THE NATURE OF THE EUROPEAN
UNION
Brendan O’Leary
ABSTRACT
The European Union (EU) is not a state, though it has some statelike attributes; it is not an empire, though it includes many former European imperial
powers; and it is not a federation, though Euro-federalists seek to make it one.
There is, however, no need to argue that the Union is a singularity, nor to
invent novel terminology, such as that deployed by “neo-functionalists” and
“intergovernmentalists” to capture its legal and political form. The EU is a
confederation, but with consociational characteristics in its decision-making
styles. This conceptualization facilitates understanding and helps explain the
patterns of crises within the Union.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
Keywords: European Union; state, theories of; empire, theories of;
federation; confederation; consociation
Teaching the European Union (EU) successfully requires avoiding several initial
mind-blockers. EU specialists tend to insist on the novelty of their subject, to
focus on its allegedly unprecedented attributes, and to use, understandably, an
in-bred terminology.1 Frequently, and with atypical lightheartedness, they quote
the quip of former Commission President Jacques Delors that the Union is an
UPO – an unidentified political object. This elegant phrasing, even more
impressive in French, conforms with the insistence that the Union is a unique
novum – unique in its non-American meaning, i.e., a singularity, albeit not
foreseen in the science fiction of artificial intelligence. We are also told that the
EU displays innovative “variable geometry,” but, “what, pray, is constant
geometry?” Some EU specialists come close to suggesting that their subject is
incomparable. Impliedly, the EU’s nature can only be understood through deep
Europe’s Malaise
Research in Political Sociology, Volume 27, 17–44
Copyright © 2020 Emerald Publishing Limited
All rights of reproduction in any form reserved
ISSN: 0895-9935/doi:10.1108/S0895-993520200000027003
17
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
18
BRENDAN O’LEARY
immersion in its treaties, institutions, and policies, accompanied by long sojourns
in the European Quarter of Brussels, preferably interrupted by a Master’s degree
at the College of Europe, and provisionally capped through completing a joint
PhD and JD dissertation at the European University Institute in Florence,
composed in three major world-languages, namely, English, law, and economics.
For them the EU is a big N of 1.
Other guides, by contrast, employ very broad but less valuable abstractions to
encapsulate the EU. For example, Gary Marks and Liesbet Hooghe, describe the
EU as “a system of multi-level governance.” Yet most polities, with the exception of
some city-states and numerous micro-states, have had multiple levels of administration or government, as the authors illustrate in their excellent study of regional
governments (Hooghe, Marks, & Schakel, 2010). “Governance,” by contrast, is
among the vaguest of expressions in widespread usage, the blame for which, perhaps
mistakenly, may be assigned to the former Labour Prime Minister Harold Wilson,
who published The Governance of Britain shortly after leaving office. Both components of his title misled: it was about the Government of the United Kingdom
(Wilson, 1976). Similarly, we are instructed that the EU is “a political system” in the
best political science textbook in English on the European Union, initially written by
my former colleague Simon Hix – later editions are coauthored. That hardly helps
the neophyte, however. The reference invokes David Easton’s framework, replete
with inputs, outputs, and feedback loops, and implicit black boxes surrounded by
demands and supports (Easton, 1965/1979). The political system tag, I suspect, is
used by Hix to avoid immediate immersion in debates between so-called “intergovernmentalists” and “neo-functionalists,” because his goal, accomplished with
skill, is to transfer rational choice analytical politics from its original site of application (the United States) across the Atlantic (Hix, 1999).
While Marks, Hooghe, and Hix cannot be accused of conceptualizations that
are obviously wrong, precisely because they go for the vague, the same cannot be
said of more popular if not populist intellectuals. Mark Leonard, for example,
was sufficiently premature to describe the EU as “the ruler of the 21st century,”
which makes the Union sound like a collective time-lord from Dr Who. He
compounded his metaphors by declaring that the EU resembles VISA, the credit
agency, though presumably not because of VISA’s propensity to encourage debt
addiction (Leonard, 2005). Less popular, and more typical of the academy is
Stefan Bartolini’s description of the Union as “post-sovereign, polycentric,
incongruent and neo-medieval” (Bartolini, 2005). That is not going to help
initiate the average Millennial in understanding the Union. Let us therefore go
through several negations – not in any Hegelian sense – to provide, if we can, a
clearer and more useful conceptualization.
THE EU’S MEMBERS ARE STATES, BUT THE EU IS NOT A
STATE, OR IS IT?
This author once cowrote an account of theories of the state (Dunleavy &
O’Leary, 1987), so should be equipped to answer the question just posed. Point
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
19
one: a state for our purposes is an independent sovereign entity, i.e., not to be
confused with states in the US federation, or the Indian union, or provinces in
Canada, or Länder in Germany and Austria. The United States is a state, though
that title used to be pluralized (sentences beginning “The United States are…” may
be found in pre-Civil War literature). Point two: a state is not a nation. Apologies
to US high-school teachers, journalists, and political scientists, but what most
Americans describe as nations are independent sovereign states, a high proportion
of which are not nations, or at least not mono-national. The United Nations, it has
been well said, is founded on a double-lie; it is neither united, nor comprised of
“nations;” it is a club of currently recognized states. Point three: there are nationstates, nationalizing states that want to be nation-states, bi-national states, and
multinational states; and some non-national states (such as the Vatican), and prenational dynastic kingdoms survive (e.g., the Sultanate of Brunei). By these
standards, the EU is multinational, because it contains multiple nations, and
comprises numerous member-states that define themselves as nation-states –
though it has bi-national members, e.g., the Flemings and Walloons of Belgium,
and some multinational imperial rumps, e.g., the Kingdom of the Spains, and until
January 31, 2020, the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland.
Just when things are getting clearer, however, the EU specialist will insist that
the EU is not multinational, but rather “post-national,” and the very same person
may use the expression “supra-national” to describe some EU institutions or
policies. Each of these terms, however, may mislead. The expression “postnational” is descriptively false if it suggests that any significant number of the
member-states have ceased to be nation-states. None have abandoned their
“national characters” – though they update them constantly. Moreover, the EU
has not, at least not yet, created a pan-European identity that has significantly
superseded the national identities of the citizens of the Union, a fact noted before
recent xenophobic and ethno-populist resurgences (Checkel & Katzenstein, 2009;
Fligstein, 2008). Small numbers of EU citizens have a self-styled cosmopolitan
European identity as their primary political identity, and perhaps allegiance, but
they do not rule the EU – at least not all of its institutions, yet. For most EU
citizens their “national” identity and citizenship are primary, though for many a
European identity and their national citizenship are complementary. Even if the
European identity became more important than member-state identity across the
majority of the Union’s citizens, it would not be clear that this “Euro-identity”
would be “non-national.” It might well be a new continental-scale national
identity, one that conceivably may resemble many extant national identities, such
as China’s, replete with its own mythologies, including a story of Europe’s
emergence, distinctiveness, and shared Christian (or post-Christian) culture. Such
constructions are already in the marketplace of ideas (Le Goff, 2007).
But what of the “supra-national,” when it is not a synonym for “post-national”?
As far as I know this expression first emerged in widespread usage, in French, to
define arrangements that allowed for law and policy to be made “above” the
national states that formed the European Coal and Steel Community (Haas, 1968).
It would be futile to try to eliminate this usage, but such laws and policies emerge
from the agreements of said member-states, who have made subsequent treaties
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
20
BRENDAN O’LEARY
that sometimes permit laws and policies to be made on the basis of qualified
majority voting. They do not then emanate from “above” the states, but from
“within” and “through” them. In Eurospeak, they make “co-decisions,” even if the
legislative initiatives formally hail from the allegedly supra-national Commission.2
So, the EU is multinational, but certainly not yet “post-national.” And there may
be better and older ways to describe so-called “supra-national” government.
The attributes of statehood now need to be briefly elaborated. Political scientists and sociologists invariably cite Max Weber, who told us that the state has
an essence, namely,
[T]he modern state can only be defined sociologically in terms of a specific means which is
peculiar to the state, as it is to all other political associations, namely physical violence.
(Gewaltsmakeit)
He went on,
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
Every state is founded on force (Gewalt), as Trotsky once said at Brest-Litovsk. That is indeed
correct… Violence is, of course, not the normal or sole means used by the state… But it is the
means specific to the state. [A] state is that human community which (successfully) lays claim to
the monopoly of legitimate physical violence within a certain territory, this ‘territory’ being
another of the defining characteristics of the state. (Weber, 1919/1994)
This definition emphasizes domestic sovereignty. Weber’s formula has three
components: monopoly of force; territory; and legitimacy. By these criteria, the
EU is not a state. There is no EU-wide police force, no EU-wide gendarmerie, and
no European army, to enforce Union authority. Policing the single market is a
function of the Court of Justice of EU but requires the cooperation of the courts
and police of the member-states. The EU’s territory is coextensive with those
portions of its member-states that are within the EU, and its customs union, and
single market; and the EU acts as the coguardian of two protectorates, Bosnia and
Herzegovina, and Kosova, outside the boundaries of its member-states.3 Legitimacy, that conceptual morass from which no traveler returns, may be left aside,
but let us agree that the EU’s is not ubiquitous. By contrast, all the member-states
of the EU are states by Weber’s definition, even if their legitimacy varies.
We are not yet out of the statal woods, however, because other disciplines do
not defer to Weber. International lawyers, generally better paid than political
sociologists, insist that the Montevideo Convention on the Rights and Duties of
States specifiesthe criteria that a State, which they always capitalize, must meet,
namely
The State as a person of international law should possess the following qualifications: (a) a
permanent population; (b) a defined territory; (c) government; and (d) capacity to enter into
relations with other States. (Montevideo Convention, 1933)
The EU has permanent residents and citizens. It has already been argued that
it has a definite territory, even if it expands and contracts, so (a) and (b) are
satisfied. The EU has a government, albeit multiheaded. Namely, the European
Council (of heads of states and government), the Council of Ministers, and the
Commission. The EU has other attributes of a government, a Council, a
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
The Nature of the European Union
21
Commission, a (bicameral) legislature, a court, and important independent public
bodies, most famously the European Central Bank. Therefore criterion (c) is met.
Last, but not least, the EU has the recognized capacity to enter into relations with
other States, notably but not only in trade agreements. There are EU ambassadors to member-States and (non-member) States, and both the former and the
latter send ambassadors to the EU. Quod erat demonstrandum. In (dated) international law the EU would seem to be a State, but in (dated) political science and
sociology it is not. Can this contradiction be resolved? The answer, as we shall
see, is yes, if a confederation is a State, and if the EU is a confederation
constituted by its member-states. But further analytical steps are required to drive
home this claim.
Additional “dimensionalizing” of the state helps. A synthetic neo-Weberian
definition – not an original contribution to the annals of political thought –
performs that expansion. Namely,
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
A modern state is (i) a differentiated and impersonal institution that is (ii) politically centralized
though not necessarily unitary; that (iii) generally exercises an effective monopoly of publicly
organized physical force and (iv) of authoritatively binding rule-making (or sovereignty) over
persons, groups, and property; and that (v) is sufficiently recognized by a sufficient number of
its subjects, and (vi) of other states, that it can (vii) maintain its organizational and policymaking powers within (viii) a potentially variable territory. (O’Leary, 2001)
The EU matches some of these eight dimensions. Its institutions are partly
differentiated from its member-states and subjects. Impersonal office-holding is the
norm: it is not familial, tribal, hereditary, feudal, or patrimonial. The EU is not
unitary, but EU law, shepherded by the Court, seeks to be cohesive and appropriately uniform and predictable. The EU, except in some English imaginations, is
strikingly difficult to describe as politically centralized. It has three cities in which
capital functions are permanently exercised, in Brussels, Strasbourg, and
Luxembourg, Other cities in the member-states are used for inter-governmental
meetings, summits, and the signing of treaties. There are, however, mechanisms to
coordinate law and policy, especially where the EU has exclusive competences. But
the EU not only has no monopoly on publicly organized physical force but also has
no monopoly on rule-making. Its institutions are an expression of shared rulemaking. There is rule-enforcement by law, and fines, but not, so far, by EU security
officials. Judging by social surveys and voting behavior, the EU is not recognized
as “statelike” by most of its citizens. The EU’s organizational, fiscal, and policymaking powers are limited, largely “regulatory.” In short, the EU is partly statelike, but not as statal as its member-states, not least in its numbers of officials. One
tempting conclusion, proposed by Bartolini, is that the EU is “a state-formation”
in-progress, characterized by limited administrative competence, strong regulatory
powers in some policy fields, very weak fiscal capabilities, and strong juridical
capacities. These descriptive components should not be controversial, but why
assume that the EU has the telos of full statehood, particularly one that would
subsume and supersede the sovereignty of its member-states, and de-nationalize
them? Differently put, why assume, that the self-styled “Brexiteers” are right,
namely that the EU is becoming a superstate, or should that be a supra-state?
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
22
BRENDAN O’LEARY
“Ever closer union” is not logically the same as predicting either a federal or a
unitary union; one can after all get asymptotically closer to a boundary without
crossing it.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
THOUGH SITUATED WHERE MANY EMPIRES WERE,
THE EU IS NOT AN EMPIRE
After 1989, it became fashionable to classify the EU as an empire. Perhaps it is
the successor to Charlemagne’s empire: his territory was close to that of the
founding Six. Or, to the empire of the Habsburgs, whether that of Charles V, or
his solely Austrian successors, or to the overlapping jurisdiction of the Holy
Roman Empire of the German Nation (Wilson, 1999, 2016). Or, perhaps the EU
is the successor of all the European empires, bar that of those that bled into Asia
and North Africa, i.e., some of the lands of the Czars, and the Ottomans. So far, I
have yet to read any serious comparison of the EU to Napoleon’s empire, but
after UKEXIT is complete the EU’s spatial scope, barring sovereign Ireland, will
resemble that of the grand empire in 1811.4 There is a Brexiteer literature in
which the EU is compared with Hitler’s empire; one lengthy indictment insinuates that “the European project” has its ideological origins among Nazis
(Laughland, 1997). One might add Napoleon, Charles V, and the Caesars if one
follows this author’s method, which forgets the origins of the European Coal and
Steel Community (Treaty of Paris) and the European Economy Community
(Treaty of Rome) – and the failed European Defense Community (EDC). These
initiatives were partly intended as power-sharing peace projects. A key goal was
to inhibit the recurrence of wars between Germany and France.
In Iberia, site of two faded imperiums, the portrait of the EU as an empire
became especially popular in the 2000s. Tasked by a Dutch journalist to describe
what the EU would be after the Lisbon Treaty entered into force, José Manuel
Barroso, the Portuguese President of the European Commission (2004–2014)
caused minor embarrassment. The ex-Maoist first tried to refuse the question, but
then chose to elaborate the usual talking points about uniqueness, the UPO, and
the pooling of sovereignty, before he went off-message. He concluded that the EU
resembles an empire, in its scale and diversity, while insisting it is not coercive, or
organized through the diktat of an imperial center.5 Barroso’s characterization
may have been inspired by his fellow Iberian, the Catalan political scientist Josep
Colomer. In Great Empires, Small Nations, and The European Empire, Colomer
maintains that the mid-scale sovereign nation-state is now subject to supersession
by cooperative coordination on a larger, imperial scale, and by the revitalization
of smaller nations, whether organized in formally sovereign states or autonomous
regions. The claim is that the latter may be able to express their cultures, and to
develop their political economies, much better inside an empire (Colomer, 2007,
2016). Combining the literature on globalization with the idea of different efficiencies of scale for the delivery of different public goods, Colomer argues that
large empires are more efficient for trade, defense, and communication systems.
He makes a critical conceptual deviation, however, by inventing non-imperialistic
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
23
empires. He names two, the Holy Roman Empire and the EU. For him the
concept of empire, without qualifying adjectives, should be confined to very
large-scale entities (in territory and population), with relatively fluctuating
boundaries, and diverse populations, ruled by compound multilayered government with overlapping jurisdictions (2007, p. 3). Colomer’s reasoning is closely
paralleled in the work of the Polish but UK-resident political scientist Jan
Zielonka who treats the EU’s eastward expansion as that of a benign empire,
replete with the polycentric, multijurisdictional traits emphasized by Bartolini
and Colomer (Zielonka, 2006). The Catalan and Pole were anticipated by
Englishman Robert Cooper, successively special adviser on foreign affairs to the
UK’s Tony Blair and director general of “external and politico-military affairs”
for the Council of the EU. In his vision, the EU is a postmodern cooperative
empire (Cooper, 2003), and a source of order. Beyond its frontiers lie benighted
lands of chaos, kleptocracies, and the ungoverned spaces of failed states. In what
seems increasingly a period piece, Cooper defended a benign humanitarian
imperial role for the EU, compatible with human rights and cosmopolitan values.
Large-scale cross-time comparisons should be encouraged. But these portraits
of the EU as an empire are not conceptually convincing. Barroso, Colomer,
Zielonka, and Cooper jointly suggest a coreless empire. Empire begins, however,
with a core that rules peripheries, including provinces, protectorates, and colonies, i.e., dependent territories that are neither sovereign nor co-sovereign
autonomous states (Doyle, 1986). An empire prohibits coordination among its
peripheries (Finer, 1997), a description that does not apply to the EU. The EU
“pentangle” of institutions – the Council, the Council of Ministers, Commission,
Parliament, Court – cannot and does not prevent the coordination of subsets of
member-states. Indeed, subsets of member-states meet regularly, sometimes to
coordinate on EU policy. Restrictive rules govern “enhanced cooperation,” but
these too have been agreed by treaty. With the highly debatable exception of
Rome (Sherwin-White, 1939/1973), an empire cannot abide the universal and
equal citizenship of its subjects; if it can, it may reasonably be suggested it is
becoming an integrated state (Siedentop, 1983). Visually, empires are “star-shaped,” or hubs with spikes. Where is the EU’s core, hub, or the center of the
starfish? In France and Germany? In the six founders? In the western fifteen
member-states that preceded the twenty first century expansion to twenty eight –
now twenty seven?
In short, an empire is not merely large and diverse, but has hierarchically
subordinated provinces, protectorates, and colonies. “Nation” became a standard
antonym of “empire” precisely with those who sought a state of equal conationals and rejected hierarchically ordered agro-literate imperial polities
(Gellner, 1983). Conversely, there is an intricate relationship between conservative hierarchical thought and the logic of empire (O’Leary, 2002; O’Neill, 2016).
No coercive or exploitative EU center oppresses or abuses member-states. During
accession, potential member-states, screened for their democratic caliber, are
obliged to legislate the entirety of current EU law, the acquis communautaire.
That process may be experienced in certain economic sectors and workforces as
exploitative, oppressive, or coercive, but the state in question freely accedes to the
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
24
BRENDAN O’LEARY
acquis to become a formally equal member-state, and a future rule-maker. The
restrictions on freedom of movement placed on the citizens of some newly
enrolled Eastern member-states were examples of unequal citizenship, but they
were time-limited. Member-states in general “delegate” powers to the pentangle
through treaties between themselves, to which each member-state must consent.
Ergo, the member-states are not provinces, peripheries, or colonies. Rather, they
are the masters of the treaties, though their domestic constitutions cannot
unilaterally control the uses the EU’s pentangle makes of its authorized powers.
To revise EU laws, they must muster a coalition with a qualified majority in the
Council and the Parliament or make a new treaty with unanimous agreement.
Metaphorically, on the right and the left, the functioning of the Eurozone,
especially since 2007–2008, is exhibit A in indictments of German “imperial
exploitation” of the rest of the Europe (for right and left perspectives see Connolly, 1995; Varoufakis, 2016, 2017). The Euro was negotiated, however, as a
quid pro quo to create a Europeanized Germany and to prevent a German Europe
after German reunification – though the details remain under historiographical
litigation.6 The unfolding of the Euro certainly gave Germany a highly
competitive exchange rate for its export industries, and the way in which the
Eurozone has been managed, in conjunction with Germany’s determinedly nonKeynesian fiscal management, has compressed demand and produced unnecessary deflation elsewhere – and in Germany. But these outcomes flowed from
joint decisions by the member-states, not by decrees from Berlin. Banking and
sovereign bailouts, administered by the troika of the Commission, the European
Central Bank (ECB), and the (partly non-European) IMF, have likewise been
narrated as the imposition of German political economy on member-states who
temporarily lost their economic sovereignty – this language, in less polite forms,
was widely used in the cases of Cyprus, Greece, Ireland, and Portugal. Yet in
each of these member-states, albeit with variations in attendant popular pressure
and anger, the state officials who prevailed backed staying in the Eurozone. Very
painful austerity programs were accepted in preference to exiting the Eurozone –
and, conceivably by law, the EU. No German or EU armies, police, or prisons
enforced these programs. Auditors monitored compliance, not soldiers in jackboots. Greek referendums were ignored, but Greece did not follow through on its
threat to exit. In short, the Eurozone, modeled on the Bundesbank and the hard
DM, was negotiated, including its known minimal or nonexistent democratic
accountability, and it was opted into, by the relevant EU member-states, and it
still has voluntary candidate-members.7 Wonder may be expressed at the choices
of particular member-states, and no one need assume German policymakers have
been benign or altruistic, but the actions of the bailed-out governments were not,
in general, submissions to imperial diktats from the German government. The
functionary who crushed the hopes of Ireland’s Fianna Fáil government and
compelled it to absorb the debts of its insolvent banks through (perhaps
unlawfully) threatening to cut Ireland off from its supply of Euros, was a
Frenchman, Jean-Claude Trichet.8 Moreover, throughout the crises of the
Eurozone, Germany has made concessions, albeit begrudgingly and belatedly, to
its fellow Europeans. And, whether mean and myopic, or otherwise, German
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
25
governments have never lacked for policy allies, notably among the Dutch and
the Finns, but also within each member-state.
The notion of the EU as a zone of benign imperial civilization surrounded by
chaotic or violent entities in its near abroad accords with the self-conceptions, and
sometimes the public statements, of some of the political elites in the Council and
Commission. Russian and Ukrainian Mafiosi, Turkish Islamists, the peoples of the
Levant and North Africa, are impliedly or explicitly “othered.” These places are
seen temporarily to house, or are paid to warehouse, illegal economic migrants,
refugees, asylum seekers, criminals, and yes, terrorists, by anyone’s definition. But
the battered Schengen zone is the result of member-state agreements on how to
manage their joint exterior borders, at land and sea. Mediterranean and Balkan
border policy notoriously depend on each frontline member-state’s security and
legal institutions. The Dublin Convention badly needs updating to distribute the
benefits and burdens of granting asylum and integrating refugees much more fairly,
efficiently, and humanely, but, as its name suggests, its provisions are in a treaty.
Has the EU become a “deputy empire,” America’s Number Two, as suggested
in vibrant passages in Perry Anderson’s New Old World (Anderson, 2009)? The
Union, however, has no significant forces of its own to play such a role, if that is
defined militarily. But its largest member-states do. In 2017, taking SIPRI’s data as
authoritative, among the top fifteen states that expend most on their militaries
were Italy (12th), Germany (9th), the United Kingdom (7th), and France (6th).
These states individually ranked behind the top five spenders – in ascending order
India, Russia, Saudi Arabia, China, and the United States. But, together the top
four EU-spenders, all NATO members, outspent Russia by 2.8:1, India by the
same, and Saudi Arabia by 2.5:1. The four top EU member-state big spenders
therefore account for over 10% of the world’s outlay on arms, and that is before
adding the budgets of other significant European spenders by global standards,
e.g., Spain, the Netherlands, Poland, Sweden, and Greece (Tian, Fleurant, Kuimova, Wezeman, & Wezeman, 2018). The UK’s exit from the EU will, however,
reduce the combined weight of the top three, France, Germany, and Italy, to 7.5%
of the global total. This excursion suggests that it is the big member-states, not the
EU per se, that provide the muscle behind European geopolitical capabilities. The
EU’s capacities are economic, where its soft power is significant; to modify an old
and racist cliché the EU is a military not a political “pygmy,” but jointly its
member-states lie third behind China and the United States in military capacities.9
In sum, the EU contains former European empires, some of which retain
dependent territories, but internally it is not an empire. Externally, the EU per se
has no significant forces deployed in bases beyond its boundaries as is typical with
imperial powers. The EU’s big member-states are more accurately portrayed, or
may represent themselves, as security deputies with special relationships with the
United States. True, most of the EU’s member-states are participants in NATO,
but the EU contains neutrals, and NATO is an alliance in which the vanguard
role is palpably American. During the EU’s expansion into the post-communist
world, as Anderson correctly emphasizes, NATO membership has so far always
preceded EU membership. Ukraine’s pro-Europeans learned to their chagrin the
consequences of seeming to try to go the other way around (Mearsheimer, 2014).
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
26
BRENDAN O’LEARY
Ukraine’s fate reminds us that EU foreign policy implementation is a work-inprogress. Coordinating 28 states is an exceptionally difficult challenge – soon to
be 27, but perhaps 28 again after the future accession of North Macedonia.
Arguably, the EU’s most successful display of geopolitical collective solidarity
has been its united front in negotiations with a member-state intent on departure
(O’Leary, 2019).
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
THE EU IS NOT A FEDERATION, THOUGH MANY WANT
IT TO BE
The EU has federalist devotees, but is it a federation? A United States of Europe
was Jean Monnet’s identifiable political object (Duchêne, 1994), and that of his
disciples (Wistrich, 1994), but has it been realized? Federations usually have
express lists of exclusive powers for the federal level; statements on shared
powers; and powers that are the ultimate jurisdiction of the states that comprise
the federation. After the Lisbon Treaty, the Union has such codifications
(Phinnemore, 2013), distinguishing exclusive Union powers, and powers shared
by the Union with member-states, and it provides principles (proportionality and
subsidiarity) to guide their development. The Union exclusively regulates the
single market (standards and competition), the customs union and external
commerce, agriculture (production, prices, and standards), and a common fisheries policy. Within the Eurozone, monetary policy is the exclusive power of the
European Central Bank, and the elements of a banking union are in formation.
Numerous other powers are shared and coordinated, especially when they have a
regulatory character – employment, energy, and environmental regulation, public
health, consumer protection, cohesion funds, transport, the movement of persons,
especially within the Schengen zone, and aspects of policing and criminal justice,
and of higher education, including research funding. There is, however, no
meaningful Union macroeconomic government, aside from the straitjacket of the
fiscal compact: in the Eurozone member-state budgets are subject to Commission
oversight. Coordination and shared powers in the EU are at their weakest in
defense and foreign affairs. By contrast, in most federations, the exclusive powers
of the federal government usually include foreign affairs, defense, security and the
intelligence services, and federation-wide taxation.
Federations, with the partial exception of the Swiss, have federal supreme
courts or constitutional courts that adjudicate disputes over powers, claim powers
over constitutional interpretation, and develop doctrines regarding whether
federal/union law or state/provincial law prevails when there is a clash of competences. The Court of Justice of the European Union looks like such courts,
claims powers of final interpretation of the treaties, and has had a record since the
1960s of upholding the supremacy of Union law over member-state law when
clashes exist in zones of shared competence, and a less prominent record of
extending the Union’s (and previously the Community’s) implied powers,
exclusive or shared (Craig & de Búrca, 2011; de Búrca & Weiler, 2012; Weiler,
1999), but that does not make it a federal court.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
27
Federations may “come together” as negotiated unions of constituent states;
they may be established to “hold together” a previously unitary state; they may
be “put together” by external or colonial force (Stepan, 2001); or they may arise
from some permutation of these processes (O’Leary, 2005b). The EU definitively
emerged from coming-together agreements between its member-states. Though
the United States initially encouraged the formation of the EU’s predecessors,
they were not put together in or by DC. But federations are not the sole entities
that bring states together.
Federations are associated with the big. One in eight of the world’s states have
belonged to the Canadian inspired Forum of Federations; four in ten of the
world’s population live in federations; and seven of the top 10 of the world’s
states in population size and in territorial extent are federations. Therefore, given
the EU’s continental scope, and its population of over 500 million before the
UK’s intended departure, it would be no geographic or demographic surprise to
assert that the EU is an emergent federation, though it is not a member of the
Forum.
Federations have been typologized on three dimensions (O’Leary, 2005b).
Integrated federations are mono-national, have majoritarian decision-making at
the federal level, and are centralized. Their polar opposites are pluralist federations, which are multinational, have consensual decision-making at the federal
level, and are decentralized. Real-world permutations, of course, exist between
these polar types. The EU is obviously not a mono-national or national federation, though two of its member-states are (Austria and Germany).10 The EU is
plainly not majoritarian: decisions within the Council and the Parliament are
typically by unanimity or by qualified majority voting. The European Parliament,
elected by proportional representation, is invariably governed by a coalition of
party families, each composed of numerous member-state parties. The European
Council, de facto, represents presidents and prime ministers from numerous
governing party families, in an obligatory grand coalition, and shifts its alignments
depending on the issues before it. In the security domain, as seen, the EU is
extraordinarily decentralized; security is overwhelmingly organized by the member-states.11 Natural and fiscal resources too are jealously guarded by the memberstates. The member-states have ensured that the residual (unspecified) powers
articulated in their joint treaties are with them.12 In short, if the EU is a federation,
it is a very weak one and belongs to the species of pluralist federations.13
The foregoing attempts a fair précis of propositions that suggest that the EU is
or is becoming a federation. The counter-arguments, however, remain compelling. Legally, federations are based on constitutions, usually mandated by constituent assemblies, in which both citizens of the federal demos and the states are
partners. The EU is a treaty-based order, marked in its origins by international
law. The Union’s curiously named constitutional treaty, itself a legal hybrid, went
down to defeat at the hands of French and Dutch voters, even though much of
the substance later went into the Treaty on European Union (Norman, 2005;
Phinnemore, 2013; Treaty of Lisbon, 2007).
The EU, like federations, has citizens, though their rights are largely derivative
of their citizenship of their member-states, despite some interesting legal cases. EU
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
28
BRENDAN O’LEARY
citizens who move to another member-state have no privileged status through the
Union in obtaining naturalization in their new residence. Strikingly, the EU’s
famous mauve passports have the emblems and names of the member-states displayed with greater prominence than the name of the Union. EU citizens do not
jointly or directly elect the executive of the EU (the Council and Commission).
Institutionally, the EU differs significantly from typical federations. Federal
executives are autonomous and preside over bureaucracies with enforcement
capacities. The EU, however, has no President directly elected by the federal
demos, with executive enforcement powers; the “permanent” President of the
European Council is elected by his or her peers among the heads of state and
government, for a two-and a half year term, renewable once, but is a coordinator
more than an enforcer. The EU has no Prime Minister nominated by the governing coalition in the House of the People, though intermittent efforts are made
to make the President of the Commission exhibit these traits. S/he has strict
limitations in composing the college of commissioners (one from each memberstate), and is nominated by the European Council, and approved by the Parliament. The Council, be it noted, has just rejected the idea that its nomination for
President of the Commission should be confined to accepting the “leading
candidate” of the plurality party family in the Parliament. The college of commissioners is collectively endorsed by the Parliament, though ways have been
found to block individually unwelcome nominees. Each member-state nominates
one commissioner, however, thanks to the Irish electorate’s refusal of the first
draft of the Lisbon Treaty (Quinlan, 2009). The Commission’s leadership has
regularly been federalist in disposition but has never had a significant democratic
mandate across the Union to upholster this tendency.
Federal agencies work in parallel with state-level bureaucracies throughout
federations, but, by contrast, within the EU most law and policy depend upon the
member-states’ bureaucracies and capacities for implementation. The EU has few
powers of direct application or enforcement. The ECB is the most notable
exception, but usually works through each of the member-state central banks,
and other regulatory bodies, all of which are deliberately depoliticized. Those
who work directly for the EU’s agencies and directorates-general, within and
without the Commission, are formally loyal to the Union, and include genuine
technocrats, but no one is surprised if they exhibit the interests, ideologies, and
ideas of their member-state of origin.
The legislature in most federations derives at least part of its mandate from a
federal demos. It usually functions with two chambers, one a federation-wide
house of the people the other a chamber of states. Certainly, the EU’s Parliament
looks its most federal institution because its mandate derives from citizens voting
in their respective member-states. Infamously, however, the limited numbers of
voters who turn out where is no compulsory voting treat these elections as
“second-order” events, akin to referendums on the popularity of incumbent
member-state governments. Voters have so far not been very responsive to
Union-wide issues; turnout fell as the Parliament’s powers grew – until the
elections of 2019. Some sardonically observe that participation is rising fastest
among those who would leave or weaken the Union. The EU’s second chamber
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
The Nature of the European Union
29
has no autonomous mandate from the citizens of the member-states. It is not
comprised of senators, but of the Council of Ministers, usually organized by
functional portfolio, rather than meeting as a plenary body. Through the Council
of Ministers, the executives of the member-states, and their civil servants, exercise
control over law-making and policy development in the Union. The degree to
which they are accountable to their own member-state legislatures varies significantly. The Commission retains its nominal power of initiating legislation, and
has expert agencies and officials who matter, but these experts are often matched
in caliber by seconded member-state officials who participate in the arcane
processes that go under the rubric of “comitology.”
The Union has an international personality, but according to its own treaties,
it is not sovereign, whereas a federation is; and, as we shall shortly claim, the
Court that adjudicates these treaties may reasonably be classified as confederal.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
THE EU IS A NEW ENTITY, BUT DOES NOT REQUIRE
CONCEPTUAL NOVELTY
EU studies have not lacked terminological innovation. Two distinguished
scholars in the vanguard of different classifications of the Union may be taken as
recent leaders of their respective “schools”; one, a leading representative of “neofunctionalism,” the other of rational choice applied to international relations,
namely, “liberal-intergovernmentalism.” Should we follow these decades-long
students of the Union and their respective apostles? Not, I think, if we are to
be proper comparativists.
Philippe Schmitter, a doyen of comparative politics, and acknowledged successor of the founding father of “neo-functionalism,” Ernest Haas, has explored
several different wordings to classify the Euro-polity, and its possible futures
(Schmitter, 2000). Rejecting the idea that the Euro-polity is a stato (state), or a
confederatio (confederation), albeit with no significant justification for the latter’s
damnation, Schmitter proposed two different Latinate neologisms to describe the
EU, especially its future. In the first, a consortio, a fixed number of states
collaborate, but with varying policy responsibilities, i.e., different subsets of
member-states cooperate in different functional domains. Differently put, the
EU’s territory is fixed, but its domains of functional cooperation are not.
Schmitter maintains consortium captures what is intended by the over-used
expression “variable geometry.” Consortium, however, is an unnecessary innovation. Confederations, after all, are entirely compatible with opt-outs. In federations, by contrast, the deliberate insistence on symmetry, meaning symmetry
in the powers of states, is a recurring demand, one that can destabilize the
accommodation of smaller nationalities, ethnicities, and cultures. But there are
nonetheless asymmetrical federations in which some states are able to exercise
opt-outs. Moreover, there are good grounds for believing that all federations
display at least some conjunction of asymmetries – in the formal legal competences of states, in their decision-making power within the federal government, in
the resources states possess, in the symbolic recognition of states, or in their
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
30
BRENDAN O’LEARY
internal structures of government (O’Leary, 2010). In short, the notions of
symmetrical and asymmetrical confederations and federations already exist, so
Occam’s razor can be exercised on consortium, which sounds too much like a
shopping mall or a corrupt conspiracy. The already overflowing lexicon of
political sociology and law should not be needlessly expanded.
Schmitter’s second proposal, condominio (condominium), is arguably even
worse. He defines it is as a political entity in which there is both territorial and
functional fluidity. He claims that the concept absorbs and usefully summarizes
the fact that the Eurozone is not coextensive with the EU, and that the Schengen
zone extends beyond the EU – as well as not encompassing all the memberstates within. But in – correct – classical usage a condominium refers to shared
sovereignty over a territory, and its people, that are not themselves sovereign
(O’Leary, 1993); it involves, minimally, two outside powers exercising sovereignty and power over another place. The usual illustrations have been
Andorra, Anglo-Egyptian Sudan, and the New Hebrides. Arguably, the EU,
NATO, and UN field organizations have exercised delegated condominium-like
powers over Bosnia and Herzegovina and Kosova, but the EU itself is no
condominium because the Union has been, and is, the creature of its memberstates. The Union is their building, or dominion. Condominium is therefore just
not appropriate to describe the Union. Moreover, it is impossible to read
Schmitter’s “modest proposals” for reforming the Union, expanding its role in
redistribution, and for deepening its democratization, as other than strongly
federalizing proposals, which casts further doubt on the merit of his wording
novelties.
Andrew Moravcsik’s work of the 1990s, elegantly structured, empirically rich,
and fluent, relentlessly sought to demonstrate that the member-states have
thoroughly controlled the development of the Union, whence “inter-governmentalism.” He sought to demonstrate that the policy preferences of the relevant
member-states flow from the economic interests of their respective domestic
constituencies, whence “liberal”– though “pluralist” might seem a better designation (Moravcsik, 1993, 1998). The Union’s institutions, on this telling, reflect
the credible commitments the member-states have made to one another to
enforce contracts that reflect their domestic economic interests. Treaties, grand
bargains, and laws, in brief, display the relative bargaining power of memberstates. The gravamen of Moravcsik’s detailed excursus from Messina to Maastricht is the primacy of the member-states in the establishment, dynamics, and
functioning of the Union. That may, and indeed should, be accepted if stated at a
sufficient level of generality. However, embracing his extirpation from explanatory significance of all autonomous policy influences, or institutional innovations,
that have flowed from the Union institutions, laws, personnel, and polices, is
quite another matter.14 Moravcsik’s member-states are too rationalist, too
capable of economic calculation, too controlling, and indeed just too capable.
For instance, accounting for the UK’s exit from the Union will pose an
extraordinary challenge for this species of rationalism, while Germany’s policy
toward the UK’s secession has not been driven by the interests of its automobile
industry.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
The Nature of the European Union
31
The EU is more than a set of credible commitments by economically rational
states, partly because it is more than an economic regime. Indeed, even its economic regimes have changed. The ECSC began under the auspices of a French
hegemon that favored both command and indicative planning. Its EU grandchild
has veered radically toward a neo-liberal, Ordo-liberal, or neo-Hayekian focus on
“mere” regulation. Understanding the EU as a confederation, in which the
confederal institutions, particularly the Parliament, Court, and Commission,
have developed some minimal autonomy, including the propensity to innovate
law, policy, or institutional functioning, seems a more sensible summary than
Moravcsik’s portrait of the Union’s institutions as mere mirrors of the instrumental economic interests of the member-states as reflected by their governments.
In short, the EU is not just an international economic organization; it is more
than a free trade agreement with a customs union; and it is not just the sum of its
powerful governments. The foundations of its precursors, and its current evolution, all require a focus on geopolitics. The EU confederation, after all, may have
become a federation had NATO failed, or had the European Defense Community materialized: it was defeated at the hands of a curious coalition of Gaullists
and Communists. So far, NATO has helped freeze the EU within its confederal
form, but the revival of Russia and renewed US isolationism, in the form of
Trump’s chaotic unilateralism, may yet change that.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
THE EU IS A CONFEDERATION, WITH
CONSOCIATIONAL DECISION-MAKING
Let us stipulate, but follow a long historiographical consensus in doing so, that a
confederation is a union of sovereign states which retain their sovereignty,
founded on voluntary treaties.15 Confederations preserve the international legal
personality of their member-states, while permitting the limited “pooling” of
delegated sovereignty. Confederations are flexible, enabling opting-in, and
opting-out of specific legal or policy domains. They may begin with unanimity
requirements among their member-states (in the EU unanimity is still required for
changes to the treaties). That is, the most fundamental reshaping of the
confederal legal order requires each state to ratify the changes according to its
own domestic requirements. Confederal institutions generally lack direct
enforcement capacities within their member-states; the latter, however, delegate
authority to confederal institutions. The executive of the confederation comprises
delegates of the member-states; its legislature, if there is one, comprises delegations from the member-states; and the highest judiciary, if there is one, adjudicates according to the terms of the treaties, and comprises judges appointed by
the respective member-states. The public officials of the confederation are
expected (in practice) to be agents of their member-states of origin. Rights of optout, powers to nullify confederal laws or decrees, and rights of generalized
amendment are normal for member-states in confederations. So, vitally, is the
right of secession entirely consistent with the member-states’ retention of their
sovereignty. In confederations the right of secession is presumed; in federations it
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
32
BRENDAN O’LEARY
is usually moot or denied, unless specifically provided for in the constitution.
Confederations are pacts among states; confederation-wide citizens are not normally parties to the foundational covenant. Lastly, unlike federations, most
confederations have had a de facto and sometimes a de jure hegemon, or leading
state.16
Accepting this conceptual conspectus as a fair account of the characteristic traits
of confederations, how does the EU match up? The EU is based on treaties – and
on the enormous derivative legislation, the acquis, that flows from the institutions
established by these treaties. The EU’s double-headed executive is strongly
confederal. The European Council comprises the heads of state and government
who oversee what flows from the interactions of Commission, the Council of
Ministers, and the Parliament. The Council nominates a designate President of the
Commission, while electing its own President from a college of former or soon-tobe former prime ministers and presidents. The President, however, is not formally,
or informally, the nominee of any hegemon. The College of Commissioners contains one nominee from each member-state, though the college is jointly ratified by
the Parliament. The member-states, despite the existence of the relatively new
Permanent President of the Council, retain a collective and rotating presidency, in
which each state, without exception, takes its turn organizing the Union’s business.
The EU’s legislature, minimally, is half confederal. The Council of Ministers
comprises member-state ministers empowered to commit their governments. At its
foundation, the predecessor to the current Parliament was equally unambiguously
confederal: its parliamentarians were delegations from the elected members of the
member-state parliaments. Direct elections after 1979 obviously changed the
Parliament’s standing, and has encouraged it, successfully, to enhance its powers –
nominally it now has equal status with the Council of Ministers in the making of
laws. However, after 40 years, though there has been convergence, there is still no
uniform electoral administration or electoral law at Union level; Members of the
European Parliament (MEPs) consistently break from their European party families if the relevant questions affect the vital interests of their member-states; and
some MEPs may be strongly guided by the Ministers from their member-states
especially when they share the same party affiliation. Union-wide election campaigns are minimal; in effect, twenty-eight second-order elections have been taking
place at member-state level. There are no true “federation-wide” parties.
What of the judiciary? Strong claims have been made for the “federal” power
and conduct of the Court of Justice of the European Union, and its precursor.
Famous cases confirming direct effect, supremacy, state liability, and indirect
effect have been taught to cohorts of students to illustrate how the Court created
a system of law, “similar to that of constitutional federal states” (Bartolini, 2005,
p. 141).17 Related cases and arguments have been shown to include the development of the doctrine of implied powers, and those of exclusivity and preemption. Legal scholars have composed accounts of the erosion of member-state
powers, and of piecemeal “juridification,” including the incremental softening of
the original three-pillar distinction of the Maastricht Treaty, which appeared to
create, in Pillars 2 and 3, zones of intergovernmental policymaking over which
the Court had no jurisdiction. Just before Maastricht, the current President of the
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
33
Court of Justice, author of the best known text on EU law in English, then a
professor, had claimed that, “[t]here is simply no nucleus of sovereignty that the
Member States can invoke, as such, against the Community” (Lenaerts, 1990,
p. 220; Lenaerts & Van Nuffel, 2011).
Yet most of the very same data can be invoked to argue that the Court,
despite its expansive interpretation of the Community/Union’s powers, and the
influence of its judgments, remains fundamentally confederal.18 The principal
Court contains one judge from each territorial member-state, a feature found in
no current federation aside from Belgium (which has but three territories). No
equivalent to a senatorial or second-chamber confirmation process applies.
Dismissal or impeachment relies on the judges themselves, as does the election of
the President of the Court, and judicial independence is further underpinned by
the announcement of decisions without the publication of dissenting opinions.
Many other procedures prevent member-state governments or MEPs from
influencing judicial decision-making. There is therefore no doubting the Court’s
independence, but that does not mean that it is a federal court. Through the
treaties, if necessary, the states can combine to restructure the Court, and to
overturn Court judgments, though that is not an easy process if one memberstates agrees with the Court. Arguably, however, the Court has to conduct itself
under the shadow of a potential treaty over-ride. In Protocol (25) of the Lisbon
Treaty, the states qualified Article 2A on the Functioning of the European
Union. Where shared competences apply, the Protocol decrees that the scope of
the Union’s competence “only covers those elements governed by the Union act
in question and therefore does not cover the whole area,” (Foster, 2018,
pp. 147–148). This protocol sought to bind the court, and the rest of the
pentangle, to prevent jurisdictional drift away from the member-states. The
Court adjudicates according to the treaties, and in enforcing Union law, it
claims, almost invariably correctly, that it is holding the states to the pledges they
have already or impliedly made. Even the development of the idea of requests for
“a preliminary ruling” – when member-state courts ask the CJEU to interpret
EU law – can be understood as a superbly nonconfrontational confederal device.
It enables the Court of Justice, which contains judges from all the member-states,
to receive a request from the relevant member-state court, and to provide a
“preliminary” rule on the point at issue. The member-states then apply this
interpretation consistent with their own jurisprudence. This procedure facilitates
coordination and coherence across the Union and allows the development of a
nonhierarchical relationship between member-state courts and the Union court,
as befits a confederal order. The Court, like its cousin the European Court of
Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (ECtHR), is also careful to allow
states “margins of appreciation.”
So far, the case has been advanced that the EU is a recognizable
confederation.19 Its historical distinctiveness lies in the economic and commercial
focus of its policymaking, by comparison with the security-focused confederations of history, its legal intensiveness (obligated by the regulation of the single
market), in its exclusively democratic membership, and in its recognition of a
common citizenship with full mobility rights. Its common citizenship is not,
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
34
BRENDAN O’LEARY
however, federal. It might be described as granting equal metic status to all citizens of member-states in other member-states. They have a right to move, reside,
and work in other member-states without discrimination. But if outside their
member-state of origin, unless they naturalize in the host state, they cannot vote
in the sovereign parliamentary or presidential elections of that host state. What is
unique is their right to vote in local government elections and in EU elections
when resident outside their member state of origin.
The EU also displays many of the turbulent attributes of confederations.
Members may come and go, opt-in and opt-out, and vary in their lawful
compliance with their pledges. Free-riding is possible because of the weak
enforcement capacities of the pentangle. Thus far, it is easier to become a memberstate than to be subsequently gravely sanctioned for noncompliance with the values
and laws of the Union. There is frequent if not constant incoherence in common
security and foreign policy because of the clashing interests and historic identifications of the member-states, and their respective geographical locations.
The Union has no formal hegemon, however. There is no consistent consensus
on whether there is an informal hegemon. Certainly, there has not been a constant one. France once played a driving role in European integration, then a
limit-setting role under de Gaulle, though it has since returned to the fray to
exercise leadership (Parsons, 2003). Today, revealingly, Germany is often called,
and with good reasons, a reluctant hegemon (Bulmer & Paterson, 2013). Are
there (nonidentical) twin hegemons? French and German leadership was
unquestionably salient from the late 1960s, beginning with Giscard d’Estaing and
Schmidt through until the late 1980s under Mitterrand and Kohl, with the British
and Italians widely judged to be less influential – though the British were in the
vanguard both of the completion of the single market, and of expansion to the
east. No one today, however, thinks that Berlin and Paris can dictate whatever
they propose, because there are, contra-hegemonic features to the EU. The
Union’s expanded size, and voting rules and representation, in the Council of
Ministers, and the Parliament, have reallocated decision-making power toward
the small- and medium-sized states. One might make the same claim about the
formal government of the ECB. And the small- and medium-sized states regard
the Court and the Commission as trustees of the treaties, and as their guardians.
Confederations survive because no dynamics provoke wholesale secession by
the member-states, and, conversely, none oblige a federation (or a unitary state) –
that might materialize through security fears, or through a powerful hegemon.20
Arguably too, the greater the cultural diversity within a union, the lower the
impetus to shift toward federal or unitarist political forms. So far, the United
States, NATO’s hegemon, has borne the costs of military leadership while protesting about European free-riding – though the sincerity of these protests may be
disputed. The economic benefits and cooperation that can be achieved within a
confederation with a credible court – a customs union, single market, and
common currency – may not require a shift toward federation, provided no major
redistributive goals are sought widely throughout the Union.
The adjectival descriptor that may usefully be attached to the EU confederation is “consociational” (Lijphart, 1969, 1975, 1977; O’Leary, 2005a). It
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
The Nature of the European Union
35
provides a suitable supplementary characterization of the Union’s decisionmaking, quicker and easier to understand than thick descriptions of how the
five institutions of the pentangle interact.21 In a consociation there is
• parity, inclusiveness, and joint decision-making in the executive and the legislature that deliberately have a strongly cross-community character;
• proportionality by number in representation and in the distribution of benefits
and burdens;
• autonomy especially in cultural, religious, and linguistic domains, and in the
recognition of territorial self-government; and, in a strong consociation;
partners enjoy veto-rights over constitutional legislation and sometimes over ordinary legislation.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
• conjoint
Decision-making within the EU pentangle fits these traits (O’Leary, 2013a,
2013b). The European Council is a grand coalition of all the member-states’
incumbent chief executives. The Council of Ministers is another grand coalition,
structured functionally. The rotating collective presidency is distinctly consociational. The Parliament, elected by PR, has multiple party families, and usually
functions without a minimum winning coalition. Tacit pacts between the centerleft, the center, and the center-right, operate, with a mild pattern of alternation in
the comparative dominance of the center-right and the center-left. Principles of
proportionality apply in EU voting rules, generally weighted in favor of the small
or medium states, and tacitly in the allocation of distributive programs across
member-states – though the older insiders have sometimes benefitted more than
the newcomers–and in the allocation of the headquarters of EU public agencies
(sited across the Union rather than concentrated in one capital). Respect for
autonomy is evident in the treaties’ recognition of member-state sovereignty, and
for all the official languages of the member-states. The EU’s language practices
conform to “the 3 1/2 1 language game” in which the coexistence of languages
may function peacefully (Laitin, 1992). English is increasingly the EU’s lingua
franca and will remain so even if its originators go into self-imposed exile. French
retains its vitality in the courts, though the Court is required to observe multilingualism in full, because of the need to communicate with the parties in the
language of the proceedings, and to ensure that its case-law is disseminated
accurately. The avoidance of cultural majoritarianism is evident in the courts and
other EU bodies which provide some margin of appreciation to member-states in
how they apply EU law, and in the formal granting of opt-outs. Veto-rights are
embedded in the unanimity requirements for changing the treaties, the custom of
unanimity in the European Council, and in the qualified majority voting rules in
the Council of Ministers and the Parliament. Consociation, however, has usually
described political arrangements within sovereign states, or regions of those
states; its partners have been communities or political parties. In the confederation of the EU, however, the member-states abide by recognizably consociational
practices for their joint decision-making; that underpins the Union’s powersharing character, and helps sustain its multinational, multiethnic, multilingual,
and multireligious peoples in peaceful coexistence.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
36
BRENDAN O’LEARY
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
IMPLICATIONS22
Classifying the EU as consociational confederation has clear implications. Territorially, the EU may be expected to fluctuate in its jurisdiction. There remain
European states intent on accession or which periodically reconsider it (from
Iceland through the Balkans to Ukraine and Turkey). Conversely, existing
member-states have the right to secede, one has done so. At least at accession,
states remarkably have the right to determine that parts of their territory may
function partly or wholly outside the acquis, or be brought in later. Lastly,
member-states may unify with other territories and subsequently become fully part
of the EU (as happened with East Germany, and as may happen with Northern
Ireland, and in the unresolved imbroglio of Northern Cyprus). The part, not the
whole, of a sovereign state sometimes determines the scale of the EU’s territory.
Functionally, as long as the EU remains confederal, we should expect some
pressure to allow opt-outs in the course of fresh policy development, especially
where functional responsibilities are shared (Adler-Nissen, 2014). We should not
expect a unidirectional flow of functional responsibilities, i.e., from the memberstates to the Union. The neo-functional tale of spillovers promoting deeper integration may have its counterpart in tales of spillbacks, in which member-states
reverse experiments they judge to have gone wrong. The most consequential
domestic sectoral question ahead will be whether the Eurozone goes beyond unified
monetary policy to develop a full banking union, at least in the regulation of
systemic banks, and whether it deepens its counter-cyclical macroeconomic coordination capacity through the development of Union-wide fiscal powers to match
those of the ECB. In the alternative, the question may become whether one or
more states are permitted to leave the Eurozone but without having to leave the
Union. Externally, the major sectoral question will be whether the combination of
a US retreat from Europe, a reassertive Russia, the rise of China, and the
completion of the UK’s exit, will jointly push this commercial confederation to
reconsider its security policy. That is, to develop a properly confederal military
capacity, with a Union army, navy, and air force, either inside or outside NATO
(Simms, 2013).
Institutionally, two patterns of crisis may be expected to flow from the diagnosis of the Union as a consociational confederation. Consociational crises may
flow from judgments of loss of parity among partners (e.g., Italian populists may
resist what they may deem a Berlin–Paris axis; or medium-sized member-states
may resist qualified majority voting). They may also follow from disproportional
outcomes (e.g., in the management of asylum seekers and economic migrants, or
in the impact from the costs of membership of the Eurozone). They may occur
after losses of autonomy (e.g., if member-states start to lose significant fiscal
freedom). Lastly, they may occur from the over-use of member-state veto powers.
The other pattern of potential institutional crisis may emanate from the
European Parliament, especially if it uses its powers without enhancing its legitimacy. In the confederal vision each member-state should regulate the conduct of
its representatives in European institutions, who should be accountable to
member-state parties and citizens, and function as their “mandatable” delegates. In
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
37
the strongest version, in the conduct of EU law-making and policy, MEPs should
have less powers and status than the ministers of member-states, and their delegated authorities (e.g., the ambassadors in COREPER, or functionally specialized
civil servants), and should be indirectly elected from and accountable to their home
parliaments, as in the world before 1979.
In the confederal understanding, the “democratic deficits,” pace David Marquand and Jürgen Habermas, are only EU-level problems if one is a federalist
(Habermas, 2012). The deficits in the confederal view are caused not by the
weakness of the European Parliament but by the member-state governments’
evisceration of their own parliaments, or their delegation of economic policymaking to independent bodies, or by their abandonment of some redistributive
welfare or tax ambitions. The European Parliament, in the confederal perspective,
is too federalist, and has had no constitutional baptism in a systematic, directly
elected, and reflective pan-European constitutional convention, or conventions in
member-states, or from ratification referendums. Treaties have ratified powers that
the Parliament has acquired, or obtained through Court rulings, without having
had previous pan-European constitutional mandates. These treaties have complex
consequences to which member-state publics are not always alert or alerted, and on
which they vote – if they vote – as a package deal; and most member-states do not
ratify Union treaties through referendums, even when they affect the sovereign
authority of their own parliaments.
In the confederal understanding, the low turnout for elections to the European
Parliament is proof of its low legitimacy. Even when supermajorities of MEPs
pass legislation or resolutions they usually jointly “represent” less than 40% of
European citizens. In sum, the Parliament lacks either democratic or federal
standing, because there is no genuine European demos. It is true that the 2019
elections, with their higher turnouts, reflect deeper politicization, but do they
display a strong federalist impulse?
If the Parliament and its Constitutional Affairs Committee took the confederal
understanding and criticism seriously it could consider some amendments. It
could have a proportional quota of MEPs from each member-state parliament to
serve as dual members alongside the directly elected MEPs; on average, MEPs
would then have a higher level of electoral endorsement. The partial return to
indirect elections might further encourage domestic parliaments to reorganize
themselves so that Union matters are appropriately processed by committees
composed of sitting MEPs, and some of these MEPs’ tasks could be performed in
Brussels extramurally and reported back to their member-state parliaments. The
Union’s acknowledged “democratic deficit” may, in the confederal vision, be
better repaired by holding member-state executives more accountable to their
local parliaments on Union matters.
CONCLUSION
The EU is history’s largest power-sharing peace project, but it has not resolved
the internal or neighboring national questions of its member-states (Mabry,
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
38
BRENDAN O’LEARY
McGarry, Moore, & O’Leary, 2013), though it has definitely not aggravated any
of them. The crises triggered by the failure of the constitutional treaty; by the
financial and banking crises; by the constitutionalizing of austerity and debtreduction programs within the Eurozone; by the failure manifestly to coordinate
foreign policy; and by the significant withdrawal of public support for traditional
parties of government in many countries, are by no means over, and they may yet
worsen. Complacency is a major danger across all the Union’s institutions. The
unfolding absurdities of UKEXIT, and its potential collateral damage, are
addressed elsewhere (O’Leary, 2018a, 2018b, 2019). UKEXIT, however, may
eventually perform aversion therapy among English enthusiasts for breaking up
the European confederation. The EU-27 have displayed remarkable solidarity
with Ireland, in preserving the Union, and in avoiding British efforts to divide
and distract them. But that does not mean the EU is in fine shape. There is no
strong call for “more Europe” across the zones of Europe the author knows well.
There is a call for a “better Europe,” the majority view, or “no Europe.”
Fortunately, the latter is still mostly a minority taste. The vice of full-blown
Euroscepticism remains concentrated in provincial England. In thinking about
making a better EU it may be wise to think prudently within confederal and
consociational understandings rather than to strike out assertively in majority
federalist or utopian democratic directions. This does not mean that Europeans
have to think unimaginatively.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
NOTES
1. My thanks to all the participants for vibrant comments in the conference at Montreal
in March 2019 that preceded this special issue, especially to Francesco Duina, John A.
Hall, and to Frédéric Mérand. I also befitted from critical comments by Mark A Pollack,
R. Daniel Keleman, Julie Lynch, and Mitchell Orenstein at the Penn-Temple Colloquium.
2. The adjective “supra-national” is widespread in international law where it seems to
refer to organizations, authority, or dispute resolution systems that emanate from outside
the relevant states but are not part of international law per se. Usage, however, does not
seem to be stable. A German jurist writes for many in saying that states “are the source of
supranational power and hold the majority of sovereign rights,” and holding that to be so
of the members of the EU (Grimm, 2015, p. 108). So, for him, the EU legal order is “supranational” yet its source comes from the member-states.
3. Circa mid-2019 several member-states have portions of their territories outside of the
EU, e.g., Greenland, the Isle of Man, Jersey, and Guernsey; for their potential significance
see O’Leary (2016). “The territorial scope of the Treaties is specified in Article 355 of the
Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union” (Consolidated version of the Treaty on
the functioning of the European Union, 2012, Article 52. 2), see Foster (2018, p. 20).
4. In 1811, the Grand Empire, saddled with Bonaparte’s relatives as fake national
monarchs, excluded much of the Balkans; Austria’s reduced domains were technically a
married-in alliance; while Sweden and Portugal were at war with the empire that was
attempting to hold down Spain (Geyl, 1949/1976).
5. Euractiv (2007). His colleague, Commissioner Margot Wallstrom, sought to shift the
subject, proposing as a “more useful” characterization the anodyne “Solutions United…
like a football club.” For Barroso’s Maoist past see “Conservative lawyer an ex-Maoist
Communist,” Irish Times, June 30, 2004, and for an interview from 1976 see retrieved from
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v5wAHv3UnXvmM.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
39
6. Rivalrous accounts exist of the trade-off and its sequencing (McKay, 1996; Moravcsik, 1998; Parsons, 2003; Zelikow & Rice, 1995).
7. For a clear economic account of European monetary union and attendant controversies see de Grauwe (2016).
8. Charlemagne, “The Trichet Letter: Poison Pen,” The Economist, November 7, 2014;
the full text of the November 2010 Jean-Claude Trichet letter to Brian Lenihan (Ireland’s
Finance Minister) was published in the Irish Times, November 6, 2014.
9. The Twa is the correct name for the people of short stature in central Africa.
10. As of mid-2019 the EU had three obvious multinational polities. One is a federation,
the Kingdom of Belgium; the other two, the Kingdom of the Spains, and the United
Kingdom, are “union-states,” not federations. The Kingdom of Denmark is the rump of a
multinational empire, and still sovereign over Greenland and the Faroe Islands.
11. The provisions on common security and defense are set out in Articles 42–46 of the
Consolidated Version of the Treaty on European Union (Foster, 2018, pp. 16–18). The
member-states are committed to aid and assist by all means in their power any of their
number that are victims of armed aggression on their territory: Article 42 (7).
12. Article 4 of the Consolidated Version of the Treaty on European Union specifies that
“competences not conferred upon the Union in the Treaties remain with the MemberStates” (Foster, 2018, p. 3).
13. Domestic policymaking in a democratic federation may be typologized, following
James Q. Wilson’s adaptation of Theodore Lowi, as threefold in character (Lowi, 1964;
critically appraised in; Moran, 2015; Wilson, 1973). Distributive policies concentrate
benefits and diffuse costs; redistributive policies take from one group or region and transfer
resources to another; and regulatory policies, developed in the collective interests of all,
typically have diffused benefits and concentrated costs. The EU’s distributive policies are
found in agriculture and regional developmental funding. The Union’s role in redistribution is minimal aside perhaps from fishing, where all redistribute to the Spanish fleet. The
incumbent member-states have sought to minimize the Union’s role in redistribution. The
EU’s revenues, a tiny fraction of the revenues of EU member-states, severely limit its
ability to redistribute; accordingly, the EU mostly performs regulatory and coordinating
functions, embedded in the acquis, making it quite distinct from the world’s large federations. One distinguished Italian analyst argues that the Union should retrench and confine
itself to the roles appropriate to a super-regulator (Majone, 1996, 2005, 2009, 2014). That
perspective will do combat with the more widespread view that the EU must grow in fiscal
capacity to match the ECB's monetary duties.
14. Previous cohorts of “inter-governmentalists,” e.g., Stanley Hoffmann, Alan Milward, and Paul Taylor, plausibly explained European institutional developments as the
outcomes of member-states’ interests and bargaining (Hoffmann, 1966; Milward, 1984,
1992, 2005; Taylor, 1991, 1993, 1995, 1996), but they did not display Moravcsik’s zeal to
exterminate any explanatory importance for such matters as geopolitics, party ideologies,
policy entrepreneurs – or for the potential initiating and coalition-building roles of medium
and small-sized states.
15. A very good guide may be found in Forsyth (1981). Article II of the Articles of
Confederation of the United States (1783) specified that, “Each state retains its sovereignty,
freedom and independence.”
16. This summation is justified by the history of confederations, from ancient Greek
leagues of city-states through to early post-independence America, the slaveholding
secessionist Confederacy, and beyond (Elazar, 1994; Forsyth, 1981; Freeman, 1863, 1893;
Hughes, 1993; Israel, 1995; Riker, 1957; Stein, 2000). This construction of confederation
excludes entities that employed the confederate title but were not what they proclaimed.
The Confederation of the Rhine, for example, was a dependency created by Napoleon. The
Confoederatio Helvetica reflects a confederal heritage, but the Swiss constitution of 1848 is
federal, albeit highly decentralized, unlike its immediate predecessor (Steinberg, 2015,
p. 45). Canadian confederation, whenever judged to have begun, resulted in a federation,
partly put together under British auspices, though its court rendered it progressively more
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
40
BRENDAN O’LEARY
decentralized (Stanley, 1974; Zines, 1991). Confederations are formalized alliances of
states, and therefore exclude tribal confederacies. The EEC was lucidly diagnosed as
confederal (Taylor, 1975). The argument here is influenced by Majone (2005) but not
identical. Contra Majone, a confederation meets the Montevideo criteria for statehood;
Majone’s claim that confederation extends Montesquieu’s idea of mixed government to the
international level is not easy to credit; and objectivity requires accepting that the development of the European Parliament, since 1979, is evidence of the partial success of Eurofederalists (Hix & Høyland, 2013). Majone was also too sanguine about the low likelihood
of secession: he predicted it would occur “only if” the EU pursued policies that seriously
violated the sovereign rights of a member or discriminated against its citizens and regions.
No matter how UKEXIT ends, the EU has not violated the UK’s sovereign rights or
negatively discriminated against its citizens or regions.
17. Van Gend en Loos (1963), Costa v ENEL (1964), Francovich (1991), Von Colson
(1984), and Marleasing (1990).
18. One of the Court’s most distinguished scholars, Joseph Weiler, has maintained that
from “the political, but not legal, point of view the Community is in fact a confederation”
(1999, p. 83). The suggestion here, by contrast, is that it is both politically and legally a
confederation. Weiler’s brilliant account of how the Court’s decisions pushed the memberstates into taking full control of the Commission, creating the Council, and emphasizing
their treaty powers, can also be read as confederal reaction to fears of run-away federalist
dispositions in other institutions.
19. The suggestion that the EU is both confederal (intergovernmental) and federal
(supranational) seems an easy comprise (Fabbrini, 2007; Hix & Høyland, 2011) but falls
apart on inspection. The argument in the main text is that the sole unambiguously
component of federation present in the EU is its Parliament, but so far it is run by
confederal coalitions of parties, rooted in the respective states. The admirably fluent and
instructive work of Luuk van Middelaar which distinguishes among confederation-states,
federation-citizens, and functionalism-offices, effectively concedes the primacy of confederation in explaining the union (van Middelaar, 2013).
20. As William Riker famously argued in his influential, albeit oft-criticized military
theory of the origins of federations (Dikshit, 1971; Riker, 1964, 1996).
21. Useful discussion of the EU and consociation began in the 1990s (Chryssochoou,
1994a, 1994b, 1997, 1998; Gabel, 1998; Hooghe, 1999; Taylor, 1991, 1995): I was a
colleague and correspondent with Taylor.
22. This section draws on a Memorandum presented at a Hearing on Electoral Reform,
before the Committee on Constitutional Affairs of the European Parliament (O’Leary,
2014).
REFERENCES
Adler-Nissen, R. (2014). Opting out of the European Union: Diplomacy, sovereignty, and European
integration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Anderson, P. (2009). The new old world. London: Verso.
Bartolini, S. (2005). Restructuring Europe: Centre formation, system building and political structuring
between the nation-state and the European Union. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bulmer, S., & Paterson, W. E. (2013). Germany as the EU’s reluctant hegemon? Of economic strength
and political constraints. Journal of European Public Policy, 20(10), 1387–1405. doi:10.1080/
13501763.2013.822824
Checkel, J. T., & Katzenstein, P. J. (Eds.). (2009). European identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Chryssochoou, D. N. (1994a). The consociational dimension of European integration: Limits and possibilities of transnational democracy. Occasional Research Papers. Institute of International Relations. Panteion University of Social and Political Sciences, Athens.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
41
Chryssochoou, D. N. (1994b). Democracy and symbiosis in the European Union: Towards a
confederal consociation? West European Politics, 17(4), 1–14.
Chryssochoou, D. N. (1997). New challenges to the study of European integration: Implications for
theory‐building. Journal of Common Market Studies, 35(4), 521–542.
Chryssochoou, D. N. (1998). Democracy in the European Union. London: IB Tauris.
Colomer, J. M. (2007). Great empires, small nations: The uncertain future of the sovereign state.
London: Routledge.
Colomer, J. M. (2016). The European empire. Scotts Valley, CA: CreateSpace Independent Publishing
Platform.
Connolly, B. (1995). The rotten heart of Europe: The dirty war for Europe’s money. London: Faber &
Faber.
Cooper, R. (2003). The breaking of nations: Order and chaos in the twenty-first century. London:
Atlantic Books.
Craig, P., & de Búrca, G.. (2011). EU law: Text, cases, and materials (6th ed.. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
de Búrca, G., & Weiler, J. (Eds.). (2012). The worlds of European constitutionalism. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
de Grauwe, P. (2016). Economics of monetary union (11th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dikshit, R. D. (1971). Military interpretation of federal constitutions: A critique. The Journal of
Politics, 33(1), 180–189.
Doyle, M. W. (1986). Empires. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Duchêne, F. (1994). Jean Monnet: The first statesman of interdependence. New York, NY: W. W.
Norton & Company.
Dunleavy, P., & O’Leary, B. (1987). Theories of the state: The politics of liberal democracy. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Easton, D. (1979). The identification of the political system. In D. Easton (Ed.), A framework for political
analysis (pp. 47–58). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press (Originally published in 1965).
Elazar, D. J. (Ed.). (1994). Federal systems of the world: A handbook of federal, confederal and
autonomy arrangements (2nd ed.). London: Longman.
Euractiv. (2007). Barroso: European Union is ‘non-imperial empire’ (long version). Retrieved from
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v5-I8M1T-GgRU&feature5related
Fabbrini, S. (2007). Compound democracies: Why the United States and Europe are becoming similar.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Finer, S. E. (1997). The history of government from the earliest times: Empires, monarchies and the
modern state (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fligstein, N. (2008). Euroclash: The EU, European identity, and the future of Europe. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Forsyth, M. (1981). Unions of states: The theory and practice of confederation. Leicester: Leicester
University Press.
Foster, N. (Ed.). (2018). Blackstone’s EU treaties & legislation 2018–2019 (29th ed.). Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Freeman, E. A. (1863). History of federal government: From the foundation of the Achaian League to the
disruption of the United States. London: Macmillan.
Freeman, E. A. (1893). History of federal government in Greece and Italy (2nd ed.). London: Macmillan.
Gabel, M. J. (1998). The endurance of supranational governance: A consociational interpretation of
the European Union. Comparative Politics, 30(4), 463–475.
Gellner, E. (1983). Nations and nationalism (2nd ed.). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Geyl, P. (1976). Napoleon: For and against. London: Penguin Books (Originally published in 1949).
Grimm, D. (2015). Sovereignty: The origin and future of a political and legal concept. New York, NY:
Columbia University Press.
Haas, E. B. (1968). The uniting of Europe: Political, social, and economic forces, 1950–1957 (2nd ed.).
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Habermas, J. (2012). The crisis of the European Union: A response. Translated by C. Cronin.
Cambridge: Polity.
Hix, S. (1999). The political system of the European Union. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
42
BRENDAN O’LEARY
Hix, S., & Høyland, B. (2011). The political system of the European Union (3rd ed.). Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Hix, S., & Høyland, B. (2013). Empowerment of the European Parliament. Annual Review of Political
Science, 16, 171–189.
Hoffmann, S. (1966). Obstinate or obsolete? The fate of the nation-state and the case of Western
Europe. Daedalus, 95(3), 862–915.
Hooghe, L. (1999). Consociationalists or weberians? Top commission officials on nationality.
Governance, 12(4), 397–424.
Hooghe, L., Marks, G., & Schakel, A. H. (2010). The rise of regional authority: A comparative study of
42 democracies. New York, NY: Routledge.
Hughes, C. (1993). Cantonalism: Federation and confederacy in the golden epoch of Switzerland. In
M. Burgess & A.-G. Gagnon (Eds.), Comparative federalism and federation (pp. 154–167).
Toronto, ON: Toronto University Press.
Israel, J. I. (1995). The Dutch republic: Its rise, greatness and fall, 1477–1806. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Laitin, D. D. (1992). Language repertoires and state construction in Africa. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Laughland, J. (1997). The tainted source: The undemocratic origins of the European idea. London:
Sphere.
Le Goff, J. (2007). The birth of Europe. Translated by J. Lloyd. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Lenaerts, K. (1990). Constitutionalism and the many faces of federalism. The American Journal of
Comparative Law, 38(2), 205–263. doi:10.2307/840100
Lenaerts, K., & Van Nuffel, P. (2011). European Union law (3rd ed.). London: Sweet & Maxwell.
Leonard, M. (2005). Why Europe will run the 21st century. New York, NY: Public Affairs.
Lijphart, A. (1969). Consociational democracy. World Politics, 21(2), 207–225.
Lijphart, A. (1975). The politics of accommodation: Pluralism and democracy in the Netherlands (2nd
ed.). Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Lijphart, A. (1977). Democracy in plural societies: A comparative exploration. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Lowi, T. J. (1964). American business, public policy, case-studies, and political theory. World Politics,
16(4), 677–715.
Mabry, T. J., McGarry, J., Moore, M., & O’Leary, B. (Eds.). (2013). Divided nations and European
integration. Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Majone, G. (1996). Regulating Europe. London: Routledge.
Majone, G. (2005). Dilemmas of European integration: The ambiguities and pitfalls of integration by
stealth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Majone, G. (2009). Europe as the would-be world power: The EU at fifty. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Majone, G. (2014). Rethinking the union of Europe post-crisis: Has integration gone too far? Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
McKay, D. H. (1996). Rush to union: Understanding the European federal bargain. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Mearsheimer, J. J. (2014). Why the Ukraine crisis is the West’s fault: The liberal delusions that provoked
Putin. Foreign Affairs, 93(5), 77–89.
van Middelaar, L. (2013). The passage to Europe: How a continent became a Union. New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press.
Milward, A. S. (1984). The reconstruction of Western Europe, 1945–51. Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press.
Milward, A. S. (1992). The European rescue of the nation-state. London: Routledge.
Milward, A. S. (2005). Politics and economics in the history of the European Union. London: Routledge.
Montevideo Convention. (1933). Montevideo Convention on the rights and duties of states. Signed at
Montevideo, December 26. Retrieved from https://www.jus.uio.no/english/services/library/
treaties/01/1-02/rights-duties-states.xml
Moran, M. (2015). Theodore J. Lowi, “American business, public policy, case studies and political
theory”. In S. J. Balla, M. Lodge, & E. Page (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of classics in public
policy and administration (online ed., pp. 1–14). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
The Nature of the European Union
43
Moravcsik, A. (1993). Preferences and power in the European community: A liberal intergovernmentalist
approach. Journal of Common Market Studies, 31(4), 473–524.
Moravcsik, A. (1998). The choice for Europe: Social purpose and state power from Messina to Maastricht. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Norman, P. (2005). The accidental constitution: The making of Europe’s constitutional treaty (2nd ed.).
Brussels: EuroComment.
O’Leary, B. (1993). Sovereignty, joint authority and shared authority. In T. Lyne, J. Marshall, B.
O’Leary, & B. Rowthorn (Eds.), Northern Ireland: Sharing authority (pp. 136–138). London:
Institute of Public Policy Research.
O’Leary, B. (2001). Introduction. In B. O’Leary, I. S. Lustick, & T. Callaghy (Eds.), Right-sizing the
state: The politics of moving borders (pp. 1–14). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
O’Leary, B. (2002). In praise of empires past: Myths and method of Kedourie’s nationalism. New Left
Review, 18, 106–130.
O’Leary, B. (2005a). Debating consociational politics: Normative and explanatory arguments. In S.
Noel (Ed.), From power-sharing to democracy: Post-conflict institutions in ethnically divided
societies (pp. 3–43). Montreal, QC: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
O’Leary, B. (2005b). Power-sharing, pluralist federation and federacy. In B. O’Leary, J. McGarry, &
K. Salih (Eds.), The future of Kurdistan in Iraq (pp. 47–91). Philadelphia, PA: University of
Pennsylvania Press.
O’Leary, B. (2010). Thinking about asymmetry and symmetry in the remaking of Iraq. In M. Weller &
K. Nobbs (Eds.), Asymmetric autonomy and the settlement of ethnic conflicts (pp. 183–212).
Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.
O’Leary, B. (2013a). Power sharing in deeply divided places: An advocate’s conclusion. In J. McEvoy
& B. O’Leary (Eds.), Power-sharing in deeply divided places (pp. 386–422). Philadelphia, PA:
University of Pennsylvania Press.
O’Leary, B. (2013b). Power sharing in deeply divided places: An advocate’s introduction. In J.
McEvoy & B. O’Leary (Eds.), Power-sharing in deeply divided places (pp. 1–66). Philadelphia,
PA: University of Pennsylvania Press.
O’Leary, B. (2014). Memorandum on the electoral law of the European Union: Confederal and federal
legitimacy and turnout. European Parliament, Committee on Constitutional Affairs, Hearing
on Electoral Reform, Brussels. Retrieved from https://www.europarl.europa.eu/cmsdata/67494/
att_20150115ATT96286-8787353330263686555.pdf
O’Leary, B. (2016). The Dalriada document: Towards a multinational compromise that respects
democratic diversity in the United Kingdom. The Political Quarterly, 87(4), 518–533.
O’Leary, B. (2018a). Postscript: New British questions or 2019 and all that! Ethnopolitics, 17(3),
325–333.
O’Leary, B. (2018b). The twilight of the United Kingdom & Tiocfaidh ár lá: Twenty years after the
Good Friday Agreement. Ethnopolitics, 17(3), 223–242.
O’Leary, B. (2019). A treatise on Northern Ireland. Consociation and confederation: From antagonism to
accommodation? (Vol. 3). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
O’Neill, D. I. (2016). Edmund Burke and the conservative logic of empire. Oakland, CA: University of
California Press.
Parsons, C. (2003). A certain idea of Europe. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Phinnemore, D. (2013). The treaty of Lisbon: Origins and negotiation. Basingstoke: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Quinlan, S. (2009). The Lisbon treaty referendum 2008. Irish Political Studies, 24(1), 107–121.
Riker, W. H. (1957). Dutch and American federalism. Journal of the History of Ideas, 18(4), 495–521.
Riker, W. H. (1964). Federalism: Origin, operation, significance. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and
Company.
Riker, W. H. (1996). European federalism: The lessons of past experience. In J. J. Hesse & V. Wright
(Eds.), Federalizing Europe? The costs, benefits and preconditions of federal political systems (pp.
9–24). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schmitter, P. C. (2000). How to democratize the European Union – And why bother? Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.
Copyright © 2020. Emerald Publishing Limited. All rights reserved.
44
BRENDAN O’LEARY
Sherwin-White, A. N. (1973). The Roman citizenship (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press (Originally
published in 1939).
Siedentop, L. (1983). Political theory and ideology: The case of the state. In D. Miller & L. Siedentop
(Eds.), The nature of political theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Simms, B. (2013). Europe: The struggle for supremacy, 1453 to the present. London: Allen Lane.
Stanley, G. F. G. (1974). The federal bargain: The contractarian basis of confederation. In K. D.
McRae (Ed.), Consociational democracy: Political accommodation in segmented societies (pp.
275–287). Toronto, ON: McClelland and Stewart.
Stein, R. M. (2000). The South won’t rise again but it’s time to study the defunct confederacy’s
constitution. Pace Law Review, 21, 395–408.
Steinberg, J. (2015). Why Switzerland? (3rd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stepan, A. C. (2001). Toward a new comparative politics of federalism, (multi)nationalism, and
democracy: Beyond Rikerian federalism. In A. C. Stepan (Ed.), Arguing comparative politics
(pp. 315–362). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Taylor, P. G. (1975). The politics of the European communities: The confederal phase. World Politics,
27(3), 336–360.
Taylor, P. G. (1991). The European community and the state: Assumptions, theories and propositions.
Review of International Studies, 17(2), 109–125.
Taylor, P. G. (1993). The lessons of the European community: The limits of European integration: The
concepts of consociation and symbiosis. In P. G. Taylor (Ed.), International organization in the
modern world: The regional and the global process (pp. 80–112). London: Pinter.
Taylor, P. G. (1995). International organization in the modern world: The regional and the global
process. London: Pinter.
Taylor, P. G. (1996). The European Union in the 1990s. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
The Member States (2012). Consolidated version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European
Union. Retrieved from http://data.europa.eu/eli/treaty/tfeu_2012/oj.
Tian, N., Fleurant, A., Kuimova, A., Wezeman, P. D., & Wezeman, S. T. (2018, May). Trends in
world military expenditure, 2017. SIPRI Fact Sheet. Retrieved from https://www.sipri.org/sites/
default/files/2018-04/sipri_fs_1805_milex_2017.pdf
Treaty of Lisbon. (2007). Treaty of Lisbon amending the treaty on European Union and the Treaty
establishing the European community. C. 306/01. Signed at Lisbon, December 13. Retrieved
from http://data.europa.eu/eli/treaty/lis/sign.
Varoufakis, Y. (2016). And the weak suffer what they must? Europe’s crisis and America’s economic
future. New York, NY: Nation Books.
Varoufakis, Y. (2017). Adults in the room: My battles with Europe’s deep establishment. London:
Bodley Head.
Weber, M. (1994). The profession and vocation of politics. In P. Lassman & R. Speirs (Eds.), Weber:
Political writings (pp. 309–369). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (Originally published
in 1919).
Weiler, J. (1999). The constitution of Europe: “Do the new clothes have an emperor?” And other essays
on European integration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, H. (1976). The governance of Britain. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
Wilson, J. Q. (1973). Political organizations. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Wilson, P. H. (1999). The Holy Roman Empire, 1495–1806: A European perspective. Basingstoke:
Macmillan.
Wilson, P. H. (2016). Heart of Europe: A history of the Holy Roman Empire. Cambridge, MA: The
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Wistrich, E. (1994). The United States of Europe. London: Routledge.
Zelikow, P., & Rice, C. (1995). Germany unified and Europe transformed: A study in statecraft.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Zielonka, J. (2006). Europe as empire: The nature of the enlarged European Union. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Zines, L. (1991). Constitutional change in the Commonwealth. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Duina, Francesco, and édéric Merand. Europe's Malaise : The Long View, Emerald Publishing Limited, 2020. ProQuest Ebook
Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/upenn-ebooks/detail.action?docID=6357746.
Created from upenn-ebooks on 2020-10-27 06:25:52.