Noether’s Theorems and Energy in General Relativity
Sebastian De Haro
Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam
Institute of Physics, University of Amsterdam
[email protected]
March 30, 2021
Abstract
This paper has three main aims: first, to give a pedagogical introduction to Noether’s
two theorems and their implications for energy conservation in general relativity, which
was a central point of discussion between Hilbert, Klein, Noether and Einstein. Second,
it introduces and compares two proposals for gravitational energy and momentum, one
of which is very influential in physics: and, so far as I know, neither of the two has been
discussed in the philosophical literature. Third, it assesses these proposals in connection
with recent philosophical discussions of energy and momentum in general relativity.
After briefly reviewing the debates about energy conservation between Hilbert, Klein,
Noether and Einstein, I give Noether’s two theorems. I show that Einstein’s gravitational energy-momentum pseudo-tensor, including its superpotential, is fixed, through
Noether’s theorem, by the boundary terms in the action. That is, the freedom to add an
arbitrary superpotential to the gravitational pseudo-tensor corresponds to the freedom to
add boundary terms to the action without changing the equations of motion. This freedom is fixed in the same way for both problems. I also review two proposals for energy
and momentum in GR, of which one is a quasi-local alternative to the local expressions,
and the other builds on Einstein’s local pseudo-tensor approach. I discuss the recent
philosophical literature on the conservation of energy and momentum in general relativity, and I assess and compare the two proposals in the light of this literature: especially,
in light of questions about diffeomorphism invariance and background-independence.
Forthcoming in: J. Read, N. Teh and B. Roberts (Eds.), The Philosophy and Physics of
Noether’s Theorems, Cambridge University Press, 2021.
1
Contents
1 Introduction
3
1.1 Noether’s theorem and general relativity . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
1.2 Illustrating Noether’s theorems in Maxwell theory . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
1.3 Einstein’s proposal, and five problems for energy and momentum in GR . . 15
2 Noether’s Theorems and the Energy-Momentum Tensor
2.1 Noether’s first theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.2 Noether’s second theorem and the boundary theorem . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.3 Two consequences of Noether’s second theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
19
19
20
23
3 Noether’s Theorems in General Relativity
26
4 Quasi-local Stress-Energy Tensors in GR
29
4.1 The Brown-York quasi-local stress-energy tensor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29
4.2 The holographic stress-energy tensor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31
4.3 Diffeomorphisms and redundancy of the description . . . . . . . . . . . . . 34
5 Gravitational Energy and Momentum, Revisited
38
5.1 Superpotentials are boundary terms in the Hamiltonian of GR . . . . . . . 38
5.2 Recent philosophical discussions of energy conservation in GR and pseudotensors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
6 A Comparison of Two Proposals
44
6.1 What else is required for us to accept pseudo-tensors? . . . . . . . . . . . . 44
6.2 Quasi-local expressions: superpotentials vs. the Brown-York stress-energy
tensor . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
6.3 Interpreting quasi-local quantitites . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
7 Summary and Conclusion
53
Acknowledgements
55
References
55
2
1
Introduction
This paper has three main aims: first, to give a pedagogical introduction to Noether’s
two theorems: and in particular to the role that her second theorem played in important
discussions between Hilbert, Klein, Noether and Einstein about the conservation of energy
and momentum in general relativity (GR). These discussions have been the subject of
recent scholarship, and are still valuable today.1
Second, I introduce for a philosophical audience two proposals for the gravitational
energy-momentum tensor: namely, Einstein’s pseudo-tensor (and the quasi-local expressions derived from it2 ) and the quasi-local definition by Brown and York, especially as
modified in the recent literature on the holographic principle. I argue that arguments
from gauge-gravity duality support the quasi-local quantities as correctly expressing the
energy and momentum of general relativity.
Third, I discuss and critically assess the various proposals in light of a recent philosophical discussion of energy and momentum in general relativity, by Hoefer (2000), Pitts
(2010), Lam (2011), Duerr (2019a), and Read (2020).
General relativity suffers from a number of problems regarding its local conservation
laws for energy and momentum. This was the subject of a crucial discussion between
Hilbert, Klein, Noether and Einstein between 1915 and 1918. What is perhaps less wellknown is that the problem of the definition and conservation of energy3 played a crucial
role in both: the genesis of general relativity and Noether’s reasons for proving her two
theorems.
To define gravitational energy and momentum, Einstein introduced a gravitational
pseudo-tensor, i.e. a quantity that is non-covariant, and is in some ways analogous to the
Christoffel symbols. However, unlike the Christoffel symbols, pseudo-tensors are not geometric objects. The question of energy and momentum, and the pseudo-tensor proposal,
are discussed in virtually all of Einstein’s papers on the subject.4 Part of the reason it
played such a prominent role, including in his November (1915, 1915a, 1915b) papers,
is because the pseudo-tensor is intimately linked to Einstein’s field equations and to the
contracted Bianchi identities.
Noether’s own work was directly motivated by the question of energy-momentum conservation, and prior to publishing her two theorems she had worked on comparing Hilbert’s
and Einstein’s approach to it. According to Hilbert, Klein, and Noether, the conservation
law in general relativity is improper, because it is given in terms of a superpotential whose
conservation law is an identity. On Klein’s interpretation, the conservation law does not
make direct use of the equations of motion, and so it has no physical content.
Einstein’s pseudo-tensor, and thus the energy, are known to have a number of other
1
See for example Kastrup (1987: pp. 116-125), Brading (2005: pp. 125-127), Brading and Brown
(2003: pp. 91, 06), Kosmann-Schwarzbach (2011: pp. 37-46), Rowe (1999: pp. 209-221; 2019: pp. 7-11,
29-34, 2019a).
2
Especially in recent work by Chang et al. (1999) and Chen et al. (2017, 2018).
3
For brevity, I will sometimes follow the literature in using ‘energy’ or ‘energy-momentum’ for the
longer ‘energy-momentum and angular momentum’, especially in expressions like ‘conservation of energymomentum and angular momentum’.
4
See for example Janssen and Renn (2007: p. 844).
3
problems: the pseudo-tensor is non-covariant, even non-geometric, and there appears to
be no unique expression for it. For many different expressions have appeared in the
literature. This non-uniqueness stems from the ability to add to the pseudo-tensor the
derivative of an arbitrary ‘superpotential’. The superpotential is such that its divergence
is identically zero, and so an arbitrary superpotential can be added into the conservation
law without modifying it. Thus, the very definition of the pseudo-tensor appears to be
ambiguous.
The philosophical interest in energy and momentum in general relativity has so far
been moderate.5 For example, Hoefer (2000), Lam (2011), and Duerr (2019, 2019a) have
criticised, and Read (2020) has defended, local definitions of energy and momentum, in
particular those involving the energy pseudo-tensor. I will give considerable attention to
this recent philosophical discussion in Sections 5.2 and 6.
There are two aspects that these recent discussions have not focussed on, and which I
will address in this paper: namely, the alleged non-uniqueness of the superpotential, and
the quasi-local (as opposed to local) definitions of energy and momentum.
I will show in Section 2 that, once the Lagrangian and its variation are fixed, Noether’s
second theorem fixes the superpotential. This holds not only for general relativity, but for
any theory with a local symmetry. In general relativity, the gravitational pseudo-tensor,
which is the Noether current corresponding to the local translation symmetry, is thus
fixed, through Noether’s theorem, by the choice of the action. In particular, the freedom
to add an arbitrary superpotential corresponds to the freedom to add boundary terms
to the action without changing the equations of motion.6 Thus the superpotential is not
arbitrary, but is fixed, through Noether’s theorem, by the choice of boundary terms in
the action. Although this is known to the experts, I have not seen these consequences of
Noether’s theorem discussed in the literature: in fact, the “problem of non-uniqueness” is
still frequently cited without a discussion of the implications of the choice of boundary conditions and boundary terms. For example, even Brading and Brown (2003: pp 101-102),
whose formulation of Noether’s second theorem I largely follow, have the superpotential
implicit in their formulas, but do not seem to recognise it as such, and they do not comment on the definition and alleged non-uniqueness of the pseudo-tensor in connection with
Noether’s theorems.7
The detailed consideration of Noether’s second theorem also allows one to address
Klein’s worry about the alleged ‘lack of physical content’ of the local energy conservation
law of general relativity. Indeed, I will argue that the distinction between ‘proper’ and
‘improper’ conservation laws, in the context of comparing general relativity with classical
mechanics, is a red herring: and that the claim that local energy conservation laws lack
5
For a detailed analysis of Hilbert’s (1916, 1917) two papers on the ‘Foundations of Physics’, see
Renn and Stachel (2007: pp. 878-902, 914-957). Hilbert’s first paper, including the changes that he
introduced into the proofs, is discussed, and compared with Einstein’s four November 1915 papers, in
Sauer (1999: pp. 539-557), Renn and Stachel (2007: pp. 872-933), and Corry et al. (1997: pp. 1271-1273).
A brief account of the interactions between Einstein and Hilbert in 1915 is in Corry (1999: pp. 177-179).
6
In a different context, Chang et al. (1999: pp. 3-4) and Chen et al. (2018: p. 4) have also made a
related connection between the superpotential and boundary conditions in the Hamiltonian, although
they do not mention Noether’s theorem in that connection.
7
For a discussion of the literature on this point, see Section 2.3.
4
physical content is misleading.
I will also introduce two different quasi-local expressions: one, due to Chang et
al. (1999), Nester (2004), and Chen et al. (2017, 2018, 2018a), directly obtained from the
total energy-momentum (i.e. the energy-momentum tensor plus the gravitational pseudotensor) suitably integrated over a volume. These authors show that, under assumptions
that I will discuss in Sections 5 and 6, this expression can be obtained from the covariant
Hamiltonian formalism of general relativity. Indeed, part of their aim appears to be to
justify the use of the pseudo-tensor from the Hamiltonian formalism.
The second expression is the Brown-York (1993) quasi-local stress-energy tensor, which
is directly defined on a two-dimensional surface. This stress-energy tensor has been studied
extensively in the physics literature, especially in the presence of a cosmological constant
(positive or negative), and has been shown to have many of the desired properties of the
quasi-local stress-energy, as I will also review.
I also compare, in Section 6, the two quasi-local proposals. While quasi-local expressions have sometimes been easily dismissed (or avoided altogether) in the philosophical
literature, I will argue that neither dismissal nor avoidance are justified. Also, we will see
that the analysis of the Brown-York stress-energy tensor in the gauge-gravity literature
gives crucial insights into the correct definition and properties of this tensor.
One obstruction to the construction of normal conservation laws for energy and momentum in curved spacetimes is the presence of a covariant derivative in the conservation
law of the energy-momentum tensor.8 One can integrate such a law to get an integral
form of the conservation law that is properly covariant only if the metric admits a timelike
Killing vector field, i.e. if the metric has a timelike isometry.
An important property of the quasi-local energy-momentum tensors is that they can
lead to covariant integral conservation laws under weaker conditions than the energymomentum tensor does. For, while the latter requires a timelike Killing vector field in the
whole spacetime, the quasi-local expression from Section 4 only requires a (conformal)
Killing vector field at the quasi-local surface, i.e. usually at asymptotic spatial or null
infinity. I show this in Section 4.2.
In physics, there are well-known global expressions (called the Bondi and ADM masses)
for the total energy at infinity, depending on whether they are integrated over spheres at
spatial infinity (in the case of asymptotically flat and AdS cases) or null infinity (in the
case of the Bondi mass). The two kinds of quasi-local quantities discussed in this paper
reproduce these expressions. But these expressions, including the quasi-local quantities,
do not necessarily have well-defined local densities.9 Chen et al. (1999: p. 2) discuss a
quasi-local formula that can be localised: its localisation gives rise to the gravitational
8
Notice that this fact is not specific to general relativity: for any translation-invariant classical field
theory on a curved spacetime has a covariantly-conserved, two-index, energy-momentum tensor. But GR
offers a specific interpretation of the source or sink terms in terms of a dynamical gravitational field.
9
This is often further explicated by an appeal to the principle of equivalence, that a local observer
cannot detect a gravitational field at a single point. This often stated, infinitesimal or strong, form of
the principle of equivalence is in Pauli (1958: p. 145); see also Brown (2005: pp. 169-170). For its role in
Einstein’s own thinking about general relativity, and its relation with the Einstein equivalence principle,
see Lehmkuhl (2019: pp. 2-7, 19-22) and Janssen (2014: pp. 174-182). The strong equivalence principle
is criticised by Norton (1985: pp. 207-208, 239-242, 245) and Curiel (2019: p. 91).
5
pseudo-tensor, which depends on the choice of coordinates. They view the interplay
between the local and quasi-local quantities as follows: ‘Appreciating the fundamental
nonlocality of the gravitational interaction yet believing in the basically local nature of
physical interactions led to the idea of quasi-local quantities: quantities that take on values
associated with a compact orientable spatial 2-surface’.
The plan of the paper is as follows. In the rest of this Introduction, I summarise
the discussion of energy and momentum between Hilbert, Klein, Noether and Einstein
(Section 1.1), illustrate Noether’s theorems for Maxwell theory as my running example
(Section 1.2), and summarise Einstein’s basic proposal of pseudo-tensors as candidates for
energy and momentum and its problems (Section 1.3). Section 1.3 lays out five problems
that organise the subsequent discussion. Section 1.1 has more of a historical character;
the rest of the paper has a more philosophical and foundational character. Section 2 then
gives Noether’s two theorems and discusses two consequences of it, one of which I have
not seen discussed in the literature (Section 2.3). Section 3 applies Noether’s theorems
to general relativity. Section 4 discusses the quasi-local Brown-York stress-energy tensor.
Sections 4.1 and 4.2 are slightly more technical than the rest of the paper, and can be
skipped by readers only interested in the philosophical discussion. Section 4.3 discusses
whether diffeomorphisms are redundancies of the description. Section 5 reviews proposals
by Chang et al. (1999) and Chen et al. (2017, 2018, 2018a) and Nester (2004) that
link the gravitational pseudo-tensor with a quasi-local expression that can be reproduced
from the covariant Hamiltonian of general relativity, under assumptions that I will point
out. Section 6 then compares the two proposals for quasi-local expressions and discusses
the status of energy-momentum in general, and the pseudo-tensors in particular, in the
philosophical literature. Sections 4 to 6 also discuss two themes that run through the
philosophical literature on energy and momentum in general relativity: namely, covariance
and background-independence.
1.1
Noether’s theorem and general relativity
Emmy Noether’s (1918) two theorems, on the correspondence between symmetries of the
action under infinitesimal transformations of a continuous group, and local conservation
laws, are better known for their applications in classical mechanics and gauge theories
than in general relativity. Yet Noether’s motivation to study this problem came chiefly
out of discussions between David Hilbert, Felix Klein, Albert Einstein, and herself about
the interpretation of general relativity, between 1915 and 1918: specifically, about the
nature of the conservation equations in GR.10 Noether’s theorem still gives the most
general—and, as I will argue in Section 2—best approach to the gravitational pseudotensor of general relativity and its associated superpotential: which was at the heart of
the debate.
10
For some of the scientific context of Noether’s theorems, including her own biography, see KosmannSchwarzbach (2020: pp. 1-9). A clear exposition of Noether’s theorems in their original form is in Rowe
(1999: pp. 223-226). Norton (1993) is a useful reference about the history of some issues in general
relativity that are complementary to the ones discussed in this Section: in particular, about general
covariance.
6
Since at least 1912, Einstein had been searching for an expression of the laws of gravitation, invariant under general coordinate transformations.11 Already in his (1913: p. 318)
Entwurf paper with Marcel Grossmann, and in his (1914: p. 99) ‘Formal Foundation’
paper, which amongst other things gave a detailed development of tensor calculus and
worked out the geodesic equation, he discussed at length (especially in his 1914) a covariant balance equation for the energy-momentum and stress tensor density, subject to
external forces. When the external forces were set to zero, he got an analogue of the local
conservation law of energy and momentum (pp. 100, 120):
∂µ (Tµ ν + tµ ν ) = 0 .
(1)
Here, T is the energy-momentum tensor density of matter,12 and t is the ‘energy tensor
of the gravitational field’ (later called the gravitational pseudo-tensor), in analogy with
the Christoffel symbols, which are the components of the ‘field strength of the gravitational field’. He gave an explicit expression for tµ ν in terms of the Christoffel symbols
(p. 120) and noted that it is not a tensor, but it is only invariant under linear (i.e. affine)
transformations. At this point, Einstein wrote his tentative field equations explicitly in
terms of the pseudo-tensor. Thus from very early on, the gravitational energy-momentum
pseudo-tensor was, in Einstein’s mind, an important ingredient of the theory that he was
seeking.
In the spring of 1915, Hilbert and Klein invited Noether to Göttingen to work with
them on the implications of the general theory of relativity (Kosmann-Schwarzbach, 2011:
p. 45; Corry, 1999: p. 177).13 Although Noether was probably not an expert on variational
methods (however, Hilbert was an expert on that),14 she was well-acquainted with the
related methods for using formal differential operators to generate algebraic and differential invariants (Rowe 2019: p. 6). Also, shortly after her arrival in 1915, Einstein gave a
series of lectures on general relativity—he was staying at Hilbert’s house during his visit.
Thus by mid-1915, Hilbert himself was working intensely to understand Einstein’s papers.
Early on, Hilbert saw a connection between two topics: (i) the theory of invariants and
geometry, and (ii) the problem of extending the special theory of relativity to general coordinate systems. This was of course a seed for Noether’s theorems (and Hilbert himself
would soon go on to give a special case of Noether’s second theorem). Likewise, Klein
would regard general relativity from the point of view of his Erlangen programme, which
he had laid out with Sophus Lie, of geometry as the search for invariants of a group.15
In two of his papers from November 1915, Einstein gave a very general expression
(1915: p. 784) for the gravitational pseudo-tensor in terms of the Lagrangian density16
and found the correct gravitational field equations (1915b: p. 845).
11
See e.g. Sauer (2005: pp. 806-808) and Kosmann-Schwarzbach (2011: p. 37).
Compare this equation with Eq. (21).
13
For the prehistory of this invitation, see Sauer (1999: p. 539-540). The prehistory of Hilbert’s acquaintance with Einstein is on pp. 527-539.
14
See Sauer (1999: pp. 535, 558, 569).
15
See Rowe (1999: p. 215; 2019a: p. 72) and Kosmann-Schwarzbach (2011: pp. 26, 40, 64).
16
See Eq. (47), which is only a minor generalisation of this equation through the addition of a totalderivative term. However, at this point Einstein’s Lagrangian was incomplete, since its variation gave
only (part of) the the Ricci tensor, rather than the Einstein tensor. A problem in this paper, to which he
returned in (1915a: pp. 799-800), was the incompatibility between his restriction to coordinate systems
12
7
As is well-known, on 20 November 1915, i.e. five days before Einstein submitted the
paper that contained the final form of his field equations (1915b),17 Hilbert submitted
his ‘Die Grundlagen der Physik’, which is an attempt to axiomatise general relativity
(and make a connection with Gustav Mie’s unification programme).18 Hilbert reproduced
Einstein’s field equations from his action and, among other results, he derived the four
contracted Bianchi identities from the invariance of the action under arbitrary transformations of coordinates. Thus in this paper Hilbert derived a special case of Noether’s
second theorem. At this point, however, the nature of these relations was unclear. Even
less clear was the meaning of the ‘energy equation’, based on an ‘energy vector’, that he
derived.19
Noether also began to work on this problem. In 1916, she wrote an unpublished
manuscript in which she studied Hilbert’s energy vector, and used Hilbert’s work to
analyse Einstein’s conservation law in general relativity. Although the manuscript is
not extant, its content is partly known from two sources: namely, the exchange of letters between Klein and Hilbert published in the Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der
Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-Physikalische Klasse, in 1917, and a partial
transcription by R. J. Humm, who studied at Berlin and Göttingen at the time (Rowe
2019, 2019a). In this manuscript, she got the contracted Bianchi identities, and in fact
she anticipated the main points of Klein’s influential lecture of 22 January 1918 for the
Göttingen Gesellschaft.
Einstein (1916a: p. 1111) endorsed Hilbert’s action in another paper, published in
November 1916, and solved the conservation equation, Eq. (1), in terms of what is now
called a ‘superpotential’,20 i.e. a quantity whose divergence is identically zero.21
On 22 January 1918, Klein delivered his famous lecture at the Mathematische Gesellschaft zu Göttingen (i.e. the Göttingen Mathematical Society), which elicited a reaction
from Hilbert one week later (Rowe 1999: p. 212; 2019: p. 8). Klein’s lecture would be
published in the Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, in
the unusual form of an exchange of letters with Hilbert (also, Klein and Hilbert lived a
short distance from one another in the Wilhelm Weber Strasse!).22 In it, he explicitly
acknowledged Noether’s help and her earlier contribution (Kosmann-Schwarzbach, 2011:
√
where −g = 1 and the requirement that the energy-momentum tensor has non-zero trace. The full,
covariant equations without any restrictions on the trace of the energy-momentum tensor appreared in
Einstein (1915b: p. 845).
17
For the now accepted resolution of the priority issue, see Corry et al. (1997: pp. 1271-1273), Sauer
(1999: pp. 539-557), and Renn and Stachel (2007: pp. 872-933).
18
Hilbert’s reference to Mie in the introduction is as follows: ‘I would like to formulate—in the sense
of the axiomatic method—a new system of basic equations of physics, out of two simple axioms, which
are of ideal beauty, and which, I believe, contain the solution of the problems by both Einstein and Mie’
(1915: p. 395; see also pp. 396, 407). For more on Mie’s influence on this paper by Hilbert, see Sauer
(1999: pp. 538, 552-555), Rowe (2019: pp. 5-7), Renn and Stachel (2007: pp. 857-867, 871-874, 899-900),
Corry (1999: p. 176).
19
Hilbert would later rewrite his two ‘Grundlagen der Physik’ papers, (1916) and (1917), publishing
them in sequence in Hilbert (1924).
20
See Eq. (22) below.
21
Such an expression already appeared in Einstein (1914: p. 1077), but this was only for his old theory,
√
in which −g = 1.
22
Klein (1917). For a reason why they chose this unusual form of publication, see Rowe (1999: p. 212).
8
p. 66):
You know that Miss Noether advises me continually regarding my work, and that
in fact it is only thanks to her that I have understood these questions. When I was
speaking recently to Miss Noether about my result concerning your energy vector,
she was able to inform me that she had derived the same result on the basis of
developments of your note... more than a year ago, and that she had then put all of
that in a manuscript (which I was subsequently able to read). She simply did not
set it out as forcefully as I recently did at the Mathematical Society.
Like Noether had done before, Klein compares Hilbert’s energy equation and Einstein’s
conservation law, Eq. (1). Klein’s main point was the disanalogy between Hilbert’s energy equation (and Einstein’s conservation law) and the conservation laws in classical
mechanics. While, in classical mechanics, energy conservation follows as a consequence
of the equations of motion, in general relativity Eq. (1) is an identity, i.e. valid without
requiring the equations of motion to be satisfied. He explained it thus:
Thus the above statement... cannot be regarded analogous to the conservation law
of energy in ordinary mechanics. For when we write the latter as d(T + U )/dt = 0,
this differential equation is not satisfied identically [as the Bianchi identity is], but
only as a consequence of the differential equations of mechanics.
He concluded the note to Hilbert with a sceptical remark: ‘After all this, I can hardly
believe that it is appropriate to characterise the very arbitrarily built quantities tµ ν as
‘energy components of the gravitational field’’. This agreed with Noether’s own view,
which she had explained to Hilbert more than a year before.
In his reply,23 Hilbert completely agreed with Klein’s comments about the lack of an
analogy between the energy equation and conservation of energy in classical mechanics.
He took this one step further, by expressing his belief that no true law of energy conservation exists in general relativity, and claiming that it is possible to prove a theorem
to this effect—to which Klein responds that he ‘would be very interested in seeing the
mathematical proof to which you alluded to in your reply’ (p. 482). Such a proof would
not be provided by Hilbert, but by Noether’s second theorem, in the following year.
Meanwhile, in 1917-1918, Einstein and Klein corresponded about Klein’s (1917) note,
which Einstein (1918: p. 673) praised for its clarity.24 Einstein disagreed that his conservation law for general relativity was an identity, since the equations of motion are used.
To this, Klein (1918a: p. 504) replied by saying that the divergence in Eq. (1) consists of
two terms:25
(1) the divergence of the Einstein field equations;
(2) the divergence of the superpotential.
Klein’s point was that the vanishing of (2) is a mathematical identity, while (1) contains the divergence of the equations of motion, rather than the equations of motion
themselves—and so, that this term is also zero, even before one takes its divergence
23
Klein (1917: p. 477).
For an account of the correspondence, see Rowe (1999: pp. 209-213).
25
This can be seen by expressing the pseudo-tensor t in terms of two contributions: the Einstein tensor
and the superpotential: see Eq. (24) below.
24
9
in the pseudo-tensor. (This differs from classical mechanics, where the equations of
motion, rather than their divergence, appear in the conservation equation). Einstein
(1918a: p. 513) disagreed: for the equations of motion were after all used, and the conservation equation used at least part of the field equations (i.e. their contraction with the
divergence).26
In the winter-spring of 1918, Noether understood the reasons for the difficulties in
the interpretation of the conservation laws of general relativity. What she set out to
investigate was indeed Klein and Hilbert’s central problem of the analogy between the
energy equations of classical mechanics and general relativity. On 23 July 1918, she
presented her work at the Göttingen Mathematical Society. In short, her second theorem
could account for the four identities that Hilbert had pointed out, so that the conservation
laws were ‘improper’, and thus disanalogous to classical mechanics.
Noether had a deeper reason for the difference between general relativity and other
theories: her theorems allowed her to ‘deduce... the proof of an assertion of Hilbert
concerning the relationship between the lack of a proper law of energy and “general
relativity”’ (Kosmann-Schwarzbach, 2011: p. 19). Namely, given an action invariant under
the group of translations, the energy relations are improper iff the action is invariant under
an infinite group which contains the group of translations as a subgroup.27
Thus Noether interpreted her theorems along Hilbertian lines: ‘As Hilbert expresses
his assertion, the lack of a proper energy law constitutes a characteristic of the general
theory of relativity’.
The paper by Klein (1918) clarifies the relationship between Einstein’s and Hilbert’s
theories, and in particular concerning their conservation laws. In this paper, he derives
what Brading and Brown (2003) call the ‘boundary theorem’, from which it follows that
the current is proportional to the field equations (and to the superpotential), so that
its divergence is identically zero—as I already mentioned above. In doing so, he made
essential use of Noether’s work (Kosmann-Schwarzbach, 2011, p. 68):28
I would be remiss if I did not thank Miss Noether once again for her active participation in my new work. She has by herself completely set out in proper form the
mathematical ideas that I use in connection with the physics problems related to
[the action], which will be presented in a note to appear shortly in these Nachrichten.
Thus by 1918, Noether’s theorem was, in the eyes of Hilbert, Klein, and Noether,
the proof that there is no proper conservation law in general relativity: which Klein
interpreted—with Hilbert’s and Noether’s approval, one should add—as the energy equations’ lacking physical content.
I will return to Einstein’s proposal for a conservation law in general relativity, and its
problems, in more detail in Section 1.3. In the next Section, I first illustrate Noether’s
two theorems in a well-known example.
26
The above summary of the argument in Klein (1918a: p. 504) and Einstein (1918, 1918a: p. 513)
follows Brading (2005: p. 126), which indeed seems to me a correct interpretation both of Klein’s letter
and of Einstein’s (1918a: p. 513) reply.
27
Noether’s use of the word ‘subgroup’ here appears to be stronger than the modern use. Her statement
assumes not just the group of translations being a subgroup of an infinite group, but also its being
embedded in a specific way: see Section 2.3. I thank Bartlomiej Czech for pushing me on this point.
28
Klein (1918: p. 189).
10
1.2
Illustrating Noether’s theorems in Maxwell theory
In this paper, I will use the Maxwell theory of electromagnetism as a running example
to illustrate various aspects of Noether’s theorems, since this theory already exemplifies
some of the issues that appear in general relativity.29
Thus let me recall how the theorems work for elementary electromagnetism without
sources: take the following action, defined on Minkowski spacetime:
Z
Z
1
4
S[A] = d x L(A; x) = −
d4 x Fµν F µν
4
Fµν := ∂µ Aν − ∂ν Aµ .
(2)
The field equations, derived by setting the variation of the action to zero, are of course:
∂ν F µν = 0 .
(3)
I will give Noether’s theorems in general form in Section 2. I here give the specific cases
that apply to Maxwell theory.
Noether’s first theorem asserts that the conservation of the energy-momentum tensor
density Tµν follows from the global translational symmetry of the action in Minkowski
spacetime (and vice versa), i.e. under a constant translation δxµ = ǫµ .30 Defining the
variation
δAµ := A′µ (x) − Aµ (x) = −ǫν ∂ν Aµ ,
(4)
Noether’s first theorem then gives:
T µ ν := δνµ L −
1
∂L
∂ν Aλ = F µλ ∂ν Aλ − δνµ F λσ Fλσ .
∂(∂µ Aλ )
4
(5)
One readily finds the following conservation law:
Eq. (3)
∂µ T µ ν = ∂µ F µλ ∂ν Aλ = 0 .
(6)
The term between brackets vanishes only if the equations of motion, Eq. (3), are satisfied:
and thus the energy-momentum is conserved if and only if (a linear combination of) the
equations of motion are satisfied, i.e. it is a weak conservation law.
29
For an introduction to Noether’s theorem for a physics audience, see e.g. Bañados et al. (2016). For
a mathematical treatment, see Olver (1986: pp. 272-283, 334-336). Bessel-Hagen (1921: pp. 44-51) was
the first to apply Noether’s first theorem to electrodynamics, using the generalised theorem involving
quasi-symmetries. He credits Klein (p. 33) with suggesting the problem: ‘Klein expressed a desire that
Miss Emmy Noether’s theorems on invariant variational problems, proved approximately two years ago,
should be applied to the Maxwell equations’. I thank Harvey Brown for recommending the work by
Bessel-Hagen.
30
Under such a translation, we have a new field A′µ (x′ ), where x′ = x + ǫ, and A′µ (x′ ) is related to
Aµ (x) by the usual tensor transformation rule for the components of one-forms, linearised in ǫ. In the
variation, we evaluate A′µ at x.
11
Notice that the first term in the energy-momentum tensor Eq. (5) is not gauge invariant
(it is also not symmetric in its two indices upon lowering one of them).31 This lack
of gauge invariance is unsurprising, given that we used a variation of the Lagrangian,
Eq. (4), that is not gauge invariant. One can get a gauge-invariant energy-momentum
tensor by constructing a gauge-invariant variation of the gauge potential, A: namely, by
allowing this variation to contain a gauge transformation, i.e. δAµ = −ǫν ∂ν Aµ + ∂µ λ,
where λ is the gauge parameter. There is a unique gauge-invariant variation of this form,
viz. δAµ = Fµν ǫν , where λ = ǫν Aν . In effect, this adds an ‘improvement term’ to the
energy-momentum tensor, i.e. a term that is a total derivative in an antisymmetric tensor
U , without modifying the equations of motion, such that the energy-momentum tensor is
still conserved:32
T ′µ ν := T µ ν + ∂λ U [µλ] ν .
(7)
The above variation gives U [µλ] ν = −F µλ Aν , which brings the energy-momentum tensor
to the standard form, and is automatically symmetric in its indices:
T ′µ ν = F µλ Fνλ −
1 µ λσ
δ F Fλσ .
4 ν
(8)
This is of course the energy-momentum tensor that also appears on the right-hand side
of the Einstein field equations. (Thus general relativity uniquely detects the energymomentum tensor of its sources: it fixes the improvement term.)
Noether’s second theorem is also exemplified by the Maxwell theory,33 which has a
local gauge symmetry:
Aµ 7→ Aµ + ∂µ λ ,
(9)
for an arbitrary smooth function λ : R4 → R. Indeed, since Fµν is itself invariant under
this symmetry, the Maxwell action is trivially invariant.
It is instructive to study the gauge invariance when we couple Maxwell’s action to a
gauge-invariant source Jµ :
Z
1
4
µν
µ
S[A, J] = d x − Fµν F + J Aµ ,
(10)
4
and require that the action is invariant up to a boundary term that does not modify the
equations of motion, so that the transformed action gives the same equations of motion
as the action Eq. (10).
The variation of this action under the gauge symmetry, Eq. (9), gives:
Z
Z
Z
4
4
µ
µ
δλ S[A, J] = d x J ∂µ λ = d x ∂µ (J λ) − d4 x (∂µ J µ ) λ ,
(11)
31
Goldberg (1958: pp. 315, 319) discusses the desirability of symmetry for the discussion of angular
momentum. See also Barbashov and Nesterenko (1983: p. 559-560).
32
Improvement terms go back to Belinfante (1938: p. 888). See also Anderson (1967: p. 273).
33
For a discussion of Noether’s theorems for Maxwell theory coupled to a complex scalar field, see
Barbashov and Nesterenko (1983: pp. 550-552) and Sus (2017: pp. 273-274).
12
where in the last step I used partial integration. The first integral on the right contains
a total derivative, which integrates to a boundary term. Although physics texts often
require that λ has compact support so that it vanishes at infinity and this boundary term
is zero,34 this is not necessary. For, as we will see in Section 2, Noether’s theorem can
be generalised to admit a variation of the action with a non-zero boundary term, because
such a term does not modify the equations of motion. Thus this term does not need to be
zero and we simply keep it. The second term must be zero if the action is to be invariant
up to a boundary term, which requires that the source is conserved:
∂µ J µ = 0 .
(12)
Writing this out in components gives the equation for the local conservation of charge:
∂ρ
+∇·J=0 .
∂t
(13)
Integrating over the volume V , bounded by the two-surface S = ∂V with outward pointing
unit vector n̂, gives the time derivative of the total charge QV enclosed by the volume:
Z
dQV
d
d3 x ρ (t, x)
=
dt
dt V
Z
Z
Eq. (13)
3
=
−
d x ∇ · J = − d2 x n̂ · J = −IS ,
(14)
V
S
where in the second line I used Gauss’ theorem. IS is the current flowing out of the
boundary S, so that this equation expresses the conservation of charge in the volume: if
the charge in V decreases, it is carried away through the boundary by a current IS , and
vice versa.
Thus, although gauge invariance is trivially satisfied by the purely electromagnetic
part of the action, it implies a physical constraint on the gauge-invariant source J to
which it is coupled; the Maxwell theory can only be consistently coupled to a conserved
current (I will return to this at the end of Section 2.2).
I will now make a point that will recur in general relativity, and which was important
in the discussions between Noether, Hilbert, Klein and Einstein, reviewed in Section 1.1.
It is sometimes said that local gauge symmetry is a “mere redundancy”, a consequence
of our reformulation of the electomagnetic fields E and B in terms of the gauge potential
Aµ with no physical significance. However, it is not true that gauge symmetry has no
physical significance. If it did not, it would indeed be very surprising that it could entail
the local charge conservation law Eq. (12).
The point is that the local gauge symmetry reduces the number of physical degrees of
freedom of the gauge potential Aµ from three to two, thus leaving a field that only has
transverse polarisations. Physically, the freedom to do a gauge transformation secures that
the longitudinal polarisation of the photon does not contribute to any of the quantities that
are usually deemed physical. This is of course crucial to get the correct phenomenology of
the photon. Thus, despite the fact that a choice of gauge does not fix anything physical,
34
See e.g. Maggiore (2005: p. 69).
13
gauge invariance does have physical content: it secures the correct number of degrees of
freedom for the photon.
Recent discussions have also concluded that the alleged lack of physical significance of
the conservation laws derived from the second theorem, as claimed by Klein (see Section
1.1), is misleading. For example, Brading and Brown (2003: p. 99) have emphasised
that symmetry transformations, such as local gauge symmetries, do have an empirical
significance, because they restrict the kinds of terms that can appear in the action and
in the equations of motion.35 Indeed, as the above already shows, imposing local gauge
symmetry implies, through Noether’s theorem, that Maxwell theory can only be coupled
to a conserved current.
Before we proceed, let us recall how one normally gets an expression analogous to the
charge conservation law, Eq. (14), for energy and momentum conservation in general
relativity. Such an expression can be derived in the presence of spacetime symmetries, in
particular in spacetimes with timelike Killing vectors K:36
∇ µ Kν + ∇ ν Kµ = 0 .
(15)
The idea here is to derive an analogue of the charge conservation equation Eq. (14) for
energy and momentum, starting from the covariant analogue of the energy and momentum
conservation equation:
∇µ T µ ν = 0 .
(16)
If K is a timelike Killing vector satisfying Eq. (15), then we can define a vector current
P µ := T µν Kν , such that:
∇µ P µ = ∇µ (T µν Kν ) = (∇µ T µν ) Kν + T µν (∇µ Kν )
Eqs. (15),(16)
=
0,
(17)
where in the last equality I used the fact that T µν is symmetric, and then used Eq. (15)
to set this term to zero. We can now readily apply to P the divergence theorem for a
35
More precisely, they admit that local gauge symmetries can have indirect, but not direct, empirical
significance, i.e. as in Galileo’s ship-type scenarios. While, in the philosophical literature, it is widely
recognised that global gauge (i.e. internal) symmetries applied to subsystems can have direct empirical
significance thus understood, there is a debate about whether local gauge symmetries can have such
significance. Early work by Kosso (2000: pp. 95, 97), Brading and Brown (2004: pp. 656-657), and
Healey (2009) stated that local gauge (internal) symmetries have no direct empirical significance, but
only indirect empirical significance (e.g. through Noether’s theorems). Their reasons for this are diverse—
e.g. for Brading and Brown, it is only ‘relative system transformations’ (i.e. subsystem transformations),
but not local gauge symmetries, that have direct empirical significance. More recently, Greaves and
Wallace (2014), and Teh (2016) have argued that local gauge symmetries, applied to subsystems, can
have a direct empirical significance, through Galileo’s ship-type scenarios. I will return to the discussion
of the empirical significance of local symmetries, in the context of general relativity, in Section 4.3.
For a characterisation of gauge symmetries as transformations that only alter the description, but not
the physical system itself, see e.g. Horský and Novotný (1969: p. 420). For a more general discussion
of symmetries in terms of ‘redundant structure’, see e.g. Ismael and van Fraassen (2003: pp. 378-380),
Caulton (2015: p. 156-158), and Belot (2013: p. 2).
36
I will discuss the general case in Section 3. Also, this equation can be relaxed to a conformal Killing
equation, as in Eq. (63) below.
14
d-dimensional region of space(time) Σ with boundary ∂Σ:
Z
Z
Z
√
d √
d
µ
µν
d x −g ∇µ P =
0=
d x ∂µ ( −g T Kµ ) =
Σ
Σ
dd−1 x
∂Σ
√
−h nµ P µ ,
(18)
where g is the metric on Σ, h is the induced metric on ∂Σ, and n is the unit vector normal
to ∂Σ.37
Here, the Killing vector is important because it allows us to construct the vector
quantity P µ from the tensor T µ ν . For, while Eq. (16) does not give rise to a partial
derivative that can be integrated (because it has one free index), the vanishing covariant
divergence of P in Eq. (17), which has no free indices, does allow for this, in Eq. (18).
The result is a conservation law that is completely analogous to charge conservation in
the Maxwell theory, as I will now show.
Take Σ to be a three-dimensional spacelike volume V with two-boundary S, and write
out the index µ = (0, i) in terms of timelike and spatial components, with coordinates xi
that cover the whole boundary surface S, but are otherwise arbitrary:
Z
Z
Z
√
√
1d
3 √
µν
0ν
d x −g T Kν + d2 x h N ni T iν Kν = 0 .
(19)
∂µ ( −g T Kµ ) =
c dt V
S
V
Here, N is the lapse function, and h is the induced metric on S. In the last term, I used
the divergence theorem Eq. (18) applied to V with
√ boundary S, to give the integral over
the surface S of the momentum density, PS = h N ni T iν Kν , through the boundary S.
The first term in the middle expression is the time derivative of the energy associated
√
with the region V , with energy density: EV = −g T 0ν Kν . Thus the expression can be
rewritten as:
1 dEV
= −PS ,
c dt
(20)
where EV is the total energy in V and PS is the integrated momentum flux through S.
This is analogous to the charge conservation law, Eq. (14). Notice that this interpretation
is possible thanks to the presence of a timelike Killing vector K in the spacetime, which
defines the energy. As we will see in Section 1.3, in the absence of Killing vectors, defining
an analogous expression is problematic.
1.3
Einstein’s proposal, and five problems for energy and momentum in GR
Having illustrated Noether’s theorems in the example of Maxwell theory, I return, in
this Section, to Einstein’s idea of energy and momentum conservation laws in general
relativity.38 I will begin by listing five problems that are prima facie associated with this
notion.39
√
√
After the second equality sign, I used: g ∇µ P µ = ∂µ ( g P µ ). For an overview of integration on
manifolds, see Wald (1984: pp. 430-434) and Landsman (2020: pp. 133-135).
38
Janssen and Renn (2007: pp. 842, 844) note that Einstein (1916a: p. 1115) is an instantiation of
Noether’s second theorem, predating the theorem itself.
39
See for example the discussion in Horký and Novotný (1969: pp. 426-430).
37
15
The first problem is the one that motivated Noether’s research into invariance and
symmetries: namely, Klein’s, Hilbert’s and Noether’s view that:
(i) Energy and momentum conservation laws in GR are improper, i.e. identities with
no physical content. This is a special property of the notion of energy in general relativity,
and prompts the question whether this is the correct interpretation of Noether’s theorem.
It also bears on the conceptual relation between energy in general relativity and in classical
mechanics. (I will return to the resolution of this problem at the end of Section 2, after I
discuss Noether’s theorem).
In the literature, two further problems about the physical consequences of Noether’s
second theorem for general relativity have been discussed. Both concern the interpretation
of the energy-momentum tensor:
(ii) When general relativity is coupled to matter, the Bianchi identity implies the
analogue of the conservation law, Eq. (16). But T µ ν is the energy-momentum tensor of
matter, rather than of the gravitational field. So, the question is what is the definition of
the energy and momentum of the gravitational field itself?40
(iii) The conservation law, Eq. (16), is not a conservation law in the usual sense. For
the energy-momentum tensor cannot be straightforwardly integrated over space to give a
conserved vector current (though this can be done if there is a Killing vector, as we saw
in Eqs. (17)-(18)).41 Namely, this equation contains two additional terms that depend
on the connection, i.e. it is not a pure derivative like the expression Eq. (12) for charge
conservation in Minkowski space.42 This suggests the question of the correct interpretation
of the putative conservation law Eq. (16).
Einstein’s (1913, 1914, 1915, 1915a, 1916a) idea to solve these problems was to use
the particular form of the Christoffel symbols that appear in the covariant analogue of
the conservation law for matter, Eq. (16), and to reinterpret the extra terms as a gravitational contribution to the energy and momentum. So, one can try to construct an
energy-momentum tensor for gravitation from the Christoffel symbols—viz. introduce a
pseudotensor tµ ν such that the conservation law contains an ordinary derivative. This can
be done by defining tµ ν so that Eq. (16) takes the form of a total derivative:
√
∂ µ ( g T µ ν + tµ ν ) = 0 .
(21)
As I already discussed in Section 1.1, Einstein interpreted tµ ν as a ‘gravitational energymomentum tensor’ density. One can associate with this tensor a superpotential, U µλ ν ,
40
Even though the energy-momentum tensor will have this property for any field theory in a curved
spacetime, there is a specific problem to GR here: namely, how to define the energy and momentum of
the gravitational field from its dynamical principles.
41
Note that this is not an exclusive property of general relativity, since it holds for the covariant
divergence of the energy-momentum tensor in any field theory on a curved spacetime. However, in
general relativity, because the gravitational field is dynamical, Eq. (16) can be reinterpreted in terms of
the gravitational energy-momentum pseudo-tensor tµ ν , as we will discuss.
42
In particular, in Eq. (18), it is possible to replace the covariant derivative in the first expression
by the partial derivative in the middle expression because we have the covariant divergence of a vector
quantity, P µ . If we had simply integrated the covariant divergence of the tensor T µ ν , this would pick up
additional terms involving the connection and it would not give a boundary term. This is also the origin
of the extra term tµ ν , in Eq. (21) below.
16
such that:
√
g T µ ν + tµ ν = ∂λ U µλ ν ,
∂µ ∂λ U µλ ν = 0 .
(22)
Einstein (1916a: p. 244) obtained the superpotential from an action that differs from the
Einstein-Hilbert action by a boundary term.
Freud’s (1939) expression for the superpotential is different from Einstein’s, namely:
√
µλγ
U µλ ν = − g g βσ Γαβγ δασν
,
(23)
µλγ
which automatically satisfies Eq. (22), because the symbol δασν
is totally antisymmetric in
its upper (and lower) indices. Another well-known expression is e.g. Landau and Lifschitz’s
(1971: p. 306)43 pseudo-tensor (see also Bergmann, 1958: p. 289).
However, even if Einstein’s strategy appears to solve the two previous problems, (ii)(iii), of finding an expression for the energy and momentum of the gravitational field,
and of recasting Eq. (16) with an ordinary derivative, so that we can integrate to get a
conserved charge, it does so at the expense of introducing two new challenges:44
(iv) Non-uniqueness: the ability to add an arbitrary superpotential U to the pseudotensor means that the pseudotensor is not unique (I have so far mentioned three expressions: Einstein’s, Freud’s, and Landau and Lifschitz’s).45 In fact, there are an infinite
number of pseudo-tensors compatible with Eq. (21). For define a gravitational (i.e. matterindependent) pseudo-tensor with an arbitrary superpotential:
tµ ν := −
1√ µ
g G ν + ∂λ U µλ ν ,
κ
(24)
where κ = 8πGN /c4 , and Gµ ν is the Einstein tensor. Provided U is antisymmetric in its
upper indices,
U µλ ν = U [µλ] ν
(see e.g. the Freud expression, Eq. (23)), the gravitational pseudo-tensor thus defined
automatically satisfies the conservation law Eq. (21) when the Einstein field equations
are satisfied:46
Thus the definition of the pseudo-tensor, Eq. (24), is ambiguous. Nester (2004: p. 264)
summarises the problem thus: ‘there is no physical meaning here, only formal math—
unless one has a good criterion for choosing the superpotential’. In my opinion, this is a
serious problem that defenders of pseudo-tensors need to solve.
(v) Lack of covariance, and lack of appropriate transformation properties: the pseudotensor is not a tensor, as can be seen from its definition in Eq. (21). For example, it
43
For a critique of the Landau-Lifshitz pseudo-tensor, see Goldberg (1958: pp. 316, 320) and Ohanian
(2010: p. 10).
44
These concerns can be found e.g. in Hoefer (2000: pp. 191-195). My (iv) corresponds to Duerr’s
(2019a: Section 3.2) label (H2), and my (v) to his (H1). I will return to Duerr’s objections in Section 6.2.
45
Horký and Novotný (1969: pp. 426-430) is an enlightening review of various approaches. See also
Komar’s (1958: pp. 935-936) expressions.
46
The expression that Einstein obtained was not antisymmetric: for a discussion, see Chen et
al. (2017: p. 12).
17
can be made to vanish at any given point in appropriately chosen coordinates.47 It is only
invariant under affine transformations.
Thus Klein (1917) concluded: ‘After all this, I can barely believe that it is useful to
designate [Einstein’s] very arbitrarily built quantities tµ ν as the components of the energy
of the gravitational field.’ Schrödinger (1950: p. 104) called the gravitational pseudotensor a ‘sham tensor’. Twenty-three years later, Misner, Thorne, Wheeler (1973, p. 467)
wrote:
Anyone who looks for a magic formula for “local gravitational energy-momentum”
is looking for the right answer to the wrong question. Unhappily, enormous time
and effort were devoted in the past to trying to “answer this question” before investigators realized the futility of the enterprise.
So, we have a strong warning from these authors that we should avoid looking for a
general local expression for the energy and momentum of the gravitational field.
As I will mention in Section 5.2, beyond the lack of covariance, the problem is also that
the pseudo-tensor does not have well-defined transformation properties: for example, it
is not a geometric object, in the sense of Anderson (1967: pp. 14-16, 424), Kucharzewski
and Kuczma (1964: pp. 15-18), and Trautman (1965: p. 84-87):48 i.e. roughly, such that
its components in a given coordinate system, together with suitable transformation properties, are well-defined.49 See the discussion in Pitts (2010: pp. 603-604, 606) and Duerr
(2019a: Section 3.3).
In Section 3, I will propose a solution of the non-uniqueness problem (iv) based on
an extension of Noether’s theorem. Although the facts that I will use are known to the
experts, I have not found this solution discussed in any detail in the literature on Noether’s
theorems that I studied—not as a solution of the alleged problem of non-uniqueness. In
Section 5.1, I will discuss a recent related proposal. In Section 5.2, I will assess how
this approach deals with problem (iii) (in particular, the problem of the need for Killing
vectors or similar structures) and with problem (v), i.e. covariance.
Penrose (1982) made a new proposal to solve (ii) that does not require a local expression for the energy and momentum, thereby circumventing problems (iii)-(v), because he
did not use the gravitational energy-momentum pseudo-tensor or other local expressions.
He argued that one can still define quasi-local energy-momentum and angular momentum, i.e. energy and momentum that are associated with a closed spacelike surface. It
refers only to the geometry of the two-surface and the extrinsic curvature quantities for
its embedding in the spacetime (Penrose, 1988: p. 1). The idea has been widely accepted,
and developed in various ways, in the literature on general relativity.50 I will return to it
in Section 4, when I discuss the Brown-York quasi-local stress-energy tensor.
47
This argument was put forward to Einstein by Schrödinger and Bauer: for details, see Horký and
Novotný (1969: p. 430). See the responses by Pitts (2010: p. 613) and Duerr (2019: p. 8).
48
See also Nijenhuis (1952: pp. 23-30), Schouten (1954: p. 67-68), and Bergmann (1958: p. 287).
49
As Trautman (1965: p. 86) mentions, spinors are not geometric objects either. In Section 6.1 I will
explain what appears to be the real worry.
50
For some of the properties that the quasi-local energy should (presumably) have, and its relation
to other definitions of energy such as the asymptotic ADM mass (for asymptotically flat spacetime
regions) and Bondi mass (for asymptotically null regions), see for example Jaramillo and Gourgoulhon
(2011: pp. 97-102, 105-107) and Christodoulou and Yau (1988: pp. 9-10).
18
2
Noether’s Theorems and the Energy-Momentum
Tensor
In this Section, I give Noether’s first theorem (Section 2.1), her second theorem (Section
2.2), and I discuss two consequences (Section 2.3) that, in my opinion, have not been
sufficiently clarified in the literature.
2.1
Noether’s first theorem
Noether’s first theorem is a statement about the invariance of an action of the form:51
Z
S[φ; x] = d4 x L(φ; x) ,
(25)
where φ is the set of fields present in the problem (labelled by a, so one writes φa if
one wishes to indicate this) under an infinitesimal transformation of the dependent andor independent variables, up to a boundary term.52 The physical significance of this
invariance of the action up to boundary term is that the equations of motion derived from
the new action, expressed in the new variables, will take the same form as in the old ones.
Following Brading and Brown (2003: pp. 91-97), on which the exposition in this Section
is largely based,53 I take the invariance to mean that, when the equations of motion are
satisfied, the action is form-invariant up to a boundary term that depends on an arbitrary
vector quantity Λµ :
Z
Z
Z
4 ′
4
′
′
′
′
δS = S[φ ; x ] − S[φ; x] = d x L(φ , x ) − d x L(φ, x) = d4 x ∂µ Λµ .
(26)
Such a transformation, which leaves the action invariant up to a boundary term, is called
a ‘quasi-symmetry’.54
Noether’s first theorem states that, if the action Eq. (25) is invariant with respect to
a continuous group of transformations Gn that is generated by n constant parameters ξ k
(where k = 1, . . . , n), in the sense just indicated, then there are n linearly independent
combinations of the field equations that are equal to the total divergence of a current, as
follows:
X ∂L
∂L
(27)
ηak = ∂µ Jkµ .
− ∂µ
∂φa
∂(∂µ φa )
a
51
For the connection between symmetries and conservation laws without the appeal of Lagrangian
methods, see Brown (2020: p. 3).
52
This boundary term was not included in Noether’s paper, and so this is a slight generalisation of
her two theorems, first proven by Bessel-Hagen (1921: p. 36), who attributes it directly to Noether: ‘I
owe this generalization to an oral communication from Emmy Noether’. See also Kosmann-Schwarzbach
(2020: p. 11) and Brown (2020: pp. 6, 8). This generalisation is standardly used in e.g. Brading and
Brown (2003: p. 93) and Bañados and Reyes (2016: p. 17).
53
For other treatments of Noether’s theorems, closely related to the one given here, see Trautman
(1962: pp. 176-179), Horský and Novotný (1969: pp. 420-424), Barbashov and Nesterenko (1983: pp. 541544), Kastrup (1987: pp. 116-117), and Brading and Brown (2000: pp. 4-8).
54
Echoing Bessel-Hagen (1921: p. 36), Olver (1986: p. 278) calls them ‘divergence symmetries’. See
also Kosmann-Schwarzbach (2020: p. 11).
19
Since the index k labels the n generators of Gn , there is one such equation for each
generator. The index a labels the various fields present in the problem, and ηak is a
field-dependent expression, defined by the variation of the fields:
δξ φa = ηak ξ k .
The current is given by the following expression:
X ∂L ∂δφa
∂δxµ ∂Λµ
Jkµ = −
−
L
+ k .
k
k
∂(∂
φ
)
∂ξ
∂ξ
∂ξ
µ
a
a
(28)
(29)
The converse is also true: if the field equations satisfy Eq. (27), then this implies the
invariance of the action under the corresponding group Gn . The theorem remains valid
in the limiting case of an infinite number of parameters, n → ∞.
The above current is weakly conserved, since the left-hand side of Eq. (27) is a linear
combination of the Euler-Lagrange field equations for φ.
Example: Maxwell theory. Let us illustrate the above for Maxwell theory, familiar
from Section 1.2.55 Thus we take the group generated by ξ k to be the group of constant
spacetime translations. Since A is a vector field, the index a labelling the different fields
can be taken to be the spacetime index µ of the vector field components Aµ . Since ξ k is
the generator of translations, ξ is also a vector field in Minkowski space, and the index
k = 1, . . . , n, labelling the generators, is also a spacetime index, ν = 1, . . . , 4. Thus
the group G4 here under consideration is the group of constant spacetime translations
generated by δxµ = ǫµ .
To see how ηak depends on the vector field A, we temporarily write it as ηµν (not
to be confused with the Minkowski metric!), and compare the general variation Eq. (28)
with the variation of the gauge field Eq. (4) (which is obtained by expanding the field
components Aµ in terms of the constant coefficients, δxµ = ǫµ ). The comparison gives
ηµν = −∂ν Aµ .
Let us check that the Noether current Eq. (29) reproduces the energy-momentum
µ
tensor of electromagnetism, Eq. (5). Since δxµ = ǫµ , we have ∂δx
= δνµ . The last term
∂ǫν
ηλν = ∂(∂∂L
∂ν Aλ = −F µλ ∂ν Aλ . Thus
in Eq. (29) is zero, and the first term is − ∂(∂∂L
µ Aλ )
µ Aλ )
we get Jνµ = −F µλ ∂ν Aλ − L δνµ = −T µ ν , i.e. the energy-momentum tensor Eq. (5). The
Noether current conservation equation Eq. (27) of course reproduces Eq. (6).
We can repeat this for the gauge-invariant variation δAµ = Fµν ǫν leading to the energymomentum tensor with the improvement term, i.e. Eq. (7). Comparing this variation
with Eq. (28), we find that ηµν = Fµν . Evaluating the current Eq. (29), we indeed get
Jνµ = −T ′µ ν , i.e. we reproduce the standard energy-momentum tensor, Eq. (8).
2.2
Noether’s second theorem and the boundary theorem
In this Section, I will give Noether’s second theorem and the identities that it implies.
I will follow the terminology in Brading and Brown (2003: pp. 100-104), who distinguish a set of formulas that they call the ‘boundary theorem’, due to Klein (1918), from
55
Noether’s theorems for Yang-Mills theory are discussed in Barbashov and Nesterenko (1983: pp. 552556).
20
Noether’s second theorem. (I will occasionally refer to both sets of formulas, collectively,
as ‘Noether’s second theorem’, since both are entailed by Noether’s general expression for
the invariance of the action under a continuous group).
The boundary theorem and Noether’s second theorem, in generalised form, assume
that the action Eq. (25) is invariant (up to a boundary term) with respect to a continuous
group of transformations G∞n that is generated by n arbitrary functions ξ k (x) (k =
1, . . . , n).
Before giving the theorems, it will be useful to introduce three important pieces of
notation. I use the Einstein summation convention for repeated indices a and, below, also
for repeated k indices:
∂L
∂L
− ∂µ
∂φa
∂(∂µ φa )
∂δxµ ∂Λµ
∂L ∂δφa
−
L
+ k
:= −
∂(∂µ φa ) ∂ξ k
∂ξ k
∂ξ
µ
∂Λ
∂L
µ
:=
+
γak
.
∂(∂ν φa )
∂(∂ν ξ k )
E a :=
(30)
Jkµ
(31)
Ukµν
(32)
The quantities here defined are, respectively, the Euler-Lagrange equations of motion, the
ν
Noether current, and the superpotential (more on this later). γak
is a (field-dependent)
µ
variation of the field, to be defined below. Λ is a boundary term that may appear in the
variation of the action, Eq. (26). Notice that we can also apply Noether’s theorem to a
single term in (i.e. to a part of) the action, to require the invariance of that particular
term. In that case, for example, E a is simply the functional variation of that term in the
action with respect to the fields φa , and likewise for the other two quantities.
Using this notation, Noether’s first theorem takes a particularly simple form:
E a ηak = ∂µ Jkµ .
(33)
ν
The expression γak
in Eq. (32), together with ηak , are the (field-dependent) variations
of the field with respect to ξ and its first derivative (repeated k indices are again summed
over) relevant to Noether’s second theorem and her boundary theorem:
µ
δφa = ηak (φ; x) ξ k (x) + γak
(φ; x) ∂µ ξ k (x).
(34)
This variation is analogous to Eq. (28), where the second term is non-zero because in
Noether’s second theorem ξ is a function of x.
The boundary theorem, with this notation, takes the following simple form:
µ
∂µ (E a γak
) = ∂µ Jkµ
µ
= Jkµ − ∂ν Ukµν
E a γak
Ukµν = −Ukνµ .
(35)
(36)
(37)
Again, the index k = 1, . . . , n labels the functions ξ k (x) that generate G∞n , and so there
is one such equation for each generator. Note that the first equation here follows from
21
the second and third.56
Noether’s second theorem reads:
µ
E a ηak = ∂µ (E a γak
)
(38)
Again, the full statement is that, if the action Eq. (25) is invariant under the group G∞n of
variations as indicated, then the Euler-Lagrange equations satisfy the identities Eq. (38).
The converse statement is here also valid.
Notice that both the boundary theorem and Noether’s second theorem, Eqs. (35)-(38),
take forms that differ from Noether’s first theorem Eq. (33). However, it is possible to
derive Noether’s first theorem, which is the special case that the continuous group of
transformations Gn is a subgroup of G∞n , i.e. Gn ⊂ G∞n . In this case, the generators ξ k
of Gn are constant, and the corresponding second term in Eq. (34) vanishes. Combining
the first of Eq. (35) with Eq. (38), we recover Noether’s first theorem, Eq. (33), with the
k generators thus identified.
Example: Maxwell theory. It will be instructive to compare with our previous notation
and reproduce the conservation law of Maxwell’s action coupled to a gauge-invariant
source, Eq. (10). The gauge symmetry modifies the field A as: δAµ = ∂µ λ. Since λ is a
function of x, Noether’s second theorem is relevant here. Comparing with Eq. (34), since
there is a single generator, namely λ, we see that k = 1 and ξ = λ (and thus, we can
drop the index k). As before, the index a is a spacetime index, a = ν. Further, δAµ only
depends on λ’s derivative and not on λ itself, so ηµ = 0 and γνµ = δνµ . In particular, this
means that there is no non-trivial subgroup of transformations with constant parameters
in this case, and so no Noether first theorem for the gauge transformations. Also, recall,
from Eq. (11), that the Rvariation of the action was zero up to a boundary term, i.e. a term
with a total derivative d4 x ∂µ Λµ . We find that Λ is given by:
Λµ = J µ λ .
(39)
This confirms my claim in Section 1.2 that, with this generalised form of Noether’s theorem, the gauge parameter λ does not need to be zero at the boundary. It is straightforward
to check the boundary theorem and Noether’s second theorem, Eqs. (35)-(38). For the
quantities defined in Eqs. (30) and (32), we get the following expressions:
E µ = J µ − ∂ν F µν
U µν = F µν .
(40)
The first equation is of course the expression for the Euler-Lagrange equation derived
from the action Eq. (10).
With these expressions in hand, it is straightforward to verify that the boundary
theorem, i.e. Eqs. (35)-(37), is trivially satisfied, given the anti-symmetry of the field
56
My notation, using the Einstein convention for the three different types of indices, also corrects errors
in Brading and Brown (2003: pp. 92, 95, 97, 101) here and in their equation corresponding to my Eq. (29),
where summation signs over a (i.e. their i) are incorrectly extended to terms that contain no index a.
22
tensor. Interestingly, the left-hand side of the expression from Noether’s second theorem,
Eq. (38), is zero (because η is zero), and so Noether’s second theorem takes the form
∂µ E µ = 0. Given the anti-symmetry of the field tensor, this is identically satisfied iff J is
conserved, independent of the satisfaction of the equations of motion of Maxwell theory.
Thus imposing gauge symmetry implies, through Noether’s theorem, that Maxwell theory
can only be coupled to a conserved current J.
2.3
Two consequences of Noether’s second theorem
I will first make a comment that I have not found in the literature on Noether’s theorems,
although it may well be known to the experts.57 These remarks are made visible by the
simplified notation above, and they will bear on the question of energy and momentum
conservation discussed in the next Section. Then I will answer Klein’s critique of the local
energy-momentum conservation law in GR.
The superpotential is fixed, through Noether’s theorem, by the boundary
terms. In studies of Noether’s theorem in connection with general relativity, emphasis is
often laid on the integration of Eq. (35) (see Brading and Brown, 2003: p. 102), as follows:
µ
+ ∂ν Ukµν ,
Jkµ = E a γak
(41)
where Ukµν is an arbitrarily chosen superpotential, analogous to the one in Eq. (24), whose
divergence is automatically zero:
∂µ ∂ν Ukµν = 0 .
(42)
Indeed, this is how Einstein himself arrived at his result, Eq. (24), for the gravitational
pseudo-tensor.
However, note that Noether’s theorem gives us, in Eq. (36), an expression for the
current that is not arbitrary but fixed:
µ
Jkµ = E a γak
+ ∂ν Ukµν ,
57
(43)
For example, Barbashov and Nesterenko (1993: p. 562) mention, for the specific energy-momentum
(pseudo-)tensors considered by Einstein and by Lorentz, that they are related by a total derivative, and
so lead to the same equations of motion. But, a few paragraphs later, they categorise the non-uniqueness
of the pseudo-tensor as a “difficulty”, without mentioning the relevance of their previous remark, nor
noting that the pseudo-tensor is unique after fixing the boundary terms of the action. Likewise, Ohanian
(2010: p. 10) has a formula for the pseudo-tensor in terms of the gravitational action, but he drops a
total derivative term from it, and he does not comment on the effect of the dropped boundary term on
the pseudo-tensor. Similar comments apply to Goldberg (1958: p. 318), Bergmann (1958: p. 288), Komar
(1958: pp. 934-935), Trautman (1962: pp. 171, 174, 190-191), and Horský-Novotný (1969: pp. 425-427),
all of whom explicitly survey and compare different expressions for the pseudo-tensor, mention the lack of
uniqueness and sometimes propose a criterion for fixing a unique expression, but fail to mention the most
obvious criterion: namely, that of fixing the boundary terms. That the superpotential is fixed, through
Noether’s theorem, by the choice boundary terms of the action, seems implicit in Wald (1993: p. 3429),
but he does not discuss or mention the gravitational pseudo-tensor or the superpotential at all. In Sections
3 and 4.2, I will further comment on the physical significance of fixing the boundary terms.
23
where U is given by Eq. (32). Since U is antisymmetric in its upper indices, it indeed
satisfies Eq. (42).58
The compatibility of Eqs. (41) and (43) requires that we must have:59 Ukµν = Ukµν .
Since U was defined in Eq. (32), and the boundary theorem depends on its having this
exact form, this means that the superpotential is not arbitrary, but is fixed through
Eq. (32).
How exactly is the superpotential fixed by Noether’s theorem? The first term in
Eq. (32) is fixed by the choice of the Lagrangian density and of the variation of the field.
The second term (depending on Λµ ) is fixed by the boundary term that appears in the
variation of the action. This means that Noether’s theorem determines the superpotential,
U , once the action and its first variation are fixed.
In the next Section, I will return to the physical interpretation of this result, and to
how it solves the problem (iv) of non-uniqueness in general relativity from Section 1.1.
A response to the Hilbert-Klein-Noether critique. The above also casts light on
the Klein-Hilbert worry, problem (i) from Section 1.3, that energy and momentum conservation laws in GR are identities that do not require using the Einstein field equations, and
hence they lack physical content. We can see that this follows from Eq. (43). Since the
Noether current J, rather than its derivative, is linear in the equations of motion, the satisfaction of the equations of motion does not play a role in securing current conservation,
i.e. in the vanishing of the current’s derivative. In other words, by the time one wants to
prove the conservation of the current, the equations of motion have “disappeared” from
it. They play a role in the current, but not in the conservation. This is unlike Noether’s
first theorem, Eq. (27), where the divergence of the current, rather than the current itself,
is linear in the equations of motion.
Noether herself took her theorems to confirm Hilbert’s view that there is no proper
energy conservation law in general relativity. She wrote (see Kosmann-Schwarzbach,
2011: p. 20):
Given [an action] S invariant under the group of translations, then the energy relations [i.e. the conservation laws corresponding to translations] are improper [i.e. the
divergences vanish identically] iff S is invariant under an infinite group which contains the group of translations as a subgroup...60 As Hilbert expresses his assertion,
58
For diffeomorphism invariant theories, the superpotential corresponds, in Wald’s (1993: p. 3429)
formulation, to the Noether charge Q, which in a 4-dimensional spacetime is a 2-form.
59
This holds up to an antisymmetric, total derivative, term of the form ∂ [µ wν] , i.e. the superpotential
obtained by integrating Eq. (35) must be compatible with Eq. (36). I thank Henrique Gomes for pointing
this out. Note that this ambiguity only appears if one integrates Eq. (35) regardless of the other equations.
Most important, this ambiguity does not affect the superpotential U of Noether’s theorem, which is
completely fixed by Noether’s theorem, through Eq. (36).
60
The group of translations being a subgroup of an infinite group is not sufficient to get improper energy
relations. For example, in the Maxwell theory in Minkowski space, the group of translations, G4 , is a
sugroup of the total group containing both translations and local gauge transformations, i.e. G4 × G∞1 ,
where G∞1 is the group of local gauge transformations: and yet, the energy relations of the Maxwell
theory are proper. Thus, for improper energy relations, it is also necessary (and this is obviously what
Noether had in mind) that the four constant generators of translations, ǫµ , are obtained by setting four
corresponding generators of the infinite group, i.e. the four functions ξ µ (x), to be constant. The latter
24
the lack of a proper law of energy constitutes a characteristic of the “general theory
of relativity”.
It is of course true that the details of the conservation are different in the two cases,
because they satisfy different theorems. Noether’s second theorem imposes more constraints.
However, as we also saw above, the boundary theorem, combined with Noether’s
second theorem, does imply an identity that looks exactly like Noether’s first theorem,
Eq. (27). The two theorems differ in that, in the case of the boundary theorem, the
equations of motion appear in the form of the current itself, while they do not appear
in Noether’s first theorem. Thus the disappearance of the equations of motion from the
divergence of the Noether current in the boundary theorem is not a fact that is additional
to its disappearance from the current itself (the two are connected through Noether’s
second theorem, Eq. (38)).
Let me make this reply to Klein (in particular) more precise. Recall his points (1) and
(2), from Section 1.1, that the divergence of the total energy-momentum tensor density,
√
i.e. τ µ ν := g T µ ν + tµ ν , has no physical meaning because it is an improper conservation
law, i.e. it consists of two terms:61 (1) the divergence of the Einstein field equations, and
(2) the divergence of the superpotential, which is identically zero. This follows from the
µ
boundary theorem, Eq. (36), which gives: ∂µ Jkµ = ∂µ (E a γak
) + ∂µ ∂ν Ukµν , where: (1) E a
appears here under the divergence, (2) the second term vanishes identically. By (1), the
equations of motion play no direct role in the vanishing of the divergence (as they do
in e.g. classical mechanics).62 Thus the equations of motion play no direct role in the
vanishing of the divergence (as they do in e.g. classical mechanics).
µ
, we rewrite this
But using Noether’s second theorem, i.e. Eq. (38), for non-zero γak
equation as: ∂µ Jkµ = E a ηak + ∂µ ∂ν Ukµν .63 Since the second term is identically zero, we
see that the Noether current J is conserved if and only if (a linear combination of) the
equations of motion are satisfied, in complete analogy with Noether’s first theorem.64
Slightly anticipating the results of the next Section, we can show this explicitly in the
1 √
g(Gµ ν − κT µ ν )
case of general relativity. Rewrite: τ µ ν = 2E µ ν + ∂λ Uνµλ , where E µ ν = 2κ
is proportional to the Einstein field equations. Using the contracted Bianchi identities,
we find: ∂µ τ µ ν = E αβ ∂ν gαβ + ∂µ ∂λ Uνµλ . Since the second term vanishes identically, the
total energy-momentum (pseudo-) tensor density is conserved if and only if a certain
linear combination of Einstein’s equations are satisfied. This seems to be what Einstein
(1918: p. 513) had in mind in his reply that part of the field equations are used,65 and he
condition is not satisfied in the Maxwell theory, but it is satisfied
p in general relativity.
√
61
Here, and in the rest of the paper, the notation g means | det(g)|.
62
Klein’s (1918a: p. 504) argument is not quite as explicit as this. This reconstruction of the argument
follows Brading (2005: p. 126): see footnote 26.
µ
63
This is different from the case of the local gauge symmetry of the Maxwell theory, because γak
there
is indeed zero, while it is non-zero in general relativity.
64
The (indirect) physical significance of Noether’s second theorem has long been recognised by philosophers. Recently, a number of authors have also emphasised the (direct) physical significance of improper
conservation laws for local gauge symmetries: see Teh (2016: p. 99) and Sus (2017: pp. 274-275).
65
Also in classical mechanics, it is only part, i.e. a linear combination, of the equations of motion that
appear on the right-hand side. Consider, as an elementary example, the Lagrangian L = 12 mẋ2i + V (x),
25
was indeed right.66
3
Noether’s Theorems in General Relativity
In this Section, I will apply Noether’s theorem to general relativity coupled to matter.67
I will first focus on the case of pure gravity, and then discuss adding matter.
Take the action Eq. (25) with Lagrangian density given by L = LE + Lm , where LE is
the Einstein Lagrangian, and Lm is the matter Lagrangian. The Einstein Lagrangian is
given by:
√ µν λ λ
2κ LE (gµν , ∂λ gµν ) :=
g g (Γµν Γλσ − Γσµλ Γλνσ )
√
√
=
(44)
g R − ∂µ ( g (g αβ Γµαβ − g µν Γλνλ )) ,
and so the Einstein action differs from the usual Einstein-Hilbert action by a total derivative term that does not affect the equations of motion.68
Let us first write out the notation for Noether’s theorems applied to the Einstein term
in the action. For, although we have a coupled gravity-matter system, we may of course
require the diffeomorphism invariance of a single term.
The field φa is then the metric tensor, and the index a is a symmetric pair of spacetime
indices, a = αβ, ranging from 1 to 4, i.e. the dimension of spacetime. Under a local
translation δxµ = ξ µ (x), the metric transforms as follows:
δgαβ = −∇α ξβ − ∇β ξα = −ξ µ ∂µ gαβ − 2gν(α ∂β) ξ ν .
(45)
The index k is also a spacetime index µ. Comparing with Eq. (34), we see that ηak is
µ
µ
equal to −∂µ gαβ , and γak
is equal to −2δ(α
gβ)ν .
Noether’s second theorem, Eq. (38), applied to the gravitational part of the action,
gives the contracted Bianchi identity for the Einstein tensor:69
1 √ αβ
√
g G ∂ν gαβ
∂µ ( g Gµ ν ) =
2
⇔ ∇µ Gµ ν = 0 ,
(46)
where i = 1, 2, 3. The time derivative of the Hamiltonian gives: dH/dt = Ei ẋi , where Ei = mẍi + ∂i V ,
i.e. the conservation law is proportional to a linear combination of the equations of motion.
µ
µ
66
Klein’s argument can go through if E a γak
= 0 without use of the equations of motion, e.g. if γak
= 0.
In that case, it is true that the first term vanishes before its derivative is taken. However, this is not the
case in general relativity.
67
For a discussion of Noether’s theorem and Kretschmann’s objection to Einstein’s treatment of general
covariance, see Brown and Brading (2002: pp. 22-25). This paper also contains a treatment of Noether’s
theorem for electrodynamics with an arbitrary background metric.
68
There are various boundary terms that one can add, depending on the choice of boundary conditions,
and these lead to different expressions for the pseudo-tensor. For a treatment of Noether’s second theorem
for the Einstein-Hilbert action, see for example Horký and Novotný (1969: p. 424). In this Section, I
follow some of the historical literature in using the Einstein action. I will return to the issue of boundary
terms and boundary conditions in Sections 4 and 5.
69
This formulation follows Noether’s (1918: p. 241) original methods, reviewed in Section 2. However, there is an important and useful reformulation of Noether’s theorem, for diffeomorphism-invariant
Lagrangians, in terms of differential forms: see Wald (1993: pp. 3428-3429) and Wald and Zoupas
(2000: pp. 2-3).
26
Noether’s second theorem, applied to the matter part of the action, gives the covariant
analogue of the energy and momentum conservation equation, i.e. Eq. (16). That equation
is, as expected, obtained as an identity, without the use of the equations of motion.
Let us write down the Noether current, Eq. (31), Jνµ =: −tµ ν , for the gravitational
part of the action:
tµ ν = −
∂LE
∂Λµ
∂ν gαβ + LE δνµ − ν .
∂(∂µ gαβ )
∂ξ
(47)
This gives a gravitational analogue of the matter energy-momentum tensor. In fact, as
I shall discuss in a moment, it is not a tensor: it is the gravitational energy-momentum
pseudo-tensor.
The boundary theorem gives the two following results. The first equation of the
boundary theorem, Eq. (35), applied to the Einstein action, gives an expression for the
divergence of the gravitational pseudo-tensor:
∂ µ tµ ν = −
1 √ αβ
1
√
g G ∂ν gαβ = − ∂µ ( g Gµ ν ) ,
2κ
κ
(48)
where in the last step I used the Bianchi identity, Eq. (46). (The same result can be
obtained by taking the divergence of Eq. (47) directly). Using Einstein’s equations, Gµν =
κ Tµν , we find Einstein’s form of the conservation law, Eq. (21). The second equation of
the boundary theorem, Eq. (36), reproduces the expression Eq. (24) for the pseudo-tensor
in terms of the superpotential.
I will now argue that this form of the boundary theorem shows that the alleged nonuniqueness of the pseudo-tensor, i.e. problem (iv) in Section 1.3, only arises if one treats
Eq. (21) independently of Noether’s theorems. For if one takes Eq. (21) as the definition
of the pseudo-tensor and integrates it, then the pseudo-tensor indeed admits an arbitrary
superpotential, as in Eq. (24).70
But if one, correctly, applies Noether’s theorem to the gravitational part of the action,
Eq. (44), then both the pseudo-tensor and the superpotential are fixed by their Noether
expressions in Eqs. (31) and (32), in terms of:
(1) the Lagrangian density,
(2) the boundary term Λµ that appears in the Noether variation of the action, Eq. (26).
Noether’s expression Eq. (32) for the superpotential indeed shows that the superpotential is not arbitrary, but is fixed when (1) and (2), including the boundary terms of
the action, are fixed. One may add boundary terms to the action without changing the
equations of motion, and in this sense there is freedom to change the superpotential by
changing the boundary terms. However, boundary terms often do change the boundary
conditions, and so the boundary terms must be such that they give the desired boundary
conditions. (Typically, the boundary conditions are not sufficient to uniquely determine
the boundary terms; the finiteness of the on-shell action is also required to fix them: see
Section 4).
70
For example, Lam (2011: pp. 1017-1018) defines the energy-momentum pseudo-tensor in terms of
an expression that automatically satisfies the conservation equation Eq. (21), as in Eq. (24), and thus
contains an arbitrary superpotential.
27
This means that the freedom to choose the superpotential has a physical meaning: it is
the freedom to change the action, without affecting the equations of motion, by boundary
terms. The latter have a physical meaning, because they determine:
(a) the boundary conditions in the variation of the metric that gives the equation of
motion;
(b) the on-shell value of the (Euclidean) action, which e.g. in thermodynamic approaches to gravity, especially in the context of black holes, is interpreted as a gravitational potential;71
(c) the boundary terms of the Hamiltonian are also determined by the boundary
terms of the Lagrangian.72 Thus the significance of the boundary terms does not hinge
on interpreting the Lagrangian physically.
Chang et al. (1999) notice that, in a Hamiltonian approach, the freedom to change the
superpotential is related to the freedom to change the boundary conditions, i.e. analogous
to my points (a) and (c) above. However, so far as I can see, they do not notice that it is
in general Noether’s theorem that completely fixes the superpotential from the variation
of the action, in particular through Eq. (32).
In the absence of Killing vectors that allow us to construct the energy by integrating a
scalar expression like Eq. (19), some authors use the pseudo-tensor to convert the covariant
derivative in Eq. (16) into a partial derivative and integrate. Thus these authors define a
total momentum vector Pµ as an integral over a spacelike volume V :73
Z
1 ν
ν
(49)
dΣν T µ + √ t µ .
Pµ :=
g
V
By choosing special coordinates, where the normal vector to the boundary S of the volume
V points along the time direction, these authors derive:
Z
√
1 dPµ
= − d 2 x N ni ( h T i µ + ti µ ) ,
(50)
c dt
S
where, as before, ni is the outward-pointing unit vector normal to S, N is the lapse
function, and h is the metric on S induced from g in these coordinates. This expression can
be shown to reproduce the well-known ADM (for Arnowitt, Deser, and Misner) formulas
for asymptotically flat spacetimes: see Arnowitt et al. (1962: p. 16), Wang (2015: p. 3),
Chen et al. (2017: p. 200), Chen et al. (2018: p. 3), Chen et al. (2018a: p. 158).74 This
expression is regarded as an analogue of the charge conservation law Eq. (14).
However, as I will discuss in Section 5, the above definition is unsatisfactory: for it
transforms covariantly only under affine transformations, and the analogy with charge
71
See e.g. Hawking (1979: pp. 772, 778-779). Wald (1993: p. 3431) and Hawking and Horowitz
(1996: pp. 1494-1495) contain reformulations of the first and second laws of black hole mechanics in
terms of the Lagrangian and its variation. For some examples, see Wald and Zoupas (2000: p. 8-14),
Jacobson et al. (1994: pp. 6592-6593).
72
For the relation between the Lagrangian and Hamiltonian approaches to GR, see for example Wald
(1984: pp. 464-465)
73
See Weinberg (1972: p. 167), Landau and Lifshitz (1971: p. 306), Chen et al. (2018: p. 3, 2018a: p. 4).
For the philosophical literature on this point, see Read (2020: p. 217) and Hoefer (2000: p. 194).
74
For a discussion of the history of the ADM mass formula, and various versions and derivations of it,
see Ohanian (2010: p. 9).
28
conservation depends on a very special embedding of the volume V in the spacetime and
on the associated choice of coordinates.
4
Quasi-local Stress-Energy Tensors in GR
It is time to discuss other proposals for the energy-momentum and angular momentum
of the gravitational field. This Section introduces two such. Section 4.1 introduces the
Brown-York quasi-local stress-energy tensor, which in Section 4.2 is then modified and
gets a holographic interpretation that, I will argue, casts light on the nature of energy and
momentum in GR. In Section 4.3, I will discuss the transformations of the Brown-York
stress-energy tensor under diffeomorphisms.
4.1
The Brown-York quasi-local stress-energy tensor
At the end of Section 1.3, where I discussed five problems with the gravitational pseudotensor, I mentioned Penrose’s idea of giving up local expressions for energy and momentum in GR, and to consider quasi-local notions instead. This Section presents one such
expression in some detail.
Brown and York’s (1993) proposal is to define the quasi-local stress-energy tensor,
associated with a spatially bounded region M , as the conjugate of the classical action
with respect to an appropriately defined metric on the boundary of that region.
The action to consider contains six terms. There is the usual Einstein-Hilbert action,
coupled to matter, and possibly including a cosmological constant term. Furthermore,
since the spacetime region M is bounded, appropriate boundary terms are required in
order to make the variational problem well-defined. Since ∂M consists of two spacelike
hypersurfaces Σ± to the past and future of M , and the timelike three-surface N that
spatially bounds M , there are three such boundary terms (where the first two are abbreviated into a single term, see Eq. (51) below).75 To make the variational problem of the
Einstein-Hilbert action well-defined, a choice of boundary conditions for the metric on the
boundary is required: Brown and York consider Dirichlet boundary conditions, i.e. keeping the metric on the boundary fixed.76 The appropriate boundary term for Dirichlet
boundary conditions is the extrinsic curvature, denoted K on the hypersurfaces Σ± , and
Θ on the three-surface N . Finally, a reference term is required that renders the value of
the action and the stress-energy tensor well-defined (I will have more to say about this
term later). Thus the action is:
Z
Z
Z
√
√
1
1
1
4 √
3
d x −g R +
dx hK
−
−γ Θ + S ref + S matter (51)
S=
2κ M
κ Σ±
κ N
{z
}
|
{z
}
|
extrinsic curvature of hypersurfaces Σ±
75
extrinsic curvature of N
Brown and York’s (1993: p. 1410) coordinates are such that the hypersurfaces Σ± and N are orthonormal to each other on the two-surface where they intersect. Furthermore, no additional term in the
action for this two-surface is required.
76
These boundary conditions also render the gravitational part of the action well-defined in case a
cosmological constant term is present.
29
Here, h is the metric on the hypersurfaces Σ± embedded in M , and γ is the metric on the
three-boundary N embedded in M . K and Θ are their corresponding extrinsic curvatures.
Varying this action with respect to the metric, we get:
Z
Z
Z
√
1
1
√ ij
4
3
µν
ij
d x E δgµν +
δS = −
d3 x γ τBY
d x h P δhij +
δγij .
(52)
2 Σ±
2 N
M
The first term contains the Einstein field equations including matter, and thus vanishes
if the field equations are satisfied. The second and third terms define the momenta conjugate to the three-metrics h on Σ± and γ on N , respectively (with Dirichlet boundary
ij
conditions, as announced). τBY
is a genuine (quasi-local) energy-momentum tensor, because it contains both spacelike and timelike components. It also contains contributions
from both the gravitational and the matter part of the action. The subscript ‘BY’ emphasises that this is the energy-momentum tensor, as defined in the proposal by Brown
and York.
Restricting for the moment to the gravitational contribution to this last term, we get
the following result for the Brown-York stress-energy tensor density:
1
ij
τBY
= − √ Θ γ ij − Θij + (subtracted terms) .
κ γ
(53)
The subtracted terms subtract a potentially divergent piece, in cases where one is evaluating this tensor at infinity. These subtracted terms are obtained by subtracting to the
action Eq. (51) the same action, evaluated on an appropriate reference spacetime. For example, if the solutions of the Einstein field equations that one considers are asymptotically
flat, one usually subtracts from Eq. (51) the same action, but evaluated on a Minkowski
solution. In this way, the ‘on-shell’ value of the action (i.e. the action evaluated on a
particular solution) is finite, and also the Brown-York stress-energy tensor is finite. I will
return to this procedure in the next Section, where I will mention an alternative way to
resolve this problem that does not appeal to the reference spacetime.
The boundary stress-energy tensor (density) satisfies one of Einstein’s equations:
ij
∇i τBY
= −T nj ,
(54)
where T nj is the matter energy-momentum tensor with one index projected normally,
and the other tangentially, to N . This is a covariant balance equation for the quasi-local
stress-energy tensor, where the contribution on the right is from the matter that passes
through the boundary.
If there is no matter passing through the boundary, and if the boundary three-metric
γij possesses a Killing vector field Ki ,77 then τ ij defines a conserved charge, i.e. we have
ij
the conservation law ∇i (τBY
Kj ) = 0, which is analogous to Eq. (17). Thus by the same
manipulations as in Section 1.2 we derive an analogue of Eqs. (19)-(20) on the boundary.
Note that, in the Brown-York proposal, the spacetime region M can be finite and
embedded in an ambient spacetime: and so, the three-surface N that spatially bounds M
77
In the context of spaces with a cosmological constant, this condition can be weakened for Ki to be
only a conformal Killing vector, i.e. one that satisfies Eq. (63).
30
need not be at infinity. In the next Section, I will discuss the case Λ < 0, and N will be
taken to be the asymptotic boundary.78
As any quasi-local energy-momentum must, the Brown-York expression agrees with
the ADM energy at infinity (see Section 3) for the special case of asymptotically flat
spacetimes (Brown and York, 1993: p. 1408).
4.2
The holographic stress-energy tensor
Consider the case of pure gravity with a negative cosmological constant, Λ < 0, , i.e. no
matter. (The Brown-York stress-energy tensor can be equally well be defined in the case
Λ > 0).79 According to AdS-CFT, the gravitational theory in the spacetime region M
with boundary ∂M is dual to a quantum field theory on the boundary, ∂M .80 As we will
see, one can use gauge-gravity duality to reinterpret the Brown-York stress-energy tensor,
evaluated on this asymptotic boundary, in terms of the dual CFT.
Since we are interested in the Brown-York stress-energy tensor that is claimed to
represent the energy and stress of the spacetime M , it will be useful to briefly mention
how it fits within gauge-gravity duality.81
Following the recent literature,82 a duality is, roughly, an isomorphism between two
theory formulations. A theory can be construed as a triple of states, quantities, and
dynamics. The statement of duality says that the sets of states, quantities, and the
dynamics of the two theories are isomorphic.
On the gravity side of the duality, a distinguished quantity should be the stress-energy
tensor of the spacetime region M . The isomorphism should relate this to an appropriate
quantity in the dual CFT. The question is: which stress-energy tensor has a dual in the
CFT? If the Brown-York stress-energy tensor is to be a candidate for the energy and stress
in the spacetime, then it ought to be related by the duality to a quantity in the CFT that
has those properties. In fact, gauge-gravity duality gives us the following correspondence:
The Brown-York stress-energy tensor, defined by the variation of the action (evaluated
on the equations of motion) with respect to a boundary three-metric on N , and with
78
For studies of the Brown-York stress-energy tensor at surfaces that are not asymptotic boundaries,
see e.g. De Haro et al. (2001a: pp. 3174). For gauge-gravity dualities (both AdS-CFT and dS-CFT) with
finite boundaries, see Harlow and Stanford (2011: pp. 4-5) and Heemskerk and Polchinski (2011: pp. 2-6).
79
See Balasubramanian et al. (2001: p. 3) and Anninos et al. (2011: pp. 4-5). Quite independent of
quantum gravity or holographic ideas, the Brown-York energy-momentum tensor has been used to define
notions of mass and momentum in spaces with a positive cosmological constant: see Balasubramanian
et al. (2001: p. 4). The asymptotic diffeomorphism group at future null infinity of asymptotically de
Sitter spaces, and the conservation equations for the associated charges, are considered in Anninos et
al. (2011: pp. 3-6) and Strominger (2001: pp. 4-5).
80
For a general introduction to gauge-gravity dualities, see Ammon and Erdmenger (2015). For a
conceptual introduction, see De Haro et al. (2016). For a sample of the recent philosophical literature
on dualities, see for example: Rickles (2011), Dieks et al. (2015), Read (2016), Huggett and Wüthrich
(2020), De Haro (2020), Read and Møller-Nielsen (2020), Butterfield (2020).
81
In what follows, I will restrict to the case of a spacetime with a Euclidean signature, so that M has
a single boundary, N , with the topology of a three-sphere. For the case with Lorentzian signature, see
Skenderis and van Rees (2008: p. 2; 2009: p. 6).
82
I here follow De Haro and Butterfield (2018: pp. 335-339), De Haro (2020: pp. 264-266), and Butterfield (2020: p. 12).
31
appropriate boundary terms that render the action finite, is dual to the expectation value
of the stress-energy tensor of the CFT defined on the background of that metric.83
This correspondence follows from the identification of the gravitational action Eq. (51)
with a given set of matter fields, evaluated on a given solution of the Einstein field
equations, with the generating functional of (connected) correlation functions in the dual
CFT, usually called WCFT :
S[γ, · · · ]|EFE ≡ WCFT [γ, · · · ] .
(55)
The left-hand side of this equation is the action Eq. (51), evaluated for a metric and set of
matter fields that satisfy Einstein’s field equations (hence the subscript ‘EFE’). (Physicists
call this an ‘on-shell’ action). γ is the metric on ∂M , and the dots indicate that there
is also a dependence on the boundary values of the matter fields. The right-hand side
of this equation is the generating functional of connected correlation functions, which is
related to the CFT’s partition function by: ZCFT = exp(−WCFT ). Again, this generating
functional depends on the metric γ, which is now viewed as a curved background on which
the CFT is defined, and other sources that the theory is defined with (these are dual to
the boundary values of the matter fields on the left).
On the right-hand side, the expectation value of the stress-energy tensor of the CFT
is defined by the functional derivative with respect to the metric:
2 δWCFT
hTij (x)iCFT = √
.
γ δγ ij (x)
(56)
But substituting Eq. (55) into Eq. (56), and comparing with Eq. (52), we see that we
indeed have the following correspondence:
′ ij
τBY
≡ hT ij iCFT .
(57)
The dash on the Brown-York stress-energy tensor indicates that this tensor is modified,
by replacing the ‘subtracted terms’ in Eq. (53) by local counterterms added to the action,
according to a standard method in holographic renormalisation.84 In what follows, I will
call hT ij iCFT ‘holographic stress-energy tensor’.
The holographic stress-energy tensor can be calculated from Eq. (53) for any given
solution of Einstein’s equations.85
The gravitational equation Eq. (54) can be reproduced from the CFT perspective.
For example, consider a two-dimensional CFT with a single (scalar) operator O which
has a non-zero expectation value hOi, coupling to a source J, the invariance of the CFT
partition function under infinitesimal changes of coordinates,
δγij = ∇i ξj + ∇j ξi ,
83
(58)
I here omit technical details, such as that the boundary metric is defined only up to a conformal
transformation. This point will resurface in Section 4.3.
84
See Henningson and Skenderis (1998: p. 5), Balasubramanian and Kraus (1999: p. 415), De Haro et
al. (2001: p. 603). For a review of holographic renormalisation, see Skenderis (2002).
85
In general this is tedious, but there is a systematic procedure to do this calculation. See De Haro
et al. (2001: pp. 602-607, 609-612), Skenderis (2002: pp. 5855-5861). For an alternative method, see
Papadimitriou and Skenderis (2004: pp. 14-18).
32
yields the following identity:
∇j hTij i = hOi ∂i J .
(59)
One can check that this result is reproduced, on the gravity side with a three-dimensional
spacetime, by the identity of Brown and York, Eq. (54), since, given the form of the
normal energy-momentum tensor T nj for the dual scalar field, the above indeed reproduces
Eq. (54).86
Noether’s theorem in connection with asymptotic symmetries is discussed in Papadimitriou and Skenderis (2005: pp. 15-19), who show, for various types of fields, that the
holographic charges are the Noether charges.
Implications of gauge-gravity duality for the gravitational energy. Let us briefly
discuss how these results bear on the problem of energy conservation. Gauge-gravity dualities give independent support to the claim that the modified Brown-York stress-energy
tensor represents the quasi-local energy. We will consider the two main features of the
holographic stress-energy tensor of the dual quantum field theory that bear on the status
of the quasi-local energy in GR:
(1) The duality map, Eq. (57), relates the Brown-York stress-energy tensor to the
holographic stress-energy tensor. This gives further support to the interpretation of the
Brown-York stress-energy tensor as representing quasi-local stress and energy. For recall
that a duality is an isomorphism of models of a single common core theory.87 The interpretation of two dual models need not be the same, but if it is the same,88 then the two dual
quantities on either side of Eq. (57) receive the same interpretation. Thus the right-hand
side of this equation, i.e. the holographic stress-energy tensor, can give us guidance about
the interpretation of the side under discussion, i.e. the gravitational, left-hand, side. And
the interpretation of the left-hand side is indeed as energy, momentum, and stress. This
is a further argument to the effect that the Brown-York stress-energy tensor represents
energy, momentum, and stress.89
Thus, in AdS-CFT, the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor in spacetime with
Λ < 0 is precisely dual to the quantity that, in the CFT, is interpreted as describing energy
and momentum: namely, the expectation value of the stress-energy tensor. The match is
a consequence of the general AdS-CFT correspondence: namely, the identification of the
gravitational action, evaluated on solutions, with the generating functional of the CFT,
Eq. (55), and of the conformal metric on the boundary, γij , with the metric of the dual
86
See De Haro et al. (2001: p. 615).
This ‘common core’ view is discussed and-or endorsed by e.g. Rickles (2011: p. 66), Dieks et
al. (2015: p. 209), De Haro (2017: p. 116), Huggett (2017: p. 84), De Haro and Butterfield (2018: p. 321),
Le Bihan and Read (2018: p. 3).
88
That it is the same depends on our developing an internal interpretation of the dual models: for
a discussion, and conditions under which this is possible, see Dieks et al. (2015: p. 209), De Haro
(2020: pp. 267-271), Read and Møller-Nielsen (2020: p. 284-288).
89
Note that the internal interpretation of the common core theory, as currently worked out, does not
support the interpretation of this energy as gravitational energy—even though this can be done on an
external interpretation (see footnote 91). For understanding the nature of the common degrees of freedom
depends on having a good development of this common core theory, which we do not currently have. For
a more detailed discussion, see De Haro (2020: pp. 275-279).
87
33
quantum field theory. This precise correspondence, which has been illustrated in many
examples, gives additional support to the statement that the Brown-York stress-energy
tensor is indeed to be thought of as energy and momentum, since it plays that role in the
boundary theory.
(2) The boundary conservation equation, Eq. (54), has a similar dual interpretation,
and is not analogus to the usual (disputed) conservation laws of GR.90 This boundary
conservation equation is dual to Eq. (59): and so, it can be interpreted as a balance
equation for the energy and stress of the common core theory, and this again strengthens
that interpretation in GR.91
4.3
Diffeomorphisms and redundancy of the description
In our discussion, in Section 5, of the two main proposals for defining energy and momentum in general relativity, diffeomorphism invariance will play a crucial role. Therefore, we
should understand the transformation properties of the Brown-York stress-energy under
various diffeomorphisms: namely, those that are descriptive redundancies and those that
are not.92
The asymptotic symmetries of gravity have been a central foundational topic in general
relativity since at least the work of Arnowitt et al. (1959, 1962), Bondi et al. (1962),
Penrose (1963, 1964), Newman et al. (1966), Geroch (1972), Ashtekar et al. (1978), among
others. For a philosophical discussion of some aspects of asymptotic symmetries, see Belot
(2018).
A central question is which asymptotic diffeomorphisms are true symmetries of a
spacetime, and which asymptotic diffeomorphisms act non-trivially on the physical degrees
of freedom of general relativity: and how these different kinds of diffeomorphisms are to
be characterised.
In spaces with a negative cosmological constant, Brown and Henneaux (1986) discovered that the asymptotic diffeomorphism of anti-de Sitter space is the conformal group
of the asymptotic boundary.93 As we will see in this Section, this asymptotic symmetry
90
There are three important disanalogies between the boundary balance equation, Eq. (54), and the
(disputed) conservation law, Eqs. (16)-(21), which are relevant to points (i)-(iv) from Section 1.3. First,
Eq. (54) distinguishes between the quasi-local gravitational energy, τBY , and matter energy-momentum,
T nj . Second, the covariant derivative is calculated using the boundary, metric-compatible, connection,
which is non-dynamical, and fixed by the boundary conditions. Third, the right-hand side is in general
non-zero, so that this is a balance equation. I will address points (iii) and (v), from Section 1.3, in Section
6.2
91
An internal interpretation (as in ‘Eq. (54) is the energy balance equation’) is usually compatible with
a judiciously chosen external interpretation (as in ‘Eq. (54) is the balance equation for the gravitational
energy’), through the process of abstraction outlined in De Haro (2021: Section 4.4). This is why, if the
internal interpretation is correct, it bears on the interpretation on GR.
92
My discussion here essentially summarises De Haro, Teh, and Butterfield (2015, 2017) and De
Haro (2017). For physics references on this topic, see Imbimbo et al. (2000: pp. 1130-1132), Skenderis
(2001: pp. 742-747).
93
The analysis by Brown and Henneaux has been extended to the case Λ > 0, including in higher
dimensions: see Strominger (2001: pp. 4-5) and Balasubramanian et al. (2001: pp. 7-8). For a more
detailed analysis of diffeomorphisms in the case Λ > 0, see Anninos et al. (2011: pp. 3-4). As we will see
in this Section, these results can be generalised to any space with Λ < 0 that is a solution of Einstein’s
34
group acts non-trivially on the quasi-local energy-momentum tensor.
Thus the question of which subgroup of the diffeomorphism group is a symmetry of a
spacetime is important from the point of view of quasi-local energy and momentum: for
the quasi-local quantities will be either invariant or else have a well-defined transformation
law under the diffeomorphisms that are true asymptotic symmetries of a spacetime, and
they transform non-trivially under diffeomorphisms that are not true symmetries.
What do we mean by the ‘true asymptotic symmetries’ of a spacetime? What we are
looking for here is a criterion that distinguishes the symmetries (diffeomorphisms) that
are true redundancies of a description, from those that entail a physical change in the
solution. We can define redundancies as follows (De Haro et al., 2017: p. 69):94
(Redundant): If a physical theory’s formulation is redundant (i.e. roughly: it uses
more variables than the number of degrees of freedom of the system being described),
one can often think of this in terms of an equivalence relation, ‘physical equivalence’,
on its states; so that gauge-invariant quantities are constant on an equivalence class,
and gauge-symmetries are maps leaving each class (called a ‘gauge-orbit’) invariant.
Leibniz’s criticism of Newtonian mechanics provides a putative example: he believed
that shifting the entire material contents of the universe by one meter must be
regarded as changing only its description, and not is physical state.
I will introduce the notion of the ‘invisibility’ of diffeomorphisms to make precise
the idea of the asymptotic symmetries that are (Redundant). I will distinguish three
relevant classes of diffeomorphisms that qualify differently under redundancy: ‘invisible’
diffeomorphisms are always (Redundant), ‘large’ diffeomorphisms are never (Redundant),
and the intermediate category of ‘visible’ diffeomorphisms can sometimes be (Redundant)
and sometimes not, depending on the interpretation that the theory is given.95 The
three classes are distinguished by the different boundary geometric structures that they
preserve.96 They are as follows:
(1) Invisible diffeomorphisms: these are diffeomorphisms under which the bulk action,
Eq. (55), evaluated on a given solution, is invariant. Also the other quantities derived
equations, with arbitrary metric at infinity.
94
There is an ongoing debate, following Greaves and Wallace (2015)—which itself argues against earlier
work: see footnote 35—whether local gauge symmetries express mere redundancies of the description, or
whether they can be empirically significant, as in Galileo’s ship scenarios: see, for example, Friederich
(2015: p. 537), Murgueitio (2020: p. 1), Murgueitio and Teh (2020: p. 3), Gomes (2020: p. 11), Gomes and
Riello (2020: pp. 3-5, 21). The approach I adopt here is, in effect, to construct a class of diffeomorphisms
(the ‘visible’ diffeomorphisms below) that are GR-analogues of the class of gauge symmetries that can
have a direct empirical equivalence in gauge theories. The latter are called ‘non-interior, boundarypreserving symmetries’ by Greaves and Wallace (2014: p. 71), and their definition is further refined by
Teh (2016: p. 116).
95
Belot (2018: pp. 964-967) also distinguishes local translations that are redundant, from those that
are physical: and he also connects this to the question of boundary conditions—although he does not
appear to consider my intermediate category of ‘visible diffeomorphisms’.
96
Class (1) is the class of ‘QFT-invisible’ diffeomorphisms in De Haro (2017a: pp. 1468, 1484), also
called ‘(simple) gravity-invisible’. Class (2) is the class of ‘QFT-visible’ diffeomorphisms, also called
‘weakly gravity-invisible’ diffeomorphisms’. For the reasons why these classes are cases of (Redundant)
or non-(Redundant), see De Haro, Teh, and Butterfield (2015, 2017) and De Haro (2017).
35
from the action, like the holographic stress-energy tensor Eq. (57), are invariant. These
diffeomorphisms fix the boundary manifold and the conformal metric.97
These diffeomorphisms count as (Redundant) symmetries, because all of the physical
quantities, for a given solution of the equations of motion, are invariant under them. In
particular, these diffeomorphisms allow us to set up an analogue of the hole argument in
a space with a negative cosmological constant, which in turn leads to the conclusion that
the diffeomorphisms in question are (Redundant).98
(2) Visible diffeomorphisms: these are diffeomorphisms that generate conformal transformations of the boundary metric, i.e. γij 7→ γ̃ij := e−2ξ(x) γij . The stress-energy tensor
transforms by a conformal factor under them, and in the case of even boundary dimensions the stress-energy tensor (and the action) pick up an additional, anomalous term
under them:
1 δA[γ]
(d−2) ξ(x)
hTij [γ](x)i + √
hTij [γ̃](x)i = e
,
(60)
γ δγ ij (x)
where γij is the metric induced on the boundary, d is the dimension of the boundary,
and A[γ] is the anomalous term, which can be calculated from the action.99 It is a
local term written in terms of curvature invariants (for the explicit expressions, see Deser
and Schwimmer (1993), Henningson and Skenderis (1998: Section 3), De Haro et al.
(2001: Section 4.2.1)). The anomaly vanishes when d = 3, i.e. for a four-dimensional
spacetime.100 Since the anomaly term vanishes in the case of a four-dimensional spacetime,
which is the case of most interest, I will not discuss it further.101
Visible diffeomorphisms are potentially physical symmetries, rather than redundancies of the description: namely, they act as conformal transformations of the boundary
quantities. Whether they are physical depends on one’s interpretation of the spacetime
within one’s theory.102
97
It is sometimes said that the diffeomorphisms that are redundancies of the theory are those that “go to
unity” at the boundary (this being the class by which the allowed diffeomorphisms have to be quotiented
in order to obtain the asymptotic symmetry group). But this is imprecise, because a diffeormorphism
can go to unity at the boundary while still inducing a non-trivial transformation of the boundary metric
γij , through its dependence on the parametrisation of the ‘radial direction” r, which results in a rescaling
of the boundary metric, and hence a diffeomorphism of type (2) below. Thus, going to unity at the
boundary is not sufficient for (Redundant). Instead, the definition of invisible diffeomorphisms makes
precise the sense in which diffeomorphisms are (Redundant).
98
See De Haro et al. (2017: p. 79).
99
To simplify the discussion, I do not distinguish between conformal transformations and Weyl rescalings of the metric. For details, see De Haro (2017a: p. 1479).
100
The anomaly can be understood as coming from the divergence of the gravitational action, Eq. (51),
at large distances. To cancel this divergence, the action is regularised and boundary counterterms are
introduced, but this renormalisation procedure breaks covariance, albeit in a controlled way, i.e. through
the additional term Eq. (60).
101
For spacetimes of odd dimension, the anomaly is proportional to powers of the boundary curvature
that depend on the dimension, and so it is also zero if the boundary metric is flat.
102
In De Haro et al. (2017: p. 79), it was argued that, on an ‘internal’ interpretation (typically, in the
context of a theory of the whole universe), two states related by visible diffeomorphisms are physically
equivalent, so that the transformations count as (Redundant) gauge symmetries. On the other hand, on
an ‘external interpretation’ (as e.g. in a Galileo’s ship scenario, where the inside of the ship is not the
36
(3) Large diffeomorphisms: these are diffeomorphisms that do not preserve sufficient
boundary structure, and so they map solutions of Einstein’s equations to physically inequivalent solutions of the equations (e.g. equations with a different total mass or angular
momentum). Such diffeomorphisms are therefore not (Redundant), but physical transformations that relate different states. In particular, they will change the value of the
holographic stress-energy tensor.103
An analysis of the diffeomorphisms as detailed as the preceding one has, so far as
I am aware, not been done for Λ > 0, and so one should proceed with some caution.
However, much work has been done on this case as well: see Anninos et al. (2011: pp. 36), Strominger (2001: pp. 4-5), Balasubramanian et al. (2001: pp. 7-8).
There are also a few general things one can say. As noted in Skenderis (2002: Appendix
A) and De Haro (2017a: pp. 1490-1491), the geometric techniques that enabled the analysis
summarised in Section 4.3 and just above, apply in the case Λ > 0 as well, due to the fact
that the differential form of Einstein’s equations in the radial variable was turned into a
set of coupled algebraic relations. The results depend only on the asymptotic solutions,
and can be continued from one case to the other, where the radial coordinate r goes into
a timelike coordinate t (the anti-de Sitter boundary is thereby mapped to the timelike
future infinity in de Sitter space).
To summarise, in case (1) we have a hole-type argument that leads us to conclude that
invisible diffeomorphisms correspond to redundancies of the theory. In case (3), such an
argument is not available, because the diffeomorphisms in question change the physical
properties of the spacetime, and we should not characterise spacetimes related by a large
diffeomorphism as physically equivalent. Case (2) is an intermediate case, where the
diffeomorphisms act as conformal transformations on the boundary quantities, and their
nature as (Redundant) or as non-(Redundant) depends on one’s interpretation (including
further use) of the solutions, say as being cosmological models of the whole universe, or
as being merely parts of the universe.
Let me say a bit more about this last case, (2), of visible diffeomorphisms, and how they
give rise to transformations of the conformal boundary: namely, conformal transformations. Choose an open neighbourhood of the boundary, such that the boundary of M is
the surface r = 0. A theorem of Fefferman and Graham (1985, 2012) guarantees that in
such an open neighbourhood of the boundary, we can write the metric in Poincaré normal
form:
ds2 =
ℓ2
2
i
j
,
dr
+
γ
(r,
x)
dx
dx
ij
r2
(61)
where xi are coordinates tangent to the boundary directions, and γij (r, x) is a metric
along this direction, that in general depends on both r and x. We obtain the earlier-used
whole world, but can be related to other parts of the world, e.g. the shore) these diffeomorphisms are not
(Redundant), but express ‘the motion of the ship relative to the quay’.
103
For example, Grumiller et al. (2016: Eq. (3.6)) report a metric that is claimed to be physically
inequivalent to the corresponding metric in normal form.
37
γij by setting r = 0, that is: γij (x) := γij (0, x) . The diffeomorphisms we are interested
in are those that “fix the location of the boundary r = 0”. They take the following form:
δxi = ξ i (x) , δr = −r ξ(x) .
(62)
Requiring that these diffeomorphisms satisfy the definition of ‘being visible’, i.e. fix: (i)
the Poincaré normal form of the metric, i.e. Eq. (61), and (ii) the boundary metric, implies
the following condition on the diffeomorphism generated by the boundary vector field ξ:104
∇i ξj (x) + ∇j ξi (x) =
2
γij (x) ∇k ξk (x) ,
d
(63)
where the covariant derivatives are with respect to the boundary metric γij (x). This
equation is the conformal Killing equation, which is precisely the condition for the vector
field ξ to be a conformal transformation, rather than an isometry, of the boundary metric
γij (x).105 This gives us a very general relation between the symmetries of the metric in
M , in Poincaré normal form Eq. (61), and the conformal group on ∂M :
The asymptotic symmetry group of the Poincaré normal form of the metric, Eq. (61),
on the manifold M , is the conformal group on the asymptotic boundary, ∂M , with boundary metric γ.
This generalises the result by Brown and Henneaux (1986), for any solution of Einstein’s equations with Λ < 0.
These diffeomorphisms give us a conformal Killing vector ξ of the boundary manifold.
As I noticed after Eq. (54), especially in footnote 77, using the properties of the holographic stress-energy tensor, Eq. (56), this can be used to derive a boundary analogue of
the energy conservation equation Eq. (20).
5
Gravitational Energy and Momentum, Revisited
In this Section, I first review two recent discussions of pseudo-tensors that I aim to justify:
one is from physics (Section 5.1) and the other is philosophical (Section 5.2). I will agree
with much of these defences of the pseudo-tensor approach—but I will nevertheless, in
Section 6, argue for the superiority, in the present state of knowledge, of the Brown-York
approach.
5.1
Superpotentials are boundary terms in the Hamiltonian of
GR
In recent work, Chang, Chen, Nester, and collaborators (1999, 2017, 2018, 2018a) have
defended a rehabilitation of pseudo-tensors that thereby casts light on the physical nature
of pseudo-tensors. Their work can be seen as arguing for a resolution of problem (iv) in
Section 1.3. Namely, they argue that pseudo-tensors:
104
See Brown and Henneaux (1986), De Haro (2017a: p. 1477).
The conformal Killing equation reproduces the ordinary Killing equation, Eq. (15), in the special
case ∇k ξk = 0.
105
38
(a) Do provide a description of energy and momentum conservation. They do this,
in particular, by establishing a relationship between pseudo-tensors and the Hamiltonian
of general relativity. The superpotential, Uλµν , can be identified with a total divergence
in the Hamiltonian of general relativity, and so different choices of the superpotential
correspond to different boundary terms/conditions. Thus problem number (iv) is thereby
resolved, because fixing the boundary terms determines the pseudotensor uniquely.
(b) Give, for apropriate choices of boundary conditions, the expected values of the
total energy and momentum as measured at infinity, i.e. the ADM and Bondi formulas,106
thus further strengthening the contention, in the resolution of problem (iv), that pseudotensors are physical.
(c) Have well-defined values in each system of coordinates. In particular, the pseudotensors give quasi-local quantities, which are naturally identified with the two-surfaces
that bound regions of space, and give correct results at infinity, as in (b).
Here I will focus on (a), which is the most distinctive part of the approach by Chang,
Chen, Nester, and collaborators. Then I will more briefly comment on (b) and (c). Let
me state, in words, the main statement that goes into arguing for (a):
Pseudotensor-Hamiltonian correspondence: The quasi-local energy-momentum over
a hypersurface Σ with constant vector N , associated with the pseudo-tensor tµ ν and superpotential Uµνλ , corresponds to a Hamiltonian H(Σ, N ) whose boundary term is given
by the expression B(N ) (and vice versa). The choice of the superpotential Uµνλ in the
pseudo-tensor determines a boundary term in the Hamiltonian (and vice versa).
Working this out in the forward direction, i.e. showing that the quasi-local energymomentum gives rise to the Hamiltonian in the way stated, goes in three main steps:
(1) Follow Einstein’s derivation of the pseudo-tensor tµ ν , in Section 1.3, and express
it in terms of the superpotential Uνµλ , in Eq. (24).
(2) “Integrate Einstein’s derivation” to get a pseudo-tensor, analogously to the steps
in Eqs. (16)-(18). Here, Chen, Nester et al. construct an energy-momentum quantity
P (N ) by integrating the total local energy-momentum density (including its matter and
gravitational contributions) over a three-dimensional spacelike hypersurface Σ. Upon the
use of the Einstein field equations, the result is a boundary term, i.e. an integral over ∂Σ.
Thus in this step they associate to each pseudo-tensor, and solution of Einstein’s field
equations, a quasi-local quantity—and this is their preferred formulation of the problem.
The details are as follows: they define energy and momentum by integrating Eq. (21)
with an arbitrary vector N :
Z
P (Σ, N ) :=
dΣν (T ν µ + tν µ )N µ
ΣZ
1
1
=
dΣν [(−Gν µ + κ T ν µ )N µ + ∂λ (N µ Uµνλ )]
κ
2
Z Σ
I
=
Hµ N µ +
B(N ) ,
(64)
Σ
∂Σ
106
See for example Jaramillo and Gourgoulhon (2011: pp. 97-102, 105-107) and Christodoulou and Yau
(1988: pp. 9-10).
39
1
dSνλ N µ Uµνλ
where I have introduced the notation Hµ = dΣν ( κ1 Gµ ν −Tµ ν ) and B(N ) = − 4κ
for the first and second terms, respectively, in the last line. Going from the first to the
second line uses Eq. (24), and going from the second to the third line uses Gauss’ law to
rewrite the total derivative, integrated over the hypersurface Σ, as an integral over the
boundary ∂Σ.
In this derivation, N is taken to be an arbitrary vector that is constant with respect to
the given system of coordinates. Such a vector always exists, although it will be different
for each system of coordinates. This will be an important point of discussion in Section
6, in connection with point (c) above.107 For the moment, I will set this aside.
As announced above, and as we see from the middle expression in Eq. (64), the volume
term in the Hamiltonian vanishes when Einstein’s field equations are satisfied, and we
are left only with the boundary term B(N ), integrated over a 2-surface. Thus we have
succeeded in constructing, from the local energy and momentum, a quasi-local quantity.108
(3) Recognise that the expression Eq. (64), which is already written in suggestive
notation, takes exactly the form of the Hamiltonian of general relativity, associated with
a finite region Σ and constant vector N :
P (Σ, N ) = −H(Σ, N ) .
(65)
The Hamiltonian is the generator of spacetime displacements of the hypersurface Σ along
a vector field N µ , and Hµ indeed has the form in Eq. (64), and vanishes if the field
equations are satisfied.
B(N ) is the boundary term of the Hamiltonian, which gives the quasi-local energy
and momentum, i.e. it is an expression for the energy and momentum on the 2-surface
∂Σ. This boundary term, as it appears in the above calculation starting from the pseudotensor, contains the superpotential. Given this correspondence, between superpotentials
and boundary terms, the Hamiltonian approach casts light on the physical significance
of the various choices of superpotentials. In particular, the variation of the boundary
term, δB(N ), must be set to zero in order to get the Einstein field equations in their
Hamiltonian form. Filling in various the choices of superpotential Uµνλ in this variation,
one finds that each choice of superpotential leads to a specific class of boundary conditions.
107
Nester (2020, personal communication) argues that, in Eq. (64), ‘the volume integrand is proportional
to the field equations, and so vanishes on-shell. The value of the integral comes only from the 2-surface
boundary term. This means that we can extend our formula, modifying the vector field N within the
region, without changing the value of the integral, as long as one keeps N constant on the boundary. Thus
it is only necessary for the vector field to match a translational Killing field of the Minkowski coordinate
reference geometry on the boundary’. Although this is of course true, the independence of the value of
the vector field N in the region inside the volume V is only valid in the last two lines of Eq. (64), i.e. for
the Hamiltonian expression. However, the step from the first to the second line of Eq. (64) does not hold
if N is not constant, because the second term is no longer a total derivative. In other words, the above
direct relation between the integrated total energy-momentum pseudo-tensor (i.e. energy-momentum plus
gravitational pseudo-tensor) and the Hamiltonian expression only holds if N is everywhere constant in
a system of coordinates adapted to the boundary. (Nester’s main interest is of course the Hamiltonian
formalism, and less so the pseudo-tensor. But, in so far as these papers aim to justify the use of pseudotensors through the Hamiltonian approach, my point is that this only works for constant vector fields N
and special systems of coordinates, as just argued).
108
This is true at least formally. See Section 6 for a discussion.
40
√
For example, the Freud expression, Eq. (23), corresponds to keeping g g µν fixed at the
boundary,109 while keeping the vector field N constant. Thus the Freud superpotential
allows Dirichet boundary conditions.
Other choices of superpotential lead to other boundary conditions, e.g. Neumann
boundary conditions where the momentum conjugate to the metric is held fixed. For
each choice of superpotential there is a corresponding boundary condition, and a quasilocal energy expression.
To show that the pseudotensor-Hamiltonian correspondence also works in the opposite
direction, one reverses the above steps: begin with the Hamiltonian, and show how its
boundary terms correspond to various superpotentials in the energy-momentum pseudotensor.
The expression Eq. (64) for the Hamiltonian, and in particular the various choices
of its boundary term, can be motivated further by using the Hamiltonian formalism.
To do this, Chen, Nester et al. construct the Hamiltonian of general relativity in form
notation. In this formalism, the various boundary terms B(N ), that naturally enforce
Dirichlet or Neumann boundary conditions in the variation, take simple forms in terms
of three geometrical quantities and their corresponding conjugate momenta: namely, the
metric, and the orthonormal frame and coframe fields. These relatively simple forms
of the boundary terms reproduce, when worked out in tensor components, the various
expressions for the superpotential found in the literature. Thus the form notation for the
Hamiltonian explains the relatively long tensor formulas for the superpotential through
simple boundary terms.
5.2
Recent philosophical discussions of energy conservation in
GR and pseudo-tensors
The philosophical discussion of energy conservation in general relativity revolves around
two main problems, mainly to do with problems (v) (lack of covariance, and lack of appropriate transformation properties) and (iii) (non-integrability) in Section 1.3. (Surprisingly,
Lam (2011: p. 1017) and Read (2020: p. 215) mention the problem (iv) of non-uniqueness,
which in my view is pressing, only in passing; other papers do not appear to mention it.)110
The first is about coordinate-dependence; the second is about background-dependence. I
give them new labels, (A) and (B), to cover other aspects of recent discussions:
(A) Lack of covariance, and lack of appropriate transformation properties. The known
expressions for the local energy and momentum in general relativity are not tensorial. In
particular, the pseudo-tensors Eq. (24) are coordinate-dependent, and so they do not have
good local (or global) definitions. (As I mentioned in Section 1.3, pseudo-tensors are only
invariant under affine transformations).
√
The condition is δ( g g µν ) = 0, which gives δg µν = 21 g µν gαβ δg αβ . This allows, but does not require,
the Dirichlet boundary condition δg µν = 0, and thus it is slightly more general than a Dirichlet boundary
condition.
110
Duerr (2019: pp. 2, 6, 9-10) does stress the importance of this ambiguity, which he calls ‘baneful’
(p. 9).
109
41
For example, Hoefer (2000: pp. 194-195) has stressed that the expressions for energy
and momentum, even in their integrated form Eq. (50), are coordinate-dependent, and so
are ill-defined—as I already mentioned at the end of Section 3.
One immediate comment to make about (A) is that it is diffeomorphism invariance,
rather than covariance, that is most important here: and that, as we saw in Section 4.3,
the various kinds of diffeomorphisms require a different treatments. Second, although the
lack of covariance can be technically and physically inconvenient, the main worry is the
pseudo-tensor’s lack of appropriate transformation properties.
(B) “Background-dependence”. The conservation of energy and momentum in general
relativity requires the introduction of “background structures”: such as a flat metric
(usually, at infinity) or timelike Killing vectors in the spacetime, see Eq. (15) and the
discussion following.111 Without such additional structures, the existing expressions for
the energy-momentum tensors do not express genuine conservation laws, and do not give
unique answers for the physical energy and momentum. While both Hoefer (2000) and
Lam (2011) admit that expressions like Eq. (50) do yield unambiguous results when such
structures are added, they ultimately reject them, because they amount to introducing
undesired “background structures”.112
For example, Hoefer (2000: p. 194) criticises the calculations of the energy-momentum
conservation equation Eq. (50) that evaluate integrals at infinity to get the total energy
and mass of the spacetime, because they assume that the spacetime is asymptotically
flat and that the coordinate system at infinity is Minkowskian. This does not give a
genuine conservation principle for general relativity, the most important reason being that
fixing the asymptotics in this way ‘goes against the most important and philosophically
progressive approach to spacetime physics: that of downplaying coordinate-dependent
notions and effects, and stressing the intrinsic, covariant and coordinate-independent as
what is important’. Thus points (A) and (B) are, for Hoefer, really part of a single worry:
namely, coordinate-dependence.113
Lam (2011: p. 1010) is more tolerant about coordinate-dependence: he concedes
that ‘there does not seem to be any contradiction’ in relying on ‘background-dependent
(coordinate-dependent) entities’. However, he worries that there is no unique definition
of pseudo-tensors, because the possibility to add a superpotential to them means that
‘one cannot say how much energy there is in a given spatial region’, i.e. problem (iv),
non-uniqueness.114
111
Absolute objects are defined e.g. in Anderson (1967: pp. 83-84; 1971: p. 166). However, as we will
discuss below, these background structures are not absolute objects in this sense.
112
Background-independence is obviously a large topic that I cannot enter in detail into here, nor will
that be required. For, as I mentioned before, the “background structures” discussed in this context are
not the same as the ones discussed in the literature on background-independence. Thus my comments will
be restricted to the specific discussion of the role of background structures in Noether’s second theorem.
For more general treatments of background-independence: see, for example, Pooley (2017: pp. 24-29) and
Read (2016a). For my own views about background-independence, see De Haro (2017).
113
Furthermore, Curiel (2019: p. 91) proves a theorem that there exists no local, divergence-free, covariant two-tensor other than a multiple of the Einstein tensor, and thus no such local candidates for a
gravitational energy-momentum tensor.
114
Pitts (2010: pp. 605-606) proposes to restore the covariance of the gravitational energy-momentum
42
But his main worry is about the introduction of “background structures”. For example,
although the standard integral formulation of the conservation equation with a Killing
vector, Eq. (19), is a genuine energy-momentum conservation law for the matter fields,
it requires the introduction of the Killing vector K, which Lam considers is an undesired
“non-dynamical background”. And likewise for the introduction of asymptotically flat
metrics at infinity in order to reproduce the ADM and Bondi formulas: these ‘depend
crucially on the background structures inserted in the form of asymptotic symmetries’
(p. 1022).
Read (2020) has recently responded (at least partially) to the critiques (A) and (B), by
arguing that a genuine stress-energy tensor does exist in general relativity, in both: (i) a
weak sense applicable in a certain class of models of the theory (namely, those that admit
appropriate Killing vectors), (ii) a strong sense, applicable in all models.
The above distinction between cases (i) and (ii) is underpinned by the existence of a
timelike Killing vector in the spacetime. Namely, in response to (B), Read (2020: p. 222)
argues that the Killing vector K that gives the well-defined energy conservation law
Eq. (20), should not be seen as “background structure”. For the existence of a Killing
vector is merely a property of the metric: if the metric has an isometry, then a Killing
vector exists. This simply means that the models with a Killing vector are a subset of all
the dynamically possible models of the theory: no additional structures are introduced
into the theory.
Read’s advocacy of energy-momentum conservation appeals to functionalism (i.e.
briefly, the idea that there exists in GR a quantity that fulfils the functional role of
gravitational stress-energy: cf. p. 224) and to the possibility of being a realist about
pseudo-tensors. The possibility of realism is motivated by Einstein’s (1918b: pp. 449-451)
own position that quantities can be coordinate-dependent, but still well-defined. Just
as the connection coefficients are frame-dependent and are intimately tied to the gravitational field115 (recall that the Newtonian gravitational potential arises from the Christoffel
symbols), it is prima facie plausible to interpret the gravitational pseudo-tensor as representing gravitational energy, momentum, and stress in a given frame of reference. Thus
Read proposes that gravitational stress-energy is always defined with respect to a given
frame of reference, analogously to how the relative velocity of a body is evaluated in the
rest frame of another body (but see the objections in the next Section).
He argues that in case (i), i.e. in those models admitting timelike Killing vectors, in
which the conservation law Eq. (19) exists, the quantity tµ ν does fulfil the role of a gravitational energy-momentum tensor, i.e. it fulfils a role analogous to that of gravitational
energy as traditionally conceived, and bears an appropriate relation to the gravitational
degrees of freedom. He proposes, based on (a) the pseudo-tensor’s fulfilling this functional
role, on (b) the larger explanatory apparatus that the advocates of gravitational energy
expressions by embracing their multiplicity: namely, by constructing a single geometric object whose
infinitely many components are the components of a given pseudotensor with respect to all possible
coordinate systems, so that they transform into each other under coordinate transformations. In the text
quoted, Lam is commenting on Pitts’ proposal, but similar remarks could apply to the pseudo-tensor
itself.
115
See Einstein (1916: p. 802), and also the discussion in Norton (1985: p. 233).
43
have available to them, and on (c) the simple and practical character of functionalism
involved: that, for this subset of models of the theory, the gravitational stress-energy
does exist, and should be labelled as genuine energy, momentum, and stress. Thus a
frame-independent gravitational stress-energy tensor does, in this sense, exist in general
relativity.
In case (ii), although a frame-independent stress-energy tensor is not available, one
can still be a realist about the pseudo-tensor. Namely, realism about the pseudo-tensor
is compatible with functionalism, since the pseudo-tensor may be defined, in each frame,
such that it is conserved. In particular, he argues from the broader idea that it is acceptable to give explanations of phenomena by appealing to coordinate-dependent effects.
If one accepts this realist line, then the gravitational stress-enegy exists in the stronger
sense, which is applicable to all the models of the theory.
While I will in part agree with Read’s two arguments in response to (A) and (B), I will
discuss, in the next Section, whether these arguments conclusively establish the existence
of local energy and momentum in general relativity—since indeed they do not offer a
satisfactory response to (A).
6
A Comparison of Two Proposals
In this Section, I will compare the two proposals for energy and momentum from the
previous two Sections. In Section 6.1, I discuss three worries about the gravitational
pseudo-tensor that, in my opinion, should be addressed before pseudo-tensors are taken
to be part of the ontology of general relativity. In Section 6.2, I will defend the holographic
stress-energy tensor from two general worries, articulated in the philosophical literature
on energy and momentum in general relativity, and already mentioned in the previous
Section. In Section 6.3, I will discuss further questions that one might have about the
physical interpretation of quasi-local quantities.
6.1
What else is required for us to accept pseudo-tensors?
In this Section I make three qualifications about Read’s (2020) rebuttal of (A) and (B).116
My second qualification is in the neighbourhood of a more technical objection by Duerr
(2019a: Section 3.3) (I will return to the resolution of a number of Duerr’s other objections
at the end of Section 6.2). My third qualification leads in to Section 6.2.
The first qualification is that, while Read (2020) frames his defence of pseudo-tensors
in terms of scientific realism, this is not necessary. For also the empiricist, e.g. van
Fraassen (1980), could argue along Read’s functionalist lines, and conclude that pseudotensors are physical quantities, which describe properties of some entities in the world—in
this case, an unobservable entity, viz. gravitational energy and momentum. Agreed: this
depends upon the empiricism under consideration. But the point is that the significance
116
A fourth point is that pseudo-tensors are non-unique because one can add an arbitrary superpotential
to them, and so it is not a priori clear how to interpret them. However, as I discussed in Section 3, this is
clarified by Noether’s second theorem, which establishes a clear relation between the superpotential and
the boundary term in the first variation of the action, see Eq. (32).
44
of pseudo-tensors goes beyond the question of whether there is a justified realism about
them: rather, it is a matter of whether the semantics of GR must invoke such an entity.
Thus while I agree that there is no a priori reason why coordinate-dependent quantities
could not be physical, and also that, in general, some coordinate-dependent quantities are
physical, I think that more work is required to admit these specific coordinate-dependent
quantities—pseudo-tensors—into one’s theory. This leads in to my next two points, about
further conditions that are required to ascribe to pseudo-tensors a semantics that is physically acceptable.
The second qualification is that, to accept pseudo-tensors as good physical quantities, one requires that they have well-defined transformation properties under (different
kinds of ) diffeomorphisms. (Of course, pseudo-tensors transform covariantly only under
affine transformations). Even if one is in principle sympathetic to the idea of coordinatedependent quantities, surely some relationship between the quantities in the different
coordinates, at least for special classes of coordinates, must be required before such quantities can be accepted in the theory.117 As the analogy below should make clear, the real
physical worry is that different coordinate systems would be, quite literally, incommensurable. This worry is, of course, in the neighbourhood of a closely related one: namely,
that pseudo-tensors are not geometric objects118 (see Anderson (1967: p. 424) and Duerr
(2019a: Section 3.3)). Therefore, it is not clear that the gravitational pseudo-tensor gives
well-defined values for the energy in the various coordinate systems.119 This is something
that Nester’s work, in my opinion, does not clarify.
Thus Hoefer’s (2000) argument that the quantities are not well-defined still seems
to have some force, because a satisfactory definition of energy and stress would involve
either giving their transformation rules or else giving a physical interpretation of the noncovariance (e.g. as in the case with boundaries, see Section 6.3). Lacking these, the realist
story about pseudo-tensors seems less convincing.
Consider the analogy with special relativity, where the 4-momentum vector p is a
physical quantity that transforms covariantly under Lorentz transformations, but its components are not invariant. Choose a coordinate system where we write (pµ ) = (E/c, p),
where E is the energy and p the spatial momentum as measured in those coordinates.
Then we know that E 2 /c4 and p2 are not invariant quantities, whereas their difference,
−E 2 /c4 + p2 , is invariant (and likewise for covariant quantities). The energy and the mo117
For example, when the number of spacetime dimensions is odd, under visible diffeomorphisms the
quasi-local stress-energy tensor picks up an anomalous term that is in general non-zero, i.e. Eq. (60).
Although this breaks covariance, it is a well-defined transformation law, and it is admissible.
118
However, as Trautman (1965: p. 86) points out, spinors are not geometric objects either.
119
In this context, Nester argues that the Hamiltonian is a fully covariant object, and that its significance
is independent of the coordinates. But this is not entirely satisfying, for two reasons: (i) As I already
mentioned in footnote 107, the direct relation Eq. (64) between the Hamiltonian and the pseudo-tensor
only holds for everywhere constant vector fields N : and so, a putative covariance of the Hamiltonian does
not automatically apply to the pseudo-tensor (which is expressly known to not be non-covariant). (ii) As
I mentioned in my reply to (A) in Section 5.2, covariance is not what matters the most, because it can be
easily achieved by introducing additional quantities. Specifically, the Hamiltonian depends on a choice of
vector field N , and the Hamiltonian approach is only covariant relative to a given such choice. But since
spacetimes do not come naturally equipped with vector fields, the Hamiltonian approach is dependent
on such a choice, which makes it liable to either: (a) introducing background structures, or (b) treating
different models differently.
45
mentum transform into each other under Lorentz transformations, and so their definition
depends on the coordinates chosen. Despite this coordinate-dependence, E and p are
physical quantities, and we can:
(1) define energy and momentum for each choice of coordinates (these definitions
being incompatible in the sense that what is defined as energy in one system is not the
energy in another system), and furthermore these definitions can be made operational
with respect to the corresponding frame, e.g. a preferred measuring apparatus;
(2) give well-defined transformation laws for E and p from one coordinate system to
another: namely, the Lorentz transformation law.
Property (2) seems to fail in the case of pseudo-tensors, and thus there is a disanalogy with other coordinate-dependent quantities that we are familiar with. The point
is not that pseudo-tensors fail to be covariant, but rather that there is no well-defined
transformation law between them.120 Even if it were still possible to define energy and
momentum in every coordinate system, as in (1), these different notions would be completely unrelated to each other—different coordinate systems would be, quite literally,
incommensurable.
The point is that it is not quite clear that one can simply drop the requirement of welldefined transformation properties under diffeomorphisms and put nothing in its place: a
coherent alternative for it seems required. At any rate, this is an objection that the
programme needs to address.121
A third qualification is that, even if Read’s arguments indeed allow taking pseudotensors as physical quantities, they do not require this. Pseudo-tensors might be the
correct definition of energy and momentum in general relativity—or they might not: for
there are alternative proposals—in particular, the quasi-local proposals. Thus the different
proposals need to be compared. I do this in the following Section.
6.2
Quasi-local expressions: superpotentials vs. the Brown-York
stress-energy tensor
In this Section, I will defend the ‘modified’ version of the Brown-York quasi-local stressenergy tensor from Section 4 as a preferred quasi-local definition of energy, momentum,
and stress in general relativity. I will partly do this by comparison with the other main
proposal, from Section 5: namely, the pseudo-tensor, and the quasi-local Hamiltonian
expression obtained from it. I will argue that the former is so far better developed,
and thus better able to answer various queries. Hence my favouring, on balance, the
Brown-York quasi-local stress-energy tensor. But since some of the details about the
pseudo-tensor approach have not been fully worked out, the latter approach, with all its
120
As I showed in Section 4.3, in spaces with boundaries, different kinds of diffeomorphisms need to be
distinguished, and for some diffeomorphism one may obtain a modified transformation law, involving the
anomalous term in Eq. (60).
121
Pitts (2010) is one such proposal. Duerr (2019a: Section 3.3) notices, that, while ‘nothing is inherently baneful about coordinate-dependent objects... [f]or pseudotensors... the coordinate-dependence is
“vicious” (Pitts): in general, the preferred coordinate transformations do not pick out the characteristic
invariants of the spacetime. The spacetime symmetries do not align with the pseudotensor’s symmetry
group’.
46
open questions, should still be considered.
By the ‘modified’ version of the Brown-York quasi-local stress-energy tensor’, or simply
the ‘Brown-York stress-energy tensor’, I will mean the quasi-local Brown-York stressenergy tensor from Section 4, modified, where this technique is available (i.e. in the case
Λ 6= 0, regardless of its sign),122 by the inclusion of counterterms: as opposed to the older
reference field configuration subtraction (see (B)-(b) below). This is all, in principle,
regardless of its possible holographic interpretation.
The quasi-local perspective has been almost entirely missed in recent philosophical
discussions of energy conservation. Lam (2011: p. 1022) mentions the existence of quasilocal stress-energy tensors, but then dismisses them, on two grounds:
(1) A ‘divide and conquer’ argument to the effect that there are different expressions
in the literature for such tensors, and that ‘the links betwen [them] are not always clear...
there is for the time being no consensus on how to build a ‘quasi-local’ notion of energy’.
(2) The quasi-local expressions allegedly also depend on particular background structures, ‘such as the dependence on some particular embedding or on some particular boundary conditions’.
I will respond to both arguments below. Let me here say, about (1), that it is not
a strong argument: for the mere existence of more than one expression, without further
analysis or elaboration, is not a good reason to reject them collectively, but rather to
further investigate which one is correct, or whether they are related. Furthermore, at
least in cases with a non-zero cosmological constant, and pace Szabados (2009) which
Lam cites, it is not really true that there is no consensus in—a large portion of—the
physics community about which is the preferred expression123 (by itself, this need of
course not be a sufficient reason to join the consensus, but neither should the reasons for
the consensus be ignored).
My comparison here will be along two main lines, which I will label (A) and (B),
that parallel the philosophical discussion in Section 5.2 (and go back to points (iii) and
(v) in Section 1.3). The first is a modification of point (A) in Section 5.2, namely:
diffeomorphism-invariance; the second is, like (B) in Section 5.2, about “backgrounddependence”, or the requirement that the theory should not contain any “background
structures”. Then, at the end of the Section, I will ask how the two approaches, the
pseudo-tensor/Hamiltonian and the Brown-York approaches, are related.
(A) The issue of diffeomorphism invariance. I begin with the Brown-York approach.
As I discussed in some detail in Section 4.3 for the case of spacetimes with a negative
cosmological constant, the properties of the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor
under diffeomorphisms of different kinds are well-understood, and can be summarised in
three points:
(1) The modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor is invariant under diffeomorphisms
that express true redundancies (in the sense of (Redundant)), i.e. invisible diffeomor122
The modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor, in the case Λ > 0, has been worked out in the
references in footnote 79.
123
The literature here is too large to survey. Some examples are e.g. the textbook Ammon and Erdmenger (2015: p. 210), Anninos et al. (2011: p. 5), Balasubramanian and Kraus (1999: p. 413), and
Skenderis (2001, 2002).
47
phisms.
(2) It is covariant under visible diffeomorphisms, i.e. those that generate a conformal
transformation on the boundary (see Eq. (63)).124
(3) It is not invariant under those diffeomorphisms that express physical transformations and are not (Redundant), i.e. those that give physically inequivalent solutions of
Einstein’s field equations. This is as one would expect (see also the discussion in the next
Section).
Thus the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor has correct transformation properties under these different kinds of diffeomorphisms.
Also, up to a possible anomaly of the diffeomorphism group of the type discussed in
Section 4.3, it is clear from the Brown-York construction that their stress-energy tensor
transforms covariantly with respect to arbitrary reparametrisations, ξi (x), of the boundary
manifold (i.e. a visible diffeomorphism) for any value of Λ. This shows that the modified
Brown-York stress-energy tensor is not liable to the allegation (A) from Section 5.2.
By contrast, in the case of pseudo-tensors and the quasi-local expressions derived from
them in Section 5, an analysis along these lines has, so far as I know, not been carried out.
There are, however, some remarks in the literature. For example, Chang et al. (1999: p. 3)
write:
[T]he energy-momentum defined by such a pseudotensor does not really depend on
the local value of the reference frame, it is actually quasi-local—it depends (through
the superpotenial) on the values of the reference frame (and the fields) only on the
boundary of a region.
The quote is perhaps somewhat optimistic. First, as I noticed in Section 5.1, there are
assumptions that go into deriving the quasi-local expression Eq. (64) from the pseudotensor, which surely do not involve just the boundary itself, but at least an open neighbourhood of it. Furthermore, the ‘dependence on the values of the reference frame’ of the
quasi-local energy that Chang et al. mention seems incompatible with its being covariant,
since the reference frame dependence comes in through the superpotential, which is not
a tensor, also not when evaluated at the boundary. In other words, we appear to be in
the situation that I discussed in Section 5.2, where there is a strong dependence on the
frame of reference chosen at the boundary, and apparently no rule to compare one system
to another.125 At any rate, these authors do not clarify how the coordinate-dependence
disappears. This contrasts with the Brown-York stress-energy tensor, which as I discussed in (2) does have satisfactory properties under changes of frame on the boundary.
Also, Chang et al. (1999) do not make a distinction between the diffeomorphisms (1)-(3),
whereas this is key to understand the transformation properties of the quasi-local energy.
In Chen et al. (1999: Section 2) and Nester (2004: pp. 272-275), a ‘covariant Hamiltonian formalism’ is worked out, in which as I already mentioned the various superpotentials
124
As I said before, I am ignoring the anomaly term in Eq. (60), which vanishes identically in fourdimensional spacetimes.
125
One might think that the Hamiltonian formalism comes to the rescue here. However, two problems
need to be addressed: first, the Hamiltonian depends on a choice of vector field N , and there is no
natural way to choose this vector field in a general manifold; second, relating the pseudo-tensor to the
Hamiltonian requires a constant vector field N , as already discussed in footnote 107.
48
are reproduced from relatively simple geometric expressions. Apart from the physical significance that one may ascribe to such covariance (see footnote 119), it is not clear how the
quasi-local energy and momentum transform under (non-affine) changes of frame on the
boundary, i.e. whether there is any way to compare quantities between different boundary
frames.
Either way, although the Hamiltonian approach to pseudo-tensors seems promising, it
needs more work before a full judgment about diffeomorphism invariance can be made.
(B) “Background-dependence”. Here, I begin with the pseudo-tensor/Hamiltonian approach. I already endorsed, in Section 5.2 (B), Read’s response to claims that pseudotensors require the introduction of background structures. Here I will defend the BrownYork approach, as regards background-independence. This will be three points, (a), (b),
(c), of which (a) is a brief response to certain criticisms of AdS-CFT:126
(a) It has occasionally, and informally, been claimed that the methods in AdS-CFT are
“background-dependent”, because they allegedly require the use of anti-de Sitter boundary conditions. This is part of a more general criticism, in Section 5.2-(B), that defining
asymptotic expressions for energy and momentum requires fixing the structure at infinity
(typically, a flat metric). Here, there are two points to be made.
First, the AdS-CFT correspondence, and in particular the calculation of the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor from Section 4.2, works for an arbitrary, smooth
boundary metric γ: and so, the claim that AdS-CFT requires ‘AdS boundary conditions’
is incorrect. This means that the space is not even asymptotically AdS: it is asymptotically locally AdS, i.e. there exists, in an open neighbourhood of the boundary, always a
choice of coordinates where the space looks like AdS—locally! But the space is in general
not AdS: it is only required that the boundary metric have conformal Killing vectors, as
in Eq. (63), if the CFT is to have a non-trivial conformal symmetry group. Thus the
boundary metric is taken to have conformal symmetries, but it does not need to have any
pre-determimed form, like e.g. being flat or being a round sphere. Examples in AdS-CFT
have been worked out for boundary manifolds of many different kinds.
Second, the above objection perhaps originates in a confusion about the role of boundary conditions in AdS-CFT. As I discussed in Section 4.1, the original Brown-York definition of the stress-energy tensor did have a dependence on a given, non-dynamical, background spacetime, through the introduction of the reference term in the action, Eq. (51).
But as I also noted after Eq. (53), this is not how the tensor is rendered finite in AdS-CFT.
Rather, one adds covariant counterterms that are intrinsic to the boundary. The renormalisation method, from Section 4.2, of adding boundary counterterms in the action, has
the advantage of removing another kind of background: namely, the reference spacetime.
Thus there is no reference spacetime that one needs to compare with.
(b) The role of boundary conditions in the approach that I am advocating here
thus differs from the idea of a reference field configuration or background subtraction.
For the boundary conditions required are merely those that are dictated by the fact
that Einstein’s equation is a second-order differential equation. For example, in globally
hyperbolic spacetimes, one standardly specifies data on an initial Cauchy surface in order
126
For a fuller treatment and references, see De Haro (2017: pp. 113-116); cf. footnote 112.
49
to solve Einstein’s equations (think of the analogy with the hole argument!).127 But
this is not in any sense a dependence on a background: rather, the specification of the
initial data is the specification of a solution among the set of all possible solutions. If the
spacetime had a boundary somewhere at a finite distance, in order to specify a solution
one would, in addition, need to specify boundary conditions. This is what one does when
one solves differential equations in spaces with boundaries: it has nothing to do with
imposing backgrounds, but rather with choosing one’s solution of interest out of the total
set.
Thus, the background-independence of the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor
is “as good as it gets” in general relativity.128
The situation is quite different for the pseudo-tensor and its quasi-local energy and
momentum. First of all, these methods have only been worked out using reference spacetimes, both in the cases Λ = 0 and Λ 6= 0. Furthermore, to my knowledge, the asymptotics
considered is only the simplest one: namely, Minkowski space and (A)dS space. Thus only
cases with a flat boundary metric γ have been considered. This may be only a matter of
technical development: but it is of course yet to be seen whether the pseudo-tensor gives
sensible (e.g. finite!) results in other cases.129
Nester (2004: p. 178) describes the problem as follows: ‘The pseudotensor coordinate
reference frame ambiguity now reappears in the guise of the reference field configration,
which must be specified on the boundary’.
Despite their differences, both approaches emphasise the physical importance of choosing boundary terms to define energy and momentum. In the superpotential approach,
boundary conditions/terms resolve the ambiguity in the specification of the superpotential. Also in the Brown-York approach are boundary terms central, since the stress-energy
tensor is defined directly in terms of boundary quantities.
This dependence of the energy and momentum on boundary conditions is natural: for
example, in classical mechanics, the momentum of a bullet of course depends on the initial
velocity with which it is shot.
(c) Nor should the requirement that the boundary spacetime has conformal Killing
vectors be seen as a dependence on a background, in the usual way. As Read (2020: p. 222)
mentions, choosing a Killing vector field is making a choice of a model among all the
possible dynamical models.
There is also a question of whether the pseudo-tensor and the Brown-York approach
127
There are of course also disanalogies: see Stachel (2014: pp. 14-15, 50).
Janssen (2014: pp. 198-202) discusses Einstein’s struggle, in his debate with de Sitter, with the need
to impose boundary conditions at infinity, and in connection his (failed) attempts to incorporate Mach’s
principle into general relativity. See also Norton (1993: pp. 806-809). In De Haro (2017: p. 115), I argue
that there are two distinct senses of ‘background-independence’: only one of which is implemented in
general relativity—hence the ‘as good as it gets’.
129
It also seems a sign of lack of communication between, at least some parts of, the communities that
the intrinsic renormalisation methods have not been applied, or even noticed, by those working on pseudotensors. For example, the review by Szabados (2009), written 12 years after gauge-gravity dualities were
discovered by Maldacena, makes a single passing mention of it, and takes no notice of how holographic
renormalisation improves on the existing methods, by not appealing to a reference spacetime (see the
discussion after Eq. (53)).
128
50
are directly related. It is unclear that they are, and a direct calculation of the Freud
superpotential for the case Λ < 0, which includes Dirichlet boundary conditions, does
not exhibit a clear or direct relationship to the Brown-York stress-energy tensor. Nester
(2004: p. 178) claims that the Hamiltonian formalism establishes a relation between the
two: ‘Quasilocally, with certain choices for the reference fields and displacement, [our
quasi-local expressions] reduce to the famous expressions of Brown and York’. However,
the exact relationship remains obscure.
As already discussed in Section 4.2, AdS-CFT gives, through its holographic correspondence with the expectation value of the stress-energy tensor of the dual quantum field
theory, Eq. (57), independent support to the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor
as being the gravitational energy and momentum.
The advantage of the quasi-local approach is perhaps best illustrated by mentioning
how it solves several problems that Duerr (2019a: Section 3.3) discusses in connection
with the pseudo-tensor (and, as I said earlier, I agree with much of Duerr’s critique).
The first has already been discussed: it is the lack of covariance, and the pseudotensor’s lacking appropriate transformation properties, i.e. my (v) from Section 1.3, which
is Duerr’s label (H1). The quasi-local stress-energy is both a geometric object and a (quasilocal) tensor under the relevant diffeomorphisms (see Section 4.3), and so this problem
does not appear.
Second, asymptotic flatness (Duerr 2019a: Section 3.3) is not a requirement of this
approach: since, as I have stressed, the quasi-local stress-energy tensor is well-defined
for both positive and negative values of Λ, and for arbitrary boundary conditions on the
metric, i.e. not just the purely de Sitter or purely anti-de Sitter boundary conditions. In
particular, this can be done for de Sitter-type solutions, which, in cosmological settings,
are more realistic than the asymptotically flat ones. Furthermore, the divergences can
be correctly renormalised by the method of holographic renormalisation. This is one of
Duerr’s main points of critique, and so this is a clear advantage of the quasi-local approach.
Third, as a general point (not specific to quasi-local energy): one of Duerr’s (2019a: Section 3.2) main criticisms to Read (2020) is that the latter assumes, rather than argues,
that the ambiguity of the pseudo-tensor can be resolved. But we have seen that Read’s
“assumption” is in fact vindicated by the details of Noether’s second theorem. For the
ambiguity is only apparent: it is fixed by a choice of boundary conditions, and of corresponding boundary terms (and this important point is common to all three approaches I
have discussed).
Gauge-gravity dualities also cast further light on the interpretation of these boundary
conditions. Each choice of boundary conditions corresponds to a different CFT (and also
a different common core theory): namely, a CFT where a different kind of source is held
fixed, with a different Lagrangian, and with a different path integral. The choices between
such CFT’s are different physical choices: which explains why their energies are different.
6.3
Interpreting quasi-local quantitites
Although, in previous Sections, I have addressed various objections to the quasi-local
energy-momentum expressions, one can still ask about the physical meaning of such quasilocal expressions. After all, the traditional view in general relativity is that physical
51
quantities are closely associated with geodesics and, in particular, with point coincidences,
that are used to delimit these quantities. Indeed, the view goes back to Einstein himself.130
In more substantivalist terms,131 it is points that are fundamental in general relativity, and
other meaningful geometric quantities ultimately reduce to quantities defined on points.
But the pseudo-quantities, especially the ones that—like the Brown-York stress-energy
tensor—are directly defined quasi-locally, without a local definition, would seem to give
some physical significance to spacelike two-surfaces, possibly located at infinity: and it is
not immediately clear what this means, both in terms of the theory’s ontology (should
we include surfaces in the theory’s ontology? And, if so, which ones?) and in empirical
terms (what is the empirical content of such terms?).
I will here offer a number of arguments to the effect that surfaces and boundaries should
be counted as part of general relativity’s ontology, and that they do have an empirical
meaning.
First, notice that the fact that points are regarded, by some substantivalists at least, as
fundamental, does not exclude the reality of finite surfaces, which, just like the manifold
itself, are made of points. Also boundaries can be understood in terms of neighbourhoods
of the manifold,132 and so as such what we call ‘the existence of a boundary’ is a topological
property of the manifold, which just is part of the ontology of the theory. Thus, once
we have a semantics for points and for neighbourhoods in general relativity (and the
latter are required for both topological and geometric reasons), this very semantics gives a
meaning to surfaces and boundaries. This point can also be argued from two philosophical
directions:
(a) An ontology that accepts points as objects should surely accept sets, classes, or
mereological fusions, of points. For example, this is standard in “free lunch” supervenience metaphysics: see Lewis (1986: pp. 211-212), Armstrong (1997: pp. 12-13), Sider
(2001: pp. xvi, 7, 59).
(b) As Butterfield (2011) argues, in his campaign against pointillisme, not all classical
physical quantities are defined at a point (where ‘defined at a point’ is here taken in the
sense of Lewis’ (1986a: pp. ix-xvi; 1994) Humean supervenience). Classical continuum
mechanics gives us many examples of ‘spatial extrinsicality: the way that an ascription
“reaches across space”’. In particular, boundaries and quasi-local energy and momentum
are as admissible in general relativity as they are in classical mechanics: ‘continuum
mechanics embraces spatial extrinsicality due to surface forces, acting at a point, with
respect to a surface through that point (see Butterfield, 2011: pp. 354, 356; my emphasis).
Second, there is no contradiction with any fact about general relativity if it turns out
that energy and momentum can only be defined quasi-locally but not everywhere locally.
There is no a priori reason why energy and momentum should exist everywhere locally
on the manifold (see e.g. Lam, 2011: p. 1023). So, if some quasi-local notion of energy
130
See Einstein (1916: p. 776) and Kretschmann (1917: pp. 576-577, 579). However, elsewhere Einstein
(1915c: p. 228) considers physically real events as consisting of more general spatio-temporal coincidences.
For a discussion of Einstein’s (1916) paper and its prehistory, see Sauer (2005). The point-coincidence
argument, and how Einstein sees in it an implicit objection to the hole argument, are discussed on p. 816.
131
For a review of substantivalist and anti-substantivalist arguments, see Pooley (2012: pp. 47-63).
132
The boundary of a manifold M is the set of points p such that p has no neighbourhood homeomorphic
with an open set of Rn , where n is the dimension of the manifold.
52
and momentum is well-defined, rather than being regarded with suspicion, it should be a
welcome possibility.
Third, there are several physical reasons to consider boundaries, and stress-energy
tensors as physical quantities defined on them. One reason is that one is interested
in considering open systems, i.e. finite regions of the universe. In such cases, the nonvanishing of the right-hand side of Eq. (54) is interpreted as matter entering or leaving the
region through the boundary. These open systems are very important for several reasons:
as modelling a real system (e.g. a black hole, and the gravitational waves that it emits), or
as a way to generate new solutions by gluing a given solution to other solutions through the
boundary (for example, solutions with different values of the cosmological constant, with
so-called ‘domain walls’ in between: see e.g. Freedman et al. (1999: pp. 376-377), Ammon
and Erdmenger (2015, p. 302-304); for gluing of spacetimes in a cosmological context, see
Carrera and Giulini (2010: pp. 170, 181)). One then needs to match the conditions of
the two solutions at the boundary, and the boundary metric and its conjugate variable,
viz. the stress-energy tensor, are the two canonical variables to control at the boundary.133
More generally, in semi-classical descriptions of quantum gravity theories, where the
solutions of general relativity coupled to matter contain objects such as strings and Dbranes, higher-dimensional surfaces such as the ones considered here “stand ready” for an
interpretation in terms of extended material membranes, i.e. as a natural generalisation
of the notion of a geodesic. In other words, such surfaces must be considered, if general
relativity is to be the semi-classical limit of these theories of quantum gravity.
7
Summary and Conclusion
In Section 1.3, I identified five putative, inter-dependent, problems for local definitions of
energy and momentum in general relativity:
(i) the Hilbert-Klein-Noether worry that the conservation laws of GR are identities,
with no physical content;
(ii) the lack of a gravitational energy-momentum tensor, analogous to the matter
energy-momentum tensor;
(iii) the lack of integral conservation laws, because of the lack of a timelike Killing
vector field in a general spacetime;
(iv) the non-uniqueness of the gravitational energy-momentum pseudo-tensor; and
(v) its lacking covariance, and its lacking appropriate geometric properties.
The Hilbert-Klein-Noether worry, (i), was addressed in Sections 2.2 and 2.3, where I
argued that the conservation of energy and momentum in GR does have physical content.
The lack of a gravitational energy-momentum tensor, (ii), can be resolved in two ways:
either by introducing the gravitational pseudo-tensor, or by defining quasi-local quantities.
133
If the Brown-York stress-energy tensor is evaluated not at conformal infinity, but at some finite
distance, then this can have several other applications in string physics. For example, the universe is
modelled in some models as the four-dimensional boundary of a five-dimensional space, placed at finite
distance from the centre of the space (so that we ‘live on a D-brane’: see e.g. Randall and Sundrum
(1999: p. 4690)). In that case, the Brown-York stress-energy tensor of the five-dimensional space acts
as an extra source for the matter energy-momentum appearing in the four-dimensional Einstein field
equations on the D-brane (De Haro et al. 2001a: p. 3171).
53
I then analysed two quasi-local proposals, and specialised questions (iii) to (v) to these
proposals.
About the lack of a timelike Killing vector field, (iii), in a general spacetime: while I
accept that this is prima facie a problem for local expressions, I noted that the modified
Brown-York stress-energy tensor only requires the existence of a conformal Killing vector
field at the quasi-local surface (usually: the asymptotic boundary).
I also argued that the putative non-uniqueness, (iv), of the gravitational energymomentum pseudotensor, i.e. the ability to add an “arbitrary” superpotential, is fixed
by Noether’s theorem directly in terms of the variation of the action, as one sees from
Eqs. (32)-(26). Specifically, it is fixed by a choice of boundary terms. So far as I know,
this possibility has not been used in the literature before, to solve the problem of nonuniqueness.134 In more detail: one can understand the ability to add an abitrary term
to the superpotential as the ability to add an arbitrary boundary term to the action
without changing the equations of motion; (this then agrees with results by Chang et
al. (1999: p. 1898) in the Hamiltonian formalism).
An important point is that standard arguments in gauge-gravity dualities, which interpret the duality in terms of a common core shared between two isomorphic models, further
support the statement that the Brown-York stress-energy tensor correctly represents the
quasi-local energy and stress of general relativity, in the corresponding spacetimes.
Finally, point (v) about covariance, and the lack of appropriate transformation properties, was re-phrased in terms of two different notions: (A) diffeomorphism invariance,
and (B) background-independence. This was done in Section 5.2 onwards.
About (A): I summarised, in Section 4.3, the properties of the modified Brown-York
stress-energy tensor under three relevant kinds of diffeomorphisms. (1) The modified
Brown-York stress-energy tensor is correctly invariant under ‘invisible’, i.e. (Redundant),
diffeomorphisms. (2) It is correctly non-invariant under ‘large’, i.e. always non-redundant,
diffeomorphisms, because they relate different models. (3) ‘Visible’ diffeomorphisms correctly give conformal transformations at infinity. These diffeomorphisms thus correspond
to the conformal transformations of the conformal field theory. (The results were obtained
for Λ < 0, but I argued that they can be extended to Λ > 0).
About (B): I agreed with Read’s (2020) defence of the background-independence of expressions involving Killing vectors: although, as mentioned under (iii), the Killing vectors
required for the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor to give an integral conservation
law satisfy a weaker condition. Also, I noted that the Brown-York stress-energy tensor
can be defined for any smooth boundary metric γ, and I clarified the role of the boundary
conditions.
In sum, the modified Brown-York stress-energy tensor gives the clearest analysis and
resolution, so far, of the above problems. As for admitting the gravitational pseudotensor itself into the ontology of general relativity: I argued that there are valid points
in Read’s (2020) defence of pseudo-tensors, although important questions remain open
(especially, about its transformation properties, and about which proposal is correct).
The Chang et al. (1999) and Chen et al. (2017, 2018) quasi-local proposal, and its relation
to the Hamiltonian of GR, also seems promising, and it clarifies the differences between
134
See footnote 57 for a brief discussion of the literature on this point.
54
the different pseudo-tensors used in the literature: but it also faces additional questions
(especially, about the status of the vector field N ).
Acknowledgements
I thank Bryan Roberts and Nic Teh for organising the conference ‘The Philosophy and
Physics of Noether’s Theorems’ at the University of Notre Dame, London Global Gateway,
and James Read, Bryan Roberts, and Nic Teh, for their invitation to contribute to this
volume. I thank James Nester for detailed correspondence and for his patience answering
my questions, and James Read, Henrique Gomes, Harvey Brown, Jeremy Butterfield,
and Jeroen van Dongen for comments. I also thank audiences at the University of Notre
Dame, London Global Gateway, the Hong Kong University of Science and Technology,
and the Tsinghua Sanya International Mathematics Forum in Hainan, China.
References
Ammon, M., Erdmenger, J. (2015). Gauge/Gravity Duality. Foundations and Applications.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Anderson, J. L. (1967). Principles of Relativity Physics. New York, London: Academic Press.
Anderson, J. L. (1971). ‘Covariance, Invariance, and Equivariance: A Viewpoint’. General
Relativity and Gravitation, vol. 2, 2, pp. 161-172.
Anninos, D., Ng, G.S., Strominger, A. (2011). ‘Asymptotic Symmetries and Charges in De
Sitter Space’, Classical and Quantum Gravity 28, 175019. [arXiv:1009.4730 [gr-qc]].
Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Arnowitt, R., Deser, S., and Misner, C. W. (1959). ‘Dynamical structure and definition of energy
in general relativity’. Physical Review, 116 (5), p. 1322.
Arnowitt, R., Deser, S., Misner, C. W. (1962). ‘The Dynamics of General Relativity’. In:
Witten, L. (Ed.), Gravitation: An Introduction to Current Research, Chapter 7. New York:
Wiley. Reprinted in: ‘Republication of: The dynamics of general relativity’. General Relativity
and Gravitation, 2008, 40 (9), pp. 1997-2027. arXiv:gr-qc/0405109.
Ashtekar, A. and Hansen, R. O. (1978). ‘A unified treatment of null and spatial infinity in
general relativity. I. Universal structure, asymptotic symmetries, and conserved quantities at
spatial infinity’. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 19, pp. 1542-1566.
Balasubramanian, V., de Boer, J. and Minic, D. (2001). ‘Mass, Entropy, and Holography in
Asymptotically de Sitter Spaces’. Physical Review, D, 65, 123508, pp. 1-15.
55
Balasubramanian, V. and Kraus, P. (1999). ‘A Stress Tensor for Anti-de Sitter Gravity’. Communications in Mathematical Physics, 208, pp. 413-428. arXiv: hep-th/9902121.
Bañados, M. and Reyes, I. (2016). ‘A Short Review of Noether’s Theorems, Gauge Symmetries
and Boundary Terms’. International Journal of Modern Physics, D, 25 (10), 1630021.
Barbashov, B. M. and Nesterenko, V. V. (1983). ‘Continuous Symmetries in Field Theory’.
Fortschritte der Physik, 31 (10), pp. 535-367.
Belinfante, F. J. (1939). ‘On the Spin Angular Momentum of Mesons’. Physica IV, 9, pp. 887898.
Belot, G. (2013). ‘Symmetry and Equivalence’. In: The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of
Physics, Batterman, R. (Ed.), chapter 9. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Belot, G. (2018). ‘Fifty Million Elvis Fans Can’t Be Wrong’. Noûs, 52 (4), pp. 946-981.
Bergmann, P. G. (1958). ‘Conservation Laws in General Relativity as the Generators of Coordinate Transformations’. Physical Review, 112 (1), pp. 287-289.
Bessel-Hagen, E. (1921). ‘Über die Erhaltungssätze der Elektrodynamik’. Mathematische Annalen, 84, pp. 258-276. English translation by M. Albinus and N. H. Ibragimov: ‘On Conservation Laws of Electrodynamics’, in Archives of ALGA, volume 3 (2006), pp. 33-51. ALGA Publications. https://www.researchgate.net/publication/311456950 Archives of ALGA vol 3. The
page numbers in the text refer to the English translation.
Bondi, H., van der Burg, M. G. J., Metzner, A. W. K. (1962). ‘Gravitational Waves in General
Relativity. VII. Waves from Axi-Symmetric Isolated Systems’, Proceedings of the Royal Society
of London. Series A, Mathematical and Physical Sciences, 269 (1336), pp. 21-52.
Brading, K. (2005). ‘A Note on General Relativity, Energy Conservation, and Noether’s Theorems’. In: The Universe of General Relativity, Kox, A. J. and Eisenstaedt, J. (Eds.), pp. 125-135.
Boston and Berlin: Birkhäuser.
Brading, K. and Brown, H. R. (2000). ‘Noether’s Theorems and Gauge Symmetries’. arXiv:hepth/0009058.
Brading, K. and Brown, H. R. (2003). ‘Symmetries and Noether’s Theorems’. In: Brading,
K. and Castellani, E. (Eds.), Symmetries in Physics. Philosophical Reflections, pp. 89-109.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brading, K. and Brown, H. R. (2004). ‘Are Gauge Symmetry Transformations Observable?’
The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, pp. 645-665.
Brown, H. R. (2005). Physical Relativity. Space-time Structure from a Dynamical Perspective.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
56
Brown, H. R. (2020). ‘Do Symmetries “Explain” Conservation Laws? The Modern Converse
Noether Theorem vs. Pragmatism’. This volume.
Brown, H. R. and Brading, K. A. (2002). ‘General Covariance from the Perspective of Noether’s
Theorems’. PhilSci: 821. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/821.
Brown, J. D. and Henneaux, M. (1986). ‘Central Charges in the Canonical Realization of
Asymptotic Symmetries: An Example from Three-Dimensional Gravity’, Communications in
Mathematical Physics 104, pp. 207-226.
Brown, J. D. and York, Jr., J. W. (1993). ‘Quasilocal Energy and Conserved Charges Derived
from the Gravitational Action’. Physical Review D, 47, pp. 1407-1419.
Butterfield, J. N. (2011). ‘Against Pointillisme: A Call to Arms’. In: Explanation, Prediction,
and Confirmation, Dieks, D., Gonzalez, W. J., Hartmann, S., Uebel, T., Weber, M. (Eds.),
pp. 347-365. Dordrecht: Springer.
Butterfield, J. N. (2020). ‘On Dualities and Equivalences Between Physical Theories’. Forthcoming in Space and Time after Quantum Gravity, Huggett, N. and Wüthrich, C. (Eds.).
Carrera, M. and Giulini, D. (2010). ‘Influence of Global Cosmological Expansion on Local
Dynamics and Kinematics’. Reviews of Modern Physics, 82 (1), pp. 169-208.
Caulton, A. (2015). ‘The Role of Symmetry in the Interpretation of Physical Theories’. Studies
in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52, pp. 153-162.
Chang, C. -C., Nester, J. M., and Chen, C.-M (1999). ‘Pseudotensors and Quasilocal EnergyMomentum’. Physical Review Letters, 83.10: 1897. arXiv:gr-qc/9809040.
Chen, C.-M., Nester, J. M., Tung, R.-S. (2017). ‘Gravitational Energy for GR and Poincaré
Gauge Theories: a Covariant Hamiltonian Approach’. In: Ni, W.-T. (Ed.), One Hundred Years
of General Relativity. From Genesis and Empirical Foundations to Gravitational Waves, Cosmology and Quantum Gravity, Volume 1, pp. 187-261. arXiv:1507.07300 [gr-qc].
Chen, C.-M., Liu, J.-L, Nester, J. M. (2018). ‘Gravitational Energy is Well-Defined’. International Journal of Modern Physics D, 27 (14), 1847017. arXiv: 1805.07692. (Page numbers refer
to the arXiv version).
Chen, C.-M., Liu, J.-L., Nester, J. M. (2018a). ‘Quasi-Local Energy from a Minkowski Reference’. General Relativity and Gravitation, 50, 158, pp. 1-14. arXiv:1811.05640 [gr-qc].
Christodoulou, D. and Yau, S.-T. (1988). ‘Some Remarks on the Quasi-Local Mass’. In: Isenberg, J. A. (Ed.), Mathematics and General Relativity, pp. 9-14. Providence, Rhode Island:
American Mathematical Society.
Corry, L. (1999). ‘Hilbert and Physics (1900-1915)’. In: The Symbolic Universe. Geometry and
57
Physics 1890-1930, J. Gray (Ed.), pp. 145-188. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Corry, L. (2004). David Hilbert and the Axiomatization of Physics (1898-1918). From Grundlagen der Geometrie to Grundlagen der Physik. Dordrecht: Springer.
Corry, L., Renn, J. and Stachel, J. (1997). ‘Belated Decision in the Hilbert-Einstein Priority
Dispute’. Science, 278 (5341), pp. 1270-1273.
Curiel, E. (2019). ‘On Geometric Objects, the Non-Existence of a Gravitational Stress-Energy
Tensor, and the Uniqueness of the Einstein Field Equation’. Studies in History and Philosophy
of Modern Physics, 66, pp. 90-102.
De Haro, S. (2017). ‘Dualities and Emergent Gravity: Gauge/Gravity Duality’, Studies in
History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 59, pp. 109-125. arXiv:1501.06162 [physics.hist-ph].
De Haro, S. (2017a). ‘The invisibility of Diffeomorphisms’. Foundations of Physics, 47, pp. 14641497. arXiv:1709.01949 [gr-qc].
De Haro, S. (2020). ‘Spacetime and Physical Equivalence’. In: Beyond Spacetime. The Foundations of Quantum Gravity, Huggett, N., Matsubara, K. and Wüthrich, C. (Eds.), pp. 257-283.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. arXiv:1707.06581 [hep-th].
De Haro, S. (2021). ‘The Empirical Under-Determination Argument Against Scientific Realism
for Dual Theories’. Erkenntnis, https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00342-0.
De Haro, S., Skenderis, K., and Solodukhin, S. (2001). ‘Holographic reconstruction of spacetime and renormalization in the AdS/CFT correspondence”, Communications in Mathematical
Physics, 217 (3), pp. 595-622. arXiv:hep-th/0002230.
De Haro, S., Skenderis, K. and Solodukhin, S. N. (2001a). ‘Gravity in Warped Compactifications and the Holographic Stress-Tensor’. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 18, pp. 3171-3180.
arXiv:hep-th/0011230.
De Haro, S. , Mayerson, D. and Butterfield, J. N. (2016). ‘Conceptual Aspects of Gauge-Gravity
Duality’. Foundations of Physics, 46, pp. 1381-1425.
De Haro, S., Teh, N. and Butterfield, J. N. (2015). ‘On the Relation between Dualities and
Gauge Symmetries’. Philosophy of Science, 83 (5), pp. 1059-1069.
De Haro, S., Teh, N. and Butterfield, J. N. (2017). ‘Comparing dualities and gauge symmetries’,
Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 59 (2017), pp. 68-80. arXiv:1603.08334.
De Haro, S. and Butterfield, J.N. (2018). ‘A Schema for Duality, Illustrated by Bosonization’.
In: Foundations of Mathematics and Physics One Century After Hilbert, Kouneiher, J. (Ed.),
pp. 305-376. Springer. arXiv:1707.06681 [physics.hist-ph].
Dieks, D., Dongen, J. van, Haro, S. de (2015). ‘Emergence in Holographic Scenarios for Gravity’.
58
Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 52 (B), pp. 203-216. arXiv:1501.04278
[hep-th].
Duerr, P. M. (2019). ‘Fantastic Beasts and Where (Not) to Find them: Energy Conservation
and Local Gravitational Energy in General Relativity’. Studies in History and Philosophy of
Modern Physics, 65, pp. 1-14.
Duerr, P. M. (2019a). ‘Against ‘functional gravitational energy’: a critical note on functionalism,
selective realism, and geometric objects and gravitational energy’. Synthese,
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02503-3.
Einstein, A. (1914). ‘Die formale Grundlage der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie’. Königlich
Preuβische Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin). Sitzungsberichte, pp. 1030-1085. In: The
Collected Papers of Albert Einstein, Vol. 6, Doc. 9, pp. 72-130. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Einstein, A. (1915). ‘Zur allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie’. Königlich Preuβische Akademie der
Wissenschaften (Berlin). Sitzungsberichte, pp. 778-786. In: The Collected Papers of Albert
Einstein, Vol. 6, Doc. 21, pp. 214-224. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1915a). ‘Zur allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie (Nachtrag)’. Königlich Preuβische
Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin). Sitzungsberichte, pp. 799-801. In: The Collected Papers
of Albert Einstein, Vol. 6, Doc. 22, pp. 225-229. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1915b). ‘Die Feldgleichungen der Gravitation’. Königlich Preuβische Akademie
der Wissenschaften (Berlin). Sitzungsberichte, pp. 844-847. In: The Collected Papers of Albert
Einstein, Vol. 6, Doc. 25, pp. 225-229. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1915c). Letter to Paul Ehrenfest. In: The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein,
Vol. 8A, Doc. 173, pp. 228-229. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1916). ‘Die Grundlage der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie’. Annalen der Physik,
49, pp. 769-822. In: The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein, Vol. 6, Doc. 30, pp. 284-339.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1916a). ‘Hamiltonsches Prinzip und allgemeine Relativitätstheorie’. Königlich
Preuβische Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin). Sitzungsberichte, pp. 1111-1116. In: The
Collected Papers of Albert Einstein, Vol. 6, Doc. 41, pp. 410-416. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1918). Letter to F. Klein, 13 March 1918. In: The Collected Papers of Albert
Einstein, Vol. 8B, Doc. 480, pp. 673-675. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1918a). Letter to F. Klein, 24 March 1918. In: The Collected Papers of Albert
Einstein, Vol. 8B, Doc. 492, pp. 697-700. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1918b). ‘Der Energiesatz in der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie’, Königlich Preuβische
59
Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin). Sitzungsberichte, pp. 448-459. In: The Collected Papers
of Albert Einstein, Vol. 7, Doc. 9, pp. 63-77. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. and Grossman, M. (1913). ‘Entwurf einer Verallgemeinerten Relativitẗstheorie und
einer Theorie der Gravitation’. Teubner, Leipzig. In: The Collected Papers of Albert Einstein,
Vol. 4, Doc. 13, pp. 302-343. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Fefferman, C. and Graham, C.R. (1985). ‘Conformal invariants’, in Elie Cartan et les Mathématiques
d’aujourd’hui, Astérisque, 95.
Fefferman, C. and Graham, C.R. (2012). ‘The Ambient Metric’, Annals of Mathematics Studies,
number 178. Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press. http://arxiv.org/abs/0710.0919.
Freedman, D. Z., Gubser, S. S., Pilch, K., Warner, N. P. (1999). ‘Renormalization Group Flows
from Holography: Supersymmetry and a c-Theorem’. Advances in Theoretical and Mathematical
Physics, 3 (2), pp. 363-417. arXiv:hep-th/9904017.
Freud, Ph. (1939). ‘Über die Ausdrücke der Gesamtenergie und des Gesamtimpulses eines
Materiellen Systems in der Allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie’. Annals of Mathematics, 40 (2),
pp. 417-419.
Friederich, S. (2015). ‘Symmetry, Empirical Equivalence, and Identity’. The British Journal for
the Philosophy of Science, 66, pp. 537-559.
Geroch, R. (1972). ‘Structure of the Gravitational Field at Spatial Infinity’, Journal of Mathematical Physics, 13, pp. 956-968.
Goldberg, J. N. (1958). ‘Conservation Laws in General Relativity’. Physical Review, 111 (1),
pp. 315-320.
Gomes, H. (2020). ‘Holism as the Empirical Significance of Symmetries’. arXiv:1910.05330
[physics.hist-ph], https://arxiv.org/abs/1910.05330.
Gomes, H. and Riello, A. (2020). ‘Large Gauge Transformations, Gauge Invariance, and the
QCD θ-Term’. arXiv:2007.04013 [physics.hist-ph], https://arxiv.org/abs/2007.04013.
Greaves, H. and Wallace, D. (2014). ‘Empirical Consequences of Symmetries’. The British
Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, pp. 59-89.
Grumiller, D. and Riegler, M. (2016). ‘Most general AdS3 boundary conditions’. The Journal
of High-Energy Physics, 1610, 023, pp. 1-22. arXiv:1608.01308 [hep-th].
Harlow, D. and Stanford, D. (2011). ‘Operator Dictionaries and Wave Functions in AdS/CFT
and dS/CFT’. arXiv:1104.2621 [hep-th].
Hawking, S. W. (1979). ‘The Path-Integral Approach to Quantum Gravity’. In: General Relativity. An Einstein Centenary Survey, Hawking, S. W. and Israel, W. (Eds.). Cambridge:
60
Cambridge University Press.
Hawking, S. W. and Horowitz, G. T. (1996). ‘The Gravitational Hamiltonian, Action, Entropy,
and Surface Terms’. Classical and Quantum Gravity, 13, pp. 1487-1498.
Healey, R. (2009). ‘Perfect Symmetries’. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60,
pp. 697-720.
Heemskerk, I. and Polchinski, J. (2011). ‘Holographic and Wilsonian Renormalization Groups’.
Journal of High-Energy Physics, 6, 31, pp. 1-27. arXiv:1010.1264 [hep-th].
Henningson, M. and Skenderis, K. (1998). ‘The Holographic Weyl Anomaly’. The Journal of
High-Energy Physics, 7, 23, pp. 1-11. arXiv: hep-th/9806087.
Hilbert, D. (1916). ‘Die Grundlagen der Physik (Erste Mitteilung). Nachrichten von der
Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse, Heft 3, pp. 395407.
Hilbert, D. (1917). ‘Die Grundlagen der Physik (Zweite Mitteilung). Nachrichten von der
Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse, pp. 53-76.
Hilbert, D. (1924). ‘Die Grundlagen der Physik’. Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse, pp. 1-32.
Hoefer, C. (2000). ‘Energy Conservation in GTR’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern
Physics, 31 (2), pp. 187-199.
Horský, J. and Novotný, J. (1969). ‘Conservation Laws in General Relativity’. Czechoslovak
Journal of Physics, B 19, pp. 419-442.
Huggett, N. (2017). ‘Target Space 6= Space’. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern
Physics, 59, pp. 81-88.
Huggett, N. and Wüthrich, C. (2020). Out of Nowhere: Duality, Chapter 7. Oxford: Oxford
University Press (forthcoming). http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/17217.
Imbimbo, C., Schwimmer, A., Theisen, S., Yankielowicz, S. (2000). ‘Diffeomorphisms and Holographic Anomalies’, Classical and Quantum Gravity, 17, pp. 1129-1138. [hep-th/9910267].
Ismael, J. and van Fraassen, B. (2003). ‘Symmetry as a Guide to Superfluous Theoretical
Structure’. In: Symmetries in Physics. Philosophical Reflections, Brading, K. and Castellani,
E. (Eds.), pp. 371-392. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jacobson, T., Kang, G. and Myers, R. C. (1994). ‘On Black Hole Entropy’. Physical Review D,
49, pp. 6587-6598. arXiv:gr-qc/9312023.
Janssen, M. (2014). “No Success Like Failure...’: Einstein’s Quest for General Relativity’.
61
In: The Cambridge Companion to Einstein, Janssen, M. and Lehner, C. (Eds.), pp. 167-227.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Janssen, M. and Renn, J. (2007). ‘Untying the Knot: How Einstein Found his Way Back to
Field Equations Discarded in the Zurich Notebook’. In: The Genesis of General Relativity,
Renn, J. and Schemel, M. (Eds.), Volume 2, Einstein’s Zurich Notebook: Commentary and
Essays, pp. 839-925. Dordrecht: Springer.
Jaramillo, J. L. and Gourgoulhon, E. (2011). ‘Mass and Angular Momentum in General Relativity’. In: Blanchet, L., Spallicci, A., Whiting, B. (Eds.), Mass and Motion in General Relativity,
pp. 87-124. Springer.
Kastrup, H. (1987). ‘The Contributions of Emmy Noether, Felix Klein and Sophus Lie to the
Modern Concept of Symmetries in Physical Systems’. In: Doncel, M. G., Hermann, A., Michel,
L., Pais, A. (Eds.), Symmetries in Physics (1600-1980), proceedings of the 1st International
Meeting on the History of Scientific Ideas held at Sant Feliu de Guı́xols, Catalonia, Spain.
Klein, F. (1917). ‘Zu Hilberts erster Note über die Grundlagen der Physik’. Nachrichten von der
Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse, pp. 469-482.
Klein, F. (1918). ‘Über die Differentialgesetze für die Erhaltung von Impuls und Energie in
der Einsteinschen Gravitationstheorie’. Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften
zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse, pp. 171-189.
Klein, F. (1918a). Letter to A. Einstein, 20 March 1918. In: The Collected Papers of Albert
Einstein, Vol. 8, Doc. 487, pp. 685-690. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Komar, A. (1958). ‘Covariant Conservation Laws in General Relativity’. Physical Review, 113
(3), pp. 934-936.
Kosmann-Schwarzbach, Y. (2011). The Noether Theorems. New York Dodrecht Heidelberg
London: Springer.
Kosmann-Schwarzbach, Y. (2020). ‘The Noether Theorems in Context’. This volume.
arXiv:2004.09254 [math.HO].
Kosso, P. (2000). ‘The Empirical Status of Symmetries in Physics’. The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 51 (1), pp. 81-98.
Kretschmann, E. (1917). ‘Über den physikalischen Sinn der Relativitätspostulate, A. Einsteins
neue und seine ursprüngliche Relativitätstheorie’. Annalen der Physik, 53 (16), pp. 575-614.
Kucharzewski, M. and Kuczma, M. (1964). ‘Basic Concepts of the Theory of Geometric Objects’.
Warsaw: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Lam, V. (2011). ‘Gravitational and Nongravitational Energy: The Need for Background Structures’. Philosophy of Science, 78, pp. 1012-1023.
62
Landau, L. D. and Lifshitz, E. M. (1971). The Classical Theory of Fields. Oxford and New
York: Pergamon Press, Third Revised English Edition.
Landsman, K. (2020). Foundations of General Relativity: From Geodesics to Black Holes.
Forthcoming at Nijmegen: Radboud University Press.
Lehmkuhl, D. (2019). ‘The Equivalence Principle(s)’. Forthcoming in: Routledge Companion to
the Philosophy of Physics. Routledge.
Lehmkuhl, D., Schiemann, G., and Scholz, E. (2017). Towards a Theory of Spacetime Theories’.
Springer.
Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.
Lewis, D. (1986a). Philosophical Papers, Volume II. New York, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Lewis, D. (1994). ‘Humean Supervenience Debugged’. Mind, 103 (412), pp. 473-490.
Maggiore, M. (2005). A Modern Introduction to Quantum Field Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Misner, C. W., Thorne, K. S., Wheeler, J. A. (1973). Gravitation. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman
and Company.
Murgueitio Ramı́rez, S. (2020). ‘A puzzle concerning local symmetries and their empirical
significance’. Forthcoming in The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. http://philsciarchive.pitt.edu/17002.
Murgueitio Ramı́rez, S. and Teh, N. J. (2020). ‘Abandoning Galileo’s Ship: The quest for
non-relational empirical significance’. Forthcoming in The British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/17429.
Nester, J. M. (2004). ‘General Pseudotensors and Quasilocal Quantities’. Classical and Quantum
Gravity, 21, pp. S261-280.
Newman, E. T. and Penrose, R. (1966). ‘Note on the Bondi-Metzner-Sachs Group’, Journal of
Mathematical Physics, 7, pp. 863-870.
Nijenhuis, A. (1952). Theory of the Geometric Object. PhD thesis, University of Amsterdam.
Noether, E. (1918). ‘Invariante Variationsprobleme’. Nachrichten von der Gesellschaft der
Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-physikalische Klasse, pp. 235-257.
Norton, J. (1985). ‘What Was Einstein’s Principle of Equivalence?’ Studies in History and
Philosophy of Science, Part A, 16 (3), pp. 203-246.
63
Norton, J. (1993). ‘General Covariance and the Foundations of General Relativity: Eight
Decades of Dispute’. Reports on Progress in Physics, 56, pp. 791-858.
Ohanian, H. C. (2010). ‘The Energy-Momentum Tensor in General Relativity and in Alternative Theories of Gravitation, and the Gravitational vs. Inertial Mass’. arXiv preprint
arXiv:1010.5557, https://arxiv.org/abs/1010.5557.
Olver, P. J. (1986). Applications of Lie Groups to Differential Equations. Berlin Heidelberg
New York: Springer-Verlag.
Papadimitriou, I. and Skenderis, K. (2004). ‘AdS/CFT Correspondence and Geometry’. IRMA
Lectures in Mathematics and Theoretical Physics, 8, pp. 73-101. hep-th/0404176 [hep-th].
Papadimitriou, I. and Skenderis, K. (2005). ‘Thermodynamics of Asymptotically Locally AdS
Spacetimes’. arXiv:hep-th/0505190.
Pauli, W. (1958). Theory of Relativity. Oxford: Pergamon Press. New York: Dover Edition,
1981.
Penrose, R. (1963). ‘Asymptotic Properties of Fields and Space-Times’, Physical Review Letters,
10 (2), pp. 66-68.
Penrose, R. (1964). ‘Conformal treatment of infinity’, In: Relativity, groups and topology,
pp. 565-584. DeWitt, B. and DeWitt, C. (Eds). New York and London: Gordon and Breach.
Republished in: General Relativity and Gravitation (2011) 43, pp. 901-922.
Penrose, R. (1982). ‘Quasi-Local Mass and Angular Momentum in General Relativity’. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, A 381, pp. 53-63.
Penrose, R. (1988). ‘Aspects of Quasi-Local Angular Momentum’. In: Isenberg, J. A. (Ed.),
Mathematics and General Relativity, pp. 1-8. Providence, Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society.
Pitts, J. B. (2010). ‘Gauge-Invariant Localization of infinitely many Gravitational Energies from
All Possible Auxiliary Structures’. General Relativity and Gravitation, 42, pp. 601-622.
Pooley, O. (2012). ‘Substantivalist and Relationist Approaches to Spacetime’. In: Batterman,
R. (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Physics, Chapter 15, pp. 1-48. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Pooley, O. (2017). ‘Background Independence, Diffeomorphism Invariance, and the Meaning of
Coordinates’. In: Lehmkuhl et al. (2017), pp. 105-143.
Randall, L. and Sundrum, R. (1999). ‘An Alternative to Compactification’. Physical Review
Letters, 83 (23), pp. 4690-4693. arXiv:hep-th/9906064.
64
Read, J. (2016). ‘The Interpretation of String-Theoretic Dualities’. Foundations of Physics, 46,
pp. 209-235.
Read, J. (2016a). Background Independence in Classical and Quantum Gravity [Master’s thesis].
University of Oxford. https://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:b22844af-aac9-4adc-a6c5-1e2815c59655
Read, J. (2020). ‘Functional Gravitational Energy’. The British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science, 71, pp. 205-232.
Read, J. and Møller-Nielsen, T. (2020). ‘Motivating Dualities’. Synthese, 197, pp. 263-291.
Renn, J. and Stachel, J. (2007). ‘Hilbert’s Foundation of Physics: From a Theory of Everything
to a Constituent of General Relativity’. In: The Genesis of General Relativity, Renn, J. and
Schemel, M. (Eds.), Volume 4, Gravitation in the Twilight of Classical Physics. The Promise of
Mathematics, pp. 857-973. Dordrecht: Springer.
Rickles, D. (2011). ‘A Philosopher Looks at String Dualities’. Studies in History and Philosophy
of Modern Physics, 42, pp. 54-67.
Rowe, D. E. (1999). ‘The Göttingen Response to General Relativity and Emmy Noether’s
Theorems’. In: The Symbolic Universe. Geometry and Physics 1890-1930, J. Gray (Ed.),
pp. 189-233. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rowe, D. E. (2019). ‘Emmy Noether on Energy Conservation in General Relativity’.
arXiv:1912.03269 [physics.hist-ph].
Rowe, D. E. (2019a). ‘On Emmy Noether’s Role in the Relativity Revolution’. The Mathematical
Intelligencer, 41, pp. 65-72.
Sauer, T. (1999). ‘The Relativity of Discovery: Hilbert’s First Note on the Foundations of
Physics’. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 53, pp. 529-575.
Sauer, T. (2005). ‘Albert Einstein, Review Paper on General Relativity Theory (1916)’. In:
Landmark Writings in Western Mathematics, 1640-1940. I. Grattan-Guinness (Ed.), pp. 802822. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Schouten, J. A. (1954). Ricci-Calculus. Berlin Heidelberg: Springer-Verlag.
Schrödinger, E. (1950). Space-time Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sider, T. (2001). Four-Dimensionalism. An Ontology of Persistence and Time. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Skenderis, K. (2001). ‘Asymptotically Anti-de Sitter Space-times and their Stress-Energy Tensor’, International Journal of Modern Physics A, 16 (5), pp. 740-749. [hep-th/0010138].
Skenderis, K. (2002). ‘Lecture Notes on Holographic Renormalization’. Classical and Quantum
65
Gravity, 19, pp. 5849-5876. arXiv:hep-th/0209067.
Skenderis, K. and van Rees, B. C. (2008). ‘Real-Time Gauge/Gravity Duality’. Physical Review
Letters, 101, 081601, pp. 1-4. arXiv:0805.0150 [hep-th].
Skenderis, K. and van Rees, B. C. (2009). ‘Real-Time Gauge/Gravity Duality: Prescription, Renormalization and Examples’. The Journal of High-Energy Physics, 5, 85, pp. 1-70.
arXiv:0812.2909 [hep-th].
Stachel, J. (2014). ‘The Hole Argument and Some Physical and Philosophical Implications’.
Living Reviews in Relativity, 17 (1), pp. 1-66.
Strominger, A. (2001). ‘The dS / CFT correspondence’, Journal of High-Energy Physics, 0110,
034. [hep-th/0106113].
Sus, A. (2017). ‘The Physical Significance of Symmetries from the Perspective of Conservation
Laws’. In: Lehmkuhl et al. (2017), pp. 267-286.
Szabados, L. B. (2009). ‘Quasi-Local Energy-Momentum and Angular Momentum in General
Relativity’. Living Reviews in Relativity, 12, 4.
Teh, N. J. (2016). ‘Galileo’s Gauge: Understanding the Empirical Significance of Gauge Symmetry’. Philosophy of Science, 83, pp. 93-118.
Trautman, A. (1962). ‘Conservation Laws in General Relativity’. In: Gravitation: An Introduction to Current Research. Witten, L. (Ed.), pp. 169-198. New York and London: John Wiley
and Sons.
Trautman, A. (1965). ‘Foundations and Current Problems in General Relativity’. In: Lectures
on General Relativity, Trautman, A., Pirani, F. A. E., Bondi, H. (Eds.), pp. 1-248. Englewood
Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.
van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wald, R. M. (1984). General Relativity. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
Wald, R. M. (1993). ‘Black Hole Entropy is the Noether Charge’. Physical Review D, 48 (8),
pp. R3427-3431. arXiv:gr-qc/9307038.
Wald, R. M. and Zoupas, A. (2000). ‘General Definition of “Conserved Quantities” in General
Relativity and Other Theories of Gravity’. Physical Review D, 61, 084027, pp. 1-16. arXiv:grqc/9911095.
Wang, M.-T. (2015). ‘Four Lectures on Quasi-Local Mass’. arXiv:1510.02931.
Weinberg, S. (1972). Gravitation and Cosmology: Principles and Applications of the General
Theory of Relativity. New York London Sydney Toronto: John Wiley and Sons.
66