriptions “naïve,” and my case on behalf of the “market as the preferred coordinating structure to stimulate interfirm recycling” untenable (Boons 2008,
148-149). This reply will revisit my two main points and engage Boons’s arguments,
evidence, and interpretations. I also treat the related work of business historian
Christine Meisner Rosen. A draft of the present reply was submitted to the journal
in which Boons’s critique of me appeared, the Journal of Industrial Ecology, but was
rejected after being peer reviewed.
On the Use and Abuse of Historical Sources
The most important sources for the claims made in the papers treated by
Boons include Peter Lund Simmonds (1862; 1876), who researched by-product
development and loop closing for decades and created a major exhibit on the
subject (Desrochers 2009b; 2011); Charles Lipsett (1963), the founder and director
2. Boons’s webpage is at http://www.eur.nl/fsw/staff/homepages/boons/ (link).
79
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
of a publishing house devoted to the waste trades; John B. C. Kershaw (1928) and
Theodor Koller (1918), respectively a chemical engineer and a chemist with years
of practical experience in various industries; and Paul Razous (1937/1921; 1905), a
French engineer who worked for several years as a governmental safety inspector.
These sources, however, represent only a small fraction of the material used in
my early papers. For instance, in Desrochers (2000), I referred to specialized
monographs on animal by-products, waste tomato seeds and skins, waste oranges,
waste liquid residues for metallurgical operations, residues from paper
manufacturing operations, and fish, wood, silk, brewery, cotton, and cement waste,
among others. Like Perry (1908)—another source I quoted occasionally—these
and other authors argued along the lines that “the commercial spirit of [the] age has
developed wonderful genius for utilizing waste products” (71); that “the greatest
source of wealth, in these days of great riches, has been acquired largely through the
wise use of that which men term waste. In all departments of life men have studied
how to utilize to the utmost the refuse and remnants that follow in the wake of
legitimate enterprise” (12-13); and that “Men are more and more patterning after
the Maker and turning everything into a source of wealth. It is a law of nature and
the closer that we keep to this law the wiser and wealthier we grow” (28).
Boons’s critique, however, is essentially limited to my use of general
overviews and omits specialized monographs. His most important point is that
their authors do not support my contention that loop closing was widespread
before 1900. Instead, they
describe technological possibilities for material recovery (inventions)
and—for some of these—their commercial exploitation by at least one
firm at some point in time. The authors do not go into the question
of how widespread the application is in a certain country. And in many
cases, these authors show that there are more waste streams to be
addressed and discuss innovations that await commercial exploitation.
In short, although technological possibilities are described, they do not
constitute proof of widespread practice. (Boons 2008, 150-151)
Boons is right that several potential opportunities were raised by Simmonds
and others, but all of them also specifically observed that countless problematic
residuals had been converted into profitable by-products (as illustrated in, among
other writings, my subsection “Turn-of-the-Century Assessments of Closed
Loops” in Desrochers 2000). Furthermore, the publishing rationale for devoting
much attention to the former rather than the latter was rather straightforward. As
one anonymous reviewer of Koller’s first (German) edition observed:
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
80
DESROCHERS
The utilisation of waste products has been for years a favorite subject
with technologists… The appearance of a work like the present [Koller]
is therefore quite in accordance with the spirit of the age, especially as
there prevail very crude notions as to what may and what may not be
profitably extracted from refuse. The author has attempted to select
from a superfluity of materials only such processes as the practical man
may apply with advantage—a task which he recognizes as difficult. Such
a work, to be really valuable, should contain nothing but what will readily
approve itself on a working scale, and nothing which is already
thoroughly familiar to manufacturers and technologists. (Anonymous
1880, 33)
The editors of the American trade journal The Manufacturer and Builder (1884,
98) made similar points in their discussion of Simmonds’s work when they pointed
out that finding a profitable use for the waste of industries opens “a rich field…
to the enterprising inventors,” that the Danish-born journalist’s contribution was
the “most instructive book for the ambitious technologist and… man of practice
to read,” and that it contained “a hundred suggestions, with latent possibilities of
rich reward, to inspire his zeal.” In short, the authors of these broad overviews
had no incentives to delve into relatively well-known practices or to document
the detail of their economic impact, especially at a time when reliable economic
data were scarce or non-existent. Discussing potentially profitable opportunities,
however, increased the marketability of their work. Despite the fact that they do
not always provide in-depth coverage of the most common and successful byproduct recovery practices of their time, these books remain the best general
treatments available on the subject and, along with other contemporary
documents, provide much more evidence as to the widespread nature of the
practice than Boons is willing to admit.
My stance finds support in the recent work of O’Brien (2008, 6) who apparently rediscovered this material without prior knowledge of my work and
similarly concludes that “although waste is usually construed as the curse of profit
and innovation, the fact is that uncountable wastes have entered, and continue
to enter, into industrial production.” Indeed, “some of these wastes have been
so central to the social and industrial development of modern societies that it is
impossible to imagine what the world today might look like without them” (idem).
O’Brien (2008, xiii) observes that there is much material on the issue, and that he
was left “with such vast heaps of research papers, media stories, social science and
engineering books that the small study in my house looks more like a landfill site
than a place of scholarly activity.”
81
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
Since 2000, when I published my first papers on the topic, new technologies
have made searching old sources much easier. Indeed, I have located much
additional evidence to back up my earlier assessments.3 That said, “rigorous”
quantification of the type favoured by engineers and economic historians remains
an impossible goal when dealing with by-product linkages, a point acknowledged in
1902 by no less an authority than the Chief Statistician for Manufactures of the U.S.
Census, in the preface to a bulletin on The Utilization of Wastes and By-Products: “[I]t is
impossible to measure statistically the addition of wealth of the country created by
turning to some useful purposes the residues and by-products which were formerly
thrown away or left to rot.” He added that “the volume thus preserved and turned
to some useful account must be enormous” (Kittredge 1902, 1).
Additional quotes from Victorian Britons of which I was unaware when I
published my early papers can further illustrate, contra Boons (2008, 151), how
prevalent was this view. In the table that follows I have limited myself to sources
now freely available online, with one exception (Cornish 1892).
Table 1: Some Victorian Assessments on the Scale and Scope of
By-Product Development.
The valuable discoveries in chemistry which have been made of late
years, and their extensive application to the useful arts, have originated a
variety of trades more or less curious in their character, but exceedingly
important in their social effect. The active industry of many thousands of
the population is at this moment employed in a manner unheard of fifty
years ago; and it is gratifying to think that this employment is afforded,
to a large extent, by the converting of commodities long regarded as
worthless into articles of great commercial value and importance. The
trades thus originating, though of a unique and singular character, are not popularly
known, if known at all, beyond the narrow limits of their immediate connection.
(Anonymous 1851, 310, my emphasis)
At the present time period, commerce is making such demands for
increased supplies of various substances, that scientific men are carefully
studying the residue of every manufacture, and the special qualities of
each new product. (Anonymous 1863, 254)
3. For links to some of this material see Desrochers and Lam (2007) and the references listed at the end of
this paper.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
82
DESROCHERS
The progress of our great chemical manufactures during the last ten
years… appears chiefly to have been directed towards the utilisation of
waste substances. (Crookes 1863, 58)
One of the blessings of modern science presents itself in the form of
economy, frugality, utilisation. Things which were formerly thrown away
as waste are now applied to man’s purposes, to an extent far beyond our
general supposition. (Anonymous 1869, 807)
With the perpetual growth of civilisation and industry comes and equal
increase in the amount of waste products caused by each new
manufacture. Every industrial process has naturally among its resultant
numerous products besides that one to obtain which it is carried on. To
utilise such by-products has been a frequent object of modern invention.
Such efforts, when successful, may be considered as accumulating so
much pure gain, by turning a useless and, therefore, cumbersome, or
even a noxious product, into a valuable and useful material.
Manufacturers have learnt that there are very few things that are really
waste, while, thanks to the investigations of science, the list of really
waste substances is daily diminishing. Perhaps it would not be difficult to
frame a list of industries of which the by-products have become of nearly
equal importance with the main process, and it is certainly true of very
many of our principal manufacturing processes that they could hardly be
carried on but for the commercial value of products once stigmatised as
waste. (Anonymous 1873, 11).
The utilisation of waste products is a subject which ought to possess
a special interest for a manufacturing nation like ourselves. The phrase
itself is indeed something like a standing reproach, as it expresses a
fact—patent to all observers—that many possible sources of national
wealth are allowed to pollute the air we breathe and the water we drink,
or to accumulate in unsightly heaps, because we do not know how to
make them available for any useful purpose. Day by day, however, this
reproach diminishes, as patient ingenuity discovers the means of
rescuing from the category of waste products materials which may be
available for various industrial processes, and while much remains to be
done, it is encouraging to note how much had already been effected.
(Anonymous 1876, 57)
Numerous substances which were formerly thrown away, destroyed, or
neglected, are now utilized… A long list of instances of this class might
83
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
be adduced if it were necessary, some of them of very great importance.
(Gore 1882, 151-152)
“Waste nothing,” is the key-note of our material industry. Just as the
farmer turns even the weeds to account, as a manure for the fields which
they encumbered, so in all things we must utilize “refuse,” and see that
everything is of use, if we take it to the right place and put it to its right
use. (Platt 1883, 336)
It is a matter of history in Europe that in some instances what were
originally regarded as waste products have become, if not the principal
objects of manufacture, at least those upon which the success of the
undertaking, from a commercial point of view, depends. (Rennie 1887,
233)
A leading feature of the Victorian epoch has been the utilisation of waste
materials and by-products. (Anonymous 1887, 299)
A full account of the various inventions by which the utilization of the
bye-products has been brought about would fill a volume, and does in
fact actually fill many volumes of technical literature. (Cornish 1892, 209)
As I illustrated in my early and more recent papers, similar comments can
be found in all rapidly industrializing market economies at the time, and most
knowledgeable writers credited market institutions (the profit motive and property
rights) for this outcome. I cannot fully restate my arguments and supporting
evidence, but will now clarify and bolster my main points.
Free Enterprise, Governmental Planning and
Intervention, and Loop-Closing
Boons’s second goal is to challenge my assessment of the effect of market
institutions on the development of loop closing. He criticizes me on at least four
counts: 1) I allegedly failed to define and explain the workings of a “free market”
satisfactorily; 2) much evidence presented by Simmonds (1862; 1876) is from polities that cannot be considered market economies; 3) Talbot (1920) and Rosen
(2007) allegedly demonstrate significant market failures and the need and capability
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
84
DESROCHERS
for governmental interventions to generate more loop closing; 4) markets are social
constructions in which structure, politics, and culture play a larger roles.
Free markets and loop closing
My view of market economies is the one traditionally espoused by thinkers
of the (European) liberal tradition.4 Markets are defined by voluntary exchanges
within the context of a price system (and its attendant profits and losses) and the
protection of private property rights. In this context, the action of one person is
limited by the property rights of another. As a result of both the price system and
private property rights, market institutions have long ensured that wealth creation
proceeds in a way that is much more sustainable than is generally understood.
Sustainable wealth creation has been fostered in several ways. First, the profit
motive has long enticed creative businesspeople and their employees to wage war
on the waste of costly resources, a view endorsed by Karl Marx and others, as
discussed in my papers. Indeed, in more recent years I have come across the work
of many nineteenth- and twentieth-century analysts who held similar views. For
example, the author of the most successful American economic textbook of the
first half of the nineteenth century stressed the importance of consuming “every
utility possessed by any substance,” that “all the fragments and remnants should
be, so far as possible, employed to some valuable purpose,” and that “all the values
must be consumed in the most profitable manner” (Wayland 1837, 421-423).
Writing less than three decades later, the American environmentalist George
Perkins Marsh (1864, 37) observed in his classic Man and Nature that the
“utilization—or, as the Germans more happily call it, the Verwerthung, the
beworthing—of waste from metallurgical, chemical and manufacturing
establishments, is among the most important results of the application of science
to industrial purposes.” These “incidental products” of laboratories and factories,
Marsh added, “often become more valuable than those for the preparation of
which they were erected.” Johannes Rudolf Wagner (1877, 3), the author of the
influential German Handbook of Chemical Technology, similarly emphasized that the
“ideal of a chemical manufactory is that there should be no real waste products
at all, but only chief or main, and by-products. The better, therefore, the waste
products are applied to good and advantageous use, the more nearly the
manufactory will approach the ideal, and the larger will be the profit.”
4. This perspective is labeled classical liberalism in the American context. Anderson and Leal (2001) is an
influential work on environmental issues written from this perspective, but does not discuss industrial byproduct development in much detail.
85
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
Second, in a market system private property rights are protected by the rule
of law. That protection helped to ensure that substantial and unreasonable interferences with the use and enjoyment of private property resulting from
neighboring manufacturing activities could be tackled effectively by individuals
whose health and property suffered from such operations. In the Anglo-Saxon
world, recourse for abnormally dangerous conditions and activities could be had
through common law doctrines of negligence, trespass, nuisance, and strict liability.
The system allowed private parties to recover monetary damages for harm caused
and even in some cases to gain an injunction that could ultimately result in a polluter’s obligation to shut down its operation until emissions had been addressed.
Liability considerations in a market economy have long stimulated innovative behaviour and the development of “win-win” innovations (Desrochers 2008a). As
such, some loop-closing developments in market economies were partly motivated, contra Boons, by “ecological and human health effects” (Boons 2008, 153).
Of course, despite positive long-term trends, significant polluting emissions
could be observed at particular locations, for the development of practical and
profitable solutions often took much effort, resources and time. As one anonymous
contributor to The Warehousemen and Drapers’ Trade Journal observed in 1876:
Much, however, as society in general may be interested in the economical
use of the materials for manufacture… it has a still greater concern in the
matter from a sanitary point of view. A few years ago, the oily and soapy
liquors of our woollen factories were universally allowed to run to waste.
The streams and canals in the neighbourhood of the works became in
consequence intolerably filthy and offensive… The fatty acids, which
would have combined with earthy salts in the water ‘to form insoluble
soaps and slimy scum which give off unpleasant odours and injurious
gases,’ have been precipitated from the factory liquor by a simple
chemical process, and are thus not only prevented from becoming a
direct and all but unbearable nuisance—which is the most important
result for society at large—but are actually changed into a source of
profit for the manufacturer. (Anonymous 1876, 57)
This pattern of outcome was also obvious to an 1886 encyclopedia contributor:
In many branches of manufacture, especially in the earlier days of their
existence, certain portions of the materials used have been cast aside as
‘waste,’ that designation implying that such portions were available for
no useful purpose. As time had advanced, first in one branch, and then in
another, this ‘waste’ material has been experimented upon with a view to
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
86
DESROCHERS
finding some profitable use for it; and in most instances the experiments
have had a more or less satisfactory result. (Anonymous 1886, 464)
Although this should go without saying, specific problems at one point in time
do not constitute a refutation of the long-run benefits of market-generated loop
closing.
Loop closing in non-market economies
Boons suggests that my case is not helped by the presence of some loopclosing activities in non-market economies, such as Russia, Japan and Hawaii at
the time of Simmonds’s (1862; 1876) writings.5 Yet, it is their absence that would
be truly astonishing, for human ingenuity predates the development of market
institutions. Forms of loop closing or waste reuse can be observed in all human
societies—indeed, I provided a number of Neolithic illustrations to this effect in
Desrochers (2000). My argument has always been that market institutions were
better than other real-world alternatives in rewarding risk-taking and in giving
economic actors strong incentives to challenge the status quo. They were thus
essential for rapid, large-scale, and sustained progress in such matters, but this
is not to say that creative people in less favourable social environments did not
sometimes find valuable uses for waste materials. In other words, the level of
success achieved by the inhabitants of Victorian England cannot be dissociated
from the institutional regime under which they lived. Burdened with extensive
governmentalization and restrictions of all kinds, the same individuals would not
have achieved similar results.
Government intervention, public planning, and loop closing
Mercantile activities have been denigrated by countless intellectuals since at
least Plato. The profit motive is denounced as encouraging selfishness and avarice
and as rewarding polluting emissions in order to reduce production costs. Some
version of this vision obviously underlies both Boons’s case against my papers and
the two main sources he uses to support his argument, Talbot (1920) and Rosen
(2007).
5. Of course, in practice all economic/social systems exhibit varying degrees of freedom and coercion.
To my knowledge, the use of currency was widespread in Russia and Japan at the time, while whalers and
traders had long integrated Pacific islands into the world economy.
87
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
Frederick Ambrose Talbot
Beginning in the late nineteenth century, a perspective emerged suggesting
that market economies were inherently wasteful. To give one illustration, Edward
Bellamy’s (1888, 157) fictional Looking Backward: 2000-1887 denounced the “four
great wastes” of the market system: “first, waste by mistaken undertakings; second,
the waste from the competition and mutual hostility of those engaged in industry;
third, the waste by periodical gluts and crises, with the consequent interruptions of
industry; fourth, the waste from idle capital and labor, at all times.” In Bellamy’s
and later writers’ view, the economic revolution associated with industrialization
both enabled and required a revolution in social organization. He and they wanted
to insulate powerful technocrats from traditional market signals of profits and
losses so that they would, through a top-down public planning process, re-orient
production for use rather than profits. This vision was taken up by an increasing
number of economists, industrial engineers, “scientific management” consultants,
and conservationists.
Most authors who shared this “wasteful production” critique of free
enterprise, however, had literally nothing to say on by-product development. Two
exceptions are Henry J. Spooner’s (1918) Wealth from Waste and Stuart Chase’s
(1926) The Tragedy of Waste. Writing on the heels of various World War I national
planning efforts, both authors had special praise for German planning measures.6
As I have argued elsewhere, the collapse of centrally planned economies has
discredited their case. Building on insights of liberal economists such as Friedrich
Hayek, I traced the failure of governmentalization in general, and centrally planned
measures to close the loop on industrial residuals in particular, to three main causes:
1) the lack of individual incentives; 2) the misallocation of resources due to the
absence or distortion of the price system; and 3) the inability of central planners
to tap into the local knowledge and know-how possessed by people (Desrochers
2004; Desrochers and Ikeda 2003).
Frederick A. Talbot’s (1920) Millions from Waste is best read as a reflection
of the intellectual climate rather than as an accurate account of industrial behavior
and results of contemporary planning initiatives. A prolific popular writer on topics
such as the history of the Canadian railway, steamships, airplanes, and the movie
and oil industries, Talbot completed only one book on waste products and aimed
it not at industrialists but at the “uninitiated reader,” although he also hoped that
his contribution “may prove of certain service to those who are fully alive to the
potentialities of refuse of every description” (5).
6. I discuss the work of these authors and their comments on German wartime planning in Desrochers and
Ikeda (2003), a piece not referenced in Boons’s essay.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
88
DESROCHERS
Talbot made some valid points that I did not hesitate to use despite
misgivings about other aspects of his analysis. For example, his observations on
the recurring pattern in the “utilitarian conjugation of waste” through which
“waste—by-product—staple… constitutes the brief evolution of more than one of
the world’s leading lines of trading” (13-14); the fact that “to relate all the fortunes
which have been amassed from the commercialization of what was once rejected
and valueless would require a volume” (17-18); and that typical German industrial
behavior toward residuals was to view them as “so much raw material for another
line of endeavor” on which one “at once sets to work to attempt to discover some
use” (19).
Talbot, however, also engaged in some speculative historical and economic
interpretations that were influenced by the wartime planning and “wasteful
production” literatures. It is these passages that Boons uses to challenge my claims
on the benefits of market institutions. For example, he quotes Talbot as stating
that “the British race is generally assailed as being woefully improvident and remiss
in the profitable exploitation of waste” (149), a statement that I do not consider
credible in light of the numerous quotations already provided here and elsewhere
(Desrochers 2009a; 2009b; 2011). Like several British commentators at the time,
Talbot deplored both the failure of British dye-stuff manufacturers (whose main
input were light oils derived from coal tar, a residual of coal gas production) to
protect their original lead against German competitors7 and British industrialists’
apparent incapacity to develop several of their inventions into commercially
successful products.
Talbot’s critique of British dye-stuff manufacturers prompts Boons (151) to
ask “if Britain is the exemplary free market, then why could this be so?” And yet,
as Kealey (2008, 224) observes, the British chemical industry grew faster between
1881 and 1911 than any other industry in the country except for public utilities.
What actually happened at the time was that the German chemical industry grew
faster than any other on earth. Despite greater government involvement and some
significant successes, however, German GDP per capita in 1914 and 1939 still
represented only approximately 75% of the British one, a share similar to what it
was in the early nineteenth century (Kealey 2008, 218-219).
In short, free-market policies do not imply that an economy will outperform
its more dirigiste competitors in every industry (especially those that benefit from
extraordinary government support), but rather that it will typically be more
prosperous overall.8
7. I discuss this historical episode in more detail in Desrochers (2008b).
8. For a more detailed discussion and several empirical facts on this issue, see the economic freedom
projects headed by the Heritage Foundation (link) and the Fraser Institute (link).
89
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
Boons also mentions approvingly Talbot’s stance on the benefits of
recovering local waste in order to reduce foreign purchases, along with his fear
that resurging post-war international trade “might bring the country back to its old
habit” (151). I take Talbot’s position on this issue to be a reflection of wartime
propaganda which singled out allegedly successful initiatives in this respect in both
the UK and Germany. Interestingly, however, he was much more circumspect in
the latter case than Spooner (1918) and Chase (1926), inasmuch as he admitted that
some German recovery initiatives “were grossly misrepresented and exaggerated”
(Talbot 1920, 76).
That was also the main conclusion of a more detailed survey on the Uses
of Waste Materials published a few years later under the aegis of the International
Institute of Agriculture of Rome (Bruttini 1923).9 The objective of this work was
to document the wartime legislative, administrative, and technical measures taken
in various countries to encourage “the collection and conversion by manufacturing
processes of waste material in view of their utilisation as food or feedingstuffs, in
the manufacture of fertilisers… etc.” (vii). Not surprisingly, the author devoted
most of his efforts on the German case and found that virtually none of these
practices proved superior to pre-War alternatives.10 The following quotation
critical of the German war food policy and rationing by a member of the Reichstag
and Prussian Diet is illustrative:
Even in the Central Committee of the Reichstag we have had to listen
to an address delivered by an official of the Imperial Ministry for the
Interior… which would have realised the wildest dreams of the
agrarians. The orator brought home to us the fact that by drying lees,
grinding straw, weeds, carcases, fish, by working up food refuse, etc. we
should be able, even during the war, and better still afterwards, to fill
the gaps in our forage reserves. But the songster then became mute. A
member of the Committee having asked Dr. HELFERICH whether this
new branch of production was remunerative, the latter… had to reply
“that the manufacture of the said substitutes is so costly that the question
is bound to arise whether once the war is over, their preparation should
be continued; the highly vaunted drying of lees, especially, is so costly,
that in certain exceptional cases they might perhaps be used as a feed for
sick animals, but never for livestock as a whole… The importance of the
9. The International Institute of Agriculture was dissolved and its functions and assets transferred to the
Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations in 1946.
10. Durr (2006) reaches a somewhat similar conclusion in his analysis of World War II American recycling
campaigns.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
90
DESROCHERS
utilisation of table refuse and that of wild plants (e.g., thistles) has been
greatly exaggerated…
Many draught animals in towns and in the country have died from
inanition, the official ration given them being quite insufficient to sustain
them. The situation was somewhat ameliorated when establishments
for treating straw were set up, which gave good results everywhere…”
(Bruttini 1923, 36-37)
In other words, much evidence suggests that the termination of numerous wartime
recovery efforts was a vindication of the greater efficiency and economic value
of pre-war trading activities. Furthermore, the fact that Talbot thought he had
identified allegedly better ways of conducting business than practices that had
actually survived competitive pressures should be met with skepticism, for he
obviously lacked the in-depth knowledge of practitioners and was unlikely to know
about all the trade-offs involved in his various suggestions.
In the end, while Talbot has interesting things to say, a portion of his analysis
reflects the increasingly dominant mistaken perspectives of his time and cannot be
used as evidence that governmental planning is a more desirable way to coordinate
inter-firm recovery linkages.
Christine Meisner Rosen11
In her recent work, business historian Christine Meisner Rosen (2007, 340)
writes that the most innovative American meatpackers found “profit in the wastes
that their contemporaries were throwing away,” but strongly emphasizes that
“sanitary regulation, pollution litigation and public protest” played a crucial role
in the modernization of the industry. Boons uses this article to champion the idea
that, above and beyond the protection offered by private property rights, increasing
the number and scope of governmental interventions can induce short-sighted
producers to devote more effort to the development of “win-win” innovations.
Yet, while it is true that Rosen argues that political interventions were needed
to bring about loop closing, Boons is apparently unaware of her remarkable
departure from her earlier writings in which she argued that loop closing was
almost nowhere to be observed in the industrial age and that early twentiethcentury engineers dealt with industrial pollution “primarily through the development and installation of end-of-pipe pollution-abatement and treatment
technologies” (Rosen 2003, 329). For instance, Rosen (1997, 126) wrote that
“[m]aterials used in manufacturing flow from the biosphere into the production
11. Rosen’s webpage is at http://facultybio.haas.berkeley.edu/faculty-list/rosen-christine (link).
91
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
process and back into the biosphere in the form of air and water pollution and solid
waste. From there they are rarely returned to the production process. Humans have
done little to recycle the materials used in the industrial world…” In spite of these
revisions, Rosen still argues against the role of markets in encouraging loop closing.
As I have detailed elsewhere (Desrochers 2008a), regulations and litigation
have long triggered some by-product development in a broad range of industries.
The idea that they were more important than the profit motive, as Rosen and
Boons argue, implies that industrialists who daily watched wasted inputs go down
drains, out smokestacks, or into waste bins were systematically unalert to the
lucrative opportunities they represented, while less knowledgeable and less
motivated outsiders knew better. Rosen (2007, 308) suggests that most American
meatpackers “were intensely disinterested… in turning their wastes into valuable
products and of doing anything beyond what they were already doing to abate their
stenches.” This is highly unlikely, based on both theory and evidence. While it
might be the case that most individuals, whatever their line of work, are resistant
to change once they are set in their ways, the fact that such behavior impairs
profitability and even survival of any firm in a competitive economy has also long
been understood by business people and researchers alike.
Rosen’s argumentation is incompatible with much available evidence. First,
by-product development was occurring on a large scale in a wide range of industries
that were not targeted to the same extent by public health officials and regulators.
Second, relatively sophisticated loop-closing operations existed in the American
meatpacking industry long before her study period (1865-1880). To give one
example, Wayland (1837, 423) describes New England industrial linkages where
soap, candle, glue and “neat’s [bovine] foot oil” operations were connected to
larger slaughterhouses, the refuse of which was used to fatten a substantial number
of hogs, insuring in the process that “every part of the slaughtered animal is
profitably consumed.” Third, similar arrangements could be observed in contemporary locations where manufacturers did not benefit from the presence of
American regulators and public health officials. Indeed, according to Simmonds
(1876, 40):
In all civilised and densely-populated countries, of the animals used for
the food of man, it may be said that nothing is wasted, every part that
is not eaten being turned to some useful purpose; the refuse fat is
converted into tallow or soap, the greater portion of the skin is made into
leather, and the scraps, with the hoofs, feet, and membranes, converted
into glue, the horns made into various useful articles, and the bones
produce phosphorus and manure.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
92
DESROCHERS
Lastly, another problem in Rosen’s and Boons’s perspective is their view of
electoral politics, especially their belief that American municipal governments
during the heydays of machine politics were following the dictates of publicminded health officials. Not only is it unlikely that the health officials were in
charge, it is also possible that the reluctance of businessmen to submit to the
regulations singled out by Rosen was an attempt to avoid coming under the direct
control of political figures such as “Boss Tweed.” And even if saint-like reformers
spearheaded public health initiatives, the powers of health officials might have
been appropriated in time by individuals of lesser purity who might have then used
various means to extract bribes, such as controlling both the access and the size of
operations in state-run abattoirs.12
Another problem with Rosen’s and Boons’s “public interest” perspective
is that, as Adam Smith never tired of telling us, well established industrialists are
fond of using the political process to serve their own interests. They may have
influenced new regulations to make it more difficult for small firms to compete
with larger operations. Well established businesspersons have always had two ways
to increase or maintain their market shares. The first is to compete by voluntary
means. The second is to use the political process to enact restrictions of various
sorts in order to suppress or hinder competition. Much evidence suggests less
charitable motives behind the advent of early environmental regulations, such as
rent-seeking opportunities and the trampling of private property rights by the
enactment of statutory laws that in effect legalized pollution (Meiners and Morriss
2000; Brubaker 1995; 2007).
Boons’s “complex” analysis and prescription
Boons’s own historical perspective on loop-closing development borrows
from the business history and economic sociology literatures in an attempt to
incorporate structural, political and cultural considerations. Some of his arguments
are interesting, while others display his own inadequate historical knowledge and
understanding of the case for free enterprise. For example, he argues that the
“market mechanism can be seen in some cases to assist in bringing about recycling
practices, but in other cases it contributes to their abandonment. Thus simple
conclusions cannot be drawn.” (156) He does not realize it, but the process he
describes reflects one of the most beneficial aspects of markets, the process of
“creative destruction” and its constant tendency to redirect resources from good
12. My view of electoral politics has been shaped and is much closer to the work of, among others,
Buchanan and Tullock (1999/1962) or Mitchell and Simmons (1994), than to any “public interest”
perspective on the issue.
93
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
to better uses. Improvements are delivered to the vast majority of consumers, and
producers are impelled to use resources more efficiently and creatively.
Contrary to Boons’s charge, my argument for leaving decision-making to
free enterprise is not simplistic at all. It actually entails a much more complex
approach than the most detailed five-year plan. What the Smith-Hayek stance
implies is that millions of individuals with very different perspectives and expertise
should be allowed to tackle, within the bounds of commutative justice, the
problems they face.
By contrast, the incentive structure in which government bureaucrats and
elected officials operate is inherently less conducive to innovation and efficient
reallocation because they are rarely held accountable for their inertia or bad
decisions. As an early British critic of socialism observed, “functionaries are under
a chronic temptation to keep on standing upon old paths. They habitually defend
the machinery and the methods to which they have got accustomed, and treat
with coolness all proposals of reform or improvement” (Robertson 1891, 58).
Similarly, politicians are under constant pressures to defend the status quo and bail
out poorly run operations. Their decisions to use other people’s money to save
wealth-destroying jobs in favored industries necessitate that other jobs in other
industries will be lost. The more governmentalized production becomes, the less
efficient and creative the economy becomes.
Ultimately, it seems clear that the available historical evidence supports my
basic dichotomy between free-enterprise and politico-bureaucratic decisionmaking processes, along with their recurring patterns of outcome.
Conclusion
Like most sustainable development theorists, Boons discounts the notion
that free enterprise might be capable of directing individuals towards both economic and environmental progress. He states as much when he argues that the
“minimalist approach” to the IE metaphor (which is limited to closing the loop
on industrial waste) “cannot serve as a basis to develop policy prescriptions for a
field in which the central concern is not the economic viability of closing loop but
rather the reduced ecological impacts that results from it.” What ultimately matters,
he says, “is not so much the quantity of instances in which material recovery is
practiced but their quality: the extent to which the loops of a system are closed
and harmful effects are prevented. This makes the modern concept of IE
fundamentally different.” (153)
The primary result of market institutions is improved standards of living.
It cannot be denied, of course, that some (sometimes significant) environmental
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
94
DESROCHERS
damage has resulted from specific market activities. It seems obvious, however,
that many individuals were and are still willing to make that trade-off, and that, over
time, the environmental track record of market economies is superior to that of any
real-world alternative in which government intervention brings its heavy hand to
issues of IE.
Looking at a more recent time period, and in particular and in the economic
and environmental divergence between market and centrally-planned economies
in the second half of the twentieth century, Bernstam (1990) argues that changes
in the amount of wastefully used resources, rather than increased production and
consumption levels, ultimately determine the relationship between economic
growth and pollution. In other words, when the growth in output exceeds the
growth in resource input required, material wealth will increase while pollution
levels decline. On the other hand, a poorer economy that uses a smaller amount
of resources less efficiently will experience greater environmental damage.13 It is
my hope that a more open-minded reading of my work will help sustainable
development theorists come around to this view.
References
Anderson, Terry L. and Donald Leal. 2001. Free-Market Environmentalism, revised
edition. New York: Palgrave.
Anonymous. 1851. The Value of Rubbish. The Living Age 30: 122-126 (originally
printed in Chambers’ Edinburgh Journal). Link
Anonymous. 1863. Review of Waste Products and Undeveloped Substances by Peter
Lund Simmonds. Popular Science Review 2: 254-258. Link
Anonymous. 1869. Waste Not! Chambers’s Journal of Popular Literature, Science and
Arts 4th Series (312): 807. Link
Anonymous. 1873. Review of Waste Products and Undeveloped Substances by P. L.
Simmonds. Journal of the Society of Arts 22 (1096): 11.
Anonymous. 1876. Waste. The Warehousemen and Drapers’ Trade Journal 5 (Feb. 12):
57. Link
Anonymous. 1880. Review of Handbuch der rationellen Verwerthung Weidergewinnung
und Verarbeitung von Abfall stiffen jeder Art by Theodor Koller. The Chemical
News and Journal of Physical Science (July 16): 33-34. Link
Anonymous. 1884. Some Words to Inventors. The Manufacturer and Builder 16(5):
98. Link
13. I expand on Bernstam’s argument in Desrochers 2010.
95
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
Anonymous. 1886. The Utilisation of “Waste Materials.” In Hazell’s Annual
Cyclopaedia, ed. E. D. Price. London: Hazell, Watson, and Viney, 464. Link
Anonymous. 1887. Her Majesty’s Jubilee—A Scientific Retrospect. The Chemical
News and Journal of Physical Science LV: 299-300. Link
Ayres, Robert U. and Leslie W. Ayres. 2002. A Handbook of Industrial Ecology.
Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.
Bellamy, Edward. 1888. Looking Backward: From 2000 to 1887. Boston: Hougton,
Mifflin and Company. Link
Bernstam, Mikhail S. 1990. The Wealth of Nations and the Environment.
Population and Development Review 16 (Supplement: Resources, Environment,
and Population, no. 2): 333-373.
Boons, Frank. 2008. History’s Lessons: A Critical Assessment of the Desrochers
Papers. Journal of Industrial Ecology 12(2): 148-158. Link
Brubaker, Elizabeth. 1995. Property Rights in the Defence of Nature. Toronto:
Earthscan Publications.
Brubaker, Elizabeth. 2007. Greener Pastures. Decentralizing the Regulation of
Agricultural Pollution. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Bruttini, Arturo. 1923. Uses of Waste Materials. London: P. S. King & Son Ltd.
Buchanan, James and Gordon Tullock. 1999 [1962]. The Calculus of Consent:
Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Link
Chase, Stuart. 1926 [1925]. The Tragedy of Waste. New York: Macmillan.
Cornish, Vaughn. 1892. Bye-Products Versus Waste-Products. Knowledge,
November 1: 208-209.
Crookes, William. 1863. Chemical Products—The Application of Waste. The
Popular Science Review II(5): 58-70. Link
Desrochers, Pierre. 2000. Market Processes and the Closing of “Industrial
Loops.” Journal of Industrial Ecology 4(1): 29-43.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2002a. Does It Pay to Be Green? Some Historical
Perspective. In Sustainable Development: Promoting Progress or Perpetuating Poverty?,
edited by J. Morris. London: Profile Books. Link
Desrochers, Pierre. 2002b. Industrial Ecology and the Rediscovery of Inter-Firm
Recycling Linkages: Historical Evidence and Policy Implications. Industrial
and Corporate Change 11(5): 1031-1057.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2002c. Natural Capitalists’ Indictment of Traditional
Capitalism: A Reappraisal. Business Strategy and the Environment 11(4): 203-220.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2004. Industrial Symbiosis: The Case for Market
Coordination. Journal of Cleaner Production 12(8-10): 1099-1110.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
96
DESROCHERS
Desrochers, Pierre. 2005. Learning from History or from Nature or from Both?:
Recycling Networks and Their Metaphors in Early Industrialisation. Progress
in Industrial Ecology 2(1): 19-34.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2007. How Did the Invisible Hand Handle Industrial Waste?
By-Product Development Before the Modern Environmental Era. Enterprise
and Society 8(2): 348-374. Link
Desrochers, Pierre. 2008a. Did the Invisible Hand Need a Regulatory Glove
to Develop a Green Thumb? Some Historical Perspective on Market
Incentives, Win-Win Innovations and the Porter Hypothesis. Environmental
and Resource Economics 41(4): 519-539. Link
Desrochers, Pierre. 2008b. Bringing Inter-Regional Linkages Back In: Industrial
Symbiosis, International Trade and the Emergence of the Synthetic Dyes
Industry in the Late 19th Century. Progress in Industrial Ecology 5(5-6): 465-481.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2009a. Does the Invisible Hand Have a Green Thumb?
Market Incentives and the Development of Wealth from Industrial Waste in
Victorian England. Geographical Journal 175 (1): 3-16.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2009b. Victorian Pioneers of Corporate Sustainability.
Business History Review 83 (4): 703-729.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2010. The Environmental Responsibility of Business Is to
Increase Its Profits (by Creating Value Within the Bounds of Private
Property Rights). Industrial and Corporate Change 19(1): 161-204.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2011. Promoting Corporate Environmental Sustainability in
the Victorian Era: The Bethnal Green Museum Permanent Waste Exhibit
(1875-1928). V&A Online Journal, Issue 3. Link
Desrochers, Pierre and Sanford Ikeda. 2003. On the Failure of Socialist
Economies to Close the Loop on Industrial By-Products: Insights from the
Austrian Critique of Planning. Environmental Politics 12(3): 102-122.
Desrochers, Pierre and Karen Lam. 2007. “Business as Usual” in the Industrial
Age: (Relatively) Lean, Green and Eco-Efficient. Electronic Journal of
Sustainable Development 1(1): 35-46. Link
Desrochers, Pierre and Samuli Leppälä. 2010. Industrial Symbiosis: Old Wine
in Recycled Bottles? Some Perspective from the History of Economic and
Geographical Thought. International Regional Science Review 33(3): 338-361.
Durr, Kenneth D. 2006. The “New Industrial Philosophy”: US Corporate
Recycling in World War II. Progress in Industrial Ecology 3(4): 361-378. Link
Gore, George. 1882. The Scientific Basis of National Progress, Including That of Morality.
London: Williams and Norgate. Link
Jordan, William George. 1897. Wonders of the World’s Waste. The Ladies’ Home
Journal, October: 8.
Kealey, Terence. 2008. Sex, Science and Profits. London: William Heinemann.
97
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO BOONS
Kershaw, John B. 1928. The Recovery and Use of Industrial and Other Waste. London:
Ernest Benn.
Kittredge, Henry G. 1902. The Utilization of Wastes and By-Products in
Manufactures with Special Reference to the Decade of 1890-1900. U.S.
Census Bulletin (190), June 16. Link
Koller, Theodor. 1918. The Utilization of Waste Products. A Treatise on the Rational
Utilization, Recovery, and Treatment of Waste Products of All Kinds. 3rd revised
edition, translated from the 2nd revised German edition. New York: D. Van
Nostrand Company. Link
Lipsett, Charles S. 1963. Industrial Wastes and Salvage: Conservation and Utilization.
2nd edition. New York: Atlas Publishing Company.
Marsh, George Perkins. 1864. Man and Nature, or Physical Geography as Modified by
Human Action. New York: Charles Scribner. Link
Meiners, Roger E. and Andrew P. Morriss, eds. 2000. The Common Law and
the Environment: Rethinking the Statutory Basis for Modern Environmental Law.
Boulder, Colo.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Mitchell, William C. and Randy T. Simmons. 1994. Beyond Politics. Markets,
Welfare, and the Failure of Bureaucracy. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press and the
Independent Institute.
O’Brien, Martin. 2008. A Crisis of Waste? Understanding the Rubbish Society. London:
Routledge.
Perry, George P. 1908. Wealth from Waste, or Gathering Up the Fragments. New York:
Fleming H. Revell Company.
Platt, James. 1883. Platt’s Essays. Vol. 1: Business—Money—Economy. London:
Simpkin, Marshall, and Co. Link
Razous, Paul. 1905. Les déchets industriels. Récupération—Utilisation. Paris: Ch.
Dunod.
Razous, Paul. 1937 [1921]. Les déchets et sous-produits industriels. Récupération—
Utilisation. Paris: Ch. Dunod.
Rennie, Edward H. 1887. President’s address. Transactions and Proceedings and
Reports of the Royal Society of South Australia IX: 225-233. Link
Robertson, Edward Stanley. 1891. The Impracticability of Socialism. In A Plea
for Liberty: An Argument Against Socialism and Socialistic Legislation, ed. Thomas
Mackay. New York: D. Appleton, 35-78. Link
Rosen, Christine Meisner. 1997. Industrial Ecology and the Greening of
Business History. Business and Economic History 26(Fall): 123-137.
Rosen, Christine Meisner. 2003. Industrial Ecology and the Transformation of
Corporate Environmental Management: A Business Historian’s Perspective.
In Inventing for the Environment, eds. Arthur Molella and Joyce Bedi.
Cambridge: MIT Press, 319-338.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
98
DESROCHERS
Rosen, Christine Meisner. 2007. The Role of Pollution Regulation and Litigation
in the Development of the U.S. Meatpacking Industry, 1865-1880. Enterprise
& Society 8(2): 297-347.
Simmonds, Peter L. 1862. Waste Products and Undeveloped Substances; or, Hints for
Enterprise in Neglected Fields. London: Robert Hardwicke. Link
Simmonds, Peter L. 1876. Waste Products and Undeveloped Substances: A Synopsis of
Progress During the Last Quarter of a Century at Home and Abroad. 3rd edition.
London: Hardwicke and Bogue. Link
Spooner, Henry J. 1918. Wealth from Waste: Elimination of Waste, a World Problem.
London: G. Routledge. Link
Talbot, Frederick A. 1920. Millions from Waste. London: Fisher Unwin Ltd. Link
Wagner, Johannes R. 1877. A Handbook of Chemical Technology. Translated and
edited from the eighth German edition, with extensive additions, by William
Crookes. New York: D. Appleton and Company. Link
Wayland, Francis. 1837. The Elements of Political Economy. New York: Leavitt, Lord
& Company. Link
About the Author
Pierre Desrochers is Associate Professor of Geography at the
University of Toronto Mississauga. His main research interests
revolve primarily around economic development,
technological innovation, business-environment interactions,
energy policy and food policy. His website is at
http://epsem.erin.utoronto.ca/desrochers/ (link) and his
email is
[email protected].
Frank Boons’ reply to this article
Christine Meisner Rosen’s reply to this article
Go to Archive of Comments section
Go to May 2012 issue
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5757
99
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5758
ECON JOURNAL WATCH 9(2)
May 2012: 100-111
Freedom Versus Coercion in
Industrial Ecology: Mind the Gap!
Frank Boons1
LINK TO ABSTRACT
Mr. Turnbull had predicted evil consequences, …and was now doing the best in his
power to bring about the verification of his own prophecies.
—Anthony Trollope (Phineas Finn, Chapter 25,
as quoted in Popper 1963)
Pierre Desrochers’ article in this issue provides an extensive reply to my
assessment of his early work on the utilization of by-products in the nineteenth
century (Boons 2008a, hereafter referred to as “my critique”). I value the opportunity to engage in a debate about this topic, especially in a journal with a broader
economic focus. Understanding the ways in which firms deal with the by-products
of their production activities is crucial for understanding processes of innovation as
well as improving insight into the ecological impact of economic activities, themes
that are both at the core of economics.2 Embedding this understanding in longterm economic development is valuable because it links the interactions of
economic actors to macro-economic change. Such change is deemed necessary by
many analysts of modern societies that are concerned with issues such as climate
change and resource scarcity.
Understanding why clusters of by-product exchanges emerge and persist
over time requires a careful collection and analysis of empirical data, a task that
1. Erasmus Universiteit, Postbus 1738, 3000 DR Rotterdam, The Netherlands.
2. Although not every economist will place the study of ecological impact at the core of economics, when
such impacts are seen in terms of relative efficiency of production processes I am quite sure they will
concur.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
100
BOONS
is especially demanding when historical records are used. Historical sources never
fulfill the requirements that one would satisfy when collecting data in the present.
Part of my criticism of what I called the Desrochers papers dealt with what I felt to be
a lack of care in dealing with such sources. In addition, through misrepresenting
several key concepts in the analysis, conclusions were drawn that I felt to be
simplistic.
I am sorry to say that in his reply to my critique, such simplicity again rears
its head. In fact, all the points I raise below can be summarized into one sentence:
Reality is more nuanced than represented by Desrochers. In this contribution I
will try not to repeat my earlier critique. Instead, I add to points already made, and
include some recent insights from the field to which Desrochers has pointed his
arrows. My points are:
1. By-product use is a concept that needs to be carefully defined. If we
adopt the definition of Desrochers, then the whole economy is rife
with by-product use. For industrial ecology, the interest in by-product
exchange is associated with its potential to reduce ecological impact,
and therefore not all by-product use is equally relevant. A critique on
how industrial ecologists conceptualize the coordination of such
exchanges must work from the definition they use.
2. Industrial ecology (or sustainability science) is not one coherent set of
ideas put forward by a group of scientists in full consensus. As in any
scientific field, issues central to the field are hotly debated. The extent
to which by-product exchanges are facilitated by the market
mechanism is one of these issues. By pretending the field to be of one
mind, Desrochers ignores such debates. This makes it difficult for him
to see where he could contribute.
3. Governance in economic systems is complex and cannot be
adequately represented by using a simple dichotomy between the free
market and government, as Desrochers consistently does. Moreover,
care needs to be taken to look at such governance in its temporal
context.
Before I move on to these points, I feel the need to dwell for a moment on
a central principle of the scientific method: falsification. Put briefly, it states that
the best way to test a hypothesis is to search for evidence that forces one to reject
it (Popper 1963). My motivation for writing an assessment of Desrochers’ work
was not that I disliked his conclusions. Although he implies as much, I am not
out to prove that government is essential to solve the world’s problems. If there is
anything I believe in it would be ‘context dependency’, so I am highly suspicious of
any conclusion unconditionally in favor of either the market, planning or another
101
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
FREEDOM VERSUS COERCION: MIND THE GAP!
‘real world alternative’ as a way of coordinating economic activities. What moved
me in the first place was the apparent lack of attention for counter-evidence, even
when it was readily available in sources used by Desrochers.
According to Desrochers, by-product exchanges are a product of autonomous economic agents searching for innovative solutions, unhampered by governments that restrict their creativity. An important conclusion consistently drawn
by Desrochers is that free markets are essential for the widespread occurrence of
by-product exchange, as they provide a necessary context. This is clear from the
following quotations: “Whether contemporary or historical, all cases of interfirm
recycling linkages were primarily the result of entrepreneurial actions triggered by
cost calculations” (Desrochers 2002, 62), and “all successful, documented cases
of industrial symbiosis to this day have been self-organizing” (Desrochers 2004,
1099). The repeated use of the word “all” indicates that the free market is considered by Desrochers to be a necessary condition for by-product exchanges to
occur. To provide a solid foundation under this conclusion it is not enough to
provide examples of free market societies where by-product exchanges occur. A
strategy of falsification calls for sensitivity to evidence of situations where byproduct exchanges occur in the absence of free-market conditions. I found it striking
that the sources used by Desrochers provided such counter-evidence (i.e.,
nineteenth-century societies lacking free markets as defined by Desrochers, yet
displaying examples of by-product use). What was even more surprising: this
evidence was simply disregarded. Such selective use of sources again appears in his
2012 reply. Veiled in an advice to the reader (“Millions from Waste is best read as
…” (88)), Desrochers takes what he can use from Talbot’s Millions from Waste, but
dismisses observations by Talbot on the contribution that governments have made
and could make.3
The scientific strategy of falsification also provides a solution to a problem
otherwise facing Desrochers: no matter how much evidence he brings to the table
that reveals by-product use in free-market societies, it does not prove that other
societies have not displayed such exchanges in a similar frequency. In contrast,
examples of societies that lack the characteristics of a free market where by-product
exchanges occur provide compelling evidence that his hypothesis is incorrect.4
This is why such counter-evidence in his own sources cannot be easily dismissed,
as Desrochers again does in his reply.
3. I will not dissect the argument dealing with this; my 2008 critique has detailed references to the relevant
sections in Talbot (1920, full text available at www.archive.org (link)).
4. Thus, falsification is efficient. In that sense, the fact that Desrochers blames me for considering only part
of his sources is beside the point. If I find in his sources (or elsewhere) one example that conflicts with his
hypothesis, that suffices.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
102
BOONS
His counterargument is to attribute such examples to generic human ingenuity.5 But to remain consistent, this means that the free market is not a necessary
condition for by-product use, and the hypothesis should be rejected. If the
hypothesis is retained in the face of this evidence, the conclusion must be that the
free market is not a necessary condition, but a much weaker condition. Indeed,
in his reply Desrochers now states that his hypothesis is that market institutions
are “better” than other real life alternative coordination mechanisms (2012, 87).
Further research should then focus on what are additional, or alternative, conditions. As I will show below, looking at more complex constellations of conditions
that produce by-product exchanges is exactly where the field of industrial ecology
is currently heading.
Defining by-product exchange
Up till now I have used concepts in the way proposed by Desrochers in order
to do justice to his formulation of the hypothesis. This does not mean I agree with
his definitions. In fact, a central point in my critique concerns the conceptualization
of by-product exchanges. In order for his attack on industrial ecologists to make
sense at all, the way in which such exchanges are defined needs to match the
definition as used in the field of industrial ecology.6 This definition includes three
important elements:
• A by-product of the production process of one firm, previously
unused, is used as an input for a production process of another firm.
Thus, by-product exchange refers to a newly established relationship
where a substance or flow crosses the boundary between two or more
firms. It thus differs from loop closing and by-product development
in general, which may take place in the same firm;
• By-product exchanges occur in regionally bounded clusters. Rather
than being a bilateral phenomenon, they are considered as regional
networks of exchange, often referred to as industrial symbiosis;
5. In addition to such ad hoc arguments, Desrochers uses faulty reasoning. One example is the immunizing
argument about his sources being silent about the diffusion of by-product exchanges (2012, 80-81). This
can be summarized as: “The fact that authors did not describe the widespread diffusion of by-product
exchanges indicates that they were widespread.” If this is true, then his sources become completely
unreliable as evidence: When they describe A, this is evidence that A occurred; if they do not describe A, it
is also evidence that A occurred.
6. This discussion might give the impression that the field of industrial ecology deals mainly with byproduct exchanges. In fact, it deals with much more. For a recent overview see Lifset and Boons (2012).
103
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
FREEDOM VERSUS COERCION: MIND THE GAP!
• The exchange is considered, at least by the researcher, because of its
potential to reduce the ecological impact of the firms involved.
Desrochers uses various labels for his research subject throughout his work; in his
article in this issue he refers to it as loop closing and by-product development. As
I indicated in my critique, his definition differs from the one used by industrial
ecologists (Boons 2008a, 152-153). Loop-closing and by-product development
indicate the economically viable use of by-products within and across the firm’s
boundary, and at least some of his historical examples occur within firms, or are
silent about whether an organizational boundary is crossed. His definition is thus
broader in the sense that it refers to any use of waste (also within a firm’s boundary).
Also, Desrochers does not address that by-product exchange, and its development
over time, is conceptualized by industrial ecologists in terms of the emergence of
larger regional industrial clusters that engage in such exchanges.7 Indeed, the iconic
example of industrial symbiosis is a set of exchanges that evolved in Kalundborg,
Denmark. While broadening the concept in one direction, Desrochers’ definition
is stricter in the sense that it only considers loop closing that is economical. As a
result of this definition, his research subject is ubiquitous in economies. In fact,
it defines exactly that which constitutes an economic system, i.e., the exchange of
scarce goods among social individuals. At the same time, it has lost most of its
relevance as a separate research subject for industrial ecologists.
As a result of his specific conceptualization, ecological impact remains obscure and thus his reply to a major point of my critique comes almost as an
afterthought. Desrochers gives two arguments regarding ecological impact. One
is provided halfway in the article (86-87), and frames pollution as a temporal
distortion from the market equilibrium. The second argument appears in the
concluding remarks, where ecological impact is framed as the result of deliberate
weighing of values in a process of collective choice. The latter point simply states
that people will make trade-offs, and whatever comes out of that is acceptable
without further discussion. This disregards a whole literature that deals with the
fact that social life is a little bit more complicated, and can only be understood if
that complexity is taken into account.8 I devoted the second half of my critique to
sketching a conceptual framework to do so, which I will not repeat here.
The temporal distortion argument is interesting because it brings in a dimension I hinted at elsewhere (Boons and Howard-Grenville 2009), and that I now
think should be more central in the analysis of industrial ecology. This concerns the
7. In his later work Desrochers has started to analyse such larger regional clusters. There he refers explicitly
to industrial symbiosis.
8. Public choice theorists have encountered many problems in developing a market perspective on
collective decision-making.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
104
BOONS
dynamic aspect of exchanges among firms (Boons et al. 2011). Desrochers states
that ecological impacts in terms of unused by-products are temporal problems,
because it takes time to find ways of utilizing waste streams. In itself, this
argumentation is incomplete; I am curious what he has to say about the waste that
results from nuclear energy production. How long do we have to wait for human
ingenuity to find an economical use for that?
I fully agree that the temporal dimension needs to be taken into account in
the analysis of by-product exchange, but not in the way suggested by Desrochers.
He assumes an equilibrium, and negative effects are construed as temporal distortions of that situation. Given the emphasis he places on innovation, this is
awkward. If I build on Desrochers’ assumptions, I envision an economy where
human ingenuity leads to a continuous stream of innovations at the level of
individual entrepreneurs. Some of these provide solutions to existing by-products,
while others create new by-products.9 Thus, at the macro-level it is incorrect to
assume an equilibrium; instead, we have a complex system where exchanges are
continuously evolving. In such a system, a certain system state (such as an
equilibrium where negative ecological impacts are absent) cannot be assumed; it
must be empirically assessed. Such an empirical assessment would need to look at:
• The way in which exchanges evolve over time, i.e., what by-product
exchanges are realized and to what extent they continue to exist over a
longer time period (either as long-term relationships or as repeated
market exchanges among pools of suppliers and customers);
• The way in which by-product exchanges are widespread through an
economy; and
• The extent to which such by-product exchanges result in decreased
ecological impact.
In my opinion, such an empirical assessment will bring us a better understanding
of the way in which by-product exchanges emerge, evolve, and disappear in an
economic system. However, this kind of analysis is not provided by Desrochers.
Industrial ecology is an evolving field where
concepts and hypotheses compete
My second point concerns industrial ecology as a scientific field. In his conclusion, Desrochers states that “Like most sustainable development theorists,
9. Given the laws of thermodynamics, any use (i.e., transformation) of existing by-products will also result
in new by-products.
105
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
FREEDOM VERSUS COERCION: MIND THE GAP!
Boons discounts the notion that free enterprise might be capable of directing
individuals towards both economic and environmental progress.” (94). He ends his
conclusion with an indiscriminate call to all sustainable development theorists to
be more open-minded. This lumping together of scholars into a huge category is
again an act of simplification. I will not begin to discuss the diversity of ”sustainable
development theorists”; I am not sure where Desrochers draws the boundary here.
I can say something about the field of industrial ecology though, and the alleged
preference of its members (being part of the larger population of sustainable
development theorists) for relying on governments for coordinating economic
activities.10
In the field of industrial ecology, as in any living scientific field, full agreement over any conclusion is unlikely. Even in the conceptualization of Thomas
Kuhn, where scientific disciplines come to a paradigmatic stage in which a coherent
set of ideas guides the activities of scientists, there is room for anomalies, disputes,
etc. In my experience, scientific fields evolve gradually, with concepts, methods
and evidence competing (Toulmin 1972). Ignoring this reality by putting up a straw
man (i.e., the sustainable development theorist) may be an effective rhetorical
strategy, but I doubt if it is helpful in advancing the historical analysis of by-product
exchange.
Within the field of industrial ecology, by-product exchange is studied under
the label of industrial symbiosis. A recent special issue of the Journal of Industrial
Ecology on industrial symbiosis deals with many aspects of this phenomenon,
including the question of coordination mechanisms. Paquin and HowardGrenville (2012) discuss how symbiotic networks in the United Kingdom evolved
over an eight-year period. These networks were facilitated by NISP, a private
initiative supported by government. This program and its role in facilitating byproduct exchanges show that the dichotomy between market and government is
a false one. NISP shows how private initiative and governmental support complement each other in making regional markets for waste products more transparent. Paquin and Howard-Grenville also find that, over time, this leads to more
advanced, innovative exchanges.
Based on several research articles, Shi et al. (2012) provide an overview of
the efforts of the Chinese government to develop eco-industrial parks as part of
its national effort to become a Circular Economy. Such parks are regional clusters
of symbiotic exchanges. The Chinese experience also reveals that by-product
exchange has different shapes depending on local institutional contexts. The
10. The International Society of Industrial Ecology, founded in 2001, is an association with global
membership; at the 2011 biannual conference over 500 participants presented their work. I am sure they
do not all fit into the mould fabricated by Desrochers.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
106
BOONS
Circular Economy is an encompassing concept building on Asian principles, and
symbiotic exchanges are one of the forms through which the Chinese government
seeks to diminish the ecological impact of its rapid economic development.
Likewise, in South Korea the government has engaged with the National Centre
for Cleaner Production in implementing a series of five-year plans to build up an
infrastructure of industrial parks that facilitate symbiotic exchanges (Park et al.
2008).
Each of these developments shows how governmental agents take an active
role in establishing regional networks of symbiotic exchanges. They all provide
counter-evidence to the strong version of Desrochers’ hypothesis and the
conclusion he consistently draws about the superiority of the free market. In order
to test the weaker version of his hypothesis, these “real-world alternatives” to the
free market need to be empirically assessed rather than dismissed at face value,
lumped together into a category labeled “coercion.”
Desrochers is right in stating that in the early days of the field, there was an
assumption that industrial symbiosis required something additional to the market
mechanism. This assumption was based on the case studies of regional symbiotic
clusters then available (Boons et al. 2011). With increased availability of data this
assumption can now be put to the test. In an analysis of a dataset of 233 symbiosis
projects, Boons and Spekkink (2012) find that a social infrastructure as a complement to the market mechanism is not a necessary condition for industrial
symbiosis. This finding leads to a further refining of the concept of by-product
exchanges. When such exchanges involve standardized commodities of little
strategic interest to firms, the market mechanism suffices. If exchanges involve
more strategic resources and specific investments, additional conditions (i.e., social
infrastructure) need to be fulfilled. The government may play a role in bringing
about these conditions.
In all, the results of current research reveal that the coordination problem
for industrial symbiosis is more complex than a dichotomous choice with only one
right answer. Moreover, researchers in the field of industrial ecology have always
had the market mechanism as one important option in their conceptual frames. In
fact, from my perspective it is curious to see Desrochers hitting so hard on the field
of industrial ecology for its alleged reliance on government. Actually, industrial
ecology can be seen as one of the research fields dealing with sustainability where
people are sensitive to the idea that interacting firms within a market context can
to some extent move towards sustainability, and that planning is not the only way
(Costa and Ferrão 2010).
107
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
FREEDOM VERSUS COERCION: MIND THE GAP!
Governance beyond a simple dichotomy
A third important simplification takes place by narrowing the contest among
coordination mechanisms down to two alternatives: the free market against
government. The former is defined in the reply by Desrochers; the definition of the
latter can be built up by collecting the adjectives and examples throughout his work:
it amounts to something like a coercive socialist planning bureaucracy making fiveyear plans. This imagery, and the argumentation against it, is clearly inspired by the
work of Hayek.11 However, the insight that the market is an efficient mechanism
when information is distributed among a large group of autonomous economic
actors does not prevent a positive role for governmental agencies in economies.
While interesting as a philosophical and theoretical argument, Hayek’s conclusions
cannot be applied without further specification to any topic.
In my work on industrial symbiosis, I have found that first of all, not all
governmental involvement in stimulating by-product exchanges is of the five-year
plan, coercive, socialist kind.12 Governmental agencies have different tools at their
disposal, ranging from experimental projects to setting standards to inducing
private firms to pick up opportunities earlier ignored. Secondly, such instruments
are not often used as an alternative to the market; they are used in conjunction with
the market mechanism, or even seek to institute a market where none formerly
operated (see the example of NISP above). I have shown the delicate interplay
between different forms of governmental action and the activities of firms in my
longitudinal analysis of industrial symbiosis in the Rotterdam harbor area (Boons
2008b).
Being sensitive to the precise ways in which governmental agencies influence
firms and the operation of markets is especially relevant when dealing with historical evidence. In the second half of the nineteenth century, government was
not in any way like the caricature sketched by Desrochers. Instead, it was in full
development, and local pollution served as one of the issues around which governmental rule setting and enforcement at the local and national level crystallized. And
moving to the situation from the 1990s onwards, the governments that industrial
ecologists are referring to are hardly comparable with socialist planning regimes.
In the Western world, many politicians and civil servants have embraced liberal
11. For a link between Hayek’s critique of socialism and the ecological embeddedness of economies, see
the work of O’Neill (2002, 2004).
12. It is interesting that in the one article where Desrochers deals explicitly with societies that lack a free
market (Desrochers and Ikeda 2003), his examples are not taken from the nineteenth century but are
instead socialist economies of the kind that Hayek criticized.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
108
BOONS
principles, bringing the market mechanism to fields previously considered to be
in the public domain. At the same time, several of the societies where by-product
exchanges are rapidly developing are Asian economies that depart in some way
from the free-market ideal type. In my view, these constitute evidence for
developing insight into the topic Desrochers claims to be interested in: the way in
which by-product exchanges can be brought about.
To conclude, I am not impressed by the additional evidence provided by
Desrochers in his reply to my critique. What I have tried to show is that the field
he is attacking has developed substantially since he launched his first attacks, and
it continues to be engaged in a process of deepening our insight into the ways in
symbiotic exchanges can be brought about. In my estimate, careful consideration
of evidence in current societies will provide more material for developing our
understanding than will searching for more material that verifies a simplistic
argument pitting freedom against coercion.
References
Boons, Frank. 2008a. History’s Lessons: A Critical Assessment of the Desrochers
Papers. Journal of Industrial Ecology 12(2): 148-158. Link
Boons, Frank. 2008b. Self-Organization and Sustainability: The Emergence of
a Regional Industrial Ecology. Emergence: Complexity and Organization 10(2):
41-48.
Boons, Frank and Jennifer Howard-Grenville (eds.). 2009. The Social
Embeddedness of Industrial Ecology. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Boons, Frank, Wouter Spekkink, and Yannis Mouzakitis. 2011. The
Dynamics of Industrial Symbiosis: A Proposal for a Conceptual Framework.
Journal of Cleaner Production 19(9-10): 905-911.
Boons, Frank and Wouter Spekkink. 2012. Levels of Institutional Capacity and
Actor Expectations About Industrial Symbiosis: Evidence from the Dutch
Stimulation Program 1999-2004. Journal of Industrial Ecology 16(1): 61-69.
Costa, Inês and Paolo Ferrão. 2010. A Case Study of Industrial Symbiosis
Development Using a Middle-Out Approach. Journal of Cleaner Production
18(10-11): 984-992.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2002. Regional Development and Inter-industry Recycling
Linkages: Some Historical Perspectives. Entrepreneurship & Regional
Development: An International Journal 14(1): 49-65.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2004. Industrial Symbiosis: The Case for Market
Coordination. Journal of Cleaner Production 12(8-10): 1099-1110.
109
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
FREEDOM VERSUS COERCION: MIND THE GAP!
Desrochers, Pierre. 2012. Freedom Versus Coercion in Industrial Ecology: A
Reply to Boons. Econ Journal Watch 9(2): 78-99. Link
Desrochers, Pierre and Sanford Ikeda. 2003. On the Failure of Socialist
Economies to Close the Loop on Industrial By-Products: Insights from the
Austrian Critique of Planning. Environmental Politics 12(3): 102-122.
Lifset, Reid and Frank Boons. 2012. Industrial Ecology: Business Management
in a Material World. In The Oxford Handbook of Business and the Natural
Environment, eds. Pratima Bansal and Andrew J. Hoffman. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 310-326.
O’Neill, John. 2002. Socialist Calculation and Environmental Valuation: Money,
Markets and Ecology. Science and Society 66(1): 137-151.
O’Neill, John. 2004. Ecological Economics and the Politics of Knowledge: The
Debate Between Hayek and Neurath. Cambridge Journal of Economics 28:
431-447.
Paquin, Raymond and Jennifer Howard-Grenville. 2012. The Evolution of
Facilitated Industrial Symbiosis. Journal of Industrial Ecology 16(1): 83-93.
Park, Hung-Suck, Eldon Rene, Soo-Mi Choi, and Anthony Chiu. 2008.
Strategies for Sustainable Development of Industrial Park in Ulsan, South
Korea—from Spontaneous Evolution to Systematic Expansion of Industrial
Symbiosis. Journal of Environmental Management 87(1): 1-13.
Popper, Karl. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Shi, Han, Jinping Tian, and Lujun Chen. 2012. China’s Quest for Ecoindustrial Parks, Part I: History and Distinctiveness. Journal of Industrial Ecology
16(1): 8-10.
Talbot, Frederick A. 1920. Millions from Waste. London: Fisher Unwin. Link
Toulmin, Steven. 1972. Human Understanding. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
About the Author
Frank Boons is associate professor at the Public
Administration Department of Erasmus University
Rotterdam, The Netherlands, and Director of the off-campus
Ph.D. program on Cleaner Production, Cleaner Products, Industrial
Ecology and Sustainability. His research deals with the governance
of material and energy flows, analyzing issues of resource
scarcity and ecological impact in relation to global economic
development. He has published widely in journals including
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
110
BOONS
Ecological Economics, Technological Forecasting and Social Change, and Technovation. His
most recent book is Creating Ecological Value: An Evolutionary Approach to Business
Strategies and the Natural Environment, published by Edward Elgar. His email is
[email protected].
Go to Archive of Comments section
Go to May 2012 issue
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5758
111
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5759
ECON JOURNAL WATCH 9(2)
May 2012: 112-121
Fact Versus Conjecture in the
History of Industrial
Waste Utilization
Christine Meisner Rosen1
LINK TO ABSTRACT
Pierre Desrochers attacks my work on waste utilization in the nineteenthcentury American slaughtering, meatpacking, and animal waste processing industries in his reply to the critique of his work that Frank Boons published in 2008 in
the Journal of Industrial Ecology. Desrochers charges that, like his main target, Frank
Boons, my research is deeply flawed because I do not agree with him that market
forces compelled nineteenth- and early twentieth-century manufacturers to recycle,
voluntarily, the vast majority of their wastes. I welcome the opportunity to respond
to his criticism of my work and to discuss—with him, Boons, and the readers of
this journal—the challenges of uncovering and analyzing the complexities of waste
utilization by industry in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries.
Desrochers’ criticism of my contribution to this discussion focuses on my
article “The Role of Pollution Regulation and Litigation in the Development of
the U.S. Meatpacking Industry, 1865-1880” (Rosen 2007). Boons uses my findings
to bolster his argument that Desrochers over-estimates the importance of market
forces in causing manufacturers to utilize their wastes, while under-estimating the
role of the state. Boons’ argument goes to the heart of what we both find
problematic about Desrochers’ work on this subject. So does Desrochers’ response
(2012).
1. Haas School of Business, University of California, Berkeley, CA 94720.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
112
ROSEN
Desrochers begins his critique of my article with a non sequitur. He complains that my discussion of waste utilization in the meat, meatpacking, and animal
waste processing industry is a “remarkable departure” from an article I published
ten years earlier (Rosen 1997), in which, he claims, that I declared “that loop closing
was almost nowhere to be observed in the industrial age” (Desrochers 2012, 91).
Besides ignoring how an open-minded scholar’s thinking can evolve over time as
she learns new things (usually considered a good thing), this is a misreading of
what I said in that earlier piece. The article, “Industrial Ecology and the Greening
of Business History” (Rosen 1997), was an agenda-setting think piece that I gave
at a 1996 conference on “The Future of Business History.” The conference was
convened to consider strategies for overcoming the limits of the firm-centric
Chandlerian paradigm then dominant in the business history field. My purpose was
not only to urge business historians to study the history of the harmful impacts of
industrial development and society’s efforts to mitigate them, but also to exhort
them to conduct research into the history of the many complicated ways in which
business managers dealt with these impacts. I emphasized that such research tasks
included uncovering and explaining the positive as well as the negative ways they
managed their waste streams. Drawing on my research on the role of reformminded business leaders in the history of pollution regulation movements (Rosen
1995) and related matters, I argued that business historians needed to recognize
that “[b]usinessmen not only resisted reformers’ efforts to regulate pollution,
ignored public complaints about pollution, covered up the toxic risks associated
with chemicals used in their manufacturing processes, and fought law suits for as
long as they could, but also experimented voluntarily with abatement technologies,
recycled wastes in many creative ways, and spearheaded smoke control movements and
other environmental reform movements.” I added that business historians “have
an obligation to investigate the wide variety of often conflicting responses business
managers made to the environmental problems their firms generated and to put
these activities in the broader context both of the evolution of the firm and the
evolution of the natural environment” (Rosen 1997, 131; italics added).
I said much the same thing in another agenda-setting article (Rosen and
Sellers 1999), in which my co-author Christopher Sellers and I urged historians to
(among other things) start studying how nineteenth- and early twentieth-century
manufacturers abated their pollution as well as how they ignored it and/or resisted
efforts to force them to abate it. As Sellers and I put it, business historians have
an obligation to investigate the roles that business managers and institutions played
in “directing the flow of energy, materials, and wastes, through all the stages of
production and consumption in the earth’s industrial system,” including the ways
in which they (as well as consumers) have “shunt[ed] them back into the production and
consumption loop by reprocessing and reusing them” (590; italics added).
113
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
HISTORY OF INDUSTRIAL WASTE UTILIZATION
In contrast to these pieces, the 2007 article that Desrochers targets for most
of his criticism is a substantive historical study, based largely on original research. It
grew out of the research I am conducting for the book I am writing on the history of
the American struggle with industrial pollution between 1840 and 1900. It explains
how pollution regulations enacted by urban sanitary reformers in New York City
during the 1860s and Chicago during the 1870s served as an important driver
behind the meatpacking industry’s adoption of improvements in waste utilization
and pollution abatement.
As the article makes clear, a wide range of trades made use of slaughterhouse
waste long before the 1860s and 70s, including the rendering, soap, candle, glue,
and bone boiling industries. What it also shows, however, is that despite their utilization of this waste, all of these industries discharged a great deal of additional,
non-utilized waste into the environment. This waste was much feared at the time
because it emitted extremely noxious stenches that were believed to contribute
to the miasmas that were then assumed to play a role in the spread of yellow
fever, cholera, and other epidemic diseases. This pollution resulted from the decay
of organic material located not only inside the slaughterhouses, rendering
establishments, and soap, glue and bone boiling factories of the day, but also in
the gutters into which these businesses discharged a great deal of blood and other
liquid and semi-liquid wastes. The noxious stenches of decay also emanated from
the overflowing barrels of liquid, solid and semi-solid slaughterhouse waste sitting
in the streets, often for many days at a time, awaiting collection and transport to the
businesses that would process them into fat, soap, glue, and other useful products,
as well as from the barrels of unusable waste placed in the street by slaughterhouses
and renderers, glue manufacturers and other animal waste processors awaiting
collection by the offal haulers charged with the responsibility of disposing them
(Rosen 2007, 298-301, 314-317, 322-325).
The article examines the regulatory movements that sanitary and civic
reformers mounted to protect the people of New York and Chicago from what
they perceived to be a serious threat to public health. The reformers mobilized to
obtain the power they needed to impose technology-based pollution abatement
regulation on the slaughtering, packing, and animal waste processing industries.
The article describes how this regulation stimulated the modernization of the meatpacking industry, including the promotion of more vertical integration and tighter
geographical co-location of slaughtering and animal waste processing, the development of larger, more mechanized independent businesses that focused on
processing animal wastes, the movement of many of these dirty businesses out
of the older, most densely settled, central parts of New York City and Chicago
to more distant locations, the development of new ways of utilizing waste more
efficiently, and improvements in stench abatement technologies. The article also
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
114
ROSEN
provides an analysis of the role that the New Jersey Chancery court played in
shutting down a large packing house that was causing exceptionally noxious pollution problems and discusses how this ruling led to the establishment of a much
better designed packing plant in a different New Jersey town that processed waste
materials in much cleaner ways (Rosen 2007, 301-330).
In dismissing the validity of my research, Desrochers denigrates the legitimacy of the documentary sources that I use to describe not only the wide array of
stench problems the meat industry was generating and the failure of many butchers,
packers, and animal waste processors to take steps to abate these problems by
improving their waste utilization methods, but also the impact the regulations and
the New Jersey court decisions had on waste utilization and stench abatement.
Yet Desrochers provides no counter-evidence to disprove any of my findings.
He simply asserts that they are “incompatible with much available evidence” and
“highly unlikely, based both on theory and evidence” (Desrochers 2012, 92). To
bolster this claim, he points to a couple of additional examples of early waste reuse
in the meat industry (92). None of these examples, however, impeach the credibility
of my findings about the pollution problems associated with slaughtering and
animal waste processing and the role that regulation played in forcing the industry
to improve the extent and methods by which it utilized the wastes that were
responsible for its stenches. His cases are simply additional, early examples of waste
reuse in the meat industry.
The “theory” on which he bases his claim that my findings are “unlikely” is
also flawed. Desrochers assumes that in the supposedly laissez faire, regulation-free
markets of nineteenth- and early twentieth-century Britain and the U.S., economic
self-interest would compel profit-maximizing manufacturers to search for ways to
derive economic gain from their wastes and that “over time, wasteful firms would
be driven out of business or forced to adapt by their more innovative competitors
who created wealth out of industrial waste” (Desrochers 2002, 1047). Ergo, waste
utilization, already common in the 1860s and 70s according to his sources, must
naturally have become very widespread “in virtually all industries” (Desrochers
2009, 5).
Leaving aside the question of whether pollution regulation was actually as
non-existent in this period as Desrochers assumes (a point my article challenges),
the problem is that his simple, cost-benefit, logic-of-the-free-market model fails
to take into account the high costs of developing, procuring, and installing
technologies for separating the materials in factory waste streams and processing
them to get them into forms where they could be used as feedstocks for new
manufacturing processes. His free-market logic also fails to take into account the
low, sometimes practically non-existent, cost of discharging industrial waste into
the air and water and depositing it on land in the 1800s and early 1900s. Waste
115
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
HISTORY OF INDUSTRIAL WASTE UTILIZATION
utilization was far from an inevitably profitable free lunch. While rational costbenefit analysis clearly led some manufacturers to engage in some kinds waste
utilization, in other cases it led rational, profit-maximizing manufacturers to choose
the opposite course: waste discharge and pollution, even when technologies for
utilizing waste were available, which they often were not. The evidence of this is
in the industrial waste that polluted rivers and streams and the factory smoke and
toxic fumes that polluted the air (Kirkwood 1876; Barber 1884; Whipple 1908,
153-169; Colten 1985; Hurley 1994; Travis 2002; Stradling 1999; Thorsheim 2006;
Maysilles 2011; Tarr 2002).
The fact that industrial air and water pollution emissions are what economists call externalities further undermines Desrochers’ contention that the free
markets of nineteenth- and early twentieth-century Britain and the U.S. produced
extensive, welfare-maximizing amounts of industrial waste utilization. As economists well understand, externalities are market imperfections that prevent prices
from capturing accurate information about the cost of production by distributing
costs away from the parties to a market exchange (in this case, manufacturers
considering the purchase of equipment to separate and convert wastes to useful
products) to bystanders, in this case the people, wildlife, and the natural world
harmed by exposure their waste discharges. By distorting prices, externalities screw
up allocative efficiency, preventing the market’s so-called “invisible hand” from
producing optimal, welfare maximizing outcomes (Pindyck and Rubinfeld 1989,
617-646).
Desrochers’ tendency to let conjecture get in the way of the facts is also
evident in the other fault he finds with my article. Complaining that I do not
understand the true nature of electoral politics in mid nineteenth-century cities,
he argues that the regulations could not have had the impact I argued they did,
because, he asserts, the meat packers and other businessmen affected by the
pollution regulations I described would have wanted “to avoid coming under the
direct control of political figures such as ‘Boss Tweed.’” In an attempt to further
trivialize the regulations’ impact, Desrochers also suggests that “even if saint-like
reformers spearheaded public health initiatives, the powers of health officials might
have been appropriated in time by individuals of lesser purity who might have then
used various means to extract bribes, such as controlling both the access and the
size of operations in state-run abattoirs.” (Desrochers 2012, 93)
In addition to being pure speculation on Desrochers’ part, these contentions
are factually wrong. As the article makes clear, the reformers wielded their regulatory power as successfully as they did in large part because they succeeded in
embedding the regulations in policies that reduced their cities’ political machines’
corrupt and incompetent control over public health administration. The New York
Metropolitan Board of Health was a state agency created by the New York State
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
116
ROSEN
legislature at the behest of the reformers (after years of lobbying) who were as antimachine as they were pro-sanitary reform. The legislature endowed the new Board
with path-breaking independence from Tammany Hall as well as with important
new regulatory powers to help them to fight the epidemic diseases ravaging the city.
The Governor appointed leading sanitary reformers to leadership positions on the
Board, and they in turn appointed a professional staff of physicians to carry out
their sanitary regulations. The institution of the Chicago regulations followed years
of struggle that led to the enactment of a new municipal charter and other goodgovernment reforms (Rosen 2007).
Equally important, the regulations enacted in New York City and Chicago
discussed in this article did not produce even one “state-run” abattoir. Instead, they
stimulated the construction of more, large, privately owned pork- and beef-packing
plants. To abate stenches, these privately owned packing plants not only were
generally fitted out with more and better waste processing and stench abatement
equipment than the ones they replaced, but also were more vertically integrated,
bringing more kinds of animal waste process into close proximity and tighter
coordination with the slaughtering of animals to reduce the opportunity for
slaughterhouse waste to decay and stink while awaiting processing into useful
products. American sanitarians often called the best-designed and equipped of
these businesses “abattoirs,” in homage to the large, compulsory, governmentoperated slaughterhouses instituted in France by sanitary reformers there. They
did so, however, to distinguish them from more conventional packing plants, not
because they were compulsory or government-owned or -operated. The sanitary
abattoir constructed in Harsimus, New Jersey, was also privately owned and
operated, as the article plainly states, by a subsidiary of the Pennsylvania Railroad
Company (Rosen 2007).
In short, Desrochers’ criticism of this article is characterized by some of the
very problems that Boons called out in his critique of Desrochers’ work in his
JIE piece (Boons 2008). Desrochers either dismisses the legitimacy of the parts of
the historical record that do not fit his preconceptions—doing so on the bases of
plausible-sounding but historically incorrect conjecture or ill-conceived reasoning
supposedly based in economic theory—or he ignores those parts of the historical
record altogether. Let me be clear: Like Boons, I believe Desrochers has made
a significant contribution by bringing to light a number of important historical
documents that draw attention to the existence of techniques that businesses in a
range of industries developed to utilize their wastes long before modern industrial
ecologists began discussing the importance of moving our modern industrial
system toward more environmentally sustainable, closed-loop production. To my
knowledge, he was the first scholar to publish a peer reviewed article on the history
of a topic that is not only very central to the field of industrial ecology, but also
117
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
HISTORY OF INDUSTRIAL WASTE UTILIZATION
interesting to business and environmental historians (Desrochers 2000).2 The
problem with his work as a whole is that he has over-generalized from these
sources, extrapolating conclusions about the extent and causation of industrial
waste use that are overly simplistic—and that, as his critique of my work indicates,
he tends to ignore or dismiss evidence that conflicts, rather than figuring out how
to integrate it into his own thinking so as to deepen his analysis.
As Boons pointed out in his JIE article, several of Desrochers’ own sources
recognized that waste re-use was far from universal in Great Britain, despite its free
market. This includes Simmonds, the title of whose 1862 book, “Waste Products
and Undeveloped Substances; or Hints for Enterprise in Neglected Fields” (Boons’
emphasis) is a clear sign that Simmonds was concerned about this failing, as well
as Talbot (1919) who discussed British reluctance to profit from the exploitation
of waste in the chemical and slaughterhouse industries. It also includes Kershaw
(1928) who discussed how waste utilization boomed in Britain during World War
I only to fall off drastically after the war ended (Boons 2008, 149-152). Desrochers
tries to diminish the significance of Boons’ analysis of Talbot’s writings by
discussing the most appropriate way to interpret Talbot’s treatment of German
waste utilization during World War I, concluding that Talbot’s discussion of the
role of the state reflected the “increasingly dominant mistaken perspectives of his
time and cannot be used as evidence that governmental planning is a more desirable
way to coordinate inter-firm recovery linkages” (Desrochers 2012, 91). However,
he fails to respond to the substance of Boons’ criticism: that Talbot expressed
concern about the failure of many British manufacturers to maximize profit by
installing the state-of-the-art waste recovery technologies in use elsewhere. And he
does not even attempt to respond to Boons’ observations regarding Simmons and
Kershaw.
Like Talbot and Kershaw, American commentators in this period often expressed concern about American manufacturers’ lack of interest in exploiting what
Francis Hall called the “MONEY IN THE JUNK PILE” (Hall 1919, 327; capitalization in original). C. B. Auel, for example, started a 1917 article on the subject
in Industrial Management by observing: “It is a fact that in manufacturing industries,
more especially among the smaller ones, considerable quantities of materials of
one kind and another find their premature way to the scrap pile” (Auel 1917, 75).
In a 1919 article in the same journal, H. E. Howe suggested some of the reasons
companies were not utilizing these wastes. These included “industries so prosperous, so well established that they can ignore wastes,” businesses that refused to
“employ competent chemists and engineers to show the way,” as well as managers
2. Indeed, I would have cited this piece in my early agenda-setting articles had I been aware of it, but it was
not published till long after they were written.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
118
ROSEN
who “look upon waste utilization as a new field so far from their experience that
they dare not enter.” Significantly, from the viewpoint of Desrochers’ insistence
on the role of the market’s invisible hand, Howe included economic factors in
his list of barriers: “Many wastes do not occur in sufficient quantity at any one
spot to make their use possible, or the cost of collection and storage defeats the
project” (Howe 1919, 93). In his 1919 article in Chemical and Metallurgical Engineering,
Hall suggested yet another reason manufacturers did not reuse their wastes, also
economic in nature: “At all times, in America particular, the general slogan has
been ‘production,’ ‘get out the product.’ With works’ executives, superintendents,
foremen and leaders all constantly absorbed in getting greater production, it is not
strange that the humble but highly profitable task of utilizing any accruing wastes
to the same degree of efficiency should be neglected” (Hall 1919, 326).
In conclusion, I want to emphasize the complexity of this issue. As the
evidence Boons and I have uncovered suggest, historians still have a great deal to
learn about the history of industrial waste reuse. To do justice to this important
subject, we will need to investigate the barriers that discouraged manufacturers
from using their wastes, as well as the full range of drivers stimulating and
encouraging them to do so, including regulatory and other public policies, as well
as economic self-interest. As Hall’s and Howe’s comments regarding the barriers
indicate, the cultural and personal beliefs of managers also influenced management
decisions regarding waste utilization. Historians need to examine their impacts as
well. We should investigate the interactions and tensions between these factors,
rather than getting hung up arguing which were more important. They were all
important. And perhaps most important, as Sellers and I pointed out over ten
years ago, we need to “be sensitive to the fact that individual managers at different
companies typically exhibited a range of attitudes toward environmental issues.
Management attitudes and practices also varied across different industries. We
need to try to understand the reasons for these differences as well analyze their
consequences—for the development of business, as well as the evolution of the
natural world” (Rosen and Sellers 1999, 593).
References
Auel, C. B. 1917. Utilization of Factory Waste. Industrial Management 54(1) (Oct.):
75-79.
Barber, Dana C. 1884. Report of a Sanitary Survey of the Schuylkill Valley. Annual
Report of the Chief Engineer of the Water Department of the City of Philadelphia:
247-314.
119
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
HISTORY OF INDUSTRIAL WASTE UTILIZATION
Boons, Frank. 2008. History’s Lessons: A Critical Assessment of the Desrochers
Papers. Journal of Industrial Ecology 12(2): 148-158. Link
Colten, Craig E. 1985. Industrial Wastes in the Calumet Area, 1869-1970. Waste
Management and Research Center, Illinois Department of Natural
Resources. Champaign, IL: WMRC.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2000. Market Processes and the Closing of “Industrial
Loops.” Journal of Industrial Ecology 4(1): 29-43.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2002. Industrial Ecology and the Rediscovery of Inter-firm
Recycling Linkages: Historical Evidence and Policy Implications. Industrial
and Corporate Change 11(5): 1031-1057.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2009. Does the Invisible Hand Have a Green Thumb?
Incentives, Linkages, and the Creation of Wealth Out of Industrial Waste in
Victorian England. Geographical Journal 175(1): 3-16.
Desrochers, Pierre. 2012. Freedom Versus Coercion in Industrial Ecology: A
Reply to Boons. Econ Journal Watch 9(2): 78-99. Link
Hall, Francis. 1919. Reclaiming Steel Works and Industrial Wastes. Chemical and
Metallurgical Engineering 20(7): 326-327.
Howe, H. E. 1919. Possibilities in Saving and Utilizing Industrial Waste. Industrial
Management 57 (Feb.): 225-229.
Hurley, Andrew. 1994. Creating Ecological Wastelands: Oil Pollution in New
York City, 1870-1900. Journal of Urban History 20 (May): 340-364.
Kershaw, J. B. 1928. The Recovery and Use of Industrial and Other Waste. London:
Ernest Benn.
Kirkwood, James P. 1876. Special Report on the Pollution of Rivers. In Seventh
Annual Report, Massachusetts State Board of Health. Boston: Wright and
Potter, 23-174.
Maysilles, Duncan. 2011. Ducktown Smoke: The Fight over One of the South’s Greatest
Environmental Disasters. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
Pindyck, Robert S. and Daniel L. Rubinfeld. 1989. Microeconomics. New York:
Macmillan Publishing Company.
Rosen, Christine Meisner. 1995. Businessmen Against Pollution in Late
Nineteenth Century Chicago. Business History Review 69 (Autumn): 351-397.
Rosen, Christine Meisner. 1997. Industrial Ecology and the Greening of
Business History. Business and Economic History 26(1): 123-137.
Rosen, Christine Meisner. 2007. The Role of Pollution Regulation and Litigation
in the Development of the U.S. Meatpacking Industry, 1865-1880. Enterprise
and Society: The International Journal of Business History 8(2): 297-347.
Rosen, Christine Meisner and Christopher Sellers. 1999. The Nature of the
Firm: Towards an Ecocultural History of Business. Business History Review 73
(Winter): 577-600.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
120
ROSEN
Simmonds, P. L. 1862. Waste Products and Undeveloped Substances; or, Hints for
Enterprise in Neglected Fields. London: Robert Hartwicke.
Stradling, David. 1999. Smokestacks and Progressives: Environmentalists, Engineers, and
Air Quality in America, 1881-1951. Baltimore and London: The Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Talbot, F. A. 1919. Millions from Waste. London: Fisher Unwin.
Tarr, Joel A. 2002. Industrial Waste Disposal in the United States as a Historical
Problem. Ambix 49(1): 4-20.
Thorsheim, Peter. 2006. Inventing Pollution: Coal, Smoke, and Culture in Britain Since
1800. Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press.
Travis, Anthony S. 2002. Contaminated Earth and Water: A Legacy of the
Synthetic Dyestuffs Industry. Ambix 49(1): 21-50.
Whipple, George C. 1908. Gas Wastes. In Report of the State Sewerage Commission to
the Legislature of 1908, New Jersey State Sewerage Commission. Somerville, N.
J.: Unionist-Gazette Association.
About the Author
Christine Meisner Rosen is an Associate Professor at the
Haas School of Business at the University of California,
Berkeley and Associate Director for Business and Economy at
the Berkeley Center for Green Chemistry. Her research focuses
on the history of American beliefs about pollution, pollution
regulation movements, and pollution abatement in the
nineteenth century. She is hard at work finishing a book on
these topics. Her email is
[email protected].
Go to Archive of Comments section
Go to May 2012 issue
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5759
121
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5760
ECON JOURNAL WATCH 9(2)
May 2012: 122-140
Race, Ethnicity, and Baseball Card
Prices: A Replication, Correction,
and Extension of Hewitt, Muñoz,
Oliver, and Regoli
David W. Findlay1 and John M. Santos2
LINK TO ABSTRACT
Since Pascal and Rapping’s (1972) seminal
article, scholars have given much attention to
racial and ethnic discrimination in professional
sports. Because high-quality performance statistics are so accessible, professional sports is a great
area for testing discrimination. Following Becker
(1971), scholars consider discrimination by other
players (employee discrimination), owners (employer discrimination), and fans (customer discrimination). Kahn (1991a, 2000) has provided
excellent reviews of the literature on discrimination in professional sports.
Our paper investigates whether consumers
in the secondary market for baseball cards3 are willing to pay more for cards of
1. Colby College, Waterville, ME 04901.
2. Robert Morris University, Chicago, IL 60605. We thank two anonymous referees for helpful comments and suggestions.
3. All cards pictured are among those used in the analysis. The authors would like to thank The Topps
Company for its assistance. Images of Topps baseball cards used courtesy of The Topps Company, Inc.
For more information about The Topps Company, please see their website at www.topps.com.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
122
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
players of a particular race or ethnicity, holding performance and card availability
constant. The issue is important. Becker and others have argued that discrimination
based on racial or ethnic preferences by employers is unlikely to persist in the
long-run in competitive markets as the discriminating employers face higher
productions costs than non-discriminating employers. Customer discrimination,
however, can potentially persist under competitive conditions as employers are
able to pass along the higher costs to customers willing to pay a premium to indulge
their racial or ethnic preferences. Kahn (1991b) has demonstrated that customer
discrimination, under certain conditions, can cause persistent wage differentials in
competitive markets.
The results of prior empirical studies of
the baseball card market and discrimination are
mixed. Evidence that black or Hispanic players
with equivalent performance statistics hold lower card prices is found by Nardinelli and Simon
(1990), Andersen and La Croix (1991), Gabriel,
Johnson, and Stanton (1999), and Fort and Gill
(2000). In contrast, evidence that race and
ethnicity have little effect on card prices is found
by Gabriel, Johnson, and Stanton (1995) and
McGarrity, Palmer, and Poitras (1999). Scahill
(2005) obtains evidence of both racial and ethnic
discrimination in the baseball card market, but
he notes that the negative effects of player race and ethnicity on card prices
disappear in the more recent years of his sample.
We add to this literature by correcting, replicating, and extending the
approach of another paper, which we introduce in the next section. Our paper
offers baseball lovers the chance to mix the pleasures of empirical economics with
references to great heroes of the game. To readers generally, it offers improved
results on the question of whether race or ethnicity affects how much card buyers
are willing to pay to own the card of the hero.
Summary of
Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver, and Regoli (2005)
Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver, and Regoli (2005) examine the effects of the race
of the baseball player on the price of his rookie card. In creating their sample of
players, Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver, and Regoli (hereafter HMOR) include only those
123
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
players who were elected to the National Baseball Hall of Fame prior to 2004.
As Jackie Robinson broke the race barrier in 1947, HMOR exclude players whose
rookie cards were issued prior to 1948; they also exclude five Hispanic players. The
result is a sample of 51 players where blacks account for 2 of the 19 pitchers and 16
of the 32 hitters.4
The dependent variable in their study is the
price of each player’s rookie card as reported in the
April 2003 issue of Beckett Baseball Card Monthly.5
HMOR hypothesize that card prices may be affected
by player performance, card availability, and player
race. HMOR (415) use the statistic Total Baseball
Ranking (TBR) as their measure of player performance, and they report that their data source is the
2001 issue of Total Baseball (Thorn, Palmer, and
Gershman 2001). For pitchers, Total Baseball Ranking equals the pitcher’s Total Pitcher Index (TPI).
For hitters, Total Baseball Ranking equals the
hitter’s Total Player Rating (TPR). Leaving the
details aside,6 we highlight only that the TPI data for a pitcher and the TPR data for
a hitter are reported in Thorn, Palmer, and Gershman (2001) by season and by
career.7 HMOR use the career totals.
Throughout our paper, even in our extensions, we keep to the parsimonious
spirit of the model specified by HMOR—the model is parsimonious in that it uses
for each player a single performance statistic. In this sense we follow HMOR and
do not investigate disaggregated measures of player performance.
HMOR (416) also hypothesize that the “value [price] of a baseball card is
affected by how scarce or rare it is.” The authors use data obtained from the
April 2003 Professional Sports Authenticator (PSA) Population Report to measure
4. See HMOR (2005) for a detailed discussion of the criteria.
5. The April 2003 issue reports two prices for each card, a LO price and a HI price. A comparison of the
data reported in HMOR with that found in Beckett (2003) reveals that HMOR use the HI price data as their
dependent variable.
6. Thorn, Palmer, and Gershman (2001, 2501) define the Total Pitcher Index as “the sum of a pitcher’s
Pitching Runs—expressed as Ranking Runs, employing the same formula used to compute Relief Ranking
Runs—Batting Runs (in the AL since 1973, zero), and Fielding Runs, all divided by the Runs per Win factor
for that year (generally around 10, historically in the 9-11 range).” They define the Total Player Rating as
“the sum of a player’s Adjusted Batting Runs, Fielding Runs, and Base Stealing Runs, minus his positional
adjustment, all divided by the Runs per Win factor for that year (generally around 10, historically in the
9-11 range)” (2501). For an even more detailed discussion of the construction of TPI and TPR, see Thorn,
Palmer, and Gershman (2001).
7. The career value of a pitcher’s TPI is simply the sum of the pitcher’s yearly TPI statistics over the course
of his career. The career value of a hitter’s TPR is calculated similarly.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
124
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
card availability. Professional Sports Authenticator (psacard.com) provides information about card prices and documents the number and quality of the cards that it
evaluates. HMOR (416) “constructed a measure of availability based on how many
rookie cards of each player in near mint or better condition were reported [by PSA]
to exist.”8
HMOR hypothesize that player race may affect rookie card prices. A race
dummy variable is constructed where Black equals one if a player was black and
equals zero otherwise. As HMOR omitted the five Hispanic players from their
sample, the reference group in their study is white players.
HMOR estimate two specifications of a baseball card price equation to
determine whether player race affects the card prices of the 51 rookie cards. They
find that card prices are higher for those players with greater career performance.
The results also indicate that increases in card availability cause reductions in card
prices. After controlling for their measures of player performance and card availability, HMOR find that player race has no statistically significant effect on card
prices in either of their specifications and suggest (419) “the possibility that Black
superstars or sports heroes are seen on the same plane as Whites. To put it
differently, on some level, the evaluation of the performance of Black [Hall of
Fame] members transcends racial consideration.”
The Sources and Errors of HMOR’s Data
Our Table 1 includes all information reported
in HMOR’s Table 1 and additional data in the final
three columns. We applaud HMOR for reporting
their data as it facilitates replication of their results.
The first column in Table 1 lists the 51 players, Hank
Aaron to Robin Yount. The second column includes
the year of the card, the manufacturer (Bowman,
Fleer Update, Leaf, and Topps), and card number.
The third column includes the April 2003 HI price
reported in Beckett (2003). The fourth column gives
the PSA availability data as reported by HMOR. The
fifth column includes the Total Pitcher Index or
Total Player Rating reported by HMOR.
8. PSA reports the number of times it has evaluated each card for each quality category. These data are
updated as PSA evaluates additional cards.
125
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
TABLE 1.
HMOR TB (2001) Difference Difference
Performance Performance
in %
in Rank
Aaron, Hank
1954 T #128
1500
164
90.1
89.1
1.1
0
Banks, Ernie
1954 T #94
800
121
24.9
26.9
−7.4
−4
Bench, Johnny
1968 T #247
125
239
30.2
25.6
18
5
Berra, Yogi
1948 B #6
450
70
34.8
37.4
−7
−4
Brett, George
1975 T #228
80
1042
43.9
40
9.8
4
Brock, Lou
1962 T # 387
125
111
2
10.5
−81
−1
Campanella, Roy
1949 B #84
700
90
22.2
22.5
−1.3
−2
Carlton, Steve
1965 T #477
150
114
35.6
33.7
5.6
6
Carter, Gary
1975 T #620
15
74
30.1
30.1
0
−3
Drysdale, Don
1957 T #18
225
83
34.7
34.6
0.3
0
Fingers, Rollie
1969 T #597
40
109
22.5
22.5
0
0
Fisk, Carlton
1972 T #79
50
96
33.4
24.9
34.1
13
Ford, Whitey
1951 B #1
1400
35
39.2
39.2
0
2
Gibson, Bob
1959 T #514
200
84
46.3
43.7
5.9
4
Hunter, Jim
1965 T #526
80
136
6.9
6
15
1
Jackson, Reggie
1969 T #260
250
252
44
42.2
4.3
3
Jenkins, Fergie
1966 T #254
70
146
32.1
29.8
7.7
3
Kaline, Al
1954 T #201
600
119
45.9
45.2
1.5
1
Killebrew, Harmon 1955 T #124
250
159
32.8
27.3
20.1
6
Kiner, Ralph
1948 B #3
150
48
27
25.9
4.2
−1
Koufax, Sandy
1955 T #123
800
179
20
20.5
−2.4
0
Lemon, Bob
1949 B #238
200
13
35.2
38.4
−8.3
−4
Mantle, Mickey
1951 B #253
8500
53
77.4
77.4
0
0
Mathews, Eddie
1952 T #407
8000
15
52.2
52.2
0
0
Mays, Willie
1951 B #305
3000
56
95.9
95.9
0
0
McCovey, Willie
1960 T #316
125
64
38.1
37.3
2.1
4
Morgan, Joe
1965 T #16
60
29
63.9
54.8
16.6
0
Murray, Eddie
1978 T #36
80
1313
34.1
34.1
0
0
Musial, Stan
1948 B #36
800
49
70.1
71.5
−2
−1
Niekro, Phil
1964 T #541
80
37
38
33.8
12.4
9
Palmer, Jim
1966 T #126
100
200
36.4
34.9
4.3
2
Perry, Gaylord
1962 T #199
80 (85)
93
36.8
34.9
5.4
4
Puckett, Kirby
1984 F #93
100
1416
32.3
32.3
0
−1
Roberts, Robin
1949 B #46
250
39
25.9
25.9
0
−1
Robinson, Brooks
1957 T #328
350
214
23.3
20.1
15.9
4
Robinson, Frank
1957 T #35
200
162
71
67.6
5
1
Robinson, Jackie
1949 L #79
1500 (1100)
81
33.3
32
4.1
2
Ryan, Nolan
1968 T #177
600
398
14.2
20.7
−31.4
−3
Schmidt, Mike
1973 T #615
150
361
77.9
79.6
−2.1
0
Seaver, Tom
1967 T #581
500
264
51.2
48.7
5.1
1
Smith, Ozzie
1979 T #116
80
796
42.4
42.4
0
−1
Snider, Duke
1949 B #226
900
55
24.3
24.1
0.8
0
Spahn, Warren
1948 B #18
300
43
43.1
50.2
−14.1
−6
Stargell, Willie
1963 T #553
125
85
31.6
31.6
0
−1
Sutton, Don
1966 T #288
50
45
13.7
13.2
3.8
0
Wilhelm, Hoyt
1952 T #392
750
38
29.2
40.8
−28.4
−21
Williams, Billy
1961 T #141
60
215
30.1
30.1
0
−3
Winfield, Dave
1974 T #456
40
699
36.9
36.9
0
3
Wynn, Early
1949 B #110
125
59
18.2
17.1
6.4
1
Yastrzemski, Carl
1960 T #148
150
280
46.1
46.7
−1.3
0
Yount, Robin
1975 T #223
50
853
31.4
46
−31.7
−22
Notes: [a] B, F, L, and T refer to Bowman, Fleer Update, Leaf, and Topps cards, respectively. [b] We give the
correct prices for Perry and J. Robinson (80 and 1500) and include in parentheses the incorrect price data reported
in HMOR for those players (85 and 1100). [c] Difference in % is the percentage point difference between the HMOR
performance data and the Total Baseball (2001) performance data. [d] Difference in Rank measures the extent to which
the player’s relative performance ranking changes when performance data reported in HMOR are used.
Name
Card
Price
Availability
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
126
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
A casual inspection of the performance data reported by HMOR for pitchers
indicates that TPI ranges from a high of 51.2 for Tom Seaver to a low of 6.9 for Jim
Hunter. For hitters, the TPR ranges from a high of 95.9 for Willie Mays to a low of
2.0 for Lou Brock. We offer these casual observations because, when we first read
the HMOR article in early 2010, it was the low performance value for Lou Brock
that caught our eye. Brock is the only hitter in HMOR’s table whose TPR statistic
is less than 20; Roy Campanella has the next highest TPR statistic, 22.2.
Despite our initial ignorance about the TPI
and TPR statistics, we decided to compare Brock’s
TPR figure reported by HMOR with that found in
Thorn, Palmer, and Gershman (2001)—the same
source of performance data reportedly used by
HMOR.9 Little did we know at the time that this
would start a process where we would discover a
large number of discrepancies and puzzles. We immediately discovered that Brock’s career TPR, as
found in HMOR’s data source, equals 10.5 and not
2.0 as HMOR reported. We then decided to obtain
the performance data for the remaining 50 players
using the same source as HMOR.10 For all 51 players
in the sample, we consulted every section of the data source (as outlined in footnote
10) to record and to verify the performance data. In so doing, we discovered
numerous differences between the data found in HMOR and those in Thorn,
Palmer, and Gershman (2001): 38 of the 51 performance data observations in
HMOR differ from those found in the 2001 edition of Total Baseball—HMOR’s
reported data source. In other words, nearly 75 percent of the performance data
observations used by HMOR were apparently incorrect. We include in column 6 in
Table 1 (see TB (2001) Performance) the correct performance data as found in the
2001 edition of Total Baseball.11
We constructed two additional variables in Table 1 to measure the magnitude
of these performance data errors. The seventh column (Difference in %) includes
the percentage point difference between the HMOR performance data and the
9. See pages 415, 416, and 425 in HMOR where HMOR discuss their performance data source.
10. The TPI data can be obtained in Thorn, Palmer, and Gershman (2001) by examining each pitcher’s
career statistics in the Pitcher Register section (pp. 1307-1957) or on the following pages: (1) p. 2317; (2) pp.
2317-2318; (3) pp. 2319-2320; and (4) pp. 2320-2321. The TPR data can be obtained from the same source
by examining each hitter’s career statistics in the Player Register section (pp. 553-1306) or on the following
pages: (1) pp. 2303-2304; (2) pp. 2304-2305; (3) pp. 2319-2320; and (4) pp. 2320-2321.
11. We did discover one discrepancy in the 2001 issue of Total Baseball for pitcher Bob Lemon. His Total
Baseball Ranking is reported to be 37.9 (see p. 2320) while his Total Pitcher Index is reported to be 38.4
(see pages 1587, 2317, and 2318). We use his TPI value of 38.4 in our paper.
127
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
performance data reported in Total Baseball. These errors range, in absolute value,
from 1.1% for Hank Aaron to 81.0% for Lou Brock. The mean absolute value
of these data errors measured in percentage terms is 11.3%. We also obtained
a performance ranking of all 51 players using the HMOR data and the data we
obtained from Total Baseball (2001). The last column (Difference in Rank) reports the
extent to which each player’s ranking changes when the data from HMOR are used.
For example, the rankings of Carlton Fisk, Hoyt Wilhelm, and Robin Yount change
rather dramatically.
Given the data discrepancies between HMOR and Total Baseball (2001), we
decided to check the remaining data reported by HMOR. To verify the accuracy
of the price data, we cross-referenced the card information reported by HMOR
with the price data found in Beckett (2003), the same data source used by HMOR.
We discovered two price data errors: (1) Gaylord Perry’s 1962 Topps rookie card
price is $80 (not $85); and (2) Jackie Robinson’s 1949 Leaf rookie card price is
$1500 (not $1100).12 We then attempted to check the availability data. To do so, we
contacted PSA and learned that they do not archive the data nor keep old issues
of their Population Report; therefore, it is impossible to verify the accuracy of the
availability data reported in HMOR.13
Our discovery of the data errors made us wonder whether HMOR’s results
are affected by these errors. Could the effects of race change? This is not a matter
of mere curiosity for it speaks to the issue of racial discrimination.
In addition, we were perplexed by HMOR’s
explicit decision to remove Hispanic players from
their sample. That decision causes an already small
sample to be nearly 10 percent smaller than it
otherwise would be. Second, the removal could
potentially impact the estimated effects of race on
card prices. Finally, by removing Hispanics from the
sample, the authors could not examine the effects of
player ethnicity on card prices. The latter implication
was the most perplexing to us given that one would
think that researchers examining customer
discrimination would include a group of players, in
this case Hispanic players, for whom such dis-
12. We discuss in more detail below what we eventually learned about the price data error for Jackie
Robinson’s rookie card.
13. While not data errors, we also discovered several card information errors in HMOR. Johnny Bench’s
card number is 247 (not 447). Steve Carlton’s rookie card was issued in 1965 (not 1975). Al Kaline’s card
number is 201 (not 210). And finally, Willie Mays’ card number is 305 (not 395).
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
128
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
crimination has already been found to exist in several previous studies of the
baseball card market.
At this point in 2010, we believed
that the errors were simply the result of
transcription errors. We decided to write
a paper that corrects, replicates, and
extends the analysis of HMOR. The obvious outlet for this paper was the Journal
of Sport & Social Issues, the same journal
that published HMOR’s 2005 paper. We
completed the paper during the summer
of 2011 and submitted it to the Journal of
Sport & Social Issues on September 1, 2011. On September 20, 2011, we received an
email from the Editor in Chief of the journal informing us that “Unfortunately, at
this time, this article is not a good fit with the journal and I have decided against
sending it out for review.”14
We immediately submitted the
paper to Econ Journal Watch, and an editor
there subsequently asked us to investigate the data errors in more detail. As
we investigated, we recalled that HMOR
cite Bill Deane’s essay, “Awards and
Honors”; the Deane essay was published
in the 1989 issue of Total Baseball. We
never imagined that HMOR would have
used different editions of Total Baseball as
their source of the performance data. During our initial investigation of the TBR
data, we learned that Total Baseball revises the TBR statistics over time (see pages
539-542 of the 2001 edition). One, therefore, cannot pool or “mix” TBR data from
different editions.
Without any other explanation for the data errors, we decided to obtain the
performance data for all 51 players from the only other edition of Total Baseball cited
by HMOR.15 We discovered the following. The TBR values for only 13 players
14. We have had our papers rejected for publication in the past and anticipate that future papers will
be rejected for publication as well. However, we were surprised and a bit perplexed that a paper that
documents such a large number of data errors, in addition to exploring a number of extensions, of a
previously published article in the same journal would not even be sent out for review.
15. We also obtained the 1991 and 1995 editions of Total Baseball to determine if HMOR may have relied on
these other editions for their performance data. None of the TBR observations reported in HMOR equals
the values found in these two editions of Total Baseball.
129
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
in HMOR’s sample are equal to the values found in Total Baseball (2001). The
TBR values for 38 players are equal to the values found in Total Baseball (1989).16
For two of the players in the sample (George Brett and Frank Robinson), the
TBR values used by HMOR are not equal to any of the values published in the
1989, 1991, 1995, and 2001 editions of Total Baseball. We believe that these two
errors are transcription errors because the values used by HMOR are closest to the
values reported in Total Baseball (1989). We thus discovered that HMOR used two
different sources for their performance data and, therefore, pooled performance
data that are revised over time.
There is an additional implication
from HMOR’s use of the 1989 issue of
Total Baseball. By obtaining data from this
earlier source, HMOR have performance data only through the 1988 season. There are ten players in their sample
whose careers continued after 1988. Of
these ten players, HMOR use the 1989
issue for five of them, namely, George
Brett (who retired in 1993), Carlton Fisk
(1993), Nolan Ryan (1993), Mike Schmidt (1989), and Robin Yount (1993). For
these five players, career performance is incomplete in the data that HMOR used to
estimate their price equations.
Also, the Jackie Robinson rookie card in HMOR is the 1949 Leaf card (#79).
HMOR list the price of that card as $1100. We discovered that Jackie Robinson had
another rookie card issued in 1949 by Bowman (#50). As reported in Beckett (2003),
the price of the Leaf card is $1500 and the price the Bowman card is $1100. We
believe that HMOR incorrectly used the Bowman price rather than the Leaf price.17
16. As it turns out, the career total TBR observations for two players in the sample (Willie Stargell and
Robin Roberts) are the same in the 1989 and 2001 editions of Total Baseball. It is a coincidence that the
career totals for Stargell and Roberts are identical across the two editions because their annual observations
are not equal in the two editions of Total Baseball. This, of course, implies that the revised calculations used
to construct the more recent TBR values caused the career total TBR statistics to change for the other 49
players in the sample.
17. The incorrect use of the Bowman price has a potentially additional implication for their results. HMOR
also obtain availability data for each card in their sample. It is possible that HMOR included in their study
the availability data for the Leaf card rather than the availability data for the Bowman card. As noted
previously, because PSA does not archive the data, we could not determine whether HMOR used the
availability data for Jackie Robinson’s Leaf or Bowman card.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
130
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
A Replication and Correction of HMOR
We estimate the same two specifications of HMOR’s price equation:
(1) Price = a0 + a1Availability + a2Performance + a3Black
(2) Price = b0 + b1Availability + b2Performance + b3Black + b4Black*Performance
where Price is the natural log of the rookie card price; Availability is the natural
log of the card availability obtained from PSA; Performance is the TPI/TPR for
pitchers/hitters, respectively; and Black is a dummy variable equal to one if the
player is black and zero otherwise. For equation (1), any effect of race on card
prices is assumed to be independent of player performance. For equation (2), the
inclusion of the interaction term, Black*Performance, allows for any race effects to
vary by player performance. We estimate the equations first using the data reported
by HMOR and then using the corrected data reported in Table 1.
We are able to replicate HMOR’s results when we use the data reported by
HMOR. This is a result in and of itself given, as noted by Winfree (2010, 48), the
“difficulties in replicating results in sports economics.” Winfree further explains
“that there can be many roadblocks to replicating the results of any empirical
study” (ibid.). We again applaud HMOR for removing one of those roadblocks by
reporting their data. Furthermore, had HMOR never reported their data, we likely
would not have discovered their data and measurement errors.
When using the correct performance and price data, none of the estimated
coefficients on the race variables, Black or Black*Performance, is statistically
significant. Our results, using the correct data, imply that player race has no effect
on card prices—a result consistent with that originally reported by HMOR.
Using least squares regression to find the equation of best fit, we obtain the
following estimate of equation (1) when we use the correct data reported in Table
118:
(3) Price = 6.265 − 0.411Availability + 0.030Performance − 0.098Black
(7.43) (2.60)
(3.44)
(0.27)
R2 = 0.30
We show in the supplement to this paper [link] that the estimated coefficient
for the Black dummy variable is not statistically significant even at the 0.10 level.
Specifically, the p-value for the t-statistic on the estimated coefficient on the Black
18. We include in parentheses the absolute value of the corresponding t-statistic for each estimated
coefficient.
131
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
dummy variable in equation (3) indicates that one could only conclude that the
Black coefficient is significantly less than 0 at a .393 significance level. Thus we find
a lack of evidence that a player’s race adversely affects the price of his rookie card,
holding constant the effects of player performance and card availability. Although
our results indicate that player race has no statistically significant effect on baseball
card prices, we are mindful of Ziliak and McCloskey (2004, 334) who note that
“statistical significance, to put it shortly, is neither necessary nor sufficient for
a finding to be economically important.” The estimated coefficient on the Black
dummy variable indicates that the price of a black player’s rookie card, all else fixed,
is 9.3% lower than that of an otherwise identical white player.19
We also examined whether our results were affected by the inclusion of
Jackie Robinson in the HMOR sample. Jackie Robinson was an epic figure who
transcends baseball. Furthermore, unlike the vast majority of the players in the
sample, he started his professional career in the Negro Baseball League. And finally, as we discussed in footnote 17, HMOR’s incorrect use of Jackie Robinson’s
Bowman rookie card price may have resulted in HMOR incorrectly using the
availability data for the Leaf card rather than the availability data for the Bowman
card. All of our previous results are basically the same after we remove Jackie
Robinson from the sample. Specifically, the size and significance of all parameters
are nearly identical to those obtained when Jackie Robinson is included in the
sample.
The negative and significant estimated coefficient on card availability in
equation (3) indicates, as expected, that increases in card availability lower the
selling price of a player’s rookie card. Of particular interest to economists is the
magnitude of the estimated coefficient on availability. Since both Availability and
Price are measured in log form, we can interpret our numerical estimate of the
Availability coefficient as implying that a 1 percent reduction in card availability
raises card prices by about 0.41 percent or, equivalently, that a 10 percent reduction
in card availability raises card selling price by approximately 4.1 percent. The
positive and significant estimated coefficient on Performance indicates, not
surprisingly, that the baseball cards of players with higher career performance levels
sell for a higher price in the secondary market.
At the end of equation (3), we report a well-known sample statistic, R2, which
measures the percent of the sample variation in the dependent variable explained
by an estimated equation. When we re-estimate HMOR’s equation (1) after cor-
19. As noted by Halvorsen and Palmquist (1980), the appropriate interpretation of the coefficient of
a dummy variable in a semilogarithmic regression equation can be calculated as 100(eβ − 1) where βd
represents the estimated coefficient of the dummy variable.
d
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
132
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
recting their reported 2003 data, our corrections raise the percent of variation in
card prices explained by HMOR’s basic model from 27 percent to 30 percent.20
Extensions of HMOR
HMOR’s basic model explains only 30 percent of the observed variation
in rookie card prices using correct data. We sought a model of card prices that
explains or predicts a greater percent.
Matching Price and Card Quality
HMOR state (416) that they use
prices listed in Beckett (2003) that are “in
near mint or mint condition.”21 A related
issue is HMOR’s use of the availability
data reported by Professional Sports
Authenticator. HMOR note (416) that
their “measure of availability [is] based
on how many rookie cards of each player
in near mint or better condition were
reported to exist.” However, we discovered that PSA determines the authenticity
and quality of cards submitted. That is, PSA will grade (i.e., categorize) cards, for
example, as excellent, near mint, near mint-mint, mint, and gem mint—each of
which will receive the corresponding numerical score of 6, 7, 8, 9, and 10. Thus, the
availability data used by HMOR represent the total number of cards rated by PSA
as near mint or better. Their availability variable, therefore, is the sum of or,
equivalently, an aggregate measure of all PSA-rated cards that are near mint, near
mint-mint, mint, and gem mint.
Upon further investigation, we discovered that PSA also reports price data
for cards with different grades. As noted in PSA’s Sports Market Report (2003, 36),
PSA’s prices “represent average dealer selling prices for PSA-graded cards. […]
The prices that appear in Sports Market Report are for sportscards that have been
graded and sold, […].” The average selling prices listed by PSA, therefore,
20. When we re-estimated equation (1) using the data reported by HMOR, we were able to replicate their
results and, therefore, obtained the same value of the R2 statistic.
21. As we discovered, however, the prices they use are the HI prices reported by Beckett. To obtain prices
of near mint or mint condition cards, one would have to use the “Price Guide Percentage by Grade” table
found on p. 15 of the April 2003 issue to adjust the HI prices by quality. It is also important to note that
these price guide percentages do vary over time.
133
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
correspond to cards that the rating company evaluates to be a specific quality (e.g.,
mint) and, therefore, do not represent an average price of, say, near mint or better
cards. This information implies that the choice of the price data depends crucially
on the type of PSA availability data one uses or creates. And given that different
prices exist for different quality cards, the question naturally arises as to the extent
to which the choice of price data series affects any model’s ability to explain card
prices.22
At this point, we realized that HMOR do not investigate what is the
appropriate price series for the aggregate card quality category they create.
Additionally, by restricting their analysis to cards of this aggregate quality category,
neither do they explore whether the magnitude of the availability effect on card
prices varies by card quality. Since PSA does not archive availability data, we are
unable to retrieve card availability by specific card quality for the 2003 data used by
HMOR. However, for 2010, we obtained availability and card quality data in realtime (April 2010) from PSA. This allows us to explore the relationship between
card availability and card prices across specific card quality categories.
2003 Data: Which Price Series Does HMOR’s Availability Measure
Best Explain?
Table 2 displays the percent of variation in rookie card prices explained by
alternative specifications of the card price equation for the corrected 2003 data
and for our update using 2010 data.23 The first two rows show the percent of
card prices explained by HMOR’s basic model when we use HMOR’s data and
when we use the correct data, respectively. Row 3 shows the gains in percent of
variation of card prices explained when we consider alternative price series and card
availability pairings beyond HMOR’s pairing (Beckett HI-PSA7 Plus).24 Specifically,
in columns 2, 3, and 4 for Alternate Model 1, we match for the 2003 data HMOR’s
availability measure with three different PSA price series. Judged by the percent of
sample variation in card prices explained, HMOR’s availability measure explains
all three PSA price series better than the Beckett price series chosen by the authors.
Additionally, as we show in the supplement to this article, the statistical significance
22. While one could argue that the PSA data serve as a proxy for the quantities of each card that exist in the
secondary market for baseball cards, we must note the following. It is possible that the same card has been
submitted to PSA by, say, five different individuals. PSA would then report a 5 for that card even though
the same card has been submitted five different times.
23. As we discussed earlier in the paper, the percent of variation in rookie baseball card prices explained
by each model specification is measured by the well-known sample statistic, R2 (also called the multiple
coefficient of determination).
24. PSA7 Plus equals the number of cards rated near mint or better.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
134
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
of the availability effect on card prices also increases when any of the three PSA
price series are matched with HMOR’s availability measure.
TABLE 2. Percent of Baseball Card Prices Explained
Price Series
Beckett
PSA7
PSA8
PSA9
Beckett
Beckett
PSA8
PSA9
Year of Data
2003
2003
2003
2003
2010
2010
2010
2010
Availability Measure
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA7
or
Higher
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA7
or
Higher
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA7
or
Higher
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA7
or
Higher
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA7
or
Higher
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA8
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA8
# of
Cards
Rated
PSA9
Source of
Availability Data
HMOR
HMOR
HMOR
HMOR
PSA
PSA
PSA
PSA
Column
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
(7)
(8)
(1) Replication of HMOR with
HMOR Data [without
Hispanics]
27%
(2) HMOR Model with
Corrected Data [without
Hispanics]
30%
37%
38%
33%
49%
52%
66%
69%
49%
53%
66%
69%
50%
53%
64%
68%
50%
53%
64%
68%
Row/
Model
(3) Alternate Model 1: Different
Price and Availability Variables
and Career Total Performance
[without Hispanics]
(4) Alternate Model 2: Different
Price and Availability Variables
and Career Total Performance
[with Hispanics]
(5) Alternate Model 3: Different
Price and Availability Variables
and Per Season Performance
[without Hispanics]
(6) Alternate Model 4: Different
Price and Availability Variables
and Per Season Performance
[with Hispanics]
36%
40%
43%
34%
Notes: [a] Beckett equals the Beckett HI price. [b] PSA7 equals near mint. [c] PSA8 equals near mint-mint. [d] PSA9
equals mint. [e] To be precise, this table reports the percent of the variation in the natural log of baseball rookie
card prices explained by each model as measured by the unadjusted multiple coefficient of determination (i.e., the
R2 statistic).
2010 Data: Which Price Series-Card Availability Pairing Best Explains
Card Prices?
Until this point, we have used HMOR’s aggregate measure of card
availability. For the 2010 data, we are able to create card availability categories,
both by aggregated card quality levels (a la HMOR) and for disaggregated card
135
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
quality levels. We take advantage of our availability data set to estimate separate
card price equations for different categories of card quality and to determine which
price-availability pairing best explains variations in rookie card prices. We find
that HMOR’s price equation with their aggregate availability category explains 49
percent of the variation in 2010 rookie card prices as compared to 30 percent for
the corrected 2003 data, indicating that HMOR’s model fits the 2010 data better
than the 2003 data. However, when we disaggregate card availability by specific
card quality and match to the corresponding quality-specific PSA price series, the
percent of rookie card prices explained rises sharply; see columns (7) and (8) for
Alternate Model 1 in Table 2.
What Is the Responsiveness of Card Prices to Changes in Card
Availability?
Our estimate of the magnitude of the effect of availability varies across the
different card quality categories reported in Table 2.25 For the 2003 availability data
reported by HMOR, we find that a 10 percent reduction in availability of cards
rated near mint or higher causes a 4.1 percent increase in card price when we
measure price with the Beckett price series used by HMOR. In contrast, for the 2010
data, we find that when we appropriately match the aggregated or disaggregated
PSA availability measure to the corresponding PSA price series, we can predict that
a 10 percent reduction in availability in the secondary market causes about a 9 to 10
percent increase in market price.
The Curious Omission of Hispanics: Does Ethnicity Matter?
HMOR did not explore whether
their important finding on race extended
to Hispanic ethnicity in the matter of
Luis Aparicio, Rod Carew, Roberto Clemente, Juan Marichal, and Tony Perez.
For the 2010 data for which we have
access to availability data, we added
Aparicio, Carew, Clemente, Marichal,
and Perez to our sample, raising the
sample size of players from 51 to 56. We
then created an additional dummy variable that equals one if the observed player is
25. In the supplement to this article, we report and discuss the estimated equations behind the results in
Table 2.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
136
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
Hispanic and equals zero otherwise. The reference group in our sample is white
players. As indicated in columns 5, 6, 7, and 8 for Alternate Models 1 and 2, the
percent of variation in card prices explained is not greatly affected one way or the
other when we add the five Hispanic players. Moreover, as the regression results we
report in the supplement to this article show, we find very little change in the size
or significance of the effects of player performance and card availability on card
prices. Additionally, race remains statistically insignificant in all equations. Finally,
we also find that there is no statistically significant effect of ethnicity on card prices.
In general, our corrections and extensions show that neither race nor ethnicity has
a statistically significant effect on card prices, and that the findings are robust to
alternative pairings of price and availability measures.
Lifetime Player Performance: Career Totals or Average Per
Season?
Our analysis to this point is based
on the performance statistic used by
HMOR, the sum of each player’s TPI or
TPR over the course of the player’s
career. An issue arises as to whether the
underlying demand for these cards
depends on how efficiently the player
achieved his career totals. Jim Palmer
and Gaylord Perry both have the same
career TPI (34.9), but Palmer did it in 19 seasons while Perry did it in 22. In fact,
Don Drysdale accumulated a slightly lower TPI (34.6) in just 14 seasons. Johnny
Bench and Carlton Fisk had similar TPR statistics (25.6 and 24.9, respectively) with
different career lengths—17 seasons for Bench and 24 seasons for Fisk. And
finally, Kirby Puckett’s career TPR statistic (32.3) was only slightly higher than
Willie Stargell’s (31.6). However, Puckett played in 9 fewer seasons than Stargell (12
versus 21). To examine this issue, we introduce a per season performance measure,
either pitcher’s TPI per season (TPI/seasons played) or hitter’s TPR per season
(TPR/seasons played). As row 5 (Alternate Model 3) of Table 2 shows for the 2003
data, the percent of variation in card price rises modestly when lifetime player
performance is measured on a per season basis. For the 2010 data, however, the
percent of card prices explained (with or without Hispanics) remains largely
unchanged when we replace the career performance variable with the career per
season average variable. Thus, we do not have a consistent answer across data sets
as to whether baseball card market participants focus more on career or on per
season achievement.
137
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
Willie Mays, Mickey Mantle,
and the Guy Next-door
In this study we follow HMOR’s
approach of using a single performance
statistic. Our study finds that race and
ethnicity of baseball greats do not matter
to the prices of rookie cards. As noted at
the outset, other studies have found
differently and others similarly. The test
is an important one. Prices communicate
information about market valuations.
Combining prices with data on performance and card quality and availability might
also tell us something about values and race or ethnicity.
Our discovery of measurement errors in HMOR’s data set together with the
omission of Hispanics from their sample raised concerns about the sensitivity of
their finding of the absence of customer discrimination in the market for baseball
cards. He and McGarrity (2004, 89) caution that “when estimating models with
small data sets, empirical research runs the risk that errors may be responsible
for the conclusions that scholars draw.” They conclude (97) that “in these cases,
careful examination of the data and robustness estimation techniques can clearly
improve the analysis.” Our corrections and extensions paint a picture of a market
in which card prices reflect career performance, independent of player race or
ethnicity.
We know how great Willie Mays and Mickey Mantle were. Race does not
appear to matter in this market. Perhaps race matters more when the individual’s
merit is less well known and people rely on their notions, often faulty, about how
merit and race (or ethnicity) co-vary.
Appendix
A supplement to this paper (link) estimates various specifications of the card
price equations used by Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver, and Regoli (2005). An Excel file
(link) contains data used in the analysis.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
138
FINDLAY AND SANTOS
References
Andersen, Torben and Sumner J. La Croix. 1991. Customer Racial
Discrimination in Major League Baseball. Economic Inquiry 29(4): 665-677.
Becker, Gary S. 1971. The Economics of Discrimination. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Beckett Baseball
Baseball. 2010. 10(3). Issue 50.
Beckett Baseball Card Monthly
Monthly. 2003. 20(4). Issue 217.
Fort, Rodney and Andrew Gill. 2000. Race and Ethnicity Assessment in Baseball
Card Markets. Journal of Sports Economics 1(1): 21-38.
Gabriel, Paul E., Curtis D. Johnson, and Timothy J. Stanton. 1995. An
Examination of Customer Racial Discrimination in the Market for Baseball
Memorabilia. Journal of Business 68(2): 215-230.
Gabriel, Paul E., Curtis D. Johnson, and Timothy J. Stanton. 1999. Customer
Racial Discrimination for Baseball Memorabilia. Applied Economics 31(11):
1331-1335.
Halvorsen, Robert and Raymond Palmquist. 1980. The Interpretation of
Dummy Variables in Semilogarithmic Equations. American Economic Review
70(3): 474-475.
He, Ling and Joseph P. McGarrity. 2004. Data Errors in Small Data Sets Can
Determine Empirical Findings. Atlantic Economic Journal 32(2): 89-99.
Hewitt, John D., Robert Muñoz, Jr., William L. Oliver, and Robert M.
Regoli. 2005. Race, Performance, and Baseball Card Values. Journal of Sport
& Social Issues 29(4): 411-425.
Kahn, Lawrence M. 1991a. Discrimination in Professional Sports: A Survey of
the Literature. Industrial and Labor Relations Review 44(3): 395-418.
Kahn, Lawrence M. 1991b. Customer Discrimination and Affirmative Action.
Economic Inquiry 29(3): 551-571.
Kahn, Lawrence M. 2000. The Sports Business as a Labor Market Laboratory.
Journal of Economic Perspectives 14(3): 75-94.
McGarrity, Joseph, Harvey D. Palmer, and Marc Poitras. 1999. Consumer
Racial Discrimination: A Reassessment of the Market for Baseball Cards.
Journal of Labor Research 20(2): 247-258.
Nardinelli, Clark and Curtis Simon. 1990. Customer Racial Discrimination in
the Market for Memorabilia: The Case of Baseball. Quarterly Journal of
Economics 105(3): 575-595.
Pascal, Anthony H. and Leonard A. Rapping. 1972. The Economics of Racial
Discrimination in Organized Baseball. In Racial Discrimination in Economic Life,
ed. Anthony H. Pascal. Lexington, Mass.: D. C. Heath and Company.
Professional Sports Authenticator. 2003. Sports Market Report. Issue 104.
139
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
RACE, ETHNICITY, AND BASEBALL CARD PRICES
Scahill, Edward M. 2005. A Reinvestigation of Racial Discrimination and
Baseball Cards. Eastern Economic Journal 31(4): 537-550.
Thorn, John, Pete Palmer, and David Reuther. 1989. Total Baseball. New York:
Warner Books.
Thorn, John, Pete Palmer, and Michael Gershman. 2001. Total Baseball.
Kingston, N.Y.: Total Sports Publishing.
Winfree, Jason A. 2010. Issues with Replicating Results in Sports Economics.
Journal of Sports Economics 11(1): 48-59.
Ziliak, Stephen T. and Deirdre N. McCloskey. 2004. Size Matters: The
Standard Error of Regressions in the American Economic Review. Econ Journal
Watch 1(2): 331-358. Link
About the Authors
David W. Findlay is the Pugh Family Professor of Economics
at Colby College where he has been a faculty member since
1985. He received his B.A. with Honours from Acadia
University (Canada) and his Ph.D. in Economics from Purdue
University. Two of his previously published articles examine
the effects of player race and ethnicity on election to the
National Baseball Hall of Fame. A native of New England, he is
a lifelong fan of the Red Sox. His email address is
[email protected].
John M. Santos is Professor of Economics in the School of
Business Administration and Morris Graduate School of
Management at Robert Morris University in Chicago, Illinois,
where he has been a faculty member since 1997. He teaches a
wide range of economics courses including labor markets and
gender. He earned his B.A. from Knox College and his Ph.D. in
Economics from the University of Illinois at UrbanaChampaign. His current research focuses on discrimination in
sports. A native Chicagoan, he grew up on the city’s south side and still lives and dies
with his White Sox. His email is
[email protected].
Robert Muñoz’s reply to this article
Go to Archive of Comments section
Go to May 2012 issue
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5760
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
140
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5761
ECON JOURNAL WATCH 9(2)
May 2012: 141-148
Beyond Race Cards in America’s
Pastime: An Appreciative Reply to
Findlay and Santos
Robert Muñoz, Jr.1
LINK TO ABSTRACT
I am one of the authors of the article—
Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver and Regoli (2005)—treated
by David Findlay and John Santos (2012) in their
piece on discrimination and the price of baseball
cards.2 I do not speak for my 2005 coauthors3, two
of whom are now retired, but there is much reason
to suppose they, like me, would salute Findlay and
Santos for their fine work in correcting, replicating,
and extending our investigation. Findlay’s and
Santos’s examination and various analyses enrich
and strengthen our findings and those of other
scholars. Their article presents a wonderful opportunity to revisit an important and fascinating
area of research in American society—baseball.
Findlay and Santos (2012) examine the data in ways that advance our parsimonious model. They undertake a wonderful and vigorous approach to both
the data and the statistical estimates. Indeed, their examination of the relationship
among price series, availability, and card quality explains a much larger percentage
1. Portland State University, Portland, OR 97207.
2. Images of Topps baseball cards used courtesy of The Topps Company, Inc. For more information about
The Topps Company, please see their website at www.topps.com.
3. Oliver’s role in the research focused on design and analysis of the statistical data.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
141
MUÑOZ
of the variation in rookie card prices. What is less clear, perhaps, is the relation of
these variables to the focus of our research question with respect to these variables,
particularly their impact on the relationship between the race of a player and the
price of his rookie card.
The examination of the impact of race on baseball card values is a research
question that has been examined in various ways with varying results depending on
sample and methodology. Some studies have found racial bias (Andersen and La
Croix 1991; Burnett and Van Scyoc 2004; Fort and Gill 2000; Gabriel, Johnson, and
Stanton 1999; Nardinelli and Simon 1990). Other research has found minimal or no
racial bias (Gabriel, Johnson, and Stanton 1995; Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver, and Regoli
2005; McGarrity, Palmer, and Poitras 1999; Messitte and Powell 1995; Mulligan
and Grube 2006; Regoli 1991; Scahill 2005).
Our research, along with that of Findlay and
Santos, has found a lack of a statistically significant
relationship between race and baseball card values.
However, we have expressed considerable reservation in the implications of these findings. Do
these findings mean that race does not affect the
value of baseball cards?
Bonilla-Silva (2003) argues that contemporary
racism is obscured by talk of meritocracy and minimal racism. Such discourse may suggest that equally
deserving African Americans rise to the top and that,
due to exceptional Black representation across
different arenas of social life, discrimination is not as
bad as it once was.
The integration of baseball provided evidence that America’s landscape was
changing. Glasser (1987) has written about the importance of baseball in the
national cultural landscape:
This progress was important on the cultural landscape during a time
of much upheaval. I date the beginning of [racial] change from 1947,
when Jackie Robinson broke the color line in baseball, because I have
always believed that the changes enacted on the cultural stage are more
profound than those on the legal stage. I was nine years old. I lived in
Brooklyn and acted out that whole drama. I went to Ebbets Field. One
day Ebbets Field was all white and the next day it was integrated. As a
nine-year old, I suddenly found myself sitting beside a fifty-two-year old
black guy drinking a beer and smoking a cigarette, and slapping hands
with him when something good happened for the Dodgers; we were part
142
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO FINDLAY AND SANTOS
the drama that was going down on the field. Everybody identified with
it. For this to be happening on national television as part of the mass
culture that hundreds of thousands of people participate in was a drama
that far exceeded in impact the business that goes on in Congress and the
Supreme Court. (Glasser 1987, 84)
Glasser’s observation makes a larger point about baseball’s ability to unite people
in a profound way, manifesting itself in the form of a major cultural event. Later
in the history of our nation, television’s response to negative stereotyping was
to include blacks in positive and important positions, such as doctors, lawyers,
business executives, and so on. However, the level of presentation greatly exceeds
the level of integration in baseball and other professions. Thus, people came to
believe that greater progress has been made since the Civil Rights Movement than
is actually the case. Although we cannot deny great changes in the the U.S. racial
landscape, the danger is that overcompensation in the visual terrain of popular
culture masks underrepresentation and inequality along the lines of race in everyday
life, the workplace, education, housing, income and other areas.
The sample of both our study and the Findlay and Santos study included
only players selected into the Hall of Fame. They are the crème de la crème emerging
from several decisions in a selection process that some studies have found to be
affected by race (Desser et al 1999; Findlay and Reid 1997), while other research
has found such effects to be limited in scope, particularly to the interaction among
race, nationality and performance (Jewell et al 2002). As for the entry into the Hall
of Fame itself, the selection process includes factors other than performance in
that it subjects Black players to an analysis of their worthiness by a primarily White
decision-making body.
Second, and relevant to both the selection process and the results of our
analyses, there are severe limitations in conceptualizing racism in a static fashion
or, more specifically, in interpreting results in dichotomous fashion or simply as
a quantitative result. It is more analytically meaningful to consider racism along a
continuum and also to consider the results in terms of the logic and meaning of
collector preferences.
Although our findings indicate a lack of significant relationship between
player race and card value, we have to keep in mind that we are looking at a
preselected sample—that is, Black players who have already been deemed worthy
of selection by the larger, dominant White society. The fact that some Black players
have been allowed into the Hall of Fame, and that the card values of these players
are similar by race, does not clearly establish that this arena of social life is free of
racism or racial thinking.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
143
MUÑOZ
Unlike the past, when African Americans were excluded from most American institutions, today we can point to almost any arena of social life in the United
States and find the inclusion of African Americans. However, the inclusion of
some African Americans does not satisfactorily account for the exclusion of many
African Americans on a widespread level. Our finding—that no statistically significant difference exists in the value of their cards based on race—must be understood as only being operative for, or indicative of, Black players found to be
acceptable for inclusion in the Hall of Fame. That is, there may be a form of tokenism at work here, a seeming level of equality based on those Black players found to
be worthwhile and acceptable by a predominantly White decision-making body.
Thus, the measure of racism here should not be limited to whether African
Americans are included or valued equally but under what conditions and based
on what criteria are African Americans included and valued equally. We indicated
in our study that to address this question researchers would need to expand our
sample and data. However, future studies that hope to shed light on the impact
of player race on card values also require a different methodology to determine
whether any racial logic or thinking exists in the mind of collectors.
It is only by way of a more qualitative approach such as focused interviews
that researchers will better understand the meaning of numbers or, more specifically, the reasoning and values attached to the prices of cards of Black and White
players. Although Feagin (2000) posits that race affects all levels of society, it is not
as simple as a yes or no question, or Black or White differences; it is also a question
of how race might affect both the outcomes and also the meanings, explanations,
and interpretations that collectors associate with the outcomes or, in this case, the
valuation of the cards. Research on questions of race is not simply a case of ‘show
me the money’—we must also ask research to show us the meaning.
144
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO FINDLAY AND SANTOS
On Latinos in the Player Sample
Findlay and Santos note that we excluded
Latinos from our investigation. Before withdrawing
commentary, I want to give a brief explanation of
that decision.
Back in 2004, Regoli invited me to examine
the findings and consider their implications within
the larger body of research on race. I played a role in
conversations about the decision to exclude Latinos
from the sample. In the statistical analyses in preparation of our research publication (Hewitt, Muñoz,
Oliver and Regoli 2005), we found no statistically
significant estimates of the impact on ethnicity on
baseball card values; this finding was subsequently
reported in Regoli, Primm and Hewitt (2007).
In a previous study (Regoli 2000) and in a subsequent study (Primm, Piquero,
Hewitt and Piquero 2010), Regoli included at least three of five Latino players
identified as Black in statistical estimates. The rationale was that baseball card
traders identify race by physical appearance. In discussing our sample, while in
the midst of conducting the research for the study, we concluded that the lack of
significance was most likely a result of the limited number of Latinos in the sample.
Thus, our research did not allow discussion of any reliable findings regarding the
impact of Latino ethnicity on the value of baseball cards. In short, the issue of
including Latinos had already been resolved by the time of our 2005 study.
Primm et al (2010) explain the complexity of racial identification and subsequent rationales in studies related to our research:
Since there were only four Latino players in the study they were combined with the Black players to form one category. There may be
differences in the value of cards between Black, White, and Latino
players that are being masked by their categorization in this study, and
this will surely be the case in the future as Latino baseball players become
an increasing and dominant presence in the game. In addition, this is
likely to open useful inquiries that explore race and ethnicity based on
skin tone (see Hunter’s (2005) discussion of “colorism”). These and
other questions regarding the role of race in sports card collecting should
offer a rich area for researchers for some time to come. (872)
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
145
MUÑOZ
Racially speaking in the United States, many Afro-Latinos—Puerto Rican,
Cuban and Dominican Americans—continue to be identified primarily as Black
(Bonilla-Silva 2003; Gonzalez 2011). It is only recently that our consciousness
about racial identity is beginning to emerge beyond the simple definition of race
relations in terms of Black and White; this recognition is exemplified by increasing
public awareness of the presence and impact of Latino players in baseball.
References
Andersen, Torben and Sumner J. La Croix. 1991. Customer Racial
Discrimination in Major League Baseball. Economic Inquiry 29: 665-677.
Bonilla-Silva, Eduardo. 2003. Racism Without Racists: Color-blind Racism and the
Persistence of Racial Inequality in the United States. New York: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Burnett, Nancy J. and Lee Van Scyoc. 2004. Discriminating Buyers of Baseball
Cards: Does Race Affect Value? Journal of Economics and Economic Education
Research 5: 101-109.
Desser, Arna, James Monks, and Michael Robinson. 1999. Baseball Hall of
Fame Voting: A Test of the Customer Discrimination Hypothesis. Social
Science Quarterly 80: 591-603.
Feagin, Joe. 2000. Racist America. New York: Routledge.
Findlay, David W. and Clifford E. Reid. 1997. Voting Behavior, Discrimination
and the National Baseball Hall of Fame. Economic Inquiry 35(3): 562-578.
Findlay, David W. and John M. Santos. 2012. Race, Ethnicity, and Baseball Card
Prices: A Replication, Correction, and Extension of Hewitt, Muñoz, Oliver,
and Regoli. Econ Journal Watch 9(2): 122-140. Link
Fort, Rodney and Andrew Gill. 2000. Race and Ethnicity Assessment in Baseball
Card Markets. Journal of Sports Economics 1: 21-38.
Gabriel, Paul E., Curtis D. Johnson, and Timothy J. Stanton. 1995. An
Examination of Customer Racial Discrimination in the Market for Baseball
Memorabilia. Journal of Business 68: 215-230.
Gabriel, Paul E., Curtis D. Johnson, and Timothy J. Stanton. 1999. Customer
Racial Discrimination for Baseball Memorabilia. Applied Economics 31:
1331-1335.
Glasser, Ira. 1987. Civil Rights and Civil Liberties. In Race: An Anthology in the First
Person, ed. Bart Schneider. New York: Three Rivers Press.
Gonzalez, Juan. 2011. Harvest of Empire: A History of Latinos in America. New York:
Penguin Books.
146
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
REPLY TO FINDLAY AND SANTOS
Hewitt, John D., Robert Muñoz, William L. Oliver, and Robert M. Regoli.
2005. Race, Performance, and Baseball Card Values. Journal of Sport & Social
Issues 29(4): 411-425.
Hunter, Margaret L. 2005. Race, Gender, and the Politics of Skin Tone. New York:
Routledge.
Jewell, Robert T., Robert W. Brown, and Scott E. Miles. 2002. Measuring
Discrimination in Major League Baseball: Evidence from the Baseball Hall
of Fame. Applied Economics 34: 167-177.
McGarrity, Joseph, Harvey Palmer, and Mark Poitras. 1999. Consumer Racial
Discrimination: A Reassessment of the Market for Baseball Cards. Journal of
Labor Research 20: 247-258.
Messitte, Jesse and Irene Powell. 1995. Customer Race Discrimination in the
Market for Baseball Cards. Paper presented at Department of Economics,
Grinnell College.
Mulligan, Robert F. and A. J. Grube. 2006. Modeling Markets for Sports
Memorabilia. Journal of Economics and Economic Education Research 7: 75-102.
Nardinelli, Clark and Curtis Simon. 1990. Customer Racial Discrimination in
the Market for Memorabilia: The Case of Baseball. Quarterly Journal of
Economics 105: 575-595.
Primm, Eric, Nicole L. Piquero, Robert M. Regoli, and Alex R. Piquero.
2010. Racial Bias in Baseball Card Collecting Revisited. Social Justice Journal 47:
865-874.
Regoli, Robert M. 1991. Racism in Baseball Card Collecting: Fact or Fiction?
Human Relations 44: 255-264.
Regoli, Robert M. 2000. Racism, Racism Everywhere: Looking Inside the Hobby
of Baseball Card Collecting. Race & Society 3: 183-192.
Regoli, Robert M., E. E. Primm, and J. D. Hewitt. 2007. Where O’ Where Did
My Baseball Cards Go? Race, Performance, and Placement in the Topps Era,
1956-1980. Social Science Journal 44: 742-750.
Scahill, Edward M. 2005. A Reinvestigation of Racial Discrimination and
Baseball Cards. Eastern Economic Journal 31: 537-550.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
147
MUÑOZ
About the Author
Robert Muñoz is an assistant professor at Portland State
University. He attended Southern Methodist University (B.S.)
and University of Colorado, Boulder (Ph.D.). Other research
areas include family structure, educational attainment, tobacco
control, cultural competency in mental health, and Latino
wellbeing. He has worked as a program director, principal
investigator and evaluator in public health, immigration and
youth projects. Robert champions higher education for diverse
students, program and pipeline development, student research opportunities, and
enhancing infrastructure and capacity for equity. Current courses include Histories,
Representations & Imaginations of Latinidad in American Culture; Southwest
Borderlands; and Race and Social Justice. Robert loves hiking, dancing, film, and
road trips across America. His email is
[email protected].
Go to Archive of Comments section
Go to May 2012 issue
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5761
148
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5762
ECON JOURNAL WATCH 9(2)
May 2012: 149-162
Characteristics of the Members of
Twelve Economic Associations:
Voting, Policy Views, and
Favorite Economists
Daniel B. Klein1, William L. Davis2,
Bob G. Figgins3, and David Hedengren4
LINK TO ABSTRACT
This article offers characterization of members of twelve professional economic associations, based on a survey of economics professors in the United
States.5 There seems to be very little literature comparing and characterizing such
memberships.6
Previously we published an article entitled “Economics Professors’ Favorite
Economic Thinkers, Journals, and Blogs (along with Party and Policy Views).”
The article reports on a large-scale survey conducted in March 2010. The response
rate was only 15.2 percent, but the gender ratio and party-voting ratio of the respondents give reason to believe that the set of 299 respondents is reasonably
1. Professor of Economics, George Mason University, Fairfax, VA 22030.
2. Professor of Economics, University of Tennessee at Martin, Martin, TN 38238.
3. Professor of Economics, University of Tennessee at Martin, Martin, TN 38238.
4. Graduate student, Department of Economics, George Mason University, Fairfax, VA 22030.
5. We thank the College of Business and Global Affairs at the University of Tennessee at Martin for
funding the survey, and we thank Robert Whaples for valuable feedback and Paul Mueller for valuable
research assistance.
6. Copp (1992) is based on a survey of samples of the members of the American Economic Association,
the Union for Radical Political Economists, and the Association for Evolutionary Economics. The paper
does not provide information that would enable comparison to our results.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
149
KLEIN, DAVIS, FIGGINS, AND HEDENGREN
representative of economics professors in the United States. Details are found in
the paper (Davis et al 2011).
The survey instrument (link) included the following question:
The following list contains the names of 12 economics associations in
the United States. Kindly mark your membership, both in terms of the
present and for any time during the past ten years.
[Check all that apply. Please check only if the membership is in your own name (not
that of an institution).]
TABLE 1. Association Membership Frequencies, of 299 respondents
Member at present
American Economic Assoc. (AEA)
Member any time
during the past 10
years
Member at present
or any time during
the past 10 years
197
66%
101
34%
254
85%
Assoc. for Evolutionary
Economics (AFEE)
9
3%
8
3%
14
5%
Assoc. for Private Enterprise
Education (APEE)
14
5%
9
3%
20
7%
Eastern Economic Assoc. (EEA)
23
8%
49
16%
65
22%
Econometric Society (ES)
45
15%
47
16%
78
26%
Intern’l Assoc. for Feminist
Economics (IAFFE)
10
3%
7
2%
15
5%
Public Choice Society (PCS)
9
3%
18
6%
27
9%
Society for the Advancement of
Socio-Economics (SASE)
5
2%
4
1%
9
3%
Society for the Development of
Austrian Economics (SDAE)
4
1%
1
0.3%
4
1%
Southern Economic Assoc. (SEA)
46
15%
63
21%
96
32%
Union for Radical Political
Economics (URPE)
9
3%
8
3%
16
5%
Western Economic Assoc. (WEA)
34
11%
59
20%
85
28%
The numbers and percentages in the first two data columns come from the check
marks that the respondent made on the survey. If we collapse those two columns
into a single column, Member at present or any time during the past 10 years, we get the
third column (which was not in the survey question). The denominator of the third
column is the set of 299 respondents. In the remainder of this paper, except where
stated otherwise, we use that combination response; that is, when we refer to the
members of an association, we mean respondents who checked being a member
“at present” or “any time during the past 10 years” or both.
We see that 85 percent of our respondents had been American Economic
Association members during the preceding ten years. The next highest percentage
150
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TWELVE ECONOMIC ASSOCIATIONS
is 32 percent for the Southern Economic Association. To the best of our knowledge, the survey mailing to 2000 economics professors did not have a regional
bias. The next highest is 28 percent for the Western Economic Association. Then
comes 26 percent for Econometrica Society, and then 22 percent for the Eastern
Economic Association. There is then a big drop down to 9 percent for the Public
Choice Society, and the other six have smaller percentages.7
Of the twelve associations, then, seven are represented by rather small
numbers in our sample—27 or fewer. We believe, however, that even a sample of
14 members is helpful in revealing salient characteristics of the membership, and
ten of twelve associations are represented in sample by 14 or more individuals.
We report on all twelve, even the Society for Advancement of Socio-Economics
(represented in the sample by nine individuals) and the Society for the Development of Austrian Economics (represented by just four individuals), but we
caution the reader about the small numbers in those cases.
The voting question was as follows:
To which political party have the candidates you’ve voted for in the past ten
years mostly belonged?
Democratic
Green
Libertarian
Republican
other
The results for the entire sample were 56.1 percent Democratic, 1.7 percent Green,
5.7 percent Libertarian, 20.7 percent Republican, with the remaining 15.8 percent
being other/cannot or do not vote/no reply.8
As in our previous paper, we use the following party-voting index:
(#Democrats + #Greens)/(#Republicans + #Libertarians + 0.1). The “+ 0.1”
appearing in the denominator is there to solve the problem that arises when it is
otherwise zero. In reading the report that follows, when you see a party-ratio score
that is wildly large, it is because there is nothing in the denominator except the 0.1.
7. We tried to obtain from each of the 12 associations its 2010 individual membership total, but succeeded
with only six of them: the AEA, APEE, ES, SDAE, URPE, and WEA. Using those membership numbers
and the “at present” data from our survey, we did an analysis that leads us to think that the AEA
representation in our survey is very accurate to the population, that the ES is under-represented somewhat,
the WEA is over-represented somewhat, and the three smaller associations are all over-represented at least
somewhat. This analysis is available upon request.
8. Subsequent to publishing our 2011 article, we discovered that the party coding of one survey (#5011)
was entered as Democratic when in fact the respondent’s answer was Libertarian (the mismatch between
the entered party coding and the policy views led us to double check). For this reason the percentages for
those two parties differ very slightly from the reporting in our 2011 article—and other numbers in the 2011
paper are off slightly because of the error.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
151
KLEIN, DAVIS, FIGGINS, AND HEDENGREN
Crudely speaking, the index is the ratio of Left to Right.9 Using this party index
with some misgivings,10 we arrive at a Left to Right ratio within the entire sample of
2.19.11
The 17 policy questions took the form as shown in the sample statement
below:
Higher minimum wages:
support
strongly
support, not
strongly
neutral
oppose, not
strongly
oppose
strongly
have no
opinion
We followed the format shown in asking these 17 policy questions:
1. Higher minimum wages
2. Tighter restrictions (e.g., tariffs and quotas) on imported goods
3. Tighter requirements for the permitting of new pharmaceuticals
and medical devices
4. Tighter restrictions on private parties engaging in discrimination
(on the basis of race, gender, age, ethnicity, religion or sexualorientation) against other private parties, in employment or
accommodations?
5. Tighter restrictions on the buying and selling of human organs
6. Tighter workplace safety regulation (e.g., by the Occupational
Safety and Health Administration (OSHA))
7. Tighter air-quality and water-quality regulation (e.g., by the Env.
Protection Ag. (EPA))
8. Tighter requirements on occupational licensing
9. Tighter restrictions on prostitution
10. Tighter restrictions on gambling
11. Tighter controls on immigration
12. Tighter restrictions on adult women having an abortion
9. When we use these terms in this paper, capitalizing the first letter, we mean merely these party groupings.
10. Our chief misgiving is in lumping the Libertarians with the Republicans. On the 17 policy questions,
we find that the Republicans and Democrats are more alike than are the Libertarians and Republicans.
Also, on three of the questions, the Democrats are meaningfully more liberal than the Republicans. But the
Libertarian group is small, and there is a virtue in parsimony in reporting (as with our party index). Also, our
respondents are all professors, and, in matters of the professoriate, it is well known that Democrats (along
with a few Greens) dominate, and all else is periphery.
11. Regarding this value of 2.19, notice that the 5.7 percent Libertarian make this index quite different from
the straight Democrat/Republican ratio, which for our sample is 2.71.
152
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TWELVE ECONOMIC ASSOCIATIONS
13. Tighter restrictions on “hard” drugs such as cocaine and heroin
14. More redistribution (e.g., transfer and aid programs and tax
progressivity)
15. More funding of the public school system
16. More benefits and coverage by Medicaid
17. More American military aid or presence abroad to promote
democracy and the rule of law
Each policy question posits a reform that ratchets up restrictions on individual
liberty or that expands tax-funded government activities. We create a liberalism12
score of domain [0, 4] by scoring the responses as follows: “support strongly” was
scored as 0, “support, not strongly” as 1, “neutral” as 2, “oppose, not strongly”
as 3, and “oppose strongly” as 4 (and “have no opinion” as missing data, not as
“neutral”). Higher scores are deemed more liberal. We are aware of the gray areas,
the semantic controversies, and the other controversies (“Doesn’t abortion violate
the liberty of the fetus?,” “What about when immigrants support interventionist
policies?,” “Doesn’t the American military sometimes promote liberty?”), but we
simply exercise our judgment and move on.13
TABLE 2. Each Association’s Party Voting Scores and Liberalism
Scores
Association
AEA
N Percent of 299
254
Party voting score
Liberalism score
85
2.14
2.29
AFEE
14
5
130.00
1.45
APEE
20
7
0.50
3.30
EEA
65
22
3.20
2.14
ES
78
26
2.70
2.26
IAFFE
15
5
116.67
1.69
PCS
27
9
0.48
3.02
9
3
7.27
1.63
SASE
4
1
0.00
3.94
SEA
SDAE
96
32
1.64
2.55
URPE
16
5
22.50
1.56
WEA
85
28
1.65
2.38
None
27
9
2.79
2.12
299
100
2.19
2.27
All
12. We use the term liberalism in the original or classical sense that is still revealed in the verb to liberalize and
is still current in much of the world.
13. Liberalism scores varied substantially by party affiliation: Democrats 1.94, Greens 1.57, Libertarians
3.52, Republicans 2.71.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
153
KLEIN, DAVIS, FIGGINS, AND HEDENGREN
On the American Economic Association
The bottom row of Table 2 shows the results for all respondents. We see
that the party voting and liberalism scores for the AEA are very close to those
for the set of all respondents. That closeness might be unsurprising, since AEA
was checked by 85 percent of the sample. It has been suggested by Klein (2006)
and McEachern (2006) that the AEA is more Democratic than the profession at
large; however, the present results indicate that those who have been a member
during the preceding ten years are ideologically equivalent to the population of U.S.
economics professors; in fact, the 45 non-members surveyed have a 2.45 voting
score, putting them slightly to the Left of the members (2.14).
During a ten-year period, most any economics professor might join the
AEA, if only because he or she attends the annual conference for reasons related
to the economics job market. One might figure that a respondent who checked
AEA membership “at present” is more likely to be an AEA faithful, so to speak,
than one who checked AEA membership “during the past 10 years” but not “at
present.”14 The liberalism score of the 197 respondents who marked “at present”
was 2.32, while that of the 57 who did not mark “at present” (but did mark “during
the past 10 years”) was 2.26, which would indicate that the average ‘faithful’ AEA
member is very slightly more liberal than the average lapsed member, going against
the speculations of Klein and McEachern. However, the party voting score for
‘faithful’ members is 2.31, which is to the Left of the lapsed members’ score (1.91).
Still, that 2.31 voting score is close to the voting score of the entire sample of
respondents (2.19). This study fails to support the notion that the AEA’s
membership is significantly more Democratic than the population of economics
professors.
It should be acknowledged that there is an important distinction between
an association’s membership and its leadership.15 That distinction highlights a
limitation of the present study: We are drawing out characteristics based on mere
members, not leaders. In the case of the general/regional associations such as the
AEA, SEA, WEA, and EEA, people often join them for reasons having little to do
with what the leadership happens to be like. So it could be that their leadership has
features that are not evident in the body of regular members.
14. Ideally, the two options about membership would have been neatly partitioned as follows: “at present”
and “any time from ten years ago up to one year ago.” That would have given three distinct sets to compare.
But we opted for an overlapping second option “any time during the past 10 years,” yielding us only two
clearly distinct sets of members, because we thought it would be too tedious to ask the respondent “any
time from ten years ago up to one year ago.”
154
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TWELVE ECONOMIC ASSOCIATIONS
The Southern, Western, Eastern, and
Econometric Associations
The entire sample of economics professors had a party voting score of 2.19
and a liberalism score of 2.27, and the AEA had scores very close to those. The
three regional associations show some departure. The Southern Economic Association has a party score of 1.64 and a liberalism score of 2.55, indicating that its
membership leans less to the Left than does the entire sample, and the Western
Economic Association has a party score of 1.65 and liberalism score of 2.38,
indicating that its membership also leans less to the Left. By contrast, the Eastern
Economic Association leans even more to the Left than does the general
population of economics professors, with a party score of 3.20 and a liberalism
score of 2.14. The Econometric Society is an association that might also be
regarded as a “general” association; its party score is 2.70 and its liberalism score is
2.26.
The Evolutionary, Feminist, Socio-Economic,
and Radical Associations
Four associations—the Association for Evolutionary Economics (AFEE),
the International Association for Feminist Economics (IAFEE), the Society for
the Advancement of Socio-Economics (SASE), and the Union for Radical Political
Economics (URPE)—have a Left preponderance that goes far beyond the entire
sample. None of the respondents who checked AFEE, IAFEE, or URPE mem15. When Klein and McEachern suggested that the AEA leaned Democratic, however, it was not chiefly
the general membership that they had in mind. Although Klein (2006, 196-199) offered sparse data about
AEA membership and voter registration—the drift of which our present results fail to support, or even
go against—the chief focus both of Klein and of McEachern was the leadership of the AEA, including the
editorships of the journals. McEachern (2006) provides data on campaign contributions during the 2004
election cycle. Regular members of the AEA were five times more likely to give to Democrats than to
Republicans, but this might not be meaningful because only 3.8 percent of the membership gave to the
Democrats. What is more significant is how that percentage climbed as one goes up the AEA pyramid:
From 3.8 percent among regular members, the rate goes to 7.1 percent among American Economic Review
authors, 10.4 percent among authors of the discretionary journals (JEL, JEP, and AER P&P), 14 percent
among editors of those journals, and 16.2 percent among search and nominating committee members
(McEachern 2006, 168-170). Meanwhile, the Republican support becomes remarkably scant. The data
strongly indicates that the elites of the AEA supported the Democratic Party vastly more than the
Republican Party and that the lopsidedness increases the higher up we go in the AEA structure.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
155
KLEIN, DAVIS, FIGGINS, AND HEDENGREN
bership responded merely Republican or Libertarian to the voting question, and
only one SASE respondent did so. And compared to the 2.27 liberalism score for
the entire sample, the liberalism scores of these four groups indicate that they are
particularly interventionist: 1.45 for AFEE, 1.69 for IAFEE, 1.63 for SASE, and
1.56 for URPE. All of these scores are below the “neutral” mark of 2.00, which
means that the members of these groups lean toward supporting the 17 proposals
for stepping up incursions on liberty—not in every case, of course, but on the
whole.
The Private Enterprise, Public Choice, and
Austrian Associations
Three of the associations—the Association for Private Enterprise Education
(APEE), the Public Choice Society (PCS), and the Society for the Development
of Austrian Economics (SDAE)—have party scores below 1.00, which means they
tilt to the Right: 0.50 for APEE, 0.48 for PCS, and 0.0 for SDAE. Only four
respondents were members of the SDAE. It is important to note that among the
38 respondents who checked membership in any of those three associations, the
party score is 0.47. Thus, the subset of economists who have been members in the
three Right associations seems to lean to the Right only about as much as the whole
population of economics professors leans to the Left!
As for liberalism scores, the four SDAE respondents nearly reached
libertarian perfection, with a score of 3.94. The 20 APEE members scored 3.30
and the 27 PCS members 3.02. As economics is the only discipline among the humanities and social sciences for which the professoriate is not highly dominated
by Left voting and corresponding policy views (Klein and Stern 2005; 2009), these
three scholarly associations are probably quite exceptional among all humanities/
social science associations for their liberalism and Right voting.
Favorite Economists of Various Ages
We also asked respondents to name their favorite economic thinkers, ranked
first, second, and third, for each of four time frames. Table 4 shows for each age
the three favorites of each association, according to our tallying system, which
gave six points to a first-place response, five points to a second, and four points
to a third. We also list in parentheses the number of pure mentions of the named
individuals. In almost all cases the point-based ranking agrees with the number
156
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TWELVE ECONOMIC ASSOCIATIONS
of pure mentions, but there is one (strict) exception: For AEA members’ favorite
economists under the age of 60, Greg Mankiw ranked slightly ahead of Daron
Acemoglu, but had one less mention.16
TABLE 3. Each Association’s Favorite Economic Thinkers (number of mentions)
Pre-20th Cent.
20th Century – deceased
Assn (N)
1st
2nd
3rd
1st
AEA
(254)
Smith,
Adam
(193)
Ricardo,
David
(91)
2nd
3rd
Marshall,
Alfred
(60)
Keynes, J.M.
(114)
Friedman,
Milton
(113)
Samuelson,
Paul
(80)
AFEE
(14)
Smith,
Adam
(11)
Marx, Karl
(7)
Mill, John
Stuart
(6)
Keynes, J.M.
(10)
Veblen,
Thorstein
(7)
Galbraith,
John K.
(5)
APEE
(20)
Smith,
Adam
(18)
Menger,
Carl
(4)
Marshall,
Alfred
(4)
Friedman,
Milton
(12)
Hayek,
Friedrich
(10)
Mises,
Ludwig von
(4)
EEA
(65)
Smith,
Adam
(46)
Ricardo,
David
(26)
Mill, John
Stuart
(18)
Keynes, J.M.
(38)
Friedman,
Milton
(24)
Samuelson,
Paul
(16)
ES
(78)
Smith,
Adam
(56)
Ricardo,
David
(32)
Marshall,
Alfred
(17)
Keynes, J.M.
(35)
Friedman,
Milton
(32)
Samuelson,
Paul
(31)
IAFFE
(15)
Smith,
Adam
(8)
Marx, Karl
(5)
Ricardo,
David
(5)
Keynes, J.M.
(10)
Robinson,
Joan
(4)
Veblen,
Thorstein
(4)
PCS
(27)
Smith,
Adam
(26)
Marshall,
Alfred
(9)
Ricardo,
David
(8)
Friedman,
Milton
(16)
Hayek,
Friedrich
(8)
Keynes,
J.M.
(7)
SASE
(9)
Smith,
Adam
(7)
Mill, John
Stuart
(3)
Marx, Karl
(3)
Keynes, J.M.
(4)
Galbraith,
John K.
(3)
Polanyi,
Karl
(2)
SDAE
(4)
Smith,
Adam
(4)
Menger,
Carl
(4)
Ricardo,
David
(1)
Hayek,
Friedrich
(4)
Mises,
Ludwig von
(3)
Rothbard,
Murray
(2)
SEA
(96)
Smith,
Adam
(74)
Ricardo,
David
(34)
Mill, John
Stuart
(21)
Friedman,
Milton
(52)
Keynes, J.M.
(38)
Samuelson,
Paul
(23)
URPE
(16)
Marx, Karl
(12)
Smith,
Adam
(12)
Ricardo,
David
(11)
Keynes, J.M.
(13)
Robinson,
Joan
(5)
Galbraith,
John K.
(5)
WEA
(85)
Smith,
Adam
(71)
Ricardo,
David
(28)
Mill, John
Stuart
(24)
Keynes, J.M.
(40)
Friedman,
Milton
(38)
Samuelson,
Paul
(21)
All
(299)
Smith,
Adam
(221)
Ricardo,
David
(106)
Marshall,
Alfred
(67)
Keynes, J.M.
(134)
Friedman,
Milton
(124)
Samuelson,
Paul
(90)
16. Details about how we sorted out responses so as to put the responses into the proper era are found in
Davis et al (2011, 133 n. 12).
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
157
KLEIN, DAVIS, FIGGINS, AND HEDENGREN
TABLE 3 (cont'd). Each Association’s Favorite Economic Thinkers (number of mentions)
Living 60 and Older
Living Under 60
Assn (N)
1st
2nd
3rd
1st
2nd
3rd
AEA
(254)
Becker,
Gary
(58)
Arrow,
Kenneth
(39)
Solow,
Robert
(31)
Krugman,
Paul
(56)
Mankiw,
Greg
(20)
Acemoglu,
Daron
(21)
AFEE
(14)
Davidson,
Paul
(2)
Sen,
Amartya
(2)
Daly,
Herman
(2)
Krugman,
Paul
(4)
Galbraith,
James K.
(3)
Mankiw,
Greg
(1)
APEE
(20)
Buchanan,
James
(8)
Coase,
Ronald
(8)
Tullock,
Gordon
(4)
Easterly,
William
(5)
Shleifer,
Andrei
(3)
Cowen,
Tyler
(3)
EEA
(65)
Arrow,
Kenneth
(11)
Becker,
Gary
(10)
Stiglitz,
Joseph
(10)
Krugman,
Paul
(17)
Mankiw,
Greg
(6)
Levitt, Steve
(5)
ES
(78)
Becker,
Gary
(19)
Arrow,
Kenneth
(17)
Solow,
Robert
(15)
Krugman,
Paul
(15)
Acemoglu,
Daron
(6)
Mankiw,
Greg
(4)
IAFFE
(15)
Arrow,
Kenneth
(4)
Stiglitz,
Joseph
(3)
Ferber,
Marianne
(2)
Folbre,
Nancy
(5)
Krugman,
Paul
(2)
Galbraith,
James K.
(2)
PCS
(27)
Buchanan,
James
(11)
Coase,
Ronald
(10)
Becker,
Gary
(8)
Acemoglu,
Daron
(4)
Easterly,
William
(4)
Shleifer,
Andrei
(3)
SASE
(9)
Stiglitz,
Joseph
(2)
Sen,
Amartya
(2)
Klein,
Lawrence
(1)
Krugman,
Paul
(3)
Frank,
Robert
(2)
Folbre,
Nancy
(1)
SDAE
(4)
Coase,
Ronald
(2)
Kirzner,
Israel
(2)
Reisman,
George
(1)
Shleifer,
Andrei
(2)
Easterly,
William
(2)
Stringham,
Edward
(1)
SEA
(96)
Becker,
Gary
(31)
Coase,
Ronald
(15)
Arrow,
Kenneth
(10)
Krugman,
Paul
(18)
Mankiw,
Greg
(13)
Levitt, Steve
(10)
URPE
(16)
Sen,
Amartya
(5)
Stiglitz,
Joseph
(4)
Becker,
Gary
(3)
Krugman,
Paul
(5)
Galbraith,
James K.
(4)
Folbre,
Nancy
(3)
WEA
(85)
Becker,
Gary
(25)
Arrow,
Kenneth
(14)
Coase,
Ronald
(12)
Krugman,
Paul
(19)
Mankiw,
Greg
(12)
Levitt, Steve
(12)
All
(299)
Becker,
Gary
(65)
Arrow,
Kenneth
(41)
Solow,
Robert
(35)
Krugman,
Paul
(60)
Mankiw,
Greg
(22)
Acemoglu,
Daron
(22)
In our paper on the favorites of the entire sample, we noted the towering
place of Adam Smith in the pre-20th century category (especially when place points
are awarded, as in Davis et al 2011, 132). The present analysis shows that appreciation for Smith also cuts across associational lines: Smith takes eleven first
places and one second place.
The personages selected provide valuable guidance to the character of members of each association. Here we shall not treat the general associations, for the
158
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TWELVE ECONOMIC ASSOCIATIONS
results mostly mirror those of the entire sample, which are treated in our previous
paper (Davis et al 2011). But we pause to comment on the other associations.
All four of the highly leftist associations (AFEE, IAFEE, SASE, and URPE)
have Karl Marx in the pre-20th century category, and in the 20th-century-deceased
category variously strong showings for J.M. Keynes, Thorstein Veblen, John K.
Galbraith, and Joan Robinson. For the over-60 living category, two standouts are
Amartya Sen and Joseph Stiglitz; and notable showings in the under-60 living
category are for Paul Krugman, James K. Galbraith, and Nancy Folbre.
Likewise, the personages selected by the three liberal associations (APEE,
PCS, and SDAE) represent such an outlook—notably, variously, Friedrich Hayek,
Milton Friedman, Ludwig von Mises, James Buchanan, Ronald Coase, William
Easterly, and Andre Shleifer.
Membership Intersections
Table 4 shows the percentage of the association listed at the top of the
column belonging to the association listed in the row. The results show relatively
high intersection rates among the leftist associations, and among the liberal associations.
TABLE 4. Percentage of the column association belonging to the row association
N
All
AEA
AFEE
APEE
EEA
ES
IAFFE
PCS
SASE
SDAE
SEA
URPE
299
254
14
20
65
78
15
27
9
4
96
16
85
86%
90%
92%
95%
93%
96%
89%
100%
95%
100%
92%
5%
11%
1%
13%
0%
44%
0%
2%
31%
4%
AEA
85%
AFEE
5%
5%
APEE
7%
7%
7%
EEA
22%
24%
50%
30%
9%
ES
5%
0%
33%
0%
100%
13%
6%
6%
24%
47%
19%
33%
0%
28%
69%
27%
13%
15%
11%
0%
26%
13%
31%
4%
11%
0%
3%
25%
5%
0%
50%
15%
6%
14%
0%
2%
25%
2%
4%
6%
1%
19%
59%
26%
29%
7%
20%
29%
IAFFE
5%
6%
14%
0%
11%
3%
PCS
9%
10%
0%
45%
8%
5%
SASE
3%
3%
29%
0%
5%
1%
7%
0%
SDAE
1%
2%
0%
20%
0%
0%
0%
7%
0%
32%
36%
14%
60%
42%
32%
20%
52%
22%
SEA
WEA
7%
100%
URPE
5%
6%
36%
5%
17%
3%
27%
4%
44%
25%
3%
WEA
28%
31%
21%
25%
35%
33%
27%
44%
22%
25%
52%
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
2%
13%
159
KLEIN, DAVIS, FIGGINS, AND HEDENGREN
Concluding Remarks: Up with Characterology
Today, major books such as Daniel Kahneman’s Thinking, Fast and Slow and
Jonathan Haidt’s The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics and
Religion exemplify a trend toward awareness of the dominating role of subterranean
sensibilities, or what David Hume might call the passions. A candid understanding
of human psychology leads one into a study of character. Important features of
character include political-party orientation and policy views, as well as admired
figures. In this paper we have used such variables to characterize the members of
twelve economic associations. For reasons articulated by Gunnar Myrdal (1969),
we believe that science and ethics are advanced when individuals are open about
their character and perspective and informed about those whom they read or listen
to.
Appendices
At the survey homepage (link), one can download the survey instrument (link),
the listing of 300 economics departments (link), and the Excel files for tables
shown in this paper (link). The raw data for this paper are available upon
request and will be posted online in September 2012.
References
Copp, Carol. 1992. Three Kinds of Economists: Memberships and
Characteristics. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 51(1): 43-56.
Davis, William L., Bob G. Figgins, David Hedengren, and Daniel B. Klein.
2011. Economics Professors’ Favorite Economic Thinkers, Journals, and
Blogs (along with Party and Policy Views). Econ Journal Watch 8(2): 126-146.
Link
Haidt, Jonathan. 2012. The Righteous Mind: Why Good People Are Divided by Politics
and Religion. New York: Pantheon.
Kahneman, Daniel. 2011. Thinking, Fast and Slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and
Giroux.
Klein, Daniel B. 2006. Sense and Sensibilities: Myrdal’s Plea for Self-Disclosure
and Some Disclosures on AEA Members. Econ Journal Watch 3(1): 180-205.
Link
160
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TWELVE ECONOMIC ASSOCIATIONS
Klein, Daniel B., William L. Davis, Bob G. Figgins, and David Hedengren.
2012. Most Economists Welcome Ideological Openness, A Survey
Indicates. The Independent Review, forthcoming.
Klein, Daniel B. and Charlotta Stern. 2005. Professors and Their Politics: The
Policy Views of Social Scientists. Critical Review 17 (3-4): 257-303. Link
Klein, Daniel B. and Charlotta Stern. 2009. By the Numbers: The Ideological
Profile of Professors. In The Politically Correct University: Problems, Scope, and
Reforms, eds. Robert Maranto, Richard Redding, and Frederick Hess.
Washington, D.C.: American Enterprise Institute: 15-33. Link
McEachern, William A. 2006. AEA Ideology: Campaign Contributions of
American Economic Association Members, Committee Members, Officers,
Editors, Referees, Authors, and Acknowledgees. Econ Journal Watch 3(1):
148-179. Link
Myrdal, Gunnar. 1969. Objectivity in Social Research. New York: Pantheon Books.
About the Authors
Daniel Klein is professor of economics at George Mason
University, fellow of the Ratio Institute, and chief editor of
Econ Journal Watch. He is the author of Knowledge and Coordination: A Liberal Interpretation (Oxford University Press,
2012). His email is
[email protected].
William L. Davis is Professor of Economics at the University
of Tennessee at Martin where he has taught undergraduate and
graduate courses for the last 22 years and currently serves as the
managing editor for the Journal of Business and Economic
Perspectives. His email is
[email protected].
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
161
KLEIN, DAVIS, FIGGINS, AND HEDENGREN
Bob Figgins is Professor of Economics at the University of
Tennessee at Martin where he has taught economics courses
for the last 40 years. His email is
[email protected].
David Hedengren is a PhD student at George Mason
University where he is a recipient of the Walter E. Williams
fellowship. His interests include economic history and applied
econometrics. His email is
[email protected].
Go to Archive of Character Issues section
Go to May 2012 issue
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5762
162
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5763
ECON JOURNAL WATCH 9(2)
May 2012: 163-169
Editorial note: This piece was first published in 1951 and reprinted in Hayek’s Studies in
Philosophy, Politics, and Economics (1967, University of Chicago Press), pp. 195-200.
EJW thanks the estate of F. A. Hayek for granting permission to reprint the article. We
abstract, and we added the
composed the short biography that appears at the end, as well as the abstract
photographs of Edwin Cannan (source: Library of the London School of Economics and Political
Science), Ludwig von Mises (Ludwig von Mises Institute), Frank Knight (Warren J. Samuels
Portrait Collection at Duke University), and Walter Eucken (Walter Eucken Institut).
Otherwise, all that follows, including all footnotes, are Hayek’s, exactly as in the 1967 volume.
The Transmission of the Ideals of
Economic Freedom
1
F. A. Hayek
LINK TO ABSTRACT
At the end of the First World War the spiritual tradition of liberalism was all
but dead. True, it was still uppermost in the thoughts of many a leading figure of
public and business life, many of whom belonged to a generation which took liberal
thought for granted. Their public pronouncements sometimes led the general
public to believe that a return to a liberal economy was the ultimate goal desired
by the majority of leading men. But the intellectual forces then at work had begun
to point in quite a different direction. Anyone familiar, thirty years ago, with the
thought of the coming generation and especially with the views propounded to the
students in their universities, could foresee developments very different from those
still hoped for by some of the public figures and the press of the time. There was
1. First published in German as a tribute to L. v. Mises on his seventieth birthday, which it was known
he did not wish to see formally noticed, in the Schweizer Monatshefte, Vol. 31, No. 6, 1951, and later in an
English translation in The Owl, London, 1951. I should not have wished to reprint this somewhat hastily
written occasional piece, if with all its imperfections and errors of translation it had not already been
used as a historical source, so that it seems desirable to make a corrected version available.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
163
HAYEK
no longer, at that time, a living world of liberal thought which could have fired the
imagination of the young.
Nonetheless, the main body of liberal thought has been safeguarded through
that eclipse in the intellectual history of liberalism which lasted throughout the
fifteen or twenty years following the First World War; indeed, during that very
period the foundations were laid for a new development. This was due, almost
exclusively, to the activities of a handful of men about whom I wish to say
something here. No doubt, they were not the only ones striving to uphold the
liberal tradition. But it seems to me that these men, each working alone and
independently of the others, were the only ones who succeeded, by their teaching,
in creating the new traditions which more recently have again united in one
common stream. The circumstances surrounding the lives of the past generation
make it hardly surprising that it should have taken so long for the like-minded
efforts of an Englishman, an Austrian and an American to be recognized as such
and to be built into the common foundation for the following generation’s work.
But the new liberal school which does now exist and about which there will be more
to say, consciously builds upon the work of these men.
The oldest, and perhaps the least known outside
his own country, was the Englishman, Edwin Cannan,
who died nearly twenty years ago. The part he played is
little known beyond a rather narrow circle. The reason
for this may be that his main interests really lay
elsewhere and that he dealt with questions of
economic policy only in occasional writings; or it may
be, perhaps, that he was more interested in practical
details than in the basic philosophical questions. Many
of his economic essays which he published in two
volumes, The Economic Outlook (1912) and An
Economist’s Protest (1927), deserve, even now, renewed
Cannan
and wider attention, and translation into other
languages. Their simplicity, clarity and sound common sense make them models
for the treatment of economic problems, and even some that were written before
1914 are still astonishingly topical. Cannan’s greatest merit, however, was the
training, over many years, of a group of pupils at the London School of Economics:
it was they who later formed what probably became the most important centre of
the new liberalism—though, it is true, at a time when such a development had
already been got under way by the work of the Austrian economist of whom we
shall presently speak. But first let us say a little more about Cannan’s pupils. The
oldest is the well-known financial expert, Sir Theodore Gregory. For many years,
when holding a chair at the London School of Economics, he too wielded great
164
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TRANSMISSION OF THE IDEALS
influence on academic youth; but he gave up teaching a good many years ago.
It was Lionel Robbins, who now has held Cannan’s chair for twenty-two years,
who became the real nucleus of a group of younger economists all very nearly
the same age, which emerged at the London School of Economics during the
’thirties. Owing to a rare combination of literary talent and a gift for organizing his
material, his writings have found a very wide circulation. Robbins’ colleague, Sir
Arnold Plant, has been teaching at the School nearly as long. He, even more than
Cannan himself, is wont to hide away his most important contributions in littleknown occasional publications, and all his friends have long been looking forward
eagerly to a book about the foundations and significance of private property. If
he ever publishes it, it should become one of the most important contributions to
the theory of modern liberalism. We cannot here list all Cannan’s pupils who have
contributed to the discussion of our problems; just to give an impression of the
scope of his influence, let us add the names of F.C. Benham, W.H. Hutt and F.W.
Paish—even though the latter was not Cannan’s student, he belongs to the same
circle.
It could be said with some justification that
Cannan really prepared the ground, in England, for
the reception of the ideas of a much younger Austrian
who has been working since the early ’twenties on the
reconstruction of a solid edifice of liberal thought in a
more determined, systematic and successful way than
anyone else. This is Ludwig von Mises who worked
first in Vienna, then in Geneva, and who is still very
actively at work now in New York. Even before the
First World War Mises had become known for his
work on monetary theory. Immediately after the war,
his prophetic book Nation, Staat und Wirtschaft (1919)
Mises
initiated a development which reached its first peak as
early as 1922 in Die Gemeinwirtschaft,2 a comprehensive critique of socialism—and at
that time, that meant a critique of all the ideologies of any serious consequence in
the literature of economic policy.
There is no space here to give the long list of important writings which
intervened between this and Mises’s second main work which appeared in 1941
in Geneva. This was written in German and was originally called Nationalökonomie;
its revised American edition, Human Action, has achieved almost unique success
for a theoretical treatise of such size. Mises’s work as a whole covers far more
than economics in the narrower sense. His penetrating studies of the philosophical
2. Translated into English by Jacques Kahane, under the title Socialism, London, Jonathan Cape, 1936.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
165
HAYEK
foundations of the social sciences and his remarkable historical knowledge place
his work much closer to that of the great eighteenth-century moral philosophers
than to the writings of contemporary economists. Mises was strongly attacked from
the very beginning because of his relentlessly uncompromising attitude; he made
enemies and, above all, did not find academic recognition until late. Yet his work
has wielded an influence which is the more lasting and the more extensive for all its
slow beginnings. Even some of Mises’s own pupils were often inclined to consider
as ‘exaggerated’ that unfaltering tenacity with which he pursued his reasoning to
its utmost conclusions; but the apparent pessimism which he habitually displayed
in his judgment of the consequences of the economic policies of his time has
proved right over and over again, and eventually an ever-widening circle came to
appreciate the fundamental importance of his writings which ran counter to the
main stream of contemporary thought in nearly every respect. Even when still in
Vienna, Mises did not lack close disciples most of who are now in the United States,
like Mises himself; they include Gottfried Haberler (Harvard University), Fritz
Machlup (Johns Hopkins University), and the present writer. But Mises’s influence
now reaches beyond the personal sphere to a far greater extent than does that of
the other two main personalities with whom we are here concerned. He alone of
them has given us a comprehensive treatment ranging over the whole economic
and social field. We may or may not agree with him on details, but there is hardly
an important question in these fields about which his readers would fail to find real
instruction and stimulation.
Mises’ influence became important not only for
the London group, but equally so for the third, the
Chicago, group. This group owes its origins to
Professor Frank H. Knight of the University of
Chicago, who is Mises’s junior by a few years. Like
Mises, Knight owes his original reputation to a
theoretical monograph; notwithstanding an early lack
of recognition, the latter’s Risk, Uncertainty and Profit
(1921) eventually became, and for many years
continued to be, one of the most influential textbooks
on economic theory, although it had not originally
been designed as such. Knight has since written a great
Knight
deal on questions of economic policy and social
philosophy—mostly in articles the majority of which have since been published in
book form. The best-known, and perhaps also the most characteristic, volume is
The Ethics of Competition and Other Essays (1935). Knight’s personal influence,
through his teaching, exceeds even the influence of his writings. It is hardly an
exaggeration to state that nearly all the younger American economists who really
166
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TRANSMISSION OF THE IDEALS
understand and advocate a competitive economic system have at one time been
Knight’s students. From the point of view which interests us here the most
important of these was Henry C. Simons, whose untimely and early death we
mourn. In the ’thirties his pamphlet, A Positive Program for Laissez Faire, offered a
new and common basis for the aspirations of America’s young liberals. Hopes for
a systematic and comprehensive work from Simons were disappointed; instead, he
left a collection of essays which appeared in 1948 under the title Economic Policy for a
Free Society. This book became very influential owing to its wealth of ideas and to the
courage with which Simons discussed such delicate problems as trade unionism.
Today, the nucleus of a group of like-minded economists—no longer confined
to Chicago—is formed by Simons’ closest friend, Aaron Director, and two of the
best-known younger American theoreticians, George Stigler and Milton Friedman.
Director has edited Simons’ papers and carried on his work.
Alas, good manners make it impossible to claim a great nation’s head of State
for any particular economic school;3 I should, otherwise, name a fourth scientist
whose influence in his own country is of comparable consequence. Instead, I shall
complete the picture by turning at once to the last group which interests us here.4
It is a German group, and differs from the others in that its origin cannot be traced
back directly to any great figure of the preceding generation. It came into being
through the association of a number of younger men whose common interest in a
liberal economic system brought them together during the years preceding Hitler’s
seizure of power. There can be no doubt that this group too received decisive
stimulus from Mises’ writings. This group had not yet made its mark in economic
literature by 1933, and at that time some of its members had to leave Germany.
3. The reference is, of course, to the late Luigi Einaudi, at the time when this article appeared President of
the Italian Republic.
4. In the original version of this sketch I unpardonably omitted to mention a promising beginning of this
liberal renaissance which, though cut short by the outbreak of war in 1939, provided many of the personal
contacts which after the war were to form the basis of a renewed effort on an international scale. In 1937
Walter Lippmann had delighted and encouraged all liberals by the publication of his brilliant restatement
of the fundamental ideals of classic liberalism in his book The Good Society. Recognizing the importance of
this work as a possible rallying point of dispersed efforts, Professor Louis Rougier of the University of
Paris then called a symposium at which at the end of August 1938 about twenty-five students of public
affairs from several European countries and the United States met at Paris to discuss the principles stated
by Lippmann. They included Louis Baudin, Walter Lippmann, Ludwig von Mises, Michael Polanyi, Lionel
Robbins, Wilhelm Röpke, Alexander Rüstow, Marcel van Zeeland and the present author. The meeting
approved the proposal for the creation of a Centre International des Etudes pour la Rénovation du
Libéralisme—but when its report appeared in print (Colloque Walter Lippmann, Paris, 1939), only a few
weeks were left before the outbreak of the Second World War and the consequent suspension of all efforts
of this kind.
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
167
HAYEK
There remained, however, one of the group’s oldest
members, Walter Eucken, who was then as yet
relatively little known. Today we realize that his
sudden death a little over a year ago robbed the liberal
revival of one of its really great men. He had matured
slowly, had long refrained from publication and had
mainly devoted himself to teaching and to practical
problems. It was not until after Germany’s collapse
that it became apparent how fruitful and beneficial his
quiet activities had been during the National Socialist
period; for only then was the circle of his friends and
students in Germany revealed as the most important
Eucken
bulwark of rational economic thinking. That was also
the time when Eucken’s first major work began to spread its influence and when he
undertook the exposition of his whole economic thought in several other works.
The future will show how much of this remains to be recovered from the papers he
left at his death. The annual Ordo which he founded continues to be the most
important publication of the entire movement.
The second leading fixture of this German group, Wilhelm Röpke, had been
in close contact with Eucken from the beginning. By 1933, Röpke had made such
a mark in public life that his stay in Hitler’s Germany immediately became
impossible. He went to Istanbul first, and has now been in Switzerland for many
years. He is the most active and the most prolific writer of the whole group and has
become known to a wide public.
If the existence of a neo-liberal movement is known far beyond the narrow
circles of experts, the credit belongs mainly to Röpke, at least so far as the Germanspeaking public is concerned.
It has been said above that all these groups which came into being in the
course of the last quarter of a century did not really get to know each other until
after the Second World War. We then witnessed a lively exchange of ideas. Today,
it has almost become a matter of history to speak of separate national groups. For
that very reason, this is perhaps the right moment to give a brief outline of this
development. Gone is the day when the few remaining liberals each went his own
way in solitude and derision; gone the day when they found no response among
the young. On the contrary, they bear a heavy responsibility now, because the new
generation demands to be told of liberalism’s answers to the great problems of our
time. An integrated structure of liberal thought is required and its application to the
problems of different countries needs to be worked out. This will only be possible
by a meeting of minds within a large group. There remain serious difficulties, in
many countries, with regard to the dissemination of the available literature, and the
168
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
TRANSMISSION OF THE IDEALS
lack of translations of some of the most important works still stands in the way
of a more rapid propagation of these ideas. But there is, today, personal contact
between most of their supporters. Twice already Switzerland has been host to
the informal, yet cohesive group which met there for the common study of its
problems and whose name derives from a Swiss place-name. Another meeting took
place in Holland in 1950, and a fourth conference in France in 1951.
The period which we have discussed in this paper can, then, be regarded as
closed. Thirty years ago liberalism may still have had some influence among public
men, but it had well-nigh disappeared as a spiritual movement. Today its practical
influence may be scant, but its problems have once more become a living body of
thought. We may feel justified in looking forward with renewed faith to the future
of liberalism.
About the Author
Friedrich A. Hayek (1899-1992) was a social philosopher
born and raised in Austria but who spent most of his career in
Britain, the United States, and Germany. Originally a soft
socialist, he converted to liberalism during his twenties, being
influenced particularly by Ludwig von Mises. Hayek led the
creation of the Mont Pelerin Society, early meetings of which
are referred to in the present text. In 1974, Hayek was a corecipient of the Riksbank Prize in Economic Sciences in
Memory of Alfred Nobel.
Go to Archive of Character Issues section
Go to May 2012 issue
Discuss this article at Journaltalk:
http://journaltalk.net/articles/5763
VOLUME 9, NUMBER 2, MAY 2012
169