Jessica Frazier (ed): Categorisation in Indian Philosophy. Thinking Inside the Box,
Ashgate, Farnham, Surrey, 2014, 115-131.
Chapter 8
Madhyamaka:
Conventional Categories in
Madhyamaka Philosophy
Preprint only. If you
would like to cite this
chapter please refer to
the final published
version.
Jan Westerhoff
The status of categories within Madhyamaka philosophy is a curious one. On the
one hand there is a strong tendency to reject philosophically refined analyses of the
constituents which make up the world, thereby rejecting systems of categories as
well. The Mādhyamika, it seems, accepts whatever conventions the world accepts
at the merely conventional level but does not propose any conventions of his own.
In fact there appear to be good reasons for such a view. Given that the membership
of an object in a category is generally taken to be a clear example of a property
an object has intrinsically, and since the Mādhyamikas reject intrinsic properties
(properties which exist by svabhāva), they should reject categories as well.
On the other hand, however, Mādhyamikas make use of the very sophisticated
and intricate categorial frameworks found in traditional Indian grammar and in
the Abhidharma. Furthermore they also vehemently argue against the use of other
frameworks, such as that of the Naiyāyikas.
This chapter will explore ways of resolving this tension and investigate more
generally what role categories play in the Madhyamaka system of philosophy.
Madhyamakas and Ontological Categories
When it comes to the study of ontological categories it may seem as if the
Mādhyamika does not have much of interest to say. Candrakīrti points out that
‘What is admitted to exist in the world, I too admit that to exist. What is admitted
to be nonexistent in the world, I too admit that to be nonexistent.’1
This assertion, made in the context of a discussion of the Buddha’s graded
teaching suitable to different kinds of disciples, appears to reflect an extreme
loko mayā sārdhaṃ vivadati nāhaṃ lokena sārdham vivadāmi / yal loke ‘sti
saṃmataṃ tan mamāpy asti saṃmataṃ / yal loke nāsti saṃmataṃ mamāpi tan nāsti
saṃmatam. In this passage of the Prasannapadā, commenting on MMK 18:8, Candrakīrti
cites the first chapter, called Trisaṃvaranirdeśaparivarta, of the Ratnakūţa (de la Valleé
Poussin 1903–13, 370.6–8).
1
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
116
conventionalism. Whatever ontological commitments ‘the world’ makes
are accepted for the purely pragmatic purpose of teaching those who hold
these commitments.
In the following we will refer to this as the common-sense principle (CS),
a principle asserting that, for the Mādhyamika, the only systems of ontological
categories asserted at the conventional level are those accepted by common
sense. For thinkers accepting this principle there seems to be no place for the
traditional philosophical enterprise of ontological theory-building: thinking about
what our most fundamental conceptual and linguistic approaches to the world
are and attempting to systematise them in a single coherent theory. Apart from
its incompatibility with ontology as traditionally conceived, CS also leads to
a rather unsatisfactory account of spelling out the notion of conventional truth
(saṃvṛtisatya). If we equate any kind of truth with popular consensus we lose the
ability to argue that the majority of people can ever be wrong about it, since being
thought to be so is being so, at least if sufficiently many people do the thinking.
This difficulty seems to be aggravated by the Madhyamaka claim that
the conventions of the world (loka) are to be understood non-analytically
(avicāratas). It is this nonanalytical mode of engagement of mundane cognitions
(of all persons) that determines what Candrakīrti calls ‘worldly convention’
(lokasaṃvṛti). These conventions form the basis of conventional truth but do not
include inquiry into the way things really are. We will refer to this claim as the
no-analysis principle (NA). The principle rejects the application of analysis to
the systems of categories licensed by CS in order to adopt one over another and
to add theoretical refinements to the systems one ends up adopting. Adopting
NA in an unqualified way entails that our conventional manner of epistemic
engagement with the world does not require us to go beyond what our senses
tell us in order to arrive at some more fundamental level of knowledge about the
world. With respect to causation Candrakīrti points out that ‘The worldly person
indeed, without starting to analyze whether it is from itself of from other and so
forth, understands only this much: from a cause an effect arises. The Master also
explained things in the same way.’2
There seems to be no room for a philosophically sophisticated theory of
causation over and above pointing out what is conventionally accepted: rice
comes from rice-seeds and barley from barley-seeds, sheep give rise to sheep,
cows to cows and so forth. Candrakīrti regarded the analysis of ordinary notions,
attempting to arrive at an understanding of them that goes beyond ordinary usage, as
fundamentally mistaken (see Tillemans 2010). This emphasis on the conventional
and commonly acknowledged later led Tibetan scholars to characterise the
loko hi svataḥ parata ityevamādikaṁ vicāram anavatārya kāraṇātkāryam utpadyata
ityetāvanmātraṁ pratipannaḥ | evam ācāryo’pi vyavasthāpayāmāsa || (de la Valleé
Poussin 1903–13, 27:4–5).
2
Madhyamaka
117
Prāsaṅgika Mādhyamikas (i.e. Candrakīrti and his followers) as ‘jig rten grags
sde pa, as ‘the school [based on] what is known by the world’ (Ruegg 2000, 58,
note 124).
Does the joint adoption of CS and NA mean we have to understand the
Madhyamaka conception of conventional truth as ‘whatever it is that people
think’, without any possibility of analysing whether what they think is actually
true? Fortunately this is not the case. In fact later Madhyamaka writers are quite
explicit that any attempt to take general opinion uncritically at face-value cannot
be a philosophically viable position. Kamalaśīla observes:
Suppose it were thought ‘Why should we analyze it, when the production of
sprouts and the like being conditioned by seeds and so forth is just simply
acknowledged by everyone from cowherds on up? Judicious people should not
analyze in order to ascertain the natures of entities, because it would follow that
there would be no end [to such analysis] and it would follow that it would not
be judicious.’ This is not right. ... Concerning this, consider this example: it is
acknowledged that perishing is something that has a cause, and though people
acknowledge that matter and the like are external objects, this can be invalidated
by a means of reliable cognition if it is subjected to analysis.3 In the same way
here too, what people acknowledge could also turn out to be false, and hence one
really should analyze it.4
How could we know that what people acknowledge turns out to be false? One
way of doing so is by determining that they have based their opinion on unreliable
epistemic instruments.5 Tsong kha pa points out that:
Kamalaśīla here refers to the Sautrāntika view that the cessation of a momentary
existent does not require a separate cause but already results from the existent itself and to
the Yogācāra denial of external objects. Both are positions to be accepted, even though they
contradict common sense. It is only by analysis of the convictions of common sense that
their deficiency can be established.
4
gal te ‘di snyam du myu gu la sogs pa’i skye ba sa bon la sogs pa’i rkyen can gnag
rdzi yan chad la grags pa kho na yin na de la dpyad par bya ci dgos / dngos po’i bdag nyid
gtan la phab pa la ni rtog pa dang ldan pa rnams dpyad par rung ba ma yin te / thug pa med
par thal bar ‘gyur ba’i phyir dang / rtog pa dang mi ltan pa nyid du thal bar ‘gyur ba’i phyir
ro snyam du sems na / de ni rigs pa ma yin te / [...] / de la dper na ‘jig pa yang rgyu dang
ldan pa nyid du grags la / gzugs la sogs pa yang phyi rol gyi don nyid du grags zin kyang /
dpyad pa byas na tshad mas gnod pa srid pa de bzhin du ‘di la yang grags pa brdzun pa’i
ngo bo yang srid pas dpyad par bya bar rung ba nyid do // Sarvadharmaniḥsvabhāvasiddhi
(Peking: 312a–312b).
5
Tsong kha pa gives three conditions for something to exist at the level of conventional
truth: 1. it appears to conventional consciousness, 2. no other epistemic instrument
contradicts it, 3. ultimate analysis (see below) does not contradict it. (tha snyad pa’i shes
pa la grags pa yin pa dang ji ltar grags pa’i don de la tha snyad pa’i tshad ma gzhan gyis
gnod pa med pa dang | de kho na nyid la’ang rang bzhin yod med tshul bzhin du dpyod
3
118
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
The internal impairments of the sense faculties are such things as cataracts,
jaundice, and such things as hallucinogenic drugs one has consumed. The
external impairments of the sense faculties are such things as mirrors, the
echoing of sounds in a cave, and the rays of the autumn sun falling on such
things as white sand … The impairments of the mental faculty are, in addition
to these, such things as erroneous philosophical views, fallacious arguments and
sleep …
Taking conventional objects grasped by such unimpaired and impaired cognitive
faculties to be real or unreal, respectively, merely conforms to ordinary cognitive
practice. This is because they actually exist as they appear or do not, according
to whether or not they are undermined by ordinary cognition. This distinction is
not drawn from the perspective of the Āryas. This is because just as such things
as reflections do not exist as they appear, such things as blue, that appear to exist
through their own characteristics to those who are afflicted by ignorance, do not
actually exist as they appear.6
The point made here is that there are some beliefs a group of people may
hold (such as that there is a snake in the dark room in front of them or water in a
desert) which can be refuted by conventional means, that is by demonstrating that
the epistemic instruments used for making these cognitions were in some way
impaired (for example by lack of light or by light reflected in a particular way) and
by replacing them by faculties which are not so impaired. It is therefore possible to
draw a distinction between what is real (a snake, water) and what is unreal (a snake
mistaken for a rope, a mirage) at the level of conventional reality. This does not
change the fact, however, that all four have the same degree of unreality at the
ultimate level, since they all lack an intrinsic nature.
It is seems to be the case, therefore, that NA has to be modified to allow the
Mādhyamika to carry out some analysis as long as he does not stray too far from
pa’ i rigs pas gnod pa mi ‘bab pa zhig ni tha snyad du yod par ‘dod la | (1985, 627:15–18,
see Cutler/Newland 2000–2004, vol. 3, 178). The following passage considers cases which
violate the second condition.
6
Samten/Garfield 2006, 485. de la dbang po la gnod pa’i skyon nang na yod pa ni rab
rib dang mig ser la sogs pa dang brag phug la sogs pa nas sgra brdzod pa dang sos ka’i
nyi ma’i ‘od zer bye ma skya bo’i yul dang nye bar gyur pa la sogs pa ste | ... yid kyi dbang
po’i gnod pa ni de dag dang grub mtha’ log pa dang gtan tshigs ltar snang dang gnyid kyi
gnod pa sogs so | ... de lta bu’i gnod pa med pa’i shes pa drug gis bzung ba’i kun rdzob pa’i
don dang | de las bzlog pa’i don la yang dag dang log par ‘jog pa ni ‘jig rten pa’i shes pa
kho na la ltos nas yin te | de dag ji ltar snang ba ltar gyi don du yod pa la ‘jig rten pa’i shes
pas gnod pa med pa dang yod pa’i phyir ro | ‘phags pa la ltos nas ni yang dag dang log pa
gnyis su med do | ji ltar gzugs brnyan la sogs pa snang ba ltar gyi don du med pa bzhin du
| ma rig pa dang ldan pa rnams la sngon po la sogs pa rang gi mtshan nyid kyis grub par
snang ba yang snang snang ba ltar gyi don du med pa’i phyir (Dhondup 2006, 2: 287–8).
Madhyamaka
119
‘what is admitted in the world’ and thus licensed by CS.7 The Mādhyamika is not
obliged to concur with any belief the people happen to hold but only with those
which are the result of applying the right kinds of epistemic instruments in the
right manner. Beliefs that do not pass this test can be dismissed as deficient. But
does the possibility of analysis at the conventional level also allow us to carry
out ontological analyses of the categorial structure of the world? Unfortunately
this is not the case. When Candrakīrti points out that worldly convention does not
engage in analysis he intends this to extend to ultimate analysis as well. Tsong kha
pa observes that
… the Master [Candrakīrti] repeatedly said that these conventionalities, such as
shape and sound etc do exist. However, they are not in the least established by
ultimate analysis (dpyod pa’i rigs pa), that is by reasoning that analyses whether
they have intrinsic nature. Thus the scrutiny of reason is not applied to them.8
Even if Candrakīrti rejects intricate theories of conventional phenomena full
of philosophical commitments he does not reject the usefulness of commonly
accepted conventional concepts such as shape and sound. At the level of
conventional truth, by means of conventional analysis, medium-sized dry goods
such as tables and chairs are known to exist and mirages, hallucinations and other
unreal objects are known not to exist. At the level of ultimate truth, however,
tables and chairs do not exist. This is because what exists ultimately is established
by ultimate analysis, which is an analysis trying to find an object’s substantial or
intrinsic nature (svabhāva). Since this, the Mādhyamikas argue, does not exist,
then tables and chairs do not exist from the perspective of ultimate truth.
The important point now, is that the categorial analysis ontologists are concerned
with is a variety of ultimate analysis and the truths it establishes are therefore
ultimate truths. Of course this does not apply to any kind of categorial analysis.
7
Tsong kha pa points out (1985, 627: 18–628: 2) that conventional consciousness does
not completely lack inquisitive powers: ‘In a sense, conventional consciousness operates
in a non-inquisitive manner. It operates within the context of how a given phenomenon
appears to it without asking, “Is this how the object actually exists, or does it just appear
that way to my mind?” It is thus called non-analytical, but it is not the case that it is utterly
non-inquisitive.’ (de la tha snyad pa’i shes pa ni cos gang la’ang ji ltar snang ba ltar gyi
rjes su ‘jug pa tsam yin gyi | snang ba’i don de blo la de ltar snang ba tsam yin nam | ‘on te
don gyi yin tshul la de ltar grub pa yin snyam di mi dpyod pa’i shes pa ma brtags par ‘so |
de nyid la ma dpyad pa’i shes pa zhes bya yi | brtag pa ye me byed pa ni min no | See Cutler/
Newland 2000–2004, vol. 3, 178). For Tsong kha pa the process of conventional analysis
may carry out specific analyses as long as these are not concerned with the way objects
actually exist.
8
gzugs sgra la sogs pa kun rdzob pa ‘di rnams yod du chug kyang de kho na la dpyod
pa’am rang bzhin yod med dpyod pa’i rigs pas gtan mi ‘grub pas de dag la rigs pa’i brtag
pa mi ‘jug go zhes slob dpon ‘dis yang yang gsungs shing | (1985, 608: 10–13. See Cutler/
Newland 2000–2004, vol. 3, 157).
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
120
Classifying knives, forks and spoons into different categories of eating implement
is perfectly fine as a categorial structure at the conventional level. Problems arise
once we pass from the realm of lower level non-ontological categories to the
higher realm of those categories ontologists are interested in.9 Nobody will want to
claim that classifying some object as a spoon will say anything about that object’s
intrinsic nature. It is classified as a spoon because there are certain conventions
about which shapes of eating implements 21st-century humans distinguish and
the object in question resembles other objects called ‘spoon’ more or less closely.
It is the existence of these conventions which make it a spoon, not any kind of
already-present spoon-ness which its classification as a spoon reflects. Classifying
an object in terms of the ontological category it belongs to (such as ‘material
object’ or ‘spatially extended object’), on the other hand, is to be understood as
based on the object’s intrinsic nature, some property it has in and through itself,
something the object could not even lose in any conceivable circumstances. (Try
imagining a world in which this spoon, or its counterpart, is not a material object).10
For this reason a theory of categories in any philosophically important sense is not
just a conventionally approved classificatory device but a theory of characteristics
objects have by svabhāva. Since the Mādhyamika denies the existence of any such
things, such a theory must necessarily be vacuous. Furthermore it cannot be any
theory that is part of the conventional analysis of phenomena, since it investigates
characteristics that are supposed to be intrinsic.11 It therefore appears that despite
the fact that conventional analysis can very well save us from the strict reading of
CS and NA that Tillemans calls the ‘dismal view’ of having to accept whatever a
sufficiently large group of people believes as ultimate truth, a theory of ontological
categories is incompatible with the main claim Madhyamaka thought sets out to
establish, namely that there is no svabhāva.
Madhyamaka and Grammatical Categories
The story does not end here, however. If we look at Madhyamaka texts we realise
that, despite the advocacy of an ordinary, cowherd-compatible view of the world,
Mādhyamikas employ fairly sophisticated categorial schemas to make their points.
9
For a discussion of different between ontological and non-ontological categories see
Westerhoff, 2004. The book-length treatment is in Westerhoff, 2005.
10
At least this is the way ontological categories are usually understood. I do not
think this view stands up to scrutiny and have given my reasons for this elsewhere.
It is, nevertheless, the dominant view of ontological categories.
11
Dan Arnold notes the fact that theoretical re-framings of conventions, such as
categorial analyses, do not themselves have any grounding in conventional practice and
are therefore not conventional truths. ‘What is conventionally true, in other words, is just
our conventions, and any technical redescription thereof is, ipso facto, not conventionally
valid’ (Arnold 2005, 98–9).
Madhyamaka
121
The schemes appear to go well past anything one would expect a principle like CS
to license. A particularly clear example of this is Candrakīrti’s use of kāraka theory
from traditional Indian grammar in explicating the second chapter of Nāgārjuna’s
MMK.12 Kāraka theory deals with the various functions objects described by
the different parts of a sentence can occupy relative to the action described by the
verb; for example, being the agent, being the recipient, being the instrument and
so forth. In order to point out these functions the relevant expressions are put in
particular cases, such as nominative, dative, instrumental etc.
In his commentary Candrakīrti notes that the verb gamyate ‘is moved’ requires
a term denoting an agent (kartṛ) that is the mover (gantṛ).13 However, Nāgārjuna
observes in MMK 2:5 that a moving mover has to be conceived of as endowed
with two kinds of motion-properties: a constitutive property by which it is a moving
object (yena tat gamyamānam) and an instantiated one by which it has the property
of moving (yat … gamanam). The idea behind this seems to be that in our ordinary
use of predication we usually single out one property as constitutive which then
provides the metaphysical condensation-nucleus which can instantiate other
properties. Something which has the properties of being shiny, blue and pot-shaped
is conceptualised either as a shiny blue pot or as a blue, pot-shaped shiny thing or as
a shiny, pot-shaped blue thing. Speaking about moving movers, however, the only
property available has to be split into two and each has to play a different role in order
to satisfy the familiar individual-property instantiation framework: one movement
constitutes an individual and the other specifies what that individual does.
But if the property of moving requires a mover, and if two different motions
have to be in play – a constitutive and an instantiated one – then this means that we
are also faced with two distinct agents, one for each motion, rather than just with
one. There seems to be something seriously wrong with analysing statements like
‘the mover moves’ according to the individual-property framework. An obvious
reply to this seems to be that the presence of many actions does not necessarily
entail the presence of many agents. We can, even though we should not, drive a
car, talk on the phone and read the newspaper at the same time. But this does not
mean there are three people in the car, a driver, a talker and a reader.
In order to address this issue we have to consider the traditional Indian
account of kārakas a bit more closely. Candrakīrti draws on Bhartṛhari’s account
when he points out that the kāraka is not a substance (dravya) but a power (śakti)
(Bhattacharya 1980, 89). It is interesting to note that Bhāviveka also argues against
Kāraka is set out by Pāṇini in the Aṣṭādhyāyi I.4.24–54; for a brief discussion see
chapter 5 of Matilal 1990.
13
In his commentary on MMK 2:6 Candrakīrti observes that ‘Since an action (kriyā)
necessarily depends on a means of accomplishing it (svasādhana) [which is] either the
object (karman) or the subject (kartṛ) [of the action], the action of motion also involves an
agent and therefore depends on an agent of motion.’ yasmād avaśyaṃ kriyā svasādhanam
apekṣate karma kartāraṃ vā | gamikriyā caivaṃ kartary avasthitā ‘to gantāram apekṣate
(PP 96: 8–9). Here sādhana is taken to be synonymous with kāraka.
12
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
122
the conception of the agent as a substance when he points out that the grammarians
consider the agent of the action of going to be the goer. He objects that the agent is
merely an assembly of conditioned factors, meaning that he took the grammarians
to regard the agent as something over and above the assembly of such factors,
namely as a substance.14 The difficulties with regarding the kārakas as substances
are apparent. After all, the very same object can fulfil different semantic functions
in different contexts. In one sentence the same expression may denote an agent, in
another a recipient. If the referent was substantially an agent, however, it could never
play a different role in a different context. It is therefore more sensible to understand
the kārakas as a set of powers denoting what the object can do in different contexts:
it has the power to act as an agent in one context, as a recipient in another and so
forth. The irresponsible driver mentioned earlier has the powers to drive, smoke and
read and each power functions as an agent for the three different actions of driving,
smoking, and reading. These powers are differentiated with reference to the actions
of which they are agents; the power to smoke is not the same as the power to drive,
because smoking is different from driving. But the constitutive and instantiated
motion discussed by Nāgārjuna are actions of the same nature and therefore should
have the same power as an agent. If they are really two motions as the analysis
demands, however, then we also have to split up the power of the agent.
Nāgārjuna and Candrakīrti use this result in order to argue that there is
something fundamentally wrong with analysing the individual referred to in
statements like ‘the mover moves’ in terms of constitutive and instantiated
properties and, more generally, that such an analysis generates problems even
when applied to other individuals. In the present discussion there is no need to
follow the further ramifications of the argument. We want to note, however, the
way in which Candrakīrti’s discussion utilises the kāraka theory.
We are obviously dealing with an example of ultimate analysis here; what is
at issue is whether objects have an intrinsic nature (svabhāva). Nevertheless, the
framework used is part of the highly intricate system that is traditional Indian
grammatical analysis. While it is a set of conventional truths it is certainly not at
the level of cowherd-compatible truths such as ‘fire is hot’ and ‘rice-sprouts come
from rice-seeds’. We would also not settle questions arising about the framework,
such as whether a kāraka is a substance or a power, by trying to determine what is
‘admitted by the world’. People other than grammarians are unlikely to have any
view on this matter and, even if they did, this would be unlikely to supply us with
the answer we were looking for. We should also note that the piece of grammatical
theory Candrakīrti uses is one that involves a substantial amount of ontological
theorising, a classification of the different kinds of relata of verbs and an analysis
of these in terms of other ontological categories, such as substances and powers.
The use of kāraka theory therefore seems to suggest that Madhyamaka arguments
can and do employ sophisticated systems of conventional truths for the purpose
of ultimate analysis.
14
In Prajñāpradīpa on MMK 2:6, see Ames 1995, 308.
Madhyamaka
123
Madhyamaka and the Categories of the Abhidharma
Madhyamaka philosophy can be regarded as a direct reaction to the philosophical
theories set out in the Abhidharma. A particularly clear example of this is to be found
in one of Nāgārjuna’s hymns, the Lokātītastava, where he goes through a variety
of ontological categories familiar from Abhidharmic analysis – the five skandhas,
the four great elements, agent and action, characteristic and characterised and so
on – in order to argue that none of them exist by svabhāva. In this text Nāgārjuna,
addressing the Buddha, says:
You are convinced that apart from the mere skandhas no sentient being exists,
and yet, great sage, you surrendered great pain for the sake of sentient beings.
O Intelligent one, you declared to the Intelligent Ones that the skandhas are like
an illusion, a mirage, a city of Gandharvas, and a dream.15
The realisation of the illusion-like nature of the skandhas (i.e. their emptiness)
is achieved on the basis of splitting up the person into five groups, according
to the theory of persons developed in the Abhidharma. Nāgārjuna rejects the
Ābhidharmika’s understanding of categories such as these but uses them in
his own discussion in order to establish the theory of universal emptiness. The
Lokātītastava and a variety of other similar texts, such as the Heart Sūtra or
Nāgārjuna’s Pratītyasamutpāda-hṛdaya-kārikā, make it clear that a grasp of the
categories of the Abhidharma constitutes a precondition of the realisation of
emptiness. These have to be understood first before before emptiness can be
realised. This is why the Heart Sūtra points out that whoever ‘… wishes to
practice the conduct within the profound Perfection of Wisdom should make
the following observation: he properly sees the five skandhas, and properly sees
them as empty.’16
According to this sūtra the Buddhist path does not therefore start out with the
theory-free or unsophisticated conventionalities of the ordinary man on the street
and proceed from them to a direct realisation of emptiness, as some readings of
CS might lead one to think. The starting point is rather the intricate analytical
frameworks the Abhidharma has projected onto the world, in this case the theory
of the five skandhas that breaks up what is commonly referred to as a person into
five clearly defined constituents.
That the exposition of the theory of emptiness is based on the Abhidharmic
categories is of course also evident from the discussion in Nāgārjuna’s MMK.
Nagarjuniana 3–4: skandhamātravinirmukto no sattvo ‘stīti te matam / sattvārthaṃ
ca paraṃ khedam agamas tvaṃ mahāmune // te ‘pi skandhās tvayā dhīman dhīmadbhyaḥ
saṃprakāśitāḥ / māyāmarīcigandharvanagarasvapnasaṃnibhāḥ (Lindtner 1982, 128).
16
gambhīrāyāṃ prajñāpāramitāyāṃ caryāṃ cartukāṃāḥ tenaivaṃ vyavalokitavyam
pañca skandhāṃstāṃśca svabhāvaśūnyān samanupaśyati sma (Vaidya 1961, vol. 1:98).
15
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
124
A variety of categories the Abhidharma accepts, such as characteristic (lakṣaṇa)
and characterised (lakṣya), cause (hetu) and condition (pratyaya), space (ākāśa)
and so on are all analysed in order to show that none of them exists with svabhāva.
Candrakīrti makes it clear that such concepts as the ‘immediately contiguous
condition’ (samanatara-pratyaya) used by Nāgarjunā are indeed the same as
employed by the Abhidharma.17 The analysis in the MMK clearly does not start
from a basis of unsophisticated conventions in order to arrive at the theory of
emptiness by analysing these. It rather speaks to someone familiar with the
highly complex framework of Abhidharma categorisation of phenomena. In order
to follow the arguments Nāgārjuna offers in the MMK it is necessary to have
a thorough acquaintance with the system of Abhidharma in order to use it as a
stepping-stone to proceed to an understanding of emptiness.
But, one might argue, perhaps it does not matter which stepping-stone one
uses. Candrakīrti does not think that there is anything wrong with the categorial
analysis of the Abhidharma at the conventional level,18 even though it is ultimately
mistaken by assuming that some phenomena exist by svabhāva. So perhaps at
the level of conventions it does not really matter which theory of categories one
comes up with. It may be one derived from the common sense of cowherds or
it may stem from the common sense of a philosopher. This is because, for each
possible theory one could propose, a variant of Nāgārjuna’s arguments can be
developed. While there is something true about this reply it does not do justice
to the complexity of the status of systems of categories in Madhyamaka thought.
This is because the Mādyhamikas are perfectly willing to criticise philosophical
theories at the conventional level, thereby appearing to contradict NA. Let us look
at one specific example.
Madhyamakas and the Nyaya Categories
We will consider two passages which appear to conflict with a straightforward
reading of NA. Both come from the Vaidalyaprakaraṇa, a treatise by Nāgārjuna
in which he presents a comprehensive criticism of the 16 Nyāya categories. The
first passage I shall examine in the context of this discussion occurs in verse
68 and considers the category of argumentative quibbles (chala). These constitute
a kind of fallacious response made by re-interpreting the meaning of one of the
17
‘In this context, the succeeding cessation of the cause, which is the condition for the
arising of the effect, is the characteristic of the immediately contiguous condition’. tatra
kāraṇasyānantaro nirodhaḥ kāryasyotpādapratyayaḥ samanantarapratyayalakṣaṇam (de la
Vallée Poussin 1903–13, 86.4). See Dhammajoti 2004, 131–2 for a discussion of definitions
of samanantara-pratyaya in different systems of Abhidharma.
18
With reference to the ‘supporting condition’ (ālamba-pratyaya) Candrakīrti notes
that it is merely conventional but not ultimate and therefore unproblematic (sāṃvṛtam
etallakṣaṇam na pāramārthikamityadoṣaḥ (la Vallée Poussin 1903–13, 85.6)).
Madhyamaka
125
discussion’s key terms. Vidyabhusana (1971, 65) gives the example of someone
denying that a boy has a new blanket (nava-kambala) by arguing that he has only
one blanket, on the basis of reading nava-kambala as ‘having nine blankets’.19
A reply based on a quibble can never be a successful move in an argument,
independent of whether the point the quibbler raises in is fact true. This is because
the quibbler changes the topic of debate: even if, as a matter of fact, the boy
only has one blanket this does not have any relevance for deciding whether this
blanket is new or old. Let us consider the passage in question.20 I have added
some comments in italics.
It is objected:
Even though according to you all have been asserted as categories, they do not
exist ultimately.
There is therefore the fault of chala in the present debate since Nāgārjuna and
his Nyāya opponent mean different things when they speak about categories.
The Nayāyika thinks they are the fundamentally real things, the Mādhyamika
that they have a merely conventional reality. But then such a discussion seems
to be as pointless as one about the causes for the collapse of a bank, where one
party is thinking about the collapse of a financial institution, and the other about
the collapse of a riverbank.
It is to be replied:
That is not the case, because there would be this consequence for all replies.
If this was really a problem then there could be never any discussion,
philosophical or otherwise, where the two parties do not agree on the meaning
of all the terms. But if agreement is to be presupposed, depending on how
comprehensive we take the meaning of terms to be (if, for example, we assume
that whether a term is taken to be instantiated is part of its meaning) it will then
be unclear why one would have a discussion in the first place. If we agree on all
facts about X, including whether or not X exists, what is there to discuss?
This variety of quibble is called vāk-chala, quibble regarding a term. For other
varieties see Vidyabhusana 1971, 65.
20
smras pa | khyod kyi thams cad tshig don du brjod pa yin gyi don dam par ma
yin no zhe na brjod par bya ste ma yin te | lan thams cad la thal bar ‘gyur ba’i phyir ro
| ‘di ni de lta bu ma yin te | gang cung zad lan du brjod pa de thams cad tshig don nyid
du ‘gyur ba’i phyir ro | gang las she na | smra ba po thams cad ni ‘thad pas gdon mi za
bar tshig nyams par byed pa yin no | de’i phyir lan du ‘thad pa yin no | tshig dor ba med
pa’am | yang na tshul ‘di mi ‘dod na de’i phyir tshig dor ba med par ‘gyur ro | (Tola and
Dragonetti 1995, 50).
19
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
126
It is not like that, because whatever I addressed in a reply, all those are meant
precisely as categories.
This is an important point. Nāgārjuna’s criticism of the Nyāya categories
does not concern their ontological status, i.e. the fact that the Naiyāyika
believes them to be ultimate existents, while the Mādhyamika only grants them
conventional existence. Nāgārjuna disputes the status of the Nyāya categories
on the conventional level, that is as a system that describes a satisfactory
systematization of the things which are in the world independent of any concerns
about their ultimate nature.
Why is that? All disputants, by agreeing, would undeniably impair their
own assertions.
If the two disputants agreed that the concept they debated about is not one, but
rather two distinct concepts then their respective assumptions of having refuted
the opinions of the other would be fallacious: all they have refuted is a straw
man, since both have been talking about different concepts
Therefore is what is said in reply not reasonable, rather than a fallacy?
If the same concept is talked about, Nāgārjuna’s refutations have to be regarded
as successful, unless they can be criticised on other grounds than that of chala.
Otherwise, if one does not assert this principle then there is no fallacy. And if one
does not assume that there are two distinct terms at issue then there is no risk of
the fallacy of talking past each other in the first place.
What is especially interesting about this passage is Nāgārjuna’s observation
that his criticism of the Nyāya categories is not a general one, arguing that they
mistakenly superimpose svabhāva onto things which really lack them and are
therefore unsatisfactory from the perspective of ultimate truth. Nāgārjuna criticises
them from the perspective of conventional truth, i.e. by arguing that the difficulties
already arise at the level of producing a categorial theory of the world, not just
when the resulting theory is interpreted in a particular way. This therefore seems
to constitute a violation of NS which rejects analysis at the conventional level.
The second passage to consider in our attempt to understand the precise
impact of NA occurs at the end of his discussion of inconclusive reasons
in verse 62 of the VP.21 Nāgārjuna here argues against the possibility of the
Naiyāyika’s reason having any argumentative force, since the objects these
21
An inconclusive (savyabhicāra) reason is a reason which leads to several conclusions
which might not be consistent with each other. See Vidyabhusana 1971, 63–4.
Madhyamaka
127
reasons refer to are momentary (skad cig ma).22 The difficulty Nāgārjuna seems
to have in mind here is that argumentative processes are spread out in time,
whereas objects are not: they come into and go out of existence in an instance.
As soon as the reason has established anything about the object it has already
passed away, as a result of which central terms in the statement of the conclusion
will not refer anymore.
In the present context we are not primarily interested in the kind of response
the Naiyāyika could give to this argument but rather in its presuppositions.
Nāgārjuna’s argument rests on a premise which is universally accepted by
Buddhists from the Abhidharma onwards, that of the momentariness of all
existents.23 Universal momentariness is a conventional truth and it would be
hard to argue that it was one acceptable according to CS, admitted by the world
‘by everyone from cowherds up’. There are therefore at least some cases in which
the Mādhyamika criticises Nyāya arguments for conventional reasons, pitching
two statements at the level of conventional truth against each other, one of which
(that of universal momentariness) is regarded as superior to the other (that of
temporally thick objects).
Not only do we find that the Mādhyamikas use analytical tools in order
to assess different systems of categories and to decide, there is also a marked
difference to be observed in the way in which they deal with the categorial systems
of the Abhidharma and those of Naiyāyikas. Whereas the former are regarded as
acceptable as long as one does not take them seriously ontologically (that is, as
long as one does not regard them as obtaining at the level of ultimate truth), the
latter are deficient even at the level of conventional reality.24 Candrakīrti explicitly
warns against incorporating such notions into one’s own system:25
It is not logically acceptable to include things postulated by the heretics, which
are contrary to reason, into one’s own doctrine.
gzhan yang | skad cig ma nyid kyi phyir yang ngo | don gang la bsgrub pa’am sun
‘byin par byed pa de la ‘jig pa yod pa yin na sgrub pa’am sun ‘byin par byed pa rigs pa
ma yin no | gnyi ga gnas pa yin na gtan tshigs sgrub pa’am sun ‘byin par byed pa yin gyi
de ‘jig pa na gtan tshigs de sgrub pa’am sun ‘byin par byed par rigs pa ma yin te | gnyi ga
gnas pa med pa’i phyir ro| (Tola and Dragonetti 1995, 47–8).
23
How the Buddha’s doctrine of universal impermanence transformed into the
doctrine of universal momentariness is a question which requires more research. For some
discussion see von Rospatt 1995, 15–39, Ronkin 2005, 59–60.
24
Sthiramati, commenting on the final chapter of the Bodhicaryāvtāra agrees by noting
that ‘what is misconstrued by the philosophical conclusions of the various heretics is false
even from the point of view of a worldly person.’ (athyāsvaṃ tīrthikasiddhāntaparikalpitaṃ
ca lokata eva mithyā, Vaidya 1988, 77: 15–16).
25
na ha tīrthikaparikalpitā yuktividhurāḥ padārthāḥ svasamaye’bhyupaganta.m
nyāyāḥ (de la Vallée Poussin 1903–13, 67.1).
22
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
128
He also points out the conventional falsity of non-Buddhist systems with
specific reference to the Saṃkhya theory of the three guṇas:26
Like the intrinsic nature (bdag nyid) imputed (brtag pa) by the heretics
completely carried away by the sleep of ignorance, what is imputed on illusions,
mirages and so on, those also do not exist from a worldly perspective.
These heretics desire to enter into reality and do not grasp the things which
are unmistaken and certainly identified, known [by all] up to ignorant people,
cowherds, women etc, [namely] arising, cessation etc. They desire for excellence
[but] are like one climbing up a tree who, not having taken hold of the first
branch, does not grasp the second; there is a great collapse by falling into the
ravines of wrong views. Apart from perceiving the two truths there will be no
obtaining of the result. Therefore their imputations, the three guṇas, etc. are
certainly non-existent according to worldly conventions.
This passage appears to be a clear endorsement of CS. Candrakīrti’s main
worry with the Sāṃkhyas and related ‘heretic’ approaches is that they postulate
metaphysical systems which are not compatible with the theories of conventional
truth generally admitted by the world. In constructing a metaphysical theory it
is necessary to base oneself on the truths allowed by CS, i.e. those commonly
accepted by the world (the first branch) in order to reach the higher branches
of absolute truth, a level at which coherence with what the world thinks is no
longer required.
In the context of this very critical attitude towards non-Buddhist philosophical
systems it might strike us as surprising that Candrakīrti accepts the Nyāya quartet
of epistemic instruments (pramāṇa), something which is rejected by Nāgārjuna
both in the VV and the VP.27 But there need not be any difficulty with this as long
as we keep two things in mind. First of all the Nyāya quartet can be conceived of
mi shes gnyid kyis rab skyod mu stegs can | rnams kyis bdag nyid ji bzhin brtag pa
dang |
sgyu ma smig rgyu sogs la brtags pa gang | de dag ‘jig rten las kyang yod min nyid
mu stegs can ‘di dag ni de kho na nyid la ‘jug par ‘dod pas skye bo ma byang ba gnag rdzi
dang bud med la sogs pa yan cad la grags pa’i dngos po skye ba dang ‘jig pa la sogs pa
phyin ci ma log par yang dag par nges par ma bzung bar | phul du byung bar ‘gro bar ‘dod
pas shing la ‘dzegs pas yal ga snga ma btang nas yal ga phyi ma ma bzung ba ltar lhung
ba chen pos lta ba ngan pa’i ri sul dag tu ltung bar ‘gyur zhing | bden pa gnyis mthong ba
dang bral ba’i ‘bras bu mi thob par ‘gyur ro de’i | phyir ‘di dag gis gang brtags pa yon tan
gsum la sogs pa de dag ni ‘jig rten gyi kun rdzob tu yod pa ma yin pa nyid do (de la Vallée
Poussin 1907–12: 105.9–106.1).
27
‘Thus the conventional understanding of things is established based on this fourfold
scheme of epistemic instruments.’ tad evaṃ pramāṇacatuṣṭayāl lokasyārthadhigamo
vyavasthāpyate (de la Vallée Poussin 1903–13, 75.9) PP 75.9.
26
Madhyamaka
129
without the Vaiśeṣika metaphysics later grafted on to it. To this extent Candrakīrti
can regard it as a theoretically useful device without a great many philosophical
implications. Secondly we should note that the property of the Nyāya quartet
rejected by Nāgārjuna is their fundamental status, the existence by svabhāva
of these instruments, while what Candrakīrti affirms is their conventional
existence, the fact that these are pragmatically useful, not that they have a special
ontological status.
To this extent the Madhyamaka view of the categorial systems of Nyāya and
Abhidharma appears similar: they are admissible on the conventional level as
long as one does not take them seriously at the ultimate level. Of course ‘taking
them seriously’ means different things in different cases: taking the dharmas
of the Abhidharma seriously ontologically means claiming that they do not in
turn depend on other things for their existence; taking the epistemic instruments
of the Nyāya seriously means assuming that they have their own nature as
instruments independent of the epistemic objects. But there are also cases where
the Mādhyamika criticise the Nyāya categories without just focusing on the
ontological status the Naiyāyikas ascribe to them which the Mādhyamikas reject.
It would be mistaken to assume that Buddhist authors simply favoured the
categorial system of the Abhidharma because, unlike that of the Naiyāyikas,
it formed an established part of the Buddhist doctrine. Such partisanship is
not supported by what these authors say themselves. They do not claim that
the problem with the Nyāya categories is that they come from a non-Buddhist
framework but that there is something conceptually wrong with them. From the
Madhyamaka perspective there are in fact good systematic reasons for favouring
the Abhidharma framework. Apart from cases where the Nyāya framework clashes
with important Buddhist theses about the nature of conventional truth (such as the
thesis of universal momentariness) the primary reason is the fact that non-Buddhist
systems of categories are generally built around the notion of a substantial self.
The Nyāya-Vaiśeṣikas hold, for example, that cognition (buddhi) is a property
of the self (ātman) (Chatterjee 1978, 11). But such a self is not accepted by the
Madhyamaka even conventionally. As such they are unable to adopt a system of
categories which at various points appeals to objects they regard as non-existent.
Conclusion
I hope that the preceding discussion has shown that the Madhyamaka view of
conventional truth cannot be that of unreflected intuitions held by everybody
‘from cowherds on up’.28 The Madhyamaka discussion employs sophisticated
28
Compare Salvini 2008, 16: ‘It is worth pointing out that here [in Candrakirti’s
commentary on MMK 24:8] loka must necessarily refer to the “common person”
(pṛthagjana), in the technical sense of someone who has not entered the Path of Seeing: in
other words, someone who is not yet a Noble One (ārya). Alternatively, it must be a Noble
130
Categorisation in Indian Philosophy
philosophical systems of categories (such as those of grammar and the Abhidharma)
in the exposition of its arguments. Not all systems of categories are deemed
equally suitable, that of the Naiyāyikas is rejected as unsatisfactory. If we consider
the way much of the Madhyamaka discussion is set up it is clear that both NA and
CS have to be understood in very specific ways. When Candrakīrti argues that
the worldly person understands, without analysis, that effects arise from causes,
he might just want to point out that there is no need for a philosophical theory
over and above the recognition of regularities in order to make conventionally
correct statements about causal processes that obtain in the world (De la Valleé
Poussin 1903–13, 27: 4–5). For making such statements no analysis is required
but that does not mean that, in the process of analysing conventional truth in
the context of Madhyamaka arguments, one account of causation may not be
preferable to another one.
Furthermore, the ‘common sense’ in CS must not be reduced to what is apparent
to the least inquisitive and least well-informed. That this kind of common sense has
no place in Madhyamaka arguments is apparent from the sophisticated theoretical
frameworks they do indeed employ in their arguments. Rather, ‘common sense’
has to be understood as ‘informed common sense’, the best theory we have for
making sense of the world. Understood in this way commonsensical theories can
be very refined and are also subject to revision.
How are we then to understand the Madhyamaka conception of categories?
It is evident that they cannot be regarded as ultimately true theories; their use is
merely transactional. As such the Mādhyamika disagrees fundamentally with the
understanding of the ontological as the ultimate furniture of the world according
to some final theory. But this does not mean that the Mādhyamika is not able
to refer to ontological categories at all but that he has to understand them in a
different way. That the Madhyamaka ascribes a merely pragmatic use to systems
of categories fits well with the fact that, unlike other schools of Buddhist thought,
they never developed such a system of their own but rather utilised those already
in existence. Due to the specific philosophical views of the Madhyamaka it
was not possible, however, to use such an ‘off the shelf’ system without further
qualification. The systems in question rather had to be rephrased in such a way that
they did not clash with the most fundamental of Madhyamaka tenets, that of the
absence of svabhāva. When the Mādhyamika speaks of Abhidharma categories,
such as the five skandhas, the four great elements, the four kinds of condition and
so on, he is in fact referring to a suitably modified Abhidharma from which the
claim that there are substantially existent objects (dharmas which are dravyasat)
has been removed.
One engaging with saṁvṛti, not in meditative absorption on emptiness … What this means
is that, the loka of the lokasaṁvṛti need not be an entirely unrefined person: in fact, even an
Abhidharma author could fit this category, as long as he would not have entered the Path of
Seeing, or even after that, when engaging in post-meditation’.
Madhyamaka
131
It may therefore be plausible to assume that when the Mādhyamika
deliberates between different systems of categories at the conventional level
he is considering two main criteria: a) its general philosophical usefulness and
b) the extent to which the systems can be made ‘svabhāva-free’. This allows him
to rank such systems and provides criteria to choose between systems, none of
which have any claim to truth at the absolute level. It is evident that there is no
fundamental tension between the Madhyamaka enterprise and the construction
of systems of categories and that this analysis is also not hindered by CS and
NA properly understood. The Mādhyamika is able to use any such system of
categories for putting forth his arguments as long it can be made to work without
the assumption that the categories in play constitute necessary and intrinsic
properties of the objects categorised.