A PASSIONATE BUDDHIST LIFE
jore_510
99..121
Emily McRae
ABSTRACT
This paper addresses the ways that we can understand and transform our
strong emotions and how this project contributes to moral and spiritual
development. To this end, I choose to think with two Tibetan Buddhist
thinkers, both of whom take up the question of how passionate emotions can
fit into spiritual and moral life: the famous, playful yogin Shabkar Tsodruk
Rangdrol (1781–1851) and the wandering, charismatic master Patrul Rinpoche (1808–1887). Shabkar’s The Autobiography of Shabkar provides excellent examples of using one’s own passionate emotions to connect to others
and gain insight into the world. Patrul Rinpoche’s The Words of My Perfect
Teacher (kun bzang bla ma’i zhal lung) focuses on passionate empathy with
the emotions of others. Drawing on these texts, I present a (distinctly
Buddhist) conception of a passionate life and argue that passionate emotional experience is a central part of moral and spiritual development more
broadly construed.
KEY WORDS:
Buddhism, emotions, ethics, passion, Patrul Rinpoche, Zhabkar
IN GEORGE ELIOT’S LAST NOVEL, Daniel Deronda, the title character
offers advice to his desperate friend Gwendolen, who suffers from debilitating moral guilt and a growing recognition of the depth of her own
selfishness. Deronda encourages her to use her suffering to connect with
others and to broaden her interests beyond the vicissitudes of her own life.
He tells her, “It is the curse of your life—forgive me—of so many lives,
that all passion is spent in that narrow round, for want of ideas and
sympathies to make a larger home for it” (Eliot 1876, 78).
This paper addresses the ways that we can “make a larger home” for
our passions and how this project contributes to moral and spiritual
development. To this end, I choose to think with two Tibetan Buddhist
thinkers, both of whom take up the question of how passionate emotions
can fit into spiritual and moral life: the famous, playful yogin Shabkar
Tsodruk Rangdrol (1781–1851) and the wandering, charismatic master
Patrul Rinpoche (1808–1887). Shabkar’s The Autobiography of Shabkar
provides excellent examples of using one’s own passionate emotions to
connect to others and gain insight into the world. Patrul Rinpoche’s The
Words of My Perfect Teacher (kun bzang la ma’i zhal lung) focuses on
Emily McRae is Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oklahoma. She
specializes in ethics, feminism, and Tibetan Buddhist philosophy. Emily McRae, Department
of Philosophy, University of Oklahoma, 555 Constitution Ave., Rm. 208, Norman, OK 73072,
[email protected]
JRE 40.1:99–121. © 2012 Journal of Religious Ethics, Inc.
100
Journal of Religious Ethics
passionate empathy with the emotions of others.1 Drawing on these texts,
I present a (distinctly Buddhist) conception of a passionate life and argue
that passionate emotional experience is a central part of moral and
spiritual development more broadly construed.
Both Shabkar and Patrul Rinpoche describe moral and spiritual life in
surprisingly passionate terms. It is surprising because it is often assumed
that Buddhism promotes the ideals of dispassion and detachment. But
Patrul Rinpoche’s and Shabkar’s understandings of emotional life runs
counter to this stereotype: passionate emotional experience is not in itself
a cause for concern, and in fact is praiseworthy when it is directed in the
right ways toward the right objects.
The assumption that Buddhism values dispassion as the central virtue
is apparent in Joel Marks’s defense of dispassion as an ethical ideal. All
feelings, he argues, have affect, belief and desire components but he
reserves the words “emotion” and “passion” for those feelings that have
strong desire components. Dispassion, therefore, is the absence of passion
(and its strong desires) rather than the absence of all affect whatsoever.
Thus he can avoid the troublesome conclusion that the dispassionate life
is one that is completely absent of all desire. Marks worries that such an
ideal would be absurd, since without any desire whatsoever, human
beings would have no basis for feeling or action. For this reason he thinks
that the typical Buddhist admonitions against desire, from which he
draws heavily, must be interpreted as being directed against strong desire.
This is reflected in his Buddhist-inspired argument for the dispassionate
ideal: “Suffering is bad. The singular cause of suffering is strong desire.
Therefore, strong desire (that is passion or emotion) is bad” (Marks 1994,
143).
In the above argument, Marks presumably has in mind the Second
Noble Truth which states that there is a cause or origin of suffering. That
cause is the attitude of clinging, grasping or fixation, often translated
simply as “desire” of “craving.”2 As Marks himself notes, English translations of Buddhist texts rarely specify that strong desire (as opposed to
simply desire) is the cause of suffering:
But is strong desire intended in the Buddhist usage? I think the answer
must be Yes, for in this way Buddhist ethics is saved from absurdity. A total
1
The Words of My Perfect Teacher (kun bzang bla ma’i zhal lung) is a recording of Jigme
Gyalwai Nyugu’s (Patrul’s “perfect teacher”) commentary on a classic revealed text entitled
The Heart-Essence of Vast Expanse (klong chen snying thig). I use the Wylie system of
transliteration throughout.
2
For example, “If this sticky, uncouth craving overcomes you in the world, your sorrows
grow like wild grass after rain. If, in the world, you overcome this uncouth craving, hard to
escape, sorrows roll off you, like water beads off a lotus” (Dhammapada 335-36); see also
Samyutta Nikaya 27.8.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
101
condemnation of desire would leave no basis for feeling and action, but these
are necessary for life. Furthermore, it does seem plausible that suffering
would result from, or be a form of, intensity of feeling and not just any
degree of feeling [Marks 1994, 143].
Marks, therefore, makes two claims: (1) Buddhist ethics condemns (or
should condemn) strong or intense feelings and that (2) such condemnation is ethically appropriate.
I disagree with both claims. Given the diversity and dynamism of
Buddhist philosophies and practices, it cannot be assumed that the
condemnation of strong feelings is a basic or universal Buddhist position.
As I will show, Patrul Rinpoche in no way suggests that all intense
feelings should be avoided; on the contrary, he encourages cultivating
them in some contexts. Furthermore, not only is dispassion (at least as
Marks defines it) not a universal Buddhist ideal, it should not be an
ethical ideal in general. By giving up all passionate emotional experience
we lose important moral insights that can transform our understanding of
ourselves, others, relationships, and the world.
I begin with a brief discussion of the passionate life as it is often
conceived of in Western philosophy and literature, particularly in the
works of Friedrich Nietzsche and, more recently, Robert Solomon (sec. 1).
I juxtapose this life to what I claim is an example of a passionate Buddhist
life, which includes understanding one’s own passionate experiences (sec.
2) and the empathizing passionately with at least some of the emotions of
others (sec. 3). Although empathy is central to many conceptions of moral
life, such as Adam Smith’s, I argue that Patrul Rinpoche’s approach is
unique with regard to the extent, intensity and passion of our empathic
experience (sec. 4). Nevertheless, the passionate life that Patrul Rinpoche
and Shabkar describe is consistent with other core features of Buddhist
teachings that they accept, such as the virtue of equanimity, the eradication of craving and aversion, and the general program to be liberated
from suffering (sec. 5). I conclude by arguing that passionate emotional
experiences contribute to moral and spiritual development in three main
ways: by contributing to psychological health and integrity, by providing
motivation for altruistic action and by offering deep insight into ourselves,
others and our relationships (sec. 6).
1. What Is a Passionate Life?
My candle burns at both ends.
It will not last the night.
But, ah, my foes and, Oh, my friends,
it gives a lovely light.
—Edna St. Vincent Millay (Millay 1922, 9)
Robert Solomon describes the passionate life as “a life defined by
emotions, by impassioned engagement and belief, by one or more quests,
102
Journal of Religious Ethics
grand projects, embracing affections . . . vaulting ambitions and essentially insatiable goals” (Solomon 2007, 86). It is often associated with
artistic sensibility and places a high value on beauty, originality and
creative expression. One who lives such a life is not afraid to strive to
achieve her grand goals, even if her attempts are ultimately futile, and
does not shy away from feeling the misery of failure or the ecstatic joy of
success. For the passionate person, these are signs of her power; they
show that she is really living the fullest life she can.3
The passionate life is often defined in opposition to the dispassionate or
tranquil life. Idealized by the Stoics (and, so the usual story goes, by
Buddhists), the dispassionate life values tranquility and peace of mind.
The passionate life, on the other hand, values energy, enthusiasm and, as
Solomon has noted, even frenzy (Solomon 1999, 18). Both the passionate
life and the life of tranquility are responses to the vicissitudes of human
life and elusiveness of long-lasting and reliable pleasure. Both reject the
idea that chasing short-lived pleasurable feelings is the final end of life,
which differentiates both lives from a hedonistic life. A defender of a life
of dispassion solves the problem of the inherent suffering of human life by
valuing peace of mind as the final end, which is attained by minimizing
and eventually eradicating violent emotional ups and downs. By contrast,
the passionate person plunges freely and gladly into the vicissitudes of
everyday life. The passionate person, as Nietzsche has famously put it,
says “Yes!” to life, with all its suffering, thus revaluing suffering itself.4
The passionate life is also usually understood as distinct from the
ordinary moral life (the life of being a good person). This may be in part
because one of the most famous advocates of a passionate life in Western
philosophy, Nietzsche, used this idea as part of his overall critique of
morality. Solomon, who notes that the passionate life need not be immoral
or even amoral, nevertheless locates an important difference between the
two kinds of lives: the passionate life does not share the skepticism of
violent emotions that is so pervasive in conceptions of the good life.5 Even
the moral sentiment theorists, such as David Hume and Adam Smith, who
were perhaps the greatest (Western) proponents of emotions in moral life,
tend to defend the so-called calm, gentle emotions, particularly sympathy.6
3
This kind of life is more commonly explored in novels, poems and autobiographies than
in philosophical texts (with the notable exceptions of Nietzsche and Kierkegaard). Aristotle,
for instance, does not include this life in his list of possible conceptions of the good human
life (NE I.5). He includes the life of pleasure, the life of the moneymaker, the life of politics,
the life of virtue and the life of contemplation.
4
See Nietzsche 1982, 101–2, 139, 269.
5
See Solomon 2003; and Solomon 1999, 17–35.
6
Hume writes, “Morality, therefore, is more properly felt than judg’d of: tho’ this feeling
or sentiments is commonly so soft and gentle, that we are apt to confound it with an idea”
(1951, 470). Also see Smith 1948, 73–82.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
103
But the passionate life is not one that only appreciates the relatively calm
or manageable emotions, but rather it honors strong and even violent
emotions. In his discussion of Nietzsche’s “will to power,” which Solomon
understands as a “general vision of the passionate life,” he claims that
Nietzsche’s passionate life is
directed to self-mastery and self-expression. It embraces such particular
passions as pride. . . . It embodies anger and its aggressive kin. . . . It
includes joy, but mainly that energetic joy that comes with victory and
strength, not the quiet and quietist “bliss” praised by Christians and
Buddhists [Solomon 2003, 88].
As the above quotation suggests, a certain fascination with the self and
self-expression—which is not mere “self-interest”—looms large in the
passionate life, for both Nietzsche and Solomon. The joy experienced in
the passionate life, which Solomon contrasts to the bliss of the Christian
and Buddhist traditions, comes with a person’s own triumphs and successes, especially with regard to her self-mastery and creative expression;
the misery or depression a passionate person feels concerns her failures in
these realms. The passionate person is driven to find creative expression
for her own experiences that are original and, in some sense, beautiful.
Unlike Nietzsche who offers this life as an empowering and life-enhancing
alternative to the “moral” life, Solomon prefers to expand the concept of
virtue to incorporate at least some passionate experiences.7
Finally, although it contains an (at times) empowering intensity and
depth of feeling, the passionate life is not a life of invulnerability. The
passionate person, by definition, is vulnerable to unbearable misery as well
as overwhelming joy. Unlike the ideal of dispassion, which often emphasizes
attaining a fearless state in which nothing can harm us, the passionate
person can be deeply hurt.8 But the passionate person can (usually) recover
because she also recognizes the possibility of great joy and has the fullness
of spirit to forgive and, perhaps more importantly, forget.9
2. Dealing with Difficult Passions: The Story of Shabkar
Take the present suffering as a painful letting in of light
—George Eliot (Eliot 1876, 79)
7
Solomon 1999, 17–35. Solomon notes that not all passions can be virtues and that
distinctions must be made between, for instance, passionate love and obsession.
8
Epictetus offers a vision of this kind of fearless state. In the opening paragraph of his
Handbook, he promises that, if we follow his Stoic program of living in accordance with
Nature, “no one will ever coerce you, no one will hinder you, you will blame no one, you will
not accuse anyone, you will not do a single thing unwillingly, you will have no enemies, and
no one will harm you, because you will not be harmed at all” (1983, 11).
9
Nietzsche argues that forgetting is an active and healthy process (1989, 56–62).
104
Journal of Religious Ethics
It has been widely assumed, by both critics and defenders of Buddhist
thought, that a good Buddhist life is a quiet, dispassionate one.10
Nietzsche famously criticized Buddhism (and other ascetic traditions) for
what he assumed to be its dispassion, deprivation, and “desire for nothingness” (1989, 32). Solomon claims that Buddhist thinkers (along with a
host of other philosophers including Socrates, Spinoza, Schopenhauer, and
Confucius) “have all been more or less staunch in their insistence that
strong, violent emotion—the sort that is said to “sweep us away”—is at
best untoward and often disastrous, even fatal” (Solomon 1999, 18). As we
have seen, in his defense of the virtue of dispassion, Joel Marks assumes
that Buddhism advocates a dispassionate life, which, on his view, is not
affectless but lacks of strong, intense emotions.11
What Nietzsche, Solomon, and Marks have in common is the assumption that dispassion is the central Buddhist virtue. This assumption is
supported by some key features of Buddhist thought and practice: the
focus on renunciation, the valorization of the hermit-saint meditating
alone in a cave, the emphasis on equanimity and the general project to be
liberated from suffering. I will argue, however, that a passionate Buddhist
life is not a contradiction in terms. In fact, we can see examples of such
lives in the spiritual autobiographies of some Tibetan Buddhist masters as
well as in the writings of Patrul Rinpoche.
One such example is the life of the Tibetan yogin Shabkar (1781–1851).
In many ways, Shabkar fits the stereotype of the Buddhist ascetic.
According to his autobiography, which is largely a collection of songs that
he composed, Shabkar spent most of his life wandering and meditating in
caves and, as his fame and popularity grew, he retreated to increasingly
secluded locations. To the dismay of his mother, he refused to marry and
have children, claiming that marriage would tighten a “noose of samsara”
around his neck. Shabkar left home as a young man to study meditation
with a famous master, a plan that was only approved by his mother once
he told her, falsely, that he would return in one year. (He did not return
until after her death.) When his mother wrote letters begging him to come
home, he urged her not to be upset and coolly pointed out that “there
might be many children who benefit their parents in this life with food,
clothes, and wealth. Yet how many parents have children staying in the
mountains, practicing the holy Dharma for the benefit of their parents’
future lives?” (Shabkar 1994, 142).
Nevertheless, Shabkar’s life is not a model of emotional disengagement.
On the contrary, he often expresses intense emotion. When his mother
died, he deeply regretted not making a greater effort to see her. (Shabkar
10
See Marks 1994; Solomon 2003; and Nietzsche GM, I.6. For discussions of the more
passionate side of Buddhist literature, see Heim 2003, 531–54.
11
See Marks 1995, 141.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
105
was on his way home when he heard that she died.) We learn that the
reason he did not visit his mother sooner was not because of emotional
detachment but rather due to a mistaken perception, one that may be
typical of children with regard to their parents. He writes, “I still thought
of my mother as being young, and thought that, even if I did not see her
for a few years, she wouldn’t die” (Shabkar 1994, 201). After his mother’s
death he describes himself as “disconsolate” and “overwhelmed” by the
memory of his mother, which stung “like a knife in [his] heart.” His
sadness, he tells us, was “fathomless” (Shabkar 1994, 201).
There is nothing in his autobiography to suggest that Shabkar’s outpouring of emotion was considered wrong, inappropriate or destructive. In
fact, in the song he sings about his mother’s death, he suggests that his
grief gave him insight into impermanence:
Again, overwhelmed by the memory of my mother, I sang this song
about her, weeping, in utter dismay:
Mother
Mother
Mother
Mother
who
who
who
who
first gave me life,
fed me and clothed me
allowed me to enter into the Dharma
now teaches me impermanence:
Having died, you have turned into a handful of bones
Your bones I have turned into tsa-tsas [ashes mixed with clay].
These tsa-tsas I have hidden in a scree.
Now even I can no longer see them.
In times to come, when I am wandering in distant places
I shall never see you again, Mother.
Not only will I never see you again, Mother,
I won’t even see the tsa-tsas of your bones.
Considering this, sorrow surges up from deep within me.
Now I do not need to do “meditations on impermanence”
My old mother, leaving me, gave me these teachings [Shabkar 1994, 203].
This vignette shows the complexity of evaluating passionate emotional
experiences and defining passionate living. On the one hand, Shabkar’s
ascetic and often solitary life hardly qualifies as an example of Solomon’s
(and Nietzsche’s) conception of a passionate life. Yet, the depth and
intensity of his emotional experience is not captured by the typical
understanding of a quiet, dispassionate life. Furthermore, Shabkar does
not treat his grief as a necessary evil, or even as an understandable
human reaction, but rather as a way of understanding deeper truths, in
this case the truth of impermanence. Although he feels his grief intensely
and is, in a sense, overwhelmed by it, he still is able to use it as an
opportunity for moral and spiritual growth. Shabkar’s story challenges the
idea that Buddhism forbids passionate emotional expression, even about
oneself and one’s own life; Shabkar has keen emotional responses to the
106
Journal of Religious Ethics
events in his own life. But these passionate experiences, such as grief,
anger, humiliation, envy, and exhilaration, are neither repressed nor
glorified but rather taken as an opportunity to connect with others and
learn about the nature of the world and human experience.
3. Understanding Passionate Responses to Others:
Patrul Rinpoche’s Meditation
Although difficult passionate experiences are experienced as an opportunity for insight and growth, they are not purposefully indulged or
cultivated. Passionate feelings of love, compassion and sympathetic joy, on
the other hand, are intentionally cultivated through relationships and
empathic imaginative contemplations. These emotions, which are generally
thought to be natural human emotions, are gradually developed to become
more intense, more reliable, more frequent and more passionate. Patrul
Rinpoche’s discussion of the Four Immeasurables—love (byampa), compassion (snying rje) sympathetic joy (dga’ ba), and equanimity (btang
snyom)—is notable for its advocacy of intense and passionate emotional
experiences. He describes cultivating an “intense” love, an “unbearable”
feeling of compassion, and a sympathetic joy that “knows no bounds.”
Patrul Rinpoche often characterizes the experiences of the compassion, love
and sympathetic joy as ma bzod pa, which literally means “intolerable” or
“un-endurable.”
Patrul Rinpoche uses passionate language to describe the four immeasurable qualities and intentionally invokes passionate emotions in his
meditations on these qualities. In describing sympathetic joy, he writes,
The image given for boundless sympathetic joy is that of a mother camel
finding her lost baby. Of all animals, camels are considered the most affectionate mothers. If a mother camel loses her baby her sorrow is correspondingly intense. But when she finds it again her joy knows no bounds. That is
the kind of sympathetic joy you should try to develop [Patrul 1994, 215].
To feel boundless joy for others’ success and happiness does not simply
mean feeling happy about the happiness of everyone. The “boundless”
here also refers to an inward boundlessness: for any particular person, we
are to feel joy that knows no bounds (that is, is boundless). His emphasis
on inner boundlessness, which refers to the strength and depth of feeling,
is what gives Patrul Rinpoche’s discussion of the Four Immeasurables its
passionate flavor. In his description of compassion, Patrul Rinpoche
evokes an image designed to activate this “inner” boundlessness:
The image given for meditating on compassion is that of a mother with no
arms, whose child is being swept away by a river. How unbearable the
anguish of such a mother would be. Her love for her child is so intense, but
as she cannot use her arms she cannot catch hold of him . . . Her heart
breaking, she runs along after him, weeping [Patrul 1994, 212–13].
A Passionate Buddhist Life
107
The meditation practices that Patrul Rinpoche recommends to cultivate
the Four Immeasurables are designed to activate these intense emotional
experiences. The depth and strength of feeling that Patrul Rinpoche’s
contemplations require are especially apparent in the following meditation on compassion:
Imagine a prisoner condemned to death by the ruler and being led to the
place of execution, or a sheep being caught and tied up by the butcher. When
you think of a condemned prisoner, instead of thinking of that suffering
person as someone else, imagine that it is you. Ask yourself what you would
do in that situation. What now? There is nowhere to run. Nowhere to hide.
No refuge and no one to protect you. You have no means of escape. You
cannot fly away. You have no strength, no army to defend you. Now, at this
very moment, all the perceptions of this life are about to cease. You will even
have to leave behind your own dear body that you have sustained with so
much care, and set out for the next life. What anguish! Train your mind by
taking the suffering of that condemned prisoner upon yourself [Patrul 1994,
201–2].
In another meditation for developing compassion, Patrul Rinpoche asks us
to imagine the pain and the panic of a sheep about to be slaughtered. He
even suggests covering one’s mouth with one’s hand in order to get a
fuller, more visceral experience of that pain and panic.12 For Patrul
Rinpoche, compassion and sympathy are not, contra Hume, calm emotions. They are passionate ones.
Patrul Rinpoche’s meditations on love and sympathetic joy, although
not as gut wrenching as the meditations on compassion, are also characterized by intense feeling. When cultivating sympathetic joy, we are
encouraged to “sincerely rejoice” in the successes of others, taking genuine
delight in their “achievements and favorable circumstances.” We “meditate from the depth of [our] heart” on how “truly glad we are that there
are such excellent people, so successful and fortunate” (Patrul 1994, 214).
When meditating on boundless love, you should continue until “you want
others to be happy just as intensely as you want to be happy yourself”
(Patrul 1994, 199).
As his choice of images and cultivation practices indicate, Patrul
Rinpoche is asking us to go to the limits of our emotional capacity—and
then go further. We develop “emotional muscle” to go deeper and deeper
with practice. In fact, his meditations, particularly on compassion, may
push us to (or beyond) our emotional limits. They leave little room for
typical defense mechanisms against emotional experience, such as distancing oneself, conceiving the situation in an abstract or general way, or
limiting oneself to feeling a “watered-down” or lukewarm version of the
12
In Tibet it was common to kill animals through suffocation.
108
Journal of Religious Ethics
emotion. On Patrul Rinpoche’s view, the emotional experiences of the Four
Immeasurables are anything but dispassionate. He is surely not recommending shying away from intense and difficult emotional experience but
rather is inviting us to engage more fully, more whole-heartedly, and to
keep doing it as an ethical-spiritual practice.
Patrul Rinpoche’s meditations encourage living a life that honors
passion in many of the ways Solomon and even Nietzsche have advocated.
It is an emotionally engaged life that not only values passionate emotions
when they arise but is in fact committed to cultivating them in certain
contexts. Contrary to the stereotype of Buddhist practice as an exercise in
emotional detachment, Patrul Rinpoche uses these meditations, at least in
part, to break habits of emotional distancing and indifference. In some
ways, he even includes the grand projects and vaulting ambitions that are
central to Solomon’s account. He is, after all, advocating the cultivation of
intense and genuine love, compassion and sympathetic joy to all sentient
beings without exception, which is just about as vaulting an ambition as
one could have.
The central difference between these two conceptions of passionate
living is that, for Patrul Rinpoche, a passionate life is a moral life
(although not the conventional life of “mores”).13 As we can see, there are
strict moral boundaries to his valuation of passion; passionate compassion
is praised, but not passionate anger or passionate envy. (In fact, Patrul
Rinpoche urges: “Uproot that evil mentality that finds it unbearable that
someone else should have such perfect plenty.”14) As Shabkar’s story
illustrates, this does not imply that the so-called afflictive emotions such
as envy and anger are repressed or denied. Rather, they are excellent
opportunities for moral and spiritual growth.15 Nevertheless, in general
afflictive emotions are not to be indulged by seeking their validation or
consciously re-triggering them. In other words, when afflictive emotions
arise we must skillfully redirect the power inherent in them for better
ends, but we do not intentionally cause them to arise or intentionally
maintain them. For Patrul Rinpoche, the passionate experiences that we
intentionally cultivate are more or less limited to love, compassion,
sympathetic joy and their related emotions, such as gratitude, devotion
and reverence. The motivation for distinguishing between afflictive and
13
In fact, Patrul Rinpoche is never shy to question social conventions that he thinks are
not in accord with the Buddha’s teaching, such as meat-eating, demon exorcism, the
relationship of monks to benefactors (which he sees as “pandering”) and the cruel, but
common, treatment of pack animals and watchdogs.
14
Patrul 1994, 213. Given his pervasive criticism of ressentiment, Nietzsche would most
likely agree with Patrul Rinpoche’s condemnation of passionate envy. However, Patrul
Rinpoche’s insistence on limiting passionate experiences to the “good” emotions is at odds
with Nietzsche’s—and Solomon’s 2007—general approach.
15
See Tenzin 1999, chap. 4; and Mingyur 2009.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
109
positive emotions rests, in part, on the fact that afflictive emotions are
characterized by attachment, which is undergirded by mistaken beliefs or
assumptions about the world. Positive emotions, on the other hand, are
characterized by non-attachment and are supported by moral insights.
(This point will be discussion in more detail in sec. 6.)
Because of the other-regarding nature of love, compassion and sympathetic joy, their passionate expressions tend to be about or for others.
Passionate responses to one’s own triumphs and defeats can, like all
experiences, be “taken on the path,” but they are not cultivated. In fact,
passionate reactions to our own successes and failures can often prohibit
us from feeling passionately for others. Attention to this fact again
distinguishes Patrul Rinpoche’s conception a passionate life from
Nietzsche’s, which holds self-mastery and personal power as the foundations of passionate life.
4. Passion and Empathy
Empathy, for Patrul Rinpoche, is one of the main vehicles for passionate
emotional response. It is by considering others’ happiness and suffering
that we become “swept away,” as Solomon puts it, by our emotions.
Although Patrul Rinpoche does not use a word in Tibetan that could be
translated as “empathy,” he employs imaginative empathic processes—such
as the ones described above as well as the common Tibetan Buddhist
practice of “exchanging self and other”—that underlie cultivating love,
compassion, and sympathetic joy.16 Following the conventions of Western
scholarship on emotions, I distinguish empathy (the psychological phenomenon of taking on the feelings and perspectives of others) from compassion
and sympathy, which employ empathy and add the extra value judgment
that another’s suffering is bad and her happiness is good. Empathy, as a
value-neutral skill, may be used for good or evil purposes (consider, for
example, sadism). Patrul Rinpoche, however, is interested in how, by taking
on the feelings and perspectives of others, we can develop positive emotions
for them. I suspect that it is for that reason that the positive emotions,
rather than a kind of value-neutral empathy, are more explicitly discussed
and theorized in his work. Nevertheless, empathizing with others is at the
heart of the project of cultivating love and compassion for them. In fact, in
Patrul Rinpoche’s work it often seems like the main barrier to developing
compassion and love is the failure of empathy, which he sees as motivated
by the mistaken belief that “you” or “they” are, morally speaking, fundamentally different from (and inferior to) “me” or “us.”
16
The meditative process of exchanging self and other is a typical practice for developing
the altruistic mind of enlightenment (bodhicitta). See Patrul 1994, 222-34; and Tsongkhapa
2000.
110
Journal of Religious Ethics
In contemporary Western ethics, empathy is also widely considered to
be one of the main mechanisms by which we expand our sphere of moral
concern beyond the egocentric.17 Empathizing with, or “feeling with,”
another’s emotional experience can take many different forms, such as
affective responses to facial expressions and other cues and highly cognitive imaginative projection.18 In Western philosophical ethics, Adam Smith
was one of the greatest proponents of well-developed empathy in moral
life. Although he uses the word “sympathy” (“empathy” has a more recent
coinage), it is clear that, at least at times, he means empathy, and usually
highly cognitive, imaginative empathy, much like the kind invoked in
Patrul Rinpoche’s contemplations.19 He writes:
By the imagination we place ourselves in [another’s] situation, we conceive
ourselves enduring all the same torments, we enter, as it were, into his body
and become in some measure the same person with him; and thence form
some idea of his sensations, and even feel something which, though weaker
in degree, is not altogether unlike them [Smith 1948, 74].
Smith asserts that we all can and do participate in imaginative projection,
although to varying extents. It is what allows us to care deeply about the
happiness and suffering of others, even when their welfare does not
directly affect our own. His identification of empathy as a primary principle of our nature (“the greatest ruffian, the most hardened violator of the
laws of society, is not altogether without it”) seems to be borne out by
recent findings in psychology and neuroscience (Smith 1948, 74).20
Although they both take empathy to be the primary ethical skill,
Smith’s account of empathic response lacks the emphasis on passion that
so pervades Patrul Rinpoche’s discussions. On Smith’s view our empathy
will only ever be a shadow of the original emotions. He writes,
Mankind, though naturally sympathetic, never conceives for what has
befallen another that degree of passion which naturally animates the person
principally concerned. That imaginary change of situation upon which their
sympathy is founded is but momentary . . . the thought that they themselves
are not really the sufferers, continually intrudes itself upon them and,
17
See Deigh 1995; Sherman, 1998; and Sherman 2004.
Snow 2000 locates three defining characteristics of empathy: that the empathizer feels
the same or similar emotion as the person with whom she is empathizing, that she feel that
emotion because the other feels it (that is, not coincidentally) and the she understands that
the other does in fact feel that emotion. See also Sober and Wilson 1998.
19
The English word “empathy” was coined by Titchner 1909.
20
For a philosophically oriented summary and analysis of many psychological studies on
this topic, see Sherman 1998 and 2004; Goleman 1994; and Rifkin 2009. Also, the discovery
of mirror neurons, which fire both when we perform an action and when we see others doing
it, seem to support Smith’s claim. For more on mirror neurons, see Motluk 2001 and
Thomson 2010.
18
A Passionate Buddhist Life
111
though it does not hinder them from conceiving a passion somewhat analogous to what is felt by the sufferer, hinders them from conceiving anything
that approaches to the same degree of violence [Smith 1948, 74].
Patrul Rinpoche would no doubt agree with Smith that our ability to
empathize is normally fairly weak. This in fact explains why Patrul
Rinpoche takes such pains to push us to empathize by, for instance,
insisting that we think about the suffering person or animal as ourselves
or our old mothers. The difference is that for Patrul Rinpoche we
strengthen our ability to empathize through practice over time. These
practices hone our empathic skills and cultivate the corresponding emotions of love, compassion, and sympathetic joy. The assumption that
empathy can be honed and love, compassion, and sympathetic joy can be
cultivated helps explain why empathy is a much more passionate experience on Patrul Rinpoche’s view than on Smith’s.
Another reason why Smith may have been reluctant to advocate the
intense empathic meditations that Patrul Rinpoche recommends is that
for Smith empathic response to directly linked with moral judgments. To
approve or disapprove of another’s emotional state is to acknowledge that
they are in agreement or disagreement with one’s own, were one in that
person’s situation. He writes, “If, upon bringing the case home to our own
breast, we find that the sentiments which it gives occasion to coincide and
tally with our own, we necessarily approve of them as proportioned and
suitable to their objects” (Smith 1948, 79). Since to empathize with
someone just is to approve of her action or response, it is important for
Smith’s ethical system that our empathy not extend further than our
moral judgments.21 The fact that we do at times empathize with someone
whose actions we do not endorse is a challenge for Smith’s account (and
one for which he does not seem to have a satisfying answer).22 Nevertheless, given his project of identifying the capacity to empathize with
implicit moral judgments, Smith’s account cannot accommodate passionate emotional experience through empathy unless that response is appropriate and proportional to its object.
Despite the similarities of their examples—for example, Patrul’s prisoner awaiting execution and Smith’s “brother on the rack”—Patrul Rinpoche does not tend to use empathic projection to understand or provoke
moral judgments.23 The point of the practices above is not (primarily) to
21
Smith writes, “to approve of the passions of another, therefore, as suitable to their
objects, is the same thing as to observe that we entirely sympathize with them” (1948, 58).
For a more detailed discussion of Smith’s link between sympathy and judgment, see
Sherman 1998, 90–91.
22
See Sherman 1998, 86–91.
23
See Smith 1948, 73. This is not to imply that Patrul Rinpoche does not issue moral
judgments, only that these are not obviously connected to the empathy practices he offers.
112
Journal of Religious Ethics
issue judgments against meat eating or capital punishment, either in
general or in particular situations. Unlike Smith, Patrul Rinpoche is not
concerned with the reasonableness of the response with which we are
empathizing. In the execution contemplation, for example, he does not
give many details about the prisoner—he may be the most hardened and
vicious criminal—which leaves little ground for making a judgment about
the justice of such a punishment.24
Instead, Patrul Rinpoche advocates imaginative empathy to cultivate
emotional dispositions that yield moral insights. The aim of these
empathic projections is to elicit targeted emotional responses, particularly
love, compassion, and sympathetic joy. According to Patrul Rinpoche,
passionate experiences of these emotions are central to moral and spiritual development and empathy triggers, sustains, and intensifies these
emotional experiences. Through empathizing with the suffering of the
animal about to be slaughtered, we naturally feel compassion for the
animal; through empathizing with the happiness of a loved one, sympathetic joy naturally arises. These feelings carry with them important
moral insights, such as the fundamental equality of members of the moral
community and the dynamic and changing nature of our world and even
ourselves (see sec. 6).
Given their different purposes, it is not surprising that Patrul Rinpoche and Smith disagree about the degree to which they think passionate empathy is possible or desirable. Since Smith is primarily
concerned with using our natural tendency to empathize as a basis for
making moral judgments, it makes sense that our empathy for others—
and our expectations to be empathized with—be kept in check. Moral
judgments are made with regard to whether a particular response is
appropriate or reasonable and it may not be appropriate or reasonable
to expect that people can feel intense and pervasive empathy, let alone
the feelings of boundless love and compassion that the empathy is meant
to provoke. Because Patrul Rinpoche is primarily interested in gradual
moral and spiritual development through passionate experiences of love,
compassion, and joy, he is not interested in limiting our empathy for
others. In fact, as I argued, he actively attempts to push our emotional
limits.
In this way, the passionate life that Patrul Rinpoche and Shabkar are
suggesting offers a unique perspective on the relationship between
passion and morality that is not fully explored by those, such as Solomon
and Nietzsche, who advocate a passionate life based on self-mastery and
self-expression, nor by moral sentiment theorist such as Smith who focus
on empathizing with the emotions of others. The passionate life I have
24
For a comparison between Adam Smith and the four boundless qualities in Theravada
Buddhism, particularly in the work of Buddhaghosa, see Heim 2007.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
113
described here shares Solomon’s and Nietzsche’s appreciation of passionate emotions but it is more explicitly “moral,” since insists on a high
degree of other-regarding motivations and commitments. It shares
Smith’s commitment to morality and altruism but rejects his insistence
that empathy is an implicit moral judgment and, as such, is less intense
or passionate than the original feeling.
5. Passion and Other Buddhist Ideals
This advocacy of the passionate life may seem to be in direct conflict
with core Buddhist ideals, namely that other Immeasurable quality,
equanimity, and the project of becoming liberated from suffering. Equanimity (or impartiality) is often considered to be a virtue of detachment
and dispassion, almost by definition. Indeed, Patrul Rinpoche characterizes equanimity as “giving up hatred for enemies and infatuation with
friends,” which seems to be a recommendation for the dispassionate life
(Patrul 1994, 196). But he differentiates boundless equanimity from what
he calls “mindless equanimity” (gti mug btang snyom), which is to “just to
think of everybody, friends and enemies, as the same, without any
particular feeling of compassion, hatred or whatever” (Patrul 1994, 198).
Mindless equanimity, he argues, brings neither benefit nor harm; it must
be infused with feelings of love and compassion.
Boundless equanimity works in conjunction with love, compassion,
and sympathy because it specifically targets the cravings and aversions
that can otherwise limit or obscure these positive emotions. According to
Patrul Rinpoche, when we practice the meditations on the four boundless qualities, we should begin with equanimity. Otherwise, he notes,
“whatever love, compassion, and sympathetic joy we generate will tend
to be one-sided and not completely pure” (Patrul 1994, 195). This is not
to say that experiences of love, compassion, and sympathetic joy do not
also help dissolve problematic distinctions between self and other, but
rather that equanimity, because of its focus on uprooting craving and
aversion can specifically address problematic notions of the self and thus
provide the basis for deeper expressions of love, compassion, and sympathetic joy.
Since the passionate life, as presented by Patrul Rinpoche, is distinct
from the life of intense craving and aversion, it is compatible with (and
indeed relies upon) equanimity. Love, compassion, and sympathetic joy
are, for Patrul Rinpoche, deep emotional commitments that are not
characterized by craving and aversion. This is because craving and
aversion are essentially reactions to grab at and cling to what we like
(craving) and push away or avoid what we do not (aversion). Love,
compassion and sympathetic joy are cultivated dispositions that focus on
the others and our relationships with them. Unlike craving and aver-
114
Journal of Religious Ethics
sion, they are neither reactive nor centered on the self. In this way,
equanimity makes possible expansive passionate experience of love,
compassion and joy. By uprooting craving and aversion, we have more
emotional space to strengthen the other immeasurable feelings.
We may still worry that Patrul Rinpoche’s advocacy of intense and
“unbearable” compassion conflicts with the broader Buddhist project of
liberation from suffering. If compassion is at least in part a project in
taking on the suffering of others, then how can the compassionate person,
especially the intensely compassionate person, be anything but miserable?
And is not misery exactly what we should be aiming to liberate ourselves
from?
As far as I know, Patrul Rinpoche did not directly take up these
questions. But there are at least two ways of answering it. One way is to
differentiate compassion from suffering or misery, which is the approach
taken by the fifth-century Indian scholar-saint Buddhaghosa in his discussion of the four boundless qualities in The Path of Purification (Visuddhimagga). Here he distinguishes each boundless quality from its “near
enemy,” a feeling that seems similar but is in fact opposed to the boundless quality. The near enemy of compassion is grief or sorrow. Buddhaghosa claims that compassion “succeeds when it makes cruelty subside and
it fails when it produces sorrow” (Buddhaghosa 1999, 310).25 Similarly, the
contemporary Tibetan Dzogchen teacher Tsoknyi Rinpoche suggests that
compassion is best characterized as tenderness, rather than as grief or
misery.26 Cultivating compassion should result in a deeper and more
extensive tenderness. If it makes us miserable or depressed, then it is not
compassion that we are cultivating but rather some kind of grief or
sorrow.
It would be difficult, however, for Patrul Rinpoche to avail himself of
this solution. He does not distinguish between such closely related emotional states such as tenderness, sadness, and grief. In fact, he seems to
be directly asking us to take on the pain with which we are empathizing.
Recall the practices that involve “experiencing the pain and the panic” of
a sheep about to be slaughtered or a prisoner about to be executed. And
just in case this pain is not visceral enough, we are encouraged to at least
partially re-create it by covering our mouths to temporarily stop breathing. It seems that Patrul Rinpoche is literally asking us to suffer as part
of developing compassion.
But how can Patrul Rinpoche’s insistence that we experience the “pain
and the panic” of those we are empathizing with be compatible with the
larger Buddhist project of liberation from suffering? The first Noble Truth
tells us that there is suffering; we suffer and others suffer. With regard to
25
26
For a contemporary defense of Buddhaghosa’s approach see Frakes 2007.
See Tsoknyi Rinpoche 2004.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
115
the suffering of others, we seem to have three options. We could try to
avoid it, which was the approach of the Buddha’s father who tried to
protect his son from the sight of the suffering and death of others. This
famously did not work. Just as surely as we cannot avoid other people, we
cannot avoid their suffering.
Alternatively, we could try to become indifferent to the suffering of
others. This does not involve avoiding the suffering of others but rather
witnessing their suffering while remaining indifferent to it. But this
sounds like the behavior of someone with psychological abnormalities (for
instance a sociopath or someone with severe autism) rather than any kind
of moral ideal. To situate the point within the context of basic Buddhist
philosophy, the strategy of becoming indifferent to the suffering of others
is an active denial of the first Noble Truth that there is suffering. By being
indifferent to others’ suffering it seems that we are not in any substantial
way recognizing that there is suffering. We are treating suffering as
something that does not matter, which violates the spirit of the first Noble
Truth.
The remaining option is to genuinely feel the suffering of others and use
these experiences for moral and spiritual development. The contemporary
Tibetan Buddhist teacher Yongey Mingyur Rinpoche writes that cultivating compassion “can break your heart.” “But,” he continues, “a broken
heart is an open heart. Every heartbreak is an opportunity for love and
compassion to flow through you” (Mingyur 2007, 182). In other words, we
can use the suffering that may arise along with compassion in order to
cultivate compassion. This involves (1) the recognition that a broken heart
is evidence of our ability to fully appreciate another’s suffering, and (2) the
practice of using that suffering to connect with and understand others. If
our compassion is tinged (or overwhelmed) by feelings of grief, sorrow or
guilt, then we can use these feelings—as we would in other occasions—as
opportunities for insight.
It should also be noted that the point of Patrul Rinpoche’s practices
is to push our emotional limits by challenging our comfort with indifference to others; the point is not to traumatize us. For instance, for
some of us actually witnessing a mother with no arms try in vain to
rescue her drowning baby would be a traumatic experience from which
it may take years to recover. Since this kind of trauma can clearly stunt
emotional growth, it would be antithetical to Patrul Rinpoche’s aims.
Just as doing overly strenuous physical exercise can be a setback for
getting in shape, overly strenuous emotional exercise can prevent emotional growth and maturity. The meditative practices for cultivating
the Immeasurables offer a more controlled environment for emotional
growth and experimentation. In this safe setting, we can hone in on
the space between indifference and trauma, which will be different for
different people at different times, in order to continue to strengthen
116
Journal of Religious Ethics
our emotional capacities. We want to break our hearts—not obliterate
them.
In this way the suffering or pain that we may feel when cultivating the
Immeasurables, especially compassion, can be conceived of as part of
moral and spiritual development. By gradually breaking our hearts in a
safe setting we learn to feel more deeply, which has significant consequences for our moral and spiritual growth. The fruit of this project of
deepening and intensifying emotional experiences—riding the boundary
between indifference and trauma—is the subject of the remainder of this
paper.
6. Why does Passion Matter?
Nietzsche claimed that “instead of taking into service the great sources
of strength, those impetuous torrents of the soul that are so often
dangerous and overwhelming, and economizing them, this most shortsighted and pernicious mode of thought, the moral mode of thought, wants
to make them dry up” (1968, 207). The insistence that passionate emotions are sources of energy and power—and that their repression leads to
a kind of impotence—is one of Nietzsche’s, and Solomon’s, strongest
recommendations for the passionate life. By not erecting barriers to
passionate emotional experiences, we gain (or maintain) access to one of
our greatest sources of power and energy. The passionate life is a psychologically healthy life.
On Solomon’s view, the passionate life promotes is a certain kind of
unity of emotional experience, which he calls emotional integrity. This
unity is complex; it is neither mere consistency nor coherence. As he
points out, we can have consistency in our emotional lives by simply
fixating on one emotion and the corresponding set of beliefs. Yet this kind
of fixation is the antithesis of emotional integrity. Emotional integrity
requires a range of emotional experiences to integrate. The dispassionate
person cannot integrate experiences she does not have, recognize, or
appreciate. She cannot understand the depth and complexity of emotionalethical life if her only goal is peace of mind. Emotional integrity includes
a “mixed, even conflicted, repertoire of feelings, emotions, and reflections,
including dissatisfaction, self-criticism, lack of contentment, and real
ethical dilemmas, that is, impossible choices and engagements” (Solomon
2007, 267). A life without such emotional complexity is, according to
Solomon, “a limited life indeed” (Solomon 2007, 267).
Emotional integrity is one of the main benefits of using our passionate
emotions as a support for moral and spiritual development. It gives us a
method for fully experiencing our emotions without repressing them,
controlling them or overly identifying with them. To use emotions as a
way to connect to others, we must have a wide variety of compelling
A Passionate Buddhist Life
117
emotions. But we must not only be capable of depth and variety of feeling;
we also need awareness of our emotional states and the capacity to reflect
on them as shared human experiences. In this way, taking our passionate
emotions as a support for moral and spiritual development requires, to
use Solomon’s terminology, both “first order feeling” and “second order
reflection.” It does not demand that our emotional experiences be accurate, coherent, or consistent but rather that, through awareness and
reflection, we can use our emotions in service of the larger commitment to
connect with others, understand human experience and the world around
us.
But taking our emotions on the path is only one aspect of the passionate life that I have described here. The other aspect is cultivating
passionate experiences of love, compassion, and joy through empathy. The
benefit of this practice is not only psychological health and integrity, but
moral and spiritual excellence. In particular, cultivating passionate experiences of the four immeasurable qualities, contributes to moral and
spiritual excellence in two ways: it provides excellent motivation for
altruistic action and can transform our perception of the world, which
allows us to understand important moral truths.
Passionate experiences of love, compassion, and sympathetic joy are
excellent motivation for altruistic actions, which is why they are commonly discussed in the context of cultivating bodhicitta (the altruistic
attitude of having concern for the well-being of all sentient beings and
the resolve to orient one’s life in order to help them). Emotions provide
compelling motivation for action; intense, passionate emotions are especially motivating. Because they are cultivated over time into emotional
dispositions, these emotions can also provide reliable motivation. And
since these passionate experiences are cultivated only in the context
some emotions, namely love, compassion, and sympathetic joy, and not
others, such as jealousy, hatred, and resentment, the actions that they
motivate will not be destructive, hurtful, or immoral.
Moreover, passionate emotional experience can also carry insight. This
can happen in two main ways. In the case of the so-called afflictive
emotions (nyon mongs), we can gain insight by skillfully using these
emotions, as Shabkar was able to do with his grief. The Immeasurables,
on the other hand, carry insight in a more direct way: by increasing our
ability to surrender to these feelings we simultaneously become more
wise.
In fact, in Patrul Rinpoche’s discussion of boundless love and compassion, he claims that these feelings are the best ways to dispel confused
ways of thinking and feeling; they are the greatest purifiers of our
obscurations, both cognitive (shes grib) and emotional (nyon mongs). In
addition to impermanence, one of the main insights that passionate
experiences of love, compassion, and sympathetic joy can reveal is the
118
Journal of Religious Ethics
fundamental equality of members of the moral community.27 By fundamental equality, I simply mean the idea, which appears widely in Western
and Eastern ethical systems, that there is some basic sense in which all
members of the moral community are equally deserving of care and
respect. For Kantians, this is often expressed as a commitment to respect
the humanity of rational beings; utilitarians focus on the equal consideration of interests of all those capable of having interests. For Patrul
Rinpoche (and other Tibetan thinkers) this basic equality is expressed as
a recognition of the fundamental similarity of experiences (the desire to be
happy, avoid suffering, etc.) and the underlying potential for moral and
spiritual development.
Passionate experiences of love, compassion, and joy facilitate in the
recognition of this basic equality of members of the moral community.
Love, described by Patrul Rinpoche as an active, engaged commitment
to the happiness of another, affirms another’s basic worth; similarly
compassion, which seeks to relieve another of her suffering, and sympathetic joy, which celebrates the success of another, rest on a basic
recognition of the inherent value of another’s basic well-being. As we
extend these feelings to increasingly many members of the moral community (thereby making these feelings “boundless” or “immeasurable”)
we come to deeply appreciate the universality of this inherent value. As
these experiences become more heart-felt and passionate, the recognition of the basic equality of members of the moral community becomes
increasingly integrated into our ways of thinking, feeling, and acting.
We do not simply know that there is a way that all members of the
moral community are equal; rather, this recognition informs our deepest
feelings, attitudes, and patterns of thinking and orients our moral and
spiritual life. In other words, the wisdom that passionate experiences
can bring does not only increase knowledge or information about the
world, it also transforms the agent.
In summary, in this paper I have argued for the following conclusions. First, contrary to popular stereotypes, there is room for some
passionate emotional experiences in Buddhist ethics, as exemplified in
the work of Shabkar and Patrul Rinpoche. Because of its emphasis on
moral development, this conception of a passionate life differs from
Solomon’s Nietzsche-inspired account. Because of its deep appreciation
27
In addition to yogic self-cultivation, Patrul Rinpoche (and other Vajrayana masters)
also emphasized the power of devotion to Buddhas, bodhisattvas and deities to provide direct
insight into the nature of reality. In particular, the preliminary (ngondro) practices such as
guru yoga seemed designed to facilitate realization through devotion rather than active
self-cultivation. Patrul Rinpoche does not seem to see these methods as in conflict and
includes them both in WPT (309–47). Due to space limitations, I cannot compare but only
point to these two methods of gaining wisdom (yogic self-cultivation and devotion to deities)
here.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
119
of a variety of passionate emotional experience, it differs from
Adam Smith’s moral sentiment theory. In this way, the conception of a
passionate life suggest by Shabkar and Patrul Rinpoche gives new
insight in the relationship between passionate emotions and moral and
spiritual development. Second, these passionate emotions are not in
conflict with cultivating equanimity, nor are they in conflict with the
project of liberation from suffering. Finally, passionate experiences of
love, compassion, and sympathetic joy contribute to moral and spiritual
life in three ways: they promote emotional integrity, they motivate
concern and care for others, and they give us tremendous insight into
the moral equality of others by breaking confused habits of thinking
and feeling.
REFERENCES
Buddhaghosa
1999
The Path of Purification. Translated by Bhikku Nanamoli. Onalaska,
Wash.: BPS Pariyatti Editions.
Deigh, John
1995
“Empathy and Universalizability.” Ethics 105 (4): 743–63.
Eliot, George
1876
Daniel Deronda. Vol. 2. New York: Harper Brothers.
Epictetus
1983
The Handbook. Translated by Nicholas White. Indianapolis, Ind.:
Hackett.
Frakes, Chris
2007
“Do the Compassionate Flourish?” Journal of Buddhist Ethics 14:
99–122.
Goleman, Daniel
1994
Emotional Intelligence. New York: Bantham Books.
Heim, Maria
2003
“The Aesthetics of Excess.” The Journal of the American Academy of
Religion 71 (3): 531–54.
2007
“Toward a Wider and Juster Initiative.” Religion Compass 1 (1):
107–19.
Hume, David
1951
A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L. A. Selby-Bigge. London:
Oxford.
Marks, Joel
1994
“Dispassion as an Ethical Ideal.” See Marks and Ames 1994, 139-59.
Marks, Joel and Roger Ames, eds.
1994
Emotions in Asian Thought: A Dialogue in Comparative Philosophy.
Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press.
Millay, Edna St. Vincent
1922
A Few Figs from Thistles. New York: Harper & Brothers.
120
Journal of Religious Ethics
Mingyur Rinpoche
2007
The Joy of Living. New York: Three Rivers.
Motluk, A.
2001
“Read My Mind.” New Scientist (January): 22–28.
Nietzsche, Friedrich
1968
The Will to Power. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York:
Vintage Books.
1982
The Portable Nietzsche. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York:
Penguin Books.
1989
On the Genealogy of Morals/Ecce Homo. Translated by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Random House.
Patrul Rinpoche
1994
The Words of My Perfect Teacher. Translated by Padmakara Translation Group. San Francisco, Calif.: Harper Collins.
Rifkin, Jeremy
2009
The Empathic Civilization. New York: Penguin.
Shabkar
1994
The Autobiography of Shabkar. Translated by Mattieu Ricard.
Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press.
Sherman, Nancy
1998
“Empathy and Imagination.” Midwest Studies in Philosophy XXII:
83-119.
2004
“Empathy and the Family.” Acta Philosophica 13.1: 23–44.
Smith, Adam
1948
A Theory of Moral Sentiments. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Snow, Nancy
2000
“Empathy.” American Philosophical Quarterly 37.1: 65–78.
Sober, Elliott and David Wilson
1998
Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Solomon, Robert
1999
The Joy of Philosophy: Thinking Thin Versus the Passionate Life. New
York: Oxford University Press.
2003
Living With Nietzsche. New York: Oxford University Press.
2007
True to Our Feelings. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tenzin, Geshe Lobsang
1999
Emotions and Their Impact on Health: An Analysis of Tibetan and
Western Approaches (Dissertation). Atlanta: Emory University.
Thomson, Helen
2010
“Empathic Mirror Neurons Found in Humans At Last.” New Scientist, 17 (April): 12.
Titchner, E.
1909
Experimental Psychology of the Thought Process. New York: Macmillan.
A Passionate Buddhist Life
121
Tsoknyi, Rinpoche
2004
Carefree Dignity: Discourses on Training in the Nature of Mind. Hong
Kong: Rangjung Yeshe.
Tsongkhapa
2000
The Great Treatise of the Stages of the Path to Enlightenment. Ithaca,
N.Y.: Snow Lion.
Copyright of Journal of Religious Ethics is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not be copied
or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission.
However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.