Academia.eduAcademia.edu

A weak defence of normativism

2014

AI-generated Abstract

This paper examines the viability of horizontal essentialist normativism regarding the mind, stemming from the challenges faced by previous normativist perspectives, particularly in their ability to equate norms with actual practices in language and thought. It critiques Zangwill's version of this normativism against the backdrop of Wittgenstein's and Kripke's rule-following dilemmas, questioning whether any proposed rules for rational relations among propositional attitudes can genuinely guide thought in a normative sense. Ultimately, the paper argues that while horizontal normativism may withstand some criticisms, it has yet to convincingly demonstrate how thought can be governed by normative rules that determine future correctness.

A weak defence of normativism Lo Presti, Patrizio 2014 Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Lo Presti, P. (2014). A weak defence of normativism. Abstract from Nature of Rules and Normativity, . Total number of authors: 1 General rights Unless other specific re-use rights are stated the following general rights apply: Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal Read more about Creative commons licenses: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/ Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. FROM SEMANTIC NORMATIVISM TO HORIZONTAL ESSENTIALIST NORMATIVISM OF MIND: UNSETTLED SCORES Proponents of normativity theses about mind and language have come under pressure to abandon most of their pet claims. With Kripke’s (1982) exposition of Wittgenstein’s (1953 § 201) ‘rule-following paradox,’ a semanticist normativity thesis became fashionable. According to it, meaning was fraught with ought in the sense that from w referring to all and only Fs, S ought to use w to refer to all and only Fs. What constituted meaning was couched in terms of norms for language use. Kripke’s point was that no purely descriptive account, or truth-functional analysis, of meaning would square with the indeterminacy of future correct uses of language from limited past ranges of applications of words. For instance, a dispositional analysis might yield the claim that the meaning of w consists in subjects’ dispositions to use w to refer to all and only Fs in the future. But Kripke, and philosophers since, argued that people are in fact disposed to make mistakes – for instance, to get 5 from 2+7. Yet such mistakes surely cannot figure among the meaning constituting facts of ‘+’. Furthermore, dispositions are hedged-in by subjective finitude such that there will always be a wide range of large numbers, or complicated enough propositions, to which no finite subject’s arithmetic or interpretative dispositions can yield an answer as to their product or reference. The trouble, it was argued, is that dispositional analysis gives a description of what people likely will do, while the relation between past and future use is prescriptive in the sense that meaning is determined by what people ought to do. The fall from grace of semantic normativism, or part of the reason for that fall at least, is found in considerations like the following: semantic categorization is like sorting objects into tables and non-tables [which] should clearly be nonnormative. Of course, saying that categorization is non-normative is not the same as saying that it cannot be used to derive normative consequences. Indeed, any categorization can be used to derive normative consequences. But not directly. … Semantic categorization is like sorting objects into tables and non-tables: no immediate normative consequences ensue. (Glüer and Wikforss 2009, 36-37). That is, while something’s being an A may make it true of w that it can be used to refer to the A, it isn’t inherent to one’s use of w that it is normatively correct to use it to refer to the A even if, as a matter of social contingencies, people may impose prescriptions to use of w only to refer to As. Such prescriptions aren’t inherent to language or language use. Philosophers who insist that, still, there’s something essentially normative about mind (or language) have reverted to a kind of content normativity (e.g. Boghossian 2003). The idea here is that belief, desire, intention and other mental states’ contents can fail (succeed) in bringing subjects into cognitive contact with their world or fail (succeed) in making subjects bring their world into conformity with their conations. The proposal is that such failure (success) be understood normatively as it being the case that it’s constitutive, of a belief, for instance, to truly represent the world, and that it’s constitutive, of a desire, for instance, to be satisfied if and only if the world is brought to ‘match’ it’s contents. In general, it is supposed to be such norms of content that determine what kind of mental state a subject has. For instance, if a state is correct if and only if it’s contents truly represent, then the state in question is cognitive, and if a state is satisfied if and only if the world is brought into conformity with it’s contents, then the state is conative (Cf. Jarvis 2012). But, again, the thesis is slipping from the normativist’s hands. Fred Dretske, among others, argue that: Beliefs and judgments must be either true or false, yes, but there is nothing normative about truth or falsity. What makes a judgment true (false) is the fact that it fails (or succeeds) in corresponding to the facts and failing (or succeeding) in corresponding to the facts is … a straightforward factual matter. Nothing normative about it. (2001, 92). Surely, one might try saying, we disvalue (value) false (true) beliefs (McHugh 2012) and frustrated (satisfied) desires. However, as Dretske points out (2001, 92-93), we also disvalue rain when picnicking. But rain, if anything, isn’t constitutively normative (Cf. Gibbard 2005). A final kind of normativism, horizontal essential normativism, can be found in Nick Zangwill (2005, 2010). According to it, there are no ‘oughts’ of though in virtue of contents but in virtue of the propositional attitude types in which contents are entertained and the relations in which those attitudes stand to each other. Here it is an essential normative property of, e.g., the conjugated beliefs that P and that if P then Q, to normatively rationalize believing that Q. Similarly, it is an essential normative property of the conjugated cognitive-conative pair of belief that X is the only means to end Y and desire for Y to normatively rationalize an intention to X. This normativism escapes the familiar potholes of earlier normativist theses in not requiring norms to obtain in addition to truth (falsity) and satisfaction (frustration) of contents. Rather it insists that in order to have thought that can be true (false) and satisfied (frustrated) to begin with a subject must have a network of propositional attitudes that, if not globally, stand in at least local rationalizing relations. Otherwise the subject cannot even be made sense of as a single thinking thing that can be wrong (right) in its cognitions, satisfied (frustrated) in its conations. I intend to assess the plausibility of this horizontal normativism about mind. I’ll expose it to arguments launched at the cousin theses reviewed to see if it stands where they fall. Since a normativist of Zangwill’s stripe resorts to rationalizing relations between propositional attitude types, he appears especially vulnerable to rule-following dilemmas of the sort originally encountered by Wittgenstein and fleshed out by Kripke. This time, though, the problem is not that of how a rule can possibly determine correct future language use from a finite range of prior uses, but that of how a rule can possibly guide a subject to bring her propositional attitudes into rationally licensed relations. If subjects are required to have beliefs about what propositional attitudes are rationally licensed by, and rationally license, other propositional attitudes, then it follows that subjects must have propositional attitudes about propositional attitudes that are rationally licenced by rules for relations between propositional attitudes – a regress threatens. But if it isn’t required that subjects have beliefs of this kind, then it seems that there’s no rule that subjects fail (succeed) in following that bestow their propositional attitudes the status of being correct in any normative sense in addition to being simply rational or irrational (Cf. Glüer and Wikforss 2013, In Press). The dialectic of the talk is to bring into full circle the dilemmas that have beset normativism since its semantic version until today, and to situate normativism about rational relations between propositional attitudes, like Zangwill’s, in that circle. I will propose that Zangwill’s horizontal normative essentialism does indeed withstand some of the criticisms that have made other kinds of normativism about the mental slip from philosophical grace. However, it will be found that the litmus test for any normativism to be persuasive still remains to be passed: if the ‘oughts’ of thought are supposed to be caught by rules of mind, then no real advance have been made by this normativism. For the original problem already pointed to, though in a slightly different context, by Wittgenstein was precisely how any rule can determine a future ‘ought’, future correctness, such that subject can follow and be guided by the rule. No argument to the effect that thought is, in any preferred sense, “fraught with ought” constitutes an answer to that challenge. Normativism, I argue, can have its day only if a plausible argument to the effect that thought is normative is coupled with a plausible explication of what the norms or rules of thought themselves consist in. That’s the holy grail of normativism about mind. Though normativism may have successfully met the first condition, it remains to meet the second.