Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
11 pages
1 file
Matteo Galletti (ed.), La mente morale. Persone, ragioni, virtù. Roma: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, 2014
In this paper I want to reconstruct and criticize the first from Anscombe's three well-known theses, namely the claim that a 'philosophy of psychology' is a preliminary task to the construction of any possible ethical theory, or that moral philosophy 'should be laid aside at any rate until we have an adequate philosophy of psychology, in which we are conspicuously lacking' . I argue that Anscombe’s idea of a “philosophy of psychology” cannot be simply identified with that of “moral psychology ” with which we are familiar now; that her main claim, namely that actions are analogous to language is quite promising; that among the implications there is not only a criticism to consequentialism but also acknowledgement of a central role for judgement, and accordingly not just a blunt refusal, but instead an unaware rediscovery of Kantian ethics; that her rediscovery of the idea of virtue is promising enough, albeit misunderstood by Anscombe herself when she presents it in terms of coming back to Aristotelian and Thomist ethics as contrasted with modern moral philosophy.
Kinesis, 2009
Anscombe (1958) believes her article demonstrates: (1) ethics cannot move forward without an adequate philosophical psychology (2) the emphatic sense of “ought” ought to bediscarded and (3) modern moral philosophers from Sidgwick to the present exhibit very few differences. Anscomberemarks that all the modern moral philosophers use the term“ought” in such a way that it demands a lawgiver. However,none of them admit of a lawgiver. Thus, she believes theyshould all be rejected. Among the modern moral ethicists,she is very critical of John Stuart Mill. I argue that Mill hasa fully developed philosophical psychology that explicatesthe importance of sympathy. From this, he is not only ableto counter her charges against utilitarianism, but also escapethe problem of using “ought” emphatically.
Philosophical Papers, 2006
This is very close to the published version of the book. There is no index, though, and some page numbers might be slightly different than in the book.
Enrahonar: an international journal of theoretical and practical reason, 2020
espanolEste articulo argumenta que habia considerablemente mas filosofia de accion en teoria moral antes de 1958 (cuando Anscombe se quejo de su falta bajo el lema «filosofia de la psicologia») que la que ha habido desde entonces. Esto se debe en parte a que Anscombe influyo en la formacion de la «teoria de la virtud» como otra posicion mas dentro de la etica normativa, y el trabajo de Anscombe contribuyo a la formacion de la «psicologia moral» como una rama completamente distinta (y ahora cada vez mas empirica) de la filosofia moral. catalaAquest article argumenta que hi havia considerablement mes filosofia d’accio en teoria moral abans de 1958 (quan Anscombe es va queixar que en faltava sota el lema «filosofia de la psicologia») que la que hi ha hagut des de llavors. Aixo es deu en part al fet que Anscombe va influir en la formacio de la «teoria de la virtut» com una posicio mes dins de l’etica normativa, i el treball d’Anscombe va contribuir a la formacio de la «psicologia moral»...
The Journal of Value Inquiry, 1974
The Oxford Handbook of Elizabeth Anscombe, 2022
Introduction In a list of twenty opinions common among Anglo-American philosophers that are inimical to the Christian religion, Anscombe includes this: "Ethics is formally independent of the facts of human life, and, for example, human physiology" (GG2, 67). Not only is that belief contrary to Christianity, it is also, on Anscombe's view, "a philosophical error and can be argued to be such on purely philosophical grounds" (GG2, 68). Here we find a characteristic of Anscombe's views on ethics generally: there is a complementarity between a purely philosophical approach and an approach informed by faith. In her treatment of the concept of sin, she offers two definitions; according to the first, a sin is a behaviour against right reason. According to the second, it is a behavior against divine law (GG2, 117). Initially, the first definition might seem at odds with her view that ethics must take account of the facts of human life. Yet, the definition must be read along with her rejection of the autonomy of ethics (GG2, 67). For her, what accords with right reason is thoroughly shaped by the facts of human life. Further, for Anscombe, these two definitions of sin are connected. If human beings were different in any of various ways, for example if we were born able to talk, never slept, sprang back to life when killed if properly kept, then what accords with right reason would be different. Moral virtues and vices would likewise be different, and so would the divine law, for it would command what is in accordance with that different nature. Hence, Anscombe adheres to a 'law conception of ethics' in the sense that she gives this term in "Modern Moral Philosophy," where it is defined as the view that "what is needed for conformity with the virtues failure in which is the mark of being bad qua man… is required by divine law" (CP3, 30). On her view, then, those who do not embrace theism can have sound ethical views: they are views about what makes one good or bad qua human being. Anscombe follows Aristotle and Aquinas in taking human beings to be themselves the starting points of a certain sort of action, that is to say, we characteristically initiate change on the basis of appetites that are shaped by a normative conception of the good. Human actions can be defective, exhibiting vice, or not, exhibiting virtue depending on whether our reasoning and appetites operate as they should. As Anscombe unequivocally puts it "'That was a morally good action' is equivalent to… 'That was a good human action', and 'That was a morally bad action' is equivalent to… 'That was a bad human action.'" (GG1, 203). Ethical norms can thereby be grounded on the kind of thing that we are, which can be grasped independently of affirming or denying any views on God. Still, the rejection of theism is not without consequences for our ethical views, according to
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice
After more than sixty years from the pioneer work of Elizabeth Anscombe Modern Moral Philosophy (1958), Virtue Ethics (VE) has firmly established itself as a prominent paradigm within moral philosophy. Since its beginning, a wide range of scholars have been confronting several issues, ranging from the importance of character to the significance of happiness and flourishing; from the insufficiency of ethical rules to the critique of situationism; from the role of moral emotions to the difference between virtuous and automatic behavior. In addition, it has been inquiring more subtle topics such as the identity of the virtueswhether they are identifiable as personality traits or as skills-, the unity of virtues, as well as virtue taxonomy (Snow 2018). Particularly, in the last few years it has been intersecting with social sciences, specifically psychology, thus approaching studies and instruments of common interest, while also facing some skepticism especially on the philosophical side. In our view, the fruitful sharing of the philosophical and the psychological methodologies appears crucial for advancing a plausible, empirically informed virtue-ethical program. Such an awareness arose gradually, facing various context-related problems. The first generation of virtue ethicistswith Anscombe, also Peter Geach, Philippa Foot, and Iris Murdochhad, on the one hand, to deal with analytical and emotivistic metaethics, and, on the other hand, with the two mainstream accounts of normative ethics: deontologism and utilitarianism or consequentialism. Such pivotal group of philosophers at the Oxford Universitymostly related to Wittgensteinargued that the core issue of moral philosophy had not been identified by existing models, either because they reduced the complexity of morality to its formal and logical aspects, or they exceeded in stressing the results of moral decisions and acts. By putting the agent, instead of their acts, at the center, they meant to concentrate their philosophical efforts on how to become good, integrating emotional and rational human dimensions, and also addressing what Anscombe termed philosophy of psychology (Anscombe 1958). The following generation of VE's followers
LAP LAMBERT Academic Publishing eBooks, 2019
Crkva u svijetu, 2021
COVID-19 ¿Estuvimos Listos? Reflexiones académicas ante el Estado, mercado y comunida, 2020
Revista Cubana De Pediatria, 2014
Aula Orientalis 40/1, 185-186, 2022
Caucasian Entomological Bulletin, 2009
Catalysis Today, 2010
International Journal of Economic and Environmental Geology, 2021
Heritage Science, 2018
Revista Ibero-Americana de Humanidades, Ciências e Educação, 2021
Зборник Матице српске за филологију и лингвистику 54/1, 2011
Journal of Current Science and Technology