Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2014, Hapág: A Journal of Interdisciplinary Theological Research
…
7 pages
1 file
For one to simply think, philosophy as a rational investigation of truths and principles of knowledge, being, and conduct, that is, philosophy as a "science," is not required. For thinking, what requisite is a reason, a human endowment constitutive of one's intelligence. One only needs a mind to be able to think. But something more is exigent for one to think twice, is to think again, to reconsider and see something from a different perspective. To think things twice, one needs a conscious apprehension of the notion of truth, a deliberate and critical engagement with principles, and a learned competency of habits of thinking that discloses the eternal freshness of reality. These are the elements that constitute philosophy not simply as a way of life, but as an academic discipline with methods and theories. Here lies philosophy's vocational relevance. Thinking things twice is not the mental disorder of indecisiveness or the unfortunate product of capriciousness. To think things twice is the stubborn instinct of human intelligence which remains restless in entrenched patterns of thought. The apprehension of the possibility of thinking things twice is the initial promise of liberation, the first step towards unshackling the mind and its powers from mental scripts that do not give birth to creativity. This explains why it is said that in the domain of philosophical discourses, questions always outlive their answers. Indeed, though philosophy, in its many faces and guises, has offered opinions, beliefs and sometimes divergent truths to the fundamental questions of life. The more important are the questions asked than the answers proffered. The convoluted transformations and shifting grounds in the history of ideas show to us how, philosophically considered, answers have no finality.
Lucilla Guidi ed., Wittgensteinian Exercises. Aesthetic and Ethical Transformations, Leiden: Fink-Brill, 2023
In this essay I discuss Wittgenstein’s view of the dissolution of philosophical problems. I argue that dissolution for the later Wittgenstein is never merely a matter of showing the nonsensicality or unworkability of a philosophical view, or that there is something wrong with philosophical problems as they have been posed. Instead, dissolution necessarily involves the introduction of an alternative view in the context of which the problems in question no longer arise. Hence, Wittgensteinian dissolutions involve as an essential component the transformation of ways of thinking. This has consequences for the interpretation of what Wittgenstein means by philosophizing without theses or theories. Philosophizing without theses or theories cannot be understood as a matter of only dissolving problems without offering any views in their place. Accordingly, not having theses or 1 Ludwig, Wittgenstein, Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000, MS 131, 48, 1946; references by manuscript/typescript number according to the von Wright catalogue. / Ludwig, Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, Oxford: Blackwell, 1998, 55. 2 theories is not a matter of not having philosophical views. In conclusion I contrast the proposed interpretation with Rupert Read’s recent reading of Wittgenstein’s philosophy as liberation from philosophical views, and this kind of liberation, which involves no commitment to any views as more correct than others, as the ethical goal of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. I argue that, whilst liberation from the thrall of views is part of Wittgenstein’s philosophical approach, this cannot by itself explain the role of ethical considerations as an aspect of his philosophy.
Open Press TiU, 2021
This handbook is an open educational and open-ended resource for whomever is interested in philosophical thinking. Each of the chapters is open in the sense of freely available and accessible to everyone. You may be a student who wants to get some background on a specific philosophical sub-discipline. You may be a teacher who wants to assign introductory reading for students. You may be a layperson interested in reading an overview of philosophical thinking, written in a clear and accessible way. Each of you: feel free to browse, download, print and use the collection as you see fit. We believe that open access is the future and that academic philosophy as presented in this volume is of potential worth to many of you out there. In this open-ended handbook you find two kinds of chapters. First, there are chapters that provide a broad introduction into a specific philosophical sub-discipline, such as political philosophy, epistemology or metaphysics. As this collection covers most of the sub-disciplines currently taught at Western philosophy departments, you can legitimately claim that you have been introduced to Western ‘philosophy’ as a whole, understood rather canonically, after having read the entire handbook. Second, there are chapters that introduce slightly more specific topics or philosophical approaches. You will always be able to know the focus of each chapter by looking at its subtitle. The open-ended nature of this handbook, means that new chapters will be added in the future. We hope that philosophy will change and grow with time to become more diverse and inclusive and that this handbook will do so as well. We think of philosophy and its evolution as an organic process, as a tree that branches out in many different directions, adding new directions as it goes along. In this handbook, we organize the wide variety of topics that philosophers discuss into four main branches, which represent important subject areas that philosophers have covered.First, there is ‘thinking about societies’, which includes chapters that cover philosophical approaches to matters of obvious societal relevance. How should we organize our societies? How should we treat others? What exactly are cultures and what role do they play in a globalized world? This branch covers philosophical discussions, theories and views on what binds and divides us as societies and communities.Second, there is ‘thinking about humans’, which includes chapters that zoom in on people, the members that make up those societies. Is there something like human nature and what does that look like? How do human minds and bodies relate to each other? Are we free or not? This branch covers what one could broadly call ‘philosophical anthropology’: philosophical discussions, theories and views on what it means to be human.Third, there is ‘thinking about thinking’, which include chapters that focus on the ways in which humans can relate to the outside world. How can we come to know things about that world? What is truth exactly? What are the values and limits of scientific understanding? How do we reason and argue and how do we do so properly? This branch covers philosophical discussions, theories and views on how humans come to believe things about themselves and the worlds they live in. Fourth, there is ‘thinking about reality’, which includes chapters that investigate those worlds in more direct ways. Do things have an essence? What do we mean when we say that some things exist and others do not? How can language help us access the reality out there? This branch covers philosophical discussions, theories and views on the world we, as humans, find ourselves in. If you like what is on offer in this handbook, you can let us know on the website https://www.openpresstiu.org/ and register for updates, for example when new chapters are added. Consider each chapter as a first and stand-alone introduction to the exciting and thought-provoking world of a specific branch of philosophy. The same will be true of future chapters. Like the chapters already included, these future chapters will be accessible for readers without any specific prior knowledge. All you need is curiosity, an open mind and a willingness to think twice.
This paper claims that what philosophy primarily does is interpret our notions, offer ways of understanding these notions that are not scientific in nature but not contrary to science either. The paper draws a distinction between conceptual analysis, a highly constrained enterprise that is supposed to bring to light what was in the concept all along, and the interpretation of notions, a creative enterprise that offers ways of understanding notions that were not already prefigured by the content of these notions-philosophy consists in the latter, not the former. It explains how these interpretations are justified and what the difference is between better and worse interpretations. The remainder of the paper is organized around three headings: philosophy and science, philosophy and language, and philosophy and progress. It claims that in philosophy there is no real progress, but that philosophy does move forward because the notions at issue are endlessly interpretable.
2022
In spite of the unprecedented nowadays communication involving the philosophers worldwide, it appears that there is still no consensus about the definition of the philosophy. While quite practical extracts addressing that issue can be found in sources such as Wikipedia and the Free Dictionary, these are somewhat blurred by the differences in the tendencies of different authors to focus on some of themes, while neglecting the others. For example, some authors concentrate on the psychological aspects such as aesthetics and ethics while the others put more emphasis on the nature and the ultimate significance of the universe. Although one can at the intersects of these trends recognise that the philosophers converge to studying of most general and fundamental questions about our relation with the world, a formal widely adopted definition seems to be still missing.
Philosophia, vol. 42 (2014), pp. 271-288., 2014
Can philosophy still be fruitful, and what kind of philosophy can be such? In particular, what kind of philosophy can be legitimized in the face of sciences? The aim of this paper is to answer these questions, listing the characteristics philosophy should have to be fruitful and legitimized in the face of sciences. Since the characteristics in question demand that philosophy search for new knowledge and new rules of discovery, a philosophy with such characteristics may be called the ‘heuristic view’. According to the heuristic view, philosophy is an inquiry into the world which is continuous with the sciences. It differs from them only because it deals with questions which are beyond the present sciences, and in order to deal with them must try unexplored routes. By so doing, when successful, it may even give birth to new sciences. In listing the characteristics that philosophy should have, the paper systematically compares them with classical analytic philosophy, because the latter has been the dominant philosophical tradition in the last century.
Philosophical Studies, 2009
2024
Санкт-Петербург 2024 3.1. Late Ancient and Early Christian philosophy: The Patristic philosophy………………………………………………………... 36 3.2. The Apex of Medieval Philosophy: The Scholastic System of St. Thomas Aquinas…………………………………… 38 3.3. The Renaissance Interlude…………………………………... 55 3.4. Reformation…………………………………………………. 59 3.5. Political thought of Renaissance. Machiavelli………………. 63 3.6. Science………………………………………………………. 65 3.7. Philosophy of Modern Times. Advocates of the Method of Science: Bacon and Hobbes……………………………………… 67 3.8. Rationalism on the Continent: Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz………………………………………………………. 72 3.9. Glossary……………………………………………………. 96 3.10. Tests………………………………………………………... 97 TOPIC IV. The Enlightenment. German classical philosophy……………. 4.1. The Enlightenment…………………………………………... 4.2. The critical philosophy of Kant……………………………... 4.3. The Transcendental aesthetic………………………………... 4.4. The antinomies of pure reason………………………………. 4.5. Kant's moral philosophy……………………………………. 4.6. German idealism and materialism…………………………... 4.7. Marx and the young Hegelians……………………………… 4.8. The Utilitarian………………………………………………. 4.9. Mill's logic…………………………………………………... 4.10. Glossary……………………………………………………. 4.11. Tests………………………………………………………... TOPIC V. Modern Western philosophy …………………………………... 5.1. Schopenhauer………………………………………………... 4.11. TESTS 1. «Sensations without concepts are blind, and concepts without sensations are empty»: A. Descartes; B. Schelling; C. Kant; D. Helvetius. 2.The central problem of I. Kant's philosophy is-A. study of the driving forces of the development of history; B. analysis of the self-development of the absolute idea; C. finding universal and necessary foundations of knowledge and humanistic values; D. investigation of the ultimate foundations of being. 3. History becomes the object of philosophical analysis in philosophy: A. Marxism; B. Аntiquity; C. Renaissance. 4. Creator and systematizer of dialectics as a philosophical method of cognition in German philosophy: A. Descartes; B. Spinoza; C. Kant; D. Hegel. 5. According to Kant's theory, time and space: A. are the eternal real attributes of the substance; B. are a priori forms of sensuality; C. arise gradually, as the knowledge of the world improves; D. are the inherent properties of individual things 6. DOES NOT apply to the laws of dialectics: A. unity and struggle of opposites; B. the identities of matter and consciousness; C. mutual transfer of quantity and quality; D. negation of negation. 7. The basic laws of dialectics formulated: A. Hegel B. Kant C. Heraclitus D. Marx 8. Hegel believed that the basis of the world is A. absolute identity B. the absolute unconscious C. an absolute idea D. absolute deity 9. Marxism's philosophical roots were thus commonly explained as derived from three sources:
INTRODUCTION
If there is one concept in the history of ideas that has been the subject to countless "thinking twice" across ages and has never died out to irrelevance in the process, it's the concept of "God." Indeed, every epoch seems to require a rethinking of God on the basis of each generation's epistemic deliverances. Georges De Schrijver in his article "God after the Big Bang: Toward a Revision of Classical Theism" argues that classical theism, an intellectual justification of a notion of creator-God understood as an order giver through God's preconceived plan needs to be abandoned. Drawing contemporary insights from science (George Coyne's appropriation of the Darwinian theory of evolution) and philosophy (Alfred North Whitehead's process philosophy), De Schrijver articulates the notion of a God in an evolutionary and creative universe, where finite entities are allowed to participate in God's creative power, and at the same time maintain this notion of God as available for religious discourses.
Sometimes to think things twice entails not so much on the creative birth of a new essential meaning but a retrieval of that which has been forgotten, the rebirth of something that lies beneath which may have been buried by successive mental accretions. Kenneth Masong's essay "Recuperating the Concept of Event in the Early Whitehead" seeks to recover a metaphysically fertile concept of event, the building block of reality, in the early works that make up Whitehead's process philosophy. Taking his cue from the contemporary philosopher Isabelle Stenger, Masong argues that a rethinking of the evental character discerned in reality provides a more dynamic metaphysics explicative of extending over, or passing into, of one event to another eschewing the discerned atomistic turn that Whitehead takes in the distinction he established between events and objects in his process philosophy.
Peace is not just a concept to be understood, but an aim that needs to be achieved. Both religion and society seek to contribute towards peace, but despite the passage of time, peace, though a commonly understood concept, still appears to be an elusive aim. Taking his cue from literature, Charles R. Strain, utilizing the ethical lenses of the Jesuit Daniel Berrigan and the Buddhist Thich Nhat Hahn, rethinks the images of the Prophet and the Bodhisattva to charter a possible way out of violence and what Strain calls "moral devolution" by means of the cultivation of virtue after the example of the prophet and the bodhisattva.
Adding his voice to political discourses aforementioned, Georges de Schrijver, in his second article in this collection entitled "The Political Ethics of Jean-François Lyotard" echoes the French philosopher's critique of modernity's "grand narratives" and its inherent tendency to espouse universalizing absolutes that mute the voices of the multiple. What De Schrijver offers in this article is a rethinking of the notion of universality, via Kant's ethics, a kind of universality that debunks its false instantiations, and offers a space for the voice of the "silent minority" in political realities through the activation of what Lyotard calls the "differend."
Still in the context of a discourse on political realities, what Dominador Bombongan Jr. offers in his article "Jacques Derrida and the Paradox of Hospitality" is a rethinking of the very notion of hospitality itself following the seminal insights of the French philosopher Jacques Derrida. For Derrida, hospitality needs to be rethought beyond the host-guest relations to which such a concept is generally understood. In a logic of pure excess, to welcome the other entails a re-evaluation of one's posture as host, and the radical acceptance of the other, beyond tolerance, as a guest. This is a dangerous yet necessary path that one has to take, at least intellectually, in order to affirm a notion of pure unconditional hospitality which the current political scene of migration seems to be in need of.
The last two articles in this volume provide a way of thinking things twice that is closer to home because they provide a rethinking of some Filipino (Eastern) concepts in the light of other (Western) philosophical systems. In a true sense, what we have in these two articles are a bridging of cultures through philosophical rethinking, an exercise of "thinking with…" In her original work of appropriating Jürgen Habermas' notion of argumentative discourse with its alleged incompatibility with the Filipino concept of kapwa, Maria Lovelyn Corpuz Paclibar argues in her article "Habermas and Argumentation in the Philippine Context" that there's no incommensurability of lifeworlds on this regard. The hermeneutic key is to identify potential rationalization processes within the Filipino modes of communication (namely nagtatalo, nag-aaway, and nag-uusap). Paclibar concludes that kwentuhan contains enabling components for reflexivity that makes possible a Habermasian rational argumentation as a procedure for resolving conflicts within the Filipino lifeworld.
In the last article in this volume, Kenneth Centeno's "Levinasian 'Barbarism' and the Challenge of Reinterpreting Pakikipagkapwa from Dussel's Liberation Ethics," the author seeks to engage himself philosophically with contemporary political issues in the Philippines by offering the perspective of liberation based on the thoughts of two contemporary philosophers: Emmanuel Levinas and Enrique Dussel. Centeno aims to achieve a rethinking of the Filipino concept of Pakikipagkapwa, in the lens of Levinasian-Dusselian philosophy, that can be used as "a powerful instrument in bringing real change and liberation in a country where the vast majority suffer different forms of exclusion and marginalization."
If there is one attribute that may be affirmed of philosophy, it is that philosophy can never be a conversation-stopper. Though addressing pertinent and perennial questions and proffering myriad answers to these, philosophy's response to questions are never walls, but always bridges. There's an inherent value in philosophical discourses that stimulates more conversations than putting an end to these. It is the hope that this collection of essays stimulates that intellectual need to "think things twice" not only on the multifarious concepts that populate our mind, but on the very thinking itself that informs our thinking. Philosophy's vocation speaks not only of its task to continue the conversation towards the pursuit of the "Harmony of harmonies" 8 by thinking things twice, but it is also tasked to invite others to join in in this conversation of "thinking with". It is our hope that this collection achieves its purpose of allowing us to see things from a different-and fresherperspective. 8 Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, 285 and 292.
Kenneth C. Masong
Ateneo de Manila University and St. Vincent School of Theology
Email: [email protected]
Pacific Gateways: Trans-Oceanic Narratives and Anglophone Literature, 1780–1914, 2024
The International Journal of Business & Management
Chiropractic Journal of Australia, 2018
Bayt al-Mashura, N°10, April 2019, 2019
Iskolakultúra, 2019
Journal of Computational Electronics, 2002
International Journal on Minority and Group Rights, 2015
Dr Heleen Sandhya Fernando
Journal of forensic practice, 2019
Academicus Magazine, 2025
Acta Numismatica, 2015
Computational Methods and Experimental Measurements XV, 2011
Journal of Immunological Methods, 2008
Clinical Immunology and Immunopathology, 1990
Pharmaceutical Research, 2004