Classical Association of Canada
Review: [untitled]
Author(s): Joseph M. Bryant
Source: Phoenix, Vol. 46, No. 3 (Autumn, 1992), pp. 276-279
Published by: Classical Association of Canada
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1088699 .
Accessed: 13/06/2011 03:16
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cac. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact
[email protected].
Classical Association of Canada is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Phoenix.
http://www.jstor.org
276
PHOENIX
(though this is strictly not a conjecture), 16.16 praecutit, the transposition
of 16.19 f. to after 14, 17.27 Diam, and 25.11 iam. Unfortunately the format
precluded a full apparatus criticus and Goold has contented himself with
simply noting divergences from Barber's OCT; only the lack of complete
textual information and the insistence upon an unobelized text prevent welcoming this warmly as the current standard edition. There are few slips,
but at 3.22.38 Baehrens' fera has sneaked in unannounced, and on 317 a
typographical error has restored a corruption of the archetype and turned
the river Asopus back into the "Aesopus."
Some will dismiss Goold's Propertius as "Bentleyolatry" or "Housmanolatry" and "Anglo-Saxon hypercriticism"; but how is it possible to be excessively critical in a text so ravaged by error that even today's conservative
editions acknowledge some 600 or more corruptions? Others will ridicule
him for emending away Propertius' alleged unique literary qualities; in fact
his Propertius displays far more of what antiquity admired in him than Barber's or Fedeli's does (much less Phillimore's or Rothstein's), and to plead
that ancient literary criticism was too primitive to realize that Propertius
was actually writing like Ezra Pound is as arrogant as it is nonsensical.
We are still far, especially in the tormented Book 2, from the poet's ipsissima uerba, but Goold's Propertius is simply the best text seen since the
elegies emerged from the obscurity of the Middle Ages; technical reasons
may prevent it serving as a standard edition, but it certainly deserves to
be regarded as the current textus receptus and as the starting point for all
future discussion of the text.
MEMORIAL
UNIVERSITY
OF NEWFOUNDLAND JAMESL. BUTRICA
DEMYSTIFYINGMENTALITIES.By G. E. R. LLOYD.Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. 1990. Pp. viii, 174.
OVER THE COURSE OF THE PAST THREE DECADES, a steady and voluminous outpouring of articles and books by one scholar in particular has
done much to deepen our understanding of a rather elusive subject. The
"Greek Miracle," the birth of Reason, the transition from Mythos to Logos-whatever one's stylistic preference, it is G. E. R. Lloyd's work which,
cumulatively, provides the most varied and nuanced approach to its many
facets. Whether investigating the social origins of Greek rationality and its
basic modalities of expression, or its internal limits and major ideological
lacunae and predilections, Lloyd's research has been marked by a rare but
requisite balance between the analytical and the empirical. The 'Tacts,"
we now readily concede, do not speak for themselves: they must be repeatedly interrogated, reconceptualized from fresh and varied perspectives. To
that end Lloyd has adopted a strategy of active engagement with the so-
BOOK REVIEWS/COMPTESRENDUS
277
cial sciences, drawing upon the categories of anthropology and sociologythough not uncritically-to educe new insights from materials either long
overworked or from sources hitherto neglected.
In Demystifying Mentalities Lloyd's effort is more explicitly confrontational: the premise that times and peoples are marked by distinctive and enduring affective-cognitive structures, i.e., mentalites, is to be tested against
what is perhaps the most significant case of all, the dynamic confluence of
myth, magic, and science that informed the mental universe of the ancient
Hellenes. Following a brief introduction, Lloyd offers four self-contained essays on various aspects of the central problematic: the halting and uneven
crystallization of "proto-scientific" modes of discourse within Greek society. The first three chapters are given over to the many-sided confrontation between traditional thought-patterns and the new forms of rationalism
developed by the pre-Socratic physikoi, the Sophists, Plato and Aristotle,
and the Hippocratics. Fundamental to this encounter-and to the Greek
"way of science" more generally-is the pronounced concern exhibited by
the new rationalists with second-order or foundation issues, i.e., questions
of ontology, epistemology, and a methodological self-awareness regarding
matters of proof and argumentation. For Lloyd this development is to be
explained not by anything so grand and vague as a collective mental mutation, a shift in mentalite, but rather by the concrete social imperatives
of polemical self-legitimation, as those involved in the articulation of new
modes of reasoning sought to "remove the ground," as it were, of their traditionalist rivals in the purveyance of knowledge. This pattern of intellectual competition, Lloyd suggests, was itself derivative, a by-product of the
unique social organization of the Greek Polis. For in addition to allowing
the structural "space" for such rivalry-neither kings, scribes, nor priests
held institutional monopolies in the domains of truth and wisdom-the Polis imparted to its citizenry considerable experience in the formulation of
arguments and the weighing of evidence as part of the legal and political
responsibilities of self-governance. These parallels and connections receive
extended treatment in the fourth chapter, where Lloyd attempts to specify
the social bases of Greek rationalism by way of comparison with ancient
China, juxtaposing the key political and cultural developments in the two
civilizations in a most revealing manner.
Since several of these subjects are covered in greater detail in Lloyd's
earlier works, most notably The Revolutions of Wisdom (1987), estimation
of this particular offering will probably turn on the perceived adequacy of
Lloyd's "demystification" of the mentalities perspective. Proponents will
no doubt find it odd that Lloyd directs most of his fire at the rather dated
formulations of Levy-Bruhl; but even so, the more basic charge that "mentalites" lack analytical precision is widely accepted in social science circles.
Lloyd's call to abandon airy speculation about collective mental states in
278
PHOENIX
favour of concrete examination of linguistic categories and styles of reasoning is surely sound, but this is more a strategy for research than a theoretical solution to our problems. After all, new modes of discourse are not,
presumably, self-generating but embody and are expressions of underlying
social psychologies (mentalites, if you will), which are thereby framed and
stabilized within emerging linguistic-cognitive patterns. Indeed, much of
the best work in the histoire des mentalites has focused on the enveloping, constraining function of languages and worldviews, which, once fashioned, establish "limits of the thinkable" and restrict the range of affective
response. As a descriptive category, the notion of relatively enduring and
distinctive mentalities (or social psychologies) is not without some validity,
as anyone comparing the artistic and philosophical offerings of the ancient
Chinese and Greeks, for example, will readily concede (Lloyd himself reaffirms the prominence of "harmony" and "tradition" in the one, "agonistic striving" and "innovation" in the other). Cultural forms, in short, are
structured, and we are thus once again obligated to confront all the old
polarized debates regarding the genesis and role of ideas of history and of
their relationships to wider patterns of social organization.
The chief limitation of the mentalities approach-and of the whole Durkheimian complex of which it is a part-lies in its reductionist tendencies:
analogues and homologies are discerned or posited between social structures and systems of thought, with the latter "explained" as functional
emanations of the former. Much of this work is undoubtedly informative
and at times brilliantly suggestive, but typically lacking is any clear account of process or mediation and specified forms of human agency. Lloyd
as critic is aware of these failings, but one senses that a residual Durkheimianism still informs his own approach on occasion, most notably in
his effort to claim a direct causal connection between Greek democracy
and the emergence of scientific rationalism. Lloyd refines previous discussions by carefully distinguishing between actual democratic practice and
its ideology ("a propaganda of openness," with an emphasis on argument
over authority), but one is still left with the problem of how this ideology
triggered, stimulated, or informed the speculations of the physikoi or the
Hippocratics. The democracy-science thesis would seem to be claiming too
much, for skill in argumentation and the custom of public debate-to say
nothing of agonal striving-figure prominently in Greek social life virtually
from the beginning, in the Homeric epics. Lloyd's research has been particularly valuable in identifying the discursive and linguistic parallels between the legal-political spheres and philosophical discussion (e.g., in lexical
mutualisms such as marturia, tekmeria, elenchos, and logon didonai), but
this reflects Greek political experience more generally, i.e., the Polis, rather
than democracy per se. One might accordingly suggest that critical ratio-
BOOK REVIEWS/COMPTESRENDUS
279
nalism and the ideology of democracy constitute two separate and distinct
cultural derivatives of the Polis-form of social organization, mutually reinforcing at certain points, but each developing according to its own internal
dynamic.
It is of course a basic axiom of sociology that some form of "existential congruence" obtains between ideas and institutions, but it is equally
obvious that the lines of causality can run in either direction, with ideas
serving as catalysts for change and as conserving ideologies. Is there, then,
an alternative model or framework that avoids the pitfalls of reductionism
without lapsing into idealist excesses? If one is seeking an integrated, comprehensive theory, the answer must be negative; the unending controversies
regarding the Marxist concept of ideology and Karl Mannheim's sociology
of knowledge attest to that. One might, however, find a promising lead in
the work of Max Weber, whose effort to lay bare the social psychologies of
the world religions pays due regard to the differences between the creation
and subsequent spread of ideas, chiefly by concentrating on the dynamic between the charismatics and virtuosi who fashion and expound new religious
images and the mass converts or "carriers"who readjust the new faith in
accordance with their social experiences and needs. There is value too in
the symbolic interactionist framework of George Herbert Mead, which takes
us beyond the standard formulations-that ideas "reflect," "mirror,"or are
"determined"by underlying social structures-by showing how "society" is
intrinsic to the development of "mind" through the internalization of the
conversation of gesture, i.e., language, a system of symbols socially created
and sustained. In the sociologies of Weber and Mead, in other words, the
emphasis is on process rather than static structural correlations, and that
is surely the direction required in the study of highly mutable phenomena
such as cultural forms and social psychologies.
If many of the interpretations and explanations in the sociological study
of culture-including Lloyd's own-appear somewhat intuitive and provisional, this is no doubt due to the enigmatic nature of the subject matter
itself. For just as the transformation of neural stimuli into cognitive responses constitutes one of the great mysteries for physiologists and biologists, so it can be said that delineating the multiform relations between
"social practice" and "consciousness" poses the greatest challenge for the
social sciences. Given that situation, co-workers from other disciplines are
especially welcome; and when, as is the case here, they combine a thorough
mastery of the source materials with a high level of analytical sophistication, the results should prove not only enlightening but also provocative.
Demystifying Mentalities qualifies as an important read in both respects.
UNIVERSITY OF NEW BRUNSWICK
JOSEPH M. BRYANT