Forthcoming in: Technē/Technology. Researching Cinema and Media
Technologies, Their Development, Use and Impact, (Annie van den Œver, Ed.)
Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press, 2013
Revisiting Christian Metz’ “Apparatus Theory.” A Dialogue
Martin Lefebvre and Annie van den Oever
French film theorist and critic, Christian Metz (1931‐1993) is well‐known for his “apparatus”
theory, which he developed in the 1970s. His works, in English translation, had a major
impact on international film theory: Language and Cinema (1971), Film Language: A Semiotics
of Cinema (1974), and The Imaginary Signifier: Psychoanalysis and the Cinema (1977).
Martin Lefebvre is the only researcher to have accessed the entire Metz archive of the
Bibliothèque du film (BiFi). He is a Québécois film scholar, editor of Recherches
sémiotiques/Semiotic Inquiry (RS/SI) as well as Professor and Concordia University Research
Chair in Film Studies (Montréal, Canada). As Director of the Advanced Research Team on the
History and Epistemology of Moving Image Studies (ARTHEMIS), he is interested in the
theoretical and epistemological changes in the field of film and moving image studies over
the decades, hence his interest in Metz, who played a crucial role in making Film and Cinema
Studies part of the academic curriculum at universities in Paris in the 70s and 80s. As he was
aware that BiFi housed a Metz archive that had been bequeathed by his son, Michael Metz,
after his father’s passing in 1993, Lefebvre was given permission to get a glimpse of the
archival material in 2008‐09 while he was working on the history of the Filmology movement
for a special issue of CINéMAS he was editing with François Albera.1 He knew Filmology had
been important for Metz and wanted to see if any traces of it could be found in the Metz
archive. Though the archive is difficult to access since it is not yet catalogued due to staff
shortages at BiFi, and impossible to photocopy for legal reasons, nonetheless, Lefebvre
realized it was a substantial archive and decided to seek legal authorizations and some
research funds from the Social Science and Humanities Research Council of Canada thus
enabling him to consult the entire archive (close to 45 boxes of materials). Since 2012
Lefebvre has been doing research in the Metz archive as part of his work on the history and
the epistemology of film and moving image studies. In an upcoming essay for October, co‐
authored with Dominique Chateau,2 Lefebvre used Metz' personal notes (e.g. quotations
from his study of Mikel Dufrenne’s Phénomenologie de l’expérience esthétique) to re‐
evaluate the role phenomenology played in Metz’ conception of cinema and in his
theoretical work. Furthermore, the archive contains unpublished manuscripts, which
Lefebvre intends to edit and make available for public use. One of those, a conference paper
from 1971 on the relation between semiology and aesthetics (“Existe‐t‐il une approche
sémiologique de l’esthétique?”) will be published in # 70 of 1895.3 Lastly, some of Metz’
seminars will be edited, annotated and published in the coming years.
In the context of this book on cinema and media technologies and while reassessing the
research done on it, a dialogue with Martin Lefebvre on Metz and “apparatus” theory was
initiated (by me) for three reasons: first, apparatus theory marked Metz’ (and the field of
1
film studies') pivotal shift from a linguistically oriented study of film to theorizing the
technologies of the cinema and their impact on viewers; second, the archive allows a new
assessment of the context from which apparatus theory emerged with the help of materials
that were not open to research so far; and thirdly, Metz’ theory needs to be revisited and
reassessed in terms of the new interest in film and media technologies today, to determine if
and how Metz’ premises, concepts, and findings could (or perhaps should) be made
productive in current research. In other words, there are historical, theoretical and
epistemological arguments to want to revisit Metz’s work of the 1970s. As to the format of
this dialogue: it will start with some introductory questions regarding the archive and Martin
Lefebvre’s first impressions of Metz’ personal notes. Secondly, Metz’ relation to Baudry will
be explored as he played a crucial role in the (intellectual and political) context in which the
first notes on the apparatus were written. Thirdly, crucial insights from Metz (in part
diverting from Baudry’s, who seems to have been more ideologically oriented) will be
assessed in more detail. Lastly, Metz’ relevance for the field today will be discussed.
The Metz Archive
AvdO: If you allow me some introductory questions regarding Metz’ archive before we
reassess Metz’ “apparatus theory.” What made you want to revisit and rethink Christian
Metz’ work?
ML: Metz’s name, as you know, is synonymous today with the rise of modern, truly
academic film theory. Metz, of course, was a die‐hard structuralist and in the current climate
where scholars are starting to historicize film studies and film theory, I thought it important
to look at Metz with a fresh pair of eyes. Indeed, there has not been much historical work
done so far on the structuralist moment in film studies. In a sense, therefore, this is a form of
disciplinary inward‐looking. However, I also realized, as soon as I opened the first box in the
archive, that this inward‐looking was more personal than I thought. You see I initially came
to film studies through Metz and semiology and though my work moved on to the
philosophical semeiotic of C. S. Peirce (I’m still a card‐carrying semiotician!), working on
Metz, on his archive, was also a way for me to reflect on my own connection with what I do
as a film scholar and teacher of film studies and on what got me interested in film studies
(and not just in films) in the first place.
AvdO: And what are your first overall impressions of his archive?
ML: As we speak, I have not completed reading all the materials I have gathered from the
Metz archive. In fact, I’ve only had a few months to peruse the materials. I can tell you, for
instance, that there are hundreds of “film reviews,” which are often 1 to 2 page summaries
of films Metz had seen. He was indeed an avid moviegoer, seeing several films a week, and
all sorts of films: American blockbusters, classical Hollywood and French films, European art
cinema, Asian films, etc. In an age before IMDb and the web and before DVDs, these notes
obviously served the role of aides‐mémoire. And yet, one also finds interesting – if short –
aesthetic judgments in them.
2
AvdO: There was a conference on Metz in Zurich in June 2013?4 Did you present some of
Metz’ personal notes and “reviews” there?
ML: Indeed, I did as part of a larger work on Metz and aesthetics – though it’s too early to
say at this point if one can establish a “Metzian canon” or, better yet, a “Metzian aesthetic”
from the notes he kept on the films he saw. Nonetheless. I did notice he was especially
attentive to the “worldly” aspect of narrative films, the settings, for instance the Vienna of
Ophuls’ films. Moreover, the archive also contains some of Metz’ scholarly reading notes.
Very copious notes on Sigmund Freud, on Rudolf Arnheim, on Jean Mitry and several other
authors he read. Again these were principally aides‐mémoire: the notes tend to follow an
author’s argument very closely. However, there are occasional critical asides and reflections,
e.g., the notes on Mikel Dufrenne’s Phénomenologie de l’expérience esthétique are
especially interesting. Some of the asides in these notes ended up almost verbatim in his
first published essay, “Le cinéma: langue ou langage.”5 These and other documents also
helped me re‐evaluate the role phenomenology played in his conception of cinema and its
role in his theorizing. One also finds there the galleys for Le Signifiant imaginaire and for his
unpublished manuscript L’esprit et ses mots. Essai sur le Witz which is a sort of dialogue with
Freud’s work on witz but doesn’t concern cinema.
AvdO: Does the archive reflect Metz’ position in film studies in Paris back then?
ML: Absolutely. The archive is in itself important as a document of the French film studies
scene. Because Metz kept every thesis report he ever wrote, it is fascinating to see how at
one point the entire milieu of French film studies (and sometimes beyond) gravitated around
him. An almost entire generation of scholars was either supervised by him or had him sit as a
jury member for their doctoral defense. Same thing when I look at the list of people who
either attended or gave presentations at his seminar (Michel Marie, Roger Odin, Michel
Colin, Alain Bergala, Raymond Bellour, Dominique Chateau and François Jost, Jean‐Paul
Simon, Jacques Aumont, Dana Polan, Francesco Casetti, and so many others).6 For several
years he was literally at the center of the field and therefore had a large role in shaping it.
AvdO: In fact, “film theory” as such seems a term disseminated from the 1970s onwards.
ML: The term, of course, originated with Canudo, though Eisenstein used it sparingly. As for
Metz, he uses it in the 1960s.
AvdO: As an inspiring theorist who liked dialogue and debate, Metz seems to have been at
the center of film studies, which, at the time, was internationally still a young and quickly
growing field of studies. His presence was felt in our country too, where he had close
friendships with Eric de Kuyper and Emile Poppe, whom he knew from their doctoral studies
in Paris; they wrote their doctoral dissertation with Greimas and Metz was part of their jury.
After this, De Kuyper and Poppe initiated film and performance studies in our country in the
late 1970s. They received Metz regularly at the (now Radboud) University of Nijmegen and
devoted a seminar to him and the apparatus theory in 1980.7 His first visit should in fact
have been one he would have made together with Stephen Heath, but Metz had to cancel
and was replaced by his assistant Michel Colin. Did he take personal notes of those visits, the
debates he took part in, these seminars, the theses he read?
3
ML: De Kuyper attended Metz’ seminar and in L’Énonciation impresonnelle Metz mentions
his film A STRANGE LOVE AFFAIR (co‐directed with Paul Verstaten in 1984). However there are
no traces, no summaries of debates in Nijmegen or elsewhere in the archive. I can tell you,
nonetheless, that his first visit to Nijmegen was in October 1986, where he gave three talks:
“Jokes, After Freud. Some Remarks, Some Examples”; “Photography and Fetish”; and
“Questions and Answers About Film Semiology.”
Conceptualizing a Theory of the “Apparatus”: Baudry and Metz
AvdO: Considering the shift in Metz’ work in the 1970s, my impression is that, coming from a
background in phenomenology and structuralist‐linguistics and after having explored the
study of film in terms of a language, a grammar, and a time‐based art driven by narration (in
“La grande syntagmatique du film narratif” and other works),8 Metz went on to analyze the
best ways in which the considerable impact of film images on the viewer’s imagination could
be understood. From his publications in Communications in the 1970s, one gets the
impression that Jean‐Louis Baudry may have played an important role in Metz’ shift from
studying film in terms of a grammar to conceptualizing the cinema experience in terms of an
apparatus, a dispositif. Now my question is two‐fold. First of all, what was the impact Baudry
had on Metz’ theorizing of the cinema in terms of an “apparatus”? Was he in fact a starting
point and an inspiration to Metz? Second, was the direction of Metz’s thinking in the end not
crucially different from Baudry’s, in that Metz was far less discourse‐oriented, less political,
less ideologically‐oriented than Baudry (and many of their Parisian intellectual
contemporaries, for that matter), if only because Metz’ primary concern was not the
analyses of the power relations inscribed in the cinema apparatus but rather the unveiling of
the mechanisms and processes working on the cinema viewer’s imagination?
ML: Before I answer your question, I think it’s important to mention that although Metz was
trained as a linguist, he was not formally trained as a philosopher and therefore his interest
in phenomenology was not technical, say unlike Husserl and his followers. Also the move
from linguistics to psychoanalysis as a model to think about cinema was not a break for
Metz. Sure, it opened up new objects and new perspectives, but Metz saw them as
complementary with his previous ‘filmo‐linguistic’ work. Common to both is a concern for
language and the symbolic. And in France, at the time both, could be joined under the
umbrella of structuralism.
Now, the issue of Metz’ relation to Baudry is a complicated one. Baudry was not a
“professional” scholar but a novelist who earned his living as a dentist. Of course, he was
also a member of the Tel Quel group between 1962 and 1975, along with Julia Kristeva,
Philippe Sollers, Marcelin Pleynet and Jacques Derrida. In reading The Imaginary Signifier
next to Baudry’s essays, I’ve always had the impression that Metz’ overall argument was
more subtle than Baudry’s. Of course, Metz, who knew Baudry well (theirs was a relatively
small intellectual circle), speaks highly of him (in The Imaginary Signifier he mentions
Baudry’s “remarkable analyses;” and adds that he sets up the problem of Freud’s optical
metaphors “very well”);9 and it’s obvious that he saw an ally in him (Baudry ended up
dedicating his book, L’Effet cinéma, to Metz in a collection, Ça cinéma, edited by an ex‐
student of Metz,’ Joël Farges).10 Yet, at the same time, there are only 5 very brief allusions to
4
Baudry in The Imaginary Signifier and, more importantly perhaps, they hardly have anything
to do with the problem of ideology or power relations per se. Baudry, let us recall, worked
on two fronts at once, combining, like Althusser, Freudo‐Lacanian psychoanalysis and
Marxist ideology critique. And it is chiefly around the issue of ideology that, it seems to me,
Metz was more careful than Baudry.
In the heated post‐68 context, it was Marcelin Pleynet, who, if I recall correctly, first
launched an attack on the apparatus (l’appareil) – understood here chiefly as the camera –
that determines cinema. In an interview conducted in the third issue of the very political
journal Cinéthique, Pleynet explained that before any discussion regarding the political
content of a film, or questioning their militancy, filmmakers (and critics) should question the
ideology produced by the camera itself: “the cinematographic apparatus is a properly
ideological apparatus, it is an apparatus that disseminates bourgeois ideology before
disseminating anything else. Before it produces a film, the technical construction of the
camera produces bourgeois ideology.”11 The culprit, it seems is the “perspectival code
directly inherited [and] constructed on the model of the Quattrocento’s scientific
perspective.”12 The camera, is “scrupulously constructed to ‘rectify’ any perspectival
anomaly, to reproduce in its authority the code of specular vision as it is defined by
Renaissance humanism.”13 A year and four issues later, Cinéthique published Baudry’s first
essay on cinema: “Effets idéologiques produits par l’appareil de base” [Ideological effects
produced by the basic apparatus].14
AvdO: The Parisian post‐68 context, which you label as “heated” certainly was deeply
political, and the critical focus on ideology must in part have sprung from that context. An
attack on the camera as an ideological “apparatus” or as part of an ideological “apparatus”
as Pleynet articulated must have fitted into that context quite well. Would you say that
Marcelin Pleynet was important for Baudry in this phase?
ML: Pleynet is briefly referenced by Baudry, and it is hard to miss the connection between
the claims of the two Tel Quelians regarding the camera (l’appareil) and its ideological
effects, with Baudry adding a key psychoanalytic turn to the argument. Perhaps a
terminological note is in order here. The French word “appareil” (apparatus) has been in
common usage to designate the camera (among other things) since 19th‐century
photography. However Baudry is, at least at first, somewhat equivocal in his use of the term.
In the 1970 article, he includes under it all the “technical” aspects and machinery of
filmmaking (indeed his diagram for l’appareil de base also includes the script and découpage,
the film stock, montage, the projector, the screen as well as the spectator); and yet,
throughout the piece he especially emphasizes the role of the camera. In the second essay of
1975, he tries to clarify the situation by stating: “In a general way, we distinguish the basic
apparatus (l’appareil de base), which concerns the ensemble of the devices and operations
required for the production of a film and its projection, from the dispositive (dispositif) which
solely concerns projection and which includes the subject to whom the projection is
addressed. Thus the basic apparatus comprises the film stock, the camera, film developing,
montage considered in its technical aspect, etc., as well as the dispositive of projection.”15
AvdO: Was Baudry important for Metz in this early phase?
5
ML: There is no doubt that Baudry’s work often overlaps with Metz’ own findings,
sometimes preceding them as in the case of his discussion of “primary” and “secondary”
identifications, of the mirror stage analogy, of the cinematic construction of a
transcendental subject/spectator. And, in turn, it is likely that Metz’ early work also had an
impact on Baudry: the latter’s idea that cinema is a machine that “represses” its film frames
(and shots) was stated by Metz, though in non‐psychoanalytical terms, as early as “Le
cinéma: langue ou langage” and served to some extent to ground the development of the
grande syntagmatique. Did Metz share his ideas with Baudry while he was working on the
essays that make up The Imaginary Signifier? According to Raymond Bellour, they saw each
other “semi‐regularly” in those days, and it is Metz who requested Baudry be invited to
submit an article to Communications 23. Metz himself published his first two
psychoanalytical articles in that same issue. Metz and Baudry thread very common
metapsychological ground: analysis of the cinema’s impression of reality, of the dream state
and regression of the viewer caught in a situation of reduced mobility and heightened visual
attention, a critique of idealism or idealist film theory, etc. And yet, beyond the
commonalities and points of contact, there are also some real differences. Perhaps this was
what Metz had in mind when he mentioned in passing, in The Imaginary Signifier, that he
was following Baudry “obliquely.”
AvdO: Where do Metz’ and Baudry’s analyses of the apparatus become distinctly different
enterprises?
ML: Beyond obvious small variations in theory and beyond the equally obvious fact that
Metz’ psychoanalytic intervention in film studies is meant to cover much more ground than
that of Baudry, there are more distinct differences. When we consider Baudry’s two essays,
we find him trying to make two separate though related points: 1) the cinema, through its
basic apparatus, creates a “phantasmatization of the subject” as transcendental ego by
calling on Quattrocento perspective and by repressing what it does technically, i.e., by
repressing the difference between individual film frames and, therefore, enabling narrative
continuity. The effect of which is to “transfer” this continuity onto the viewing subject,
maintaining it “whole” or “unified” and therefore maintaining the idealism that dominant
ideology requires (namely the notion that consciousness is independent from its objects and
from social relations); and 2) the idea that the success of this apparatus rests on a specific
desire whose assouvissement requires, within the apparatus, a specific dispositive
(dispositif), one akin to that described by Plato in his myth of the cave, but also by Freud in
the Traumdeutung. Baudry describes this to be a regressive desire for an earlier moment in
psychic life where perceptions and representations are undifferentiated, a form of wish‐
fulfillment fantasy that mixes perception and representation: one where real perception
paradoxically turns into the perception of representations (rather than offering itself as the
perception of reality). This second point, of course, is very close to Metz’ own analysis of
spectatorship. Now, as I mentioned earlier the key distinction between Baudry and Metz
concerns the social sphere (ideology), or better yet, the relation between the “symbolic” and
the “social” and Metz’ caution with regards to the way they interact and coalesce. But there
is also a second important difference which concerns the place of phenomenology in Metz’
argument. Let me begin by this second point.
As Dominique Chateau and I have tried to show,16 Metz spent his entire career
finding ways to accommodate phenomenology and semiology, including when semiology
6
merged with psychoanalysis. In an unpublished book manuscript, Metz even referred to The
Imaginary Signifier as a work of “phenomenological psychoanalysis” – a claim Baudry would
certainly not have made regarding his own work! Metz’ analysis of spectator identification,
the analogy with the Lacanian mirror, the study of the scopic drive from sections III and IV of
The Imaginary Signifier are in fact a reiteration, through psychoanalysis, of the
phenomenological argument first given a decade earlier in his paper on the impression of
reality (“A propos de l’impression de réalité au cinéma”).17 The same terms of reference are
used: the specificity of cinema as related to its perceptual regime, its uncommon perceptual
richness, the fact that it nonetheless gives us shadows instead of “real” objects, the
comparison with theatre, etc. Like Baudry, Metz claims that the spectator is led to
misrecognize himself as the transcendental ego of Husserlian phenomenology. This leads to
a critique of the idealist‐phenomenological tradition in film studies for being blind to the
deception it falls prey to, for failing to recognize the alienated nature of the spectatorial self
as subject of pure perception. And yet, and here Metz distances himself considerably from
Baudry’s analysis, just like the ego (in Lacanian terms) cannot escape being deluded in front
of the mirror, Metz argues that without the transformation of the spectator’s perceptual
consciousness into a “false consciousness” (the latter translating itself phenomenally in the
spectator’s alienated consciousness as cinema’s impression of reality), film would be
incomprehensible. The point, then, is not so much to politically combat alienation (the
“mirror effect ”) as to explain it, to see its function in the overall experience of cinema (at
least narrative fiction film). Perhaps this is also a way to disarm it, but not so much to
denounce and oppose it, since this would amount to oppose the pleasure film brings which
is the source of Metz’ writing. Interestingly, this is how Metz (symptomatically) read Laura
Mulvey’s famous piece of 1975, “Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema.”18 In his undated
notes on the essay he writes: “[…] the article speaks very little, barely at all, of the means to
be used to destroy the old cinema. Could it be that the article is an alibi to study and love the
latter?”
AvdO: And then there is the different attitude toward ideology?
ML: We’ve just briefly touched on it. The other key point indeed has to do with ideology. The
social – which is the domain of study of history, political economy, sociology, anthropology,
etc – is for Metz the source of all symbolism, with the latter being the object of study of
semiology and psychoanalysis (the one investigating what Freud called the secondary
process and the other the primary process). Metz however refuses the vulgar Marxist
temptation to look at the symbolic as a superstructure whose only task would be to
reproduce the infrastructure from where it arises. In fact, the symbolic for Metz is neither
wholly superstructural nor entirely infrastructural: he calls it, following Marxist philosopher
Lucien Sève, a juxtastructure. That is to say, it is distinct from the social infrastructure and,
yet unlike the superstructure, interacts with it at the same level, even in part adding itself to
it. The example Metz takes from Sève being biology in relation to the social base. This, in
fact, is an interesting example if one considers a manuscript I found in the Metz archive at
BiFi. These are notes, entitled “Vision binoculaire et vision monoculaire (idéologie et
données psycho‐physiologiques” written for his seminar of 1973‐74.19 The manuscript
considers in detail depth perception in mono‐ and binocular vision, describing the inverse
square law of distance, the law of consistency of size and shape and other principles that
ensure a good gestalt. However, the manuscript concludes by asking “in what measure and
7
in what way is perspective ideological”? The simple answer is that perspective is and is not
ideological. The key here is to distinguish between the discovery (or invention) of
perspective, its functioning and its use (for what ends or purpose?). First, Metz explains,
perspective was a discovery (the discovery of certain mechanisms of vision) and an invention
(the integration of these mechanisms to the production of a visual stimulus). This means that
the code of perspective “contains within it a scientific knowledge,” such as the knowledge of
the inverse square law, as well as the knowledge that this law, which is active in natural
perception, is unknown to its natural “users.” Consequently, in the functioning of
perspective not everything is a deception. First, the depth we feel (the “impression of
depth”) isn’t simulated (not an illusion or a deception) but is really present: “because it
results from the same mechanisms that produce it in real vision.” Indeed, Metz shows that
there are several monocular factors (masking, movement, axial movements involving the law
of inverse square) that play an important role in depth perception in binocular vision. These
factors are monocular in that they are optically independent of the fact that both eyes
perceive bidimensional images that are slightly different. Secondly, true binocular vision as
we experience it with both our eyes is really absent – and really felt to be absent – from
bidimensional perspectival representations. We don’t mistake perspectival images for 3‐D
stimulus, and though they reconstruct some of the mechanisms of real depth perception
they don’t pretend to do more than that. However, in the functioning of perspective there
are also forms of ideological deception. For one thing, perspective imagery functions on the
basis of “hiding” the very code it relies on. The functioning of the code gives the illusion of its
absence due to the resemblance or impression of reality it fosters. This is a key Metzian idea:
the code, when it “works,” always suppresses itself as code. Also ideological is the
(psychological) denial that accompanies perspective imagery: the viewer knows that true
depth is absent, and yet the presence of an impression of depth due to the monocular
factors mentioned above, drives him/her to do as if real depth were present. However
maximum ideology resides in the use that is made of the perspective code, namely in the
fact that it is most often used with “the sole end to represent stories (or visual spectacles, as
in painting) by endowing them with an air of truth.” It's this sort of subtle response to the
problem of perspective that ultimately distinguishes Metz’ approach from Baudry’s
notwithstanding all they do share. Furthermore, if I may, Metz was a true cinephile, even
though he was fully aware of how the love of film risks short‐circuiting theory (he discusses
this in the opening pages of The Imaginary Signifier). I would go so far as to say that this
cinephilia forms the repressed side of The Imaginary Signifier. It’s “symptoms” are fairly
obvious to one who knows his work well. Not so much I think for Baudry (at least in the two
essays discussed here), which, paradoxically (perversely perhaps?), may well have been
something Metz appreciated in Baudry’s work.
AvdO: Interestingly, both Baudry and the love for cinema are mentioned in the opening
pages of The Imaginary Signifier. It always seemed to me that his reflections on the cinema
as an apparatus were triggered by both: Baudry’s theorizing; and Metz’ wish to determine
how the “love for the cinema” affects theorizing. As to his love for cinema: when Metz
discusses the different relations to the “equipment of the cinema” in the small chapter on
the “The cinema as technique,”20 he explains that “a partial component of cinematic
pleasure is to be carried away by the film (or the fiction, if there is one),” another “to
appreciate as such the machinery that is carrying [one] away.”21 The filmic pleasure of
connoisseurs or cinephiles specifically “lodges in the gap between the two”: the appareil de
8
base (which is concealed or absent) and its effects (which are overwhelmingly present).22
This triggers and facilitates the interest for technique in cinephiles. It is not accidental that all
sorts of professionals, such as directors and critics, do often “demonstrate a real ‘fetishism
of technique,’” as Metz argues, adding that he uses the word “fetishism” here in an ordinary
sense.23 A fetish always being material, there is an obvious concern amongst cinephiles with
the “cinema in its physical state.” Furthermore, of all the arts “the cinema is the one that
involves the most extensive and complex equipment;” the language of the cinema is greatly
dependent on the “hardware.”24 Regarding his concern with theorizing the apparatus of the
cinema, it seems to me that Metz’ primary objective – slightly different from Baudry’s
indeed – was to explain the powerful effects created by the cinema, more particularly the
mechanisms and processes working in viewers when they go to the cinema, talk about the
cinema, love the cinema…; moreover, to lay bare the ways in which these very powerful
mechanisms might affect or were affecting the new scholarly enterprise they were all
engaged in: introducing the study of film as an academic discipline in Paris’ universities in
those days. Most of those studying film were cinephiles to begin with. They simply “loved
cinema,” classical cinema not in the least. As opposed to academic scholars in the other arts,
the problem was not how to understand film. Film is difficult to explain because it is easy to
understand – a statement by Metz that always stuck. Studying film was a new and wholly
different matter. The complex mechanisms which made film so easy and effective needed
explaining, and perhaps those in classical films in the first place. Was one function of his
apparatus theory not simply: to point out that the study of film would need to live up to the
very specific demands of an art of which “the ‘technical’ dimension is more obtrusive […]
than elsewhere”?25 For sure, I see in Metz no love for gadgets as was often apparent in the
(then new) study of new media in the early 1990s.
Furthermore, would you argue that his background in phenomenology may in some
ways have prepared him well for this new enterprise? I specifically think of Merleau‐Ponty
and the one observation which is always the focus of interest of phenomenological media
theories: the transparency of the medium or the self‐denial of the medium; the observation
that “media display something without displaying themselves” (Wiesing).26 The paradigmatic
example of a medium being transparent is language: when successfully used, the meaning
comes across and the signs are immediately forgotten. “The perfection of language lies in its
capacity to pass unnoticed” (Merleau‐Ponty).27 Obviously, it is quite a challenge to try to
explain the transparency of an art form which (certainly when compared to languages and
literature) is so heavenly loaded with hardware as the cinema is; moreover, the film medium
is subject to constant technological innovations which make themselves felt as part of the
apparatus of the cinema, and do create medium awareness, if only momentarily. One way to
explain the process of rendering the techniques transparent for Metz was in terms of codes
which created (restored) the reality effects of film. As you just put forward as a key Metzian
idea: the code, once it “works,” always conceals itself. As does the medium.
ML: Firstly, I think technology, per se, is not a key concern for Metz even though, materially,
the cinematic signifier as he understands it is determined by it. We can come back to the
idea of juxtastructure mentioned above. In discussing Merleau‐Ponty’s notion that cinema is
a “phenomenological art,” Metz writes the following:
9
It can only be so because its objective determinations make it thus. The position of
the Ego in cinema does not derive from a miraculous resemblance between cinema
and the natural characteristics of all perception; on the contrary, it is anticipated and
marked in advance by the institution (equipment, layout of film theatres, mental
apparatus [dispositif] that interiorizes all of this), and also by the more general
characteristics of the mental apparatus (appareil) (such as projection, the mirror
structure, etc). which, although less strictly dependent on a period of social history
and a technology, by no means express the sovereignty of a “human vocation,” but
rather inversely, are themselves fashioned by certain particularities of man as an
animal (as the only animal that is not an animal): his primitive Hilflosigkeit, his
dependence for care (long lasting source of the imaginary, of object relations, of the
great oral figures of feeding), the motor prematurity of the infant which condemns it
to first recognize itself through the sense of sight (and therefore in a way exterior to
itself) anticipating a muscular unity that it does not yet possess.
In short, phenomenology may contribute to the knowledge of cinema (and it
has done so) insofar as it happens to resemble it, and yet it is cinema and
phenomenology, in their common illusion of perceptual mastery that need be
brought to light by the real conditions of society and man.28
So part of the institution of cinema is dependent on technology (equipment, layout of film
theatres) as a condition of society (in Marxist terms, the infrastructure), but next to it,
juxtaposed to it, are psycho‐physical determinations. It is the connection, the juxtastructure,
between these two determinations that is of interest to Metz in studying the institution of
cinema which he defines as the meeting of three “machines”: the industrial machine which
is “external” (industrial and business practices of filmmaking, film distribution and exhibition,
but also film technology, equipment, etc.); the psychology of the spectator, which is an
“internal” machine (it interiorizes aspects of the industry – the political economy of cinema –
through a libidinal economy in a juxtaposed circuit of exchanges); and finally film criticism as
a third machine further juxtaposed to the other two machines. In this scheme, it is true,
Marxism and (semio‐)psychoanalysis, political economy and libidinal economy are on the
side of “science” and “knowledge,” as they independently – or semi‐independently – shed
light on the determining conditions of the cinema institution. In short, with regards to
psychoanalysis, technology is only of interest to Metz in terms of its juxtastructural relation
to the psycho‐physiological determination of the cinema institution.
In the brief section of The Imaginary Signifier you mention, the analogy is between
the structure of fetishism and the situation of cinephiles who “know” how much the cinema
requires a heavy investment (in both senses of the term: financial/industrial and libidinal) in
equipment or technique and yet nonetheless appreciate the (classical) film as if it were an
immediate transcription of a world that gives itself over to contemplation. The point being
that the more one knows about film (not just technique, but everything connected with the
enunciative side of filmmaking writ large: contractual details of the production of a film,
directorial intentions, etc., but also scholarly knowledge of film history, film aesthetics and
theory), the more one has to disavow this knowledge in order to achieve the kind of
“fetishistic” pleasure classical fiction cinema is capable of procuring. Even here, however, the
argument isn’t a deterministic one: film technology doesn’t necessarily lead to such psychic
structuring as Metz is describing. Take the case of very early spectators. It seems they were
interested in the projection equipment almost as much as they were in the images (or
10
“world”) it projected. The projector and its exhibition were part of the overall spectacle of
motion pictures, along with the projected images even though, one could argue, the
projector ”faded” from sight (and mind – or at least from attention) as soon as the lights
went out and the screen began to register the moving shadows (the projector could still be
overheard however). This said, the coming of encased projection booths in nickelodeons (in
part for security reasons) implied that the projector, now conceptually “domesticated,” was
no longer part of the “show” and could be construed as evidence that it’s presence might in
fact disturb those attending the spectacle. Its disappearance, if you will, enacting (or helping
enact) at an institutional level the sort of disavowal that characterizes the fetishistic
structure Metz claims for the spectator and especially the cinephile, the spectator “in the
know.” For Metz, who is interested in classical cinema’s ability to construct a world,
interested in what he calls the romanesque (the novelistic), the pleasure the film affords is
always shaded by some degree of disavowal and therefore by perversion.
In the manuscript I mentioned earlier which will be published in 1895 (“Existe‐t‐il une
approche sémiologique de l’esthétique?,” a conference paper from 1971), Metz compares
the tasks of semiology and psychoanalysis in trying to answer the question of what sort of
cinema, if any, semiology could endorse. He writes:
Every film effectively engages primary processes (for example, condensation and
displacement), but usually they remain ignored (by the filmmaker as much as by the
audience). And this is why (see Lyotard) they can accomplish desire (not fulfill it, but
accomplish it hallucinatingly)
Now it is obvious that an expanded semiology would be led to pursue to some
extent a film that would take as its subject, as its goal the analytical exhibition of the
way condensation and displacement function. Yet, by the same token this film would
be fatally deceptive and mobilize defenses. Desire would find in it its un‐
accomplishment (except where part of the libidinal economy has genuinely moved
over to the side of a desire to unmask, a desire to know, that is to say, in the end, an
assumed voyeurism, an attitude that would be at once perversion and its opposite.
Instituting in each of us such an economy is no simple undertaking).29
That same year, 1971, Metz wrote an important essay on special effects (“Trucages et
cinéma”)30 where he distinguished clearly between two forms of pleasure in the cinema:
pleasure arising from the diegesis (in this case, invisible special effects) and pleasure arising
from the “cinema‐machine,” a form of pleasure which is more closely tied with the film’s
enunciation (in this case, the pleasure concerns special affects that are recognized as such
and therefore function as a feat to be celebrated in that regard). These remarks help explain
why Metz came late to the problem of enunciation in the cinema: his pleasure lay on the
side of the diegesis which he nonetheless relentlessly and ruthlessly assaulted in seeking to
lay bare its mechanisms, its codes. This isn’t to say that his work on enunciation is devoid of
“cinephilia.” Quite the opposite, in fact: it’s the book where he cites the most films, almost
at times a catalogue, and often offering loving descriptions where adjectives such as
“magnifique” (à propos Urgence by Raymond Depardon), “les belles images” (à propos Le
Trou by Jacques Becker) abound. Perhaps the “displacement” of the site of pleasure, from
diegesis to enunciation required this new form of writing. At the Zurich conference, Dana
Polan showed very convincingly how L’Énonciation impersonnelle is a very “loving book” and
I agree with him that it “goes against the argument that exposing the apparatus breaks down
11
ideology”31 as the people at Screen had inferred. Indeed, in his unpublished “review” of WHO
FRAMED ROGER RABBIT (Zemeckis, 1988) Metz writes: “It is the triumph of the signifier, since
the story doesn’t matter anymore, and the only thing the cinema does here is to self‐exhibit,
but this triumph is not what post‐68 materialism would have believed. With the “signifier” it
is the money‐grubbers (les marchands de soupe) who triumph.”32
Now, to come back to your question, perhaps it was the phenomenologist in him that
expressed itself in that pleasure in the diegesis, the pleasure from seeing a world, the
cinephilic pleasure – the very pleasure Bazin, among others, expressed in his reviews.
However his “attacks” on the normal working of the code, his constant attempts to go
beyond or behind perception show the dilemma he was in: his discourse was not to be
confused with Bazin’s. In the end, and this is obvious in The Imaginary Signifier,
phenomenology was essential and valued by Metz, but only as the (required) negative side
(or dialectical flip‐side if you prefer) of the semio‐psychoanalytical enterprise.
AvdO: In retrospect, how do you assess Metz’ work in the 1970s? Put differently, would you
agree that apparatus theory contributed to the constitution of cinema studies as an object
sui generis, defined by a number of concepts – the cinema apparatus, the appareil de base,
the dispositif, etc. – that changed the study of film in that very period? Moreover, do you
feel film and media scholars today may still gain interesting insights from Metz’ reflections
on the apparatus as developed in The Imaginary Signifier (taking into account that these
essays were written in the heyday of psychoanalysis and that the latter lost much of its aura
since)? Or would you rather argue that Metz’ (and Baudry's) apparatus theory today is
mainly interesting from a historical and epistemological perspective?
ML: In the end, the impact of 1970s apparatus theory was perhaps greater than could’ve
been anticipated at the time, even though much of it is largely pooh‐poohed today. For one
thing, it gave new vigor to the study of spectatorship within the orbit of film and media
studies. Whereas spectator studies had always been marginal forms of sociological and
psychological interests in the discipline (from the Payne Fund studies all the way to the
Filmologie movement), apparatus theory was instrumental in initiating a move away from
the film itself (or from cinematographic codes as manifested in films) as sole object of study.
And while it was certainly guilty of the very idealism it sought to critique, offering a
universalizing conception of the spectator, as it was soon pointed out, it nonetheless opened
up an new area of study. Furthermore, by offering a target for historicized, local‐specific,
gendered as well as cognitive accounts of spectatorship – all of which criticized apparatus
theory in part or in toto – one could say it was also dialectially/negatively valuable and
important for our field. Thus, there can be no doubt that it had a profound impact on film
and media studies. That’s for the historical value of apparatus theory.
AvdO: Agreed, the historical value cannot be denied, but looking from an epistemological
perspective, would the apparatus theory still be important to the field of film studies today?
ML: If one looks at the issue epistemologically, then I think one of the questions raised by
apparatus theory concerns the good usage of analogy in theory. Let’s go back to Baudry for a
minute. There is no denying that the canonical ideal of Western film going – a situation we
find today in cinémathèques more so than in any suburban multiplex – shares a number of
features with Plato’s myth of the cave. One question, then, is what are we to make of such
12
(suggestive) likeness? And more importantly: what are we to make of the differences, what
are the “limits” of the analogy? In short: how are we to productively make use of analogies,
keeping in mind that this is what they are. Now to put it simply: Plato’s cave is an allegory,
film going isn’t. What Baudry’s analogy was inadvertently doing was turning film going into
an allegory, hence the idealistic, universalizing traits that clung to it. What Baudry produced,
then, was an image. But is this image, in itself, useful? And to what end? One problem with
this image, as media archaeologists and historians have shown us through their work, is that
it kept hidden important historical facts about various apparatuses, spectatorial situations,
different dispositives which have played a role in the emergence of cinema. Images show us
things, but they can also turn out to hide things away.
I think this is also where Metz is more interesting, in this regard, than Baudry. To be
sure, Metz uses analogies – there’s nothing intrinsically wrong with that, quite the opposite.
But his analogies are properly structural. This is always how he worked. If you look at the
wonderfully rich essay that ends The Imaginary Signifier, the long piece on metaphor and
metonymy, you see that he’s not really interested in these terms, “metaphor” and
“metonymy,” per se. What interests him is the deep semantic and logical structure they
stand for, a structure which is independent of their surface manifestation in rhetoric or
verbal language. A deep structure that seems to manifest itself also in dreams (according to
psychoanalysis) and in films. This is why his isn’t an attempt to “map” linguistics or classical
rhetoric onto film. The point for him, moreover, is always to account for an impression film
leaves on the viewer, in this case the impression that films mean more than what they show,
than what is given to visual perception alone. The same holds true for the other essays of
that book, including “The Imaginary Signifier” where a good deal of what is at stake concerns
classical cinema’s impression of reality and its involvement in the pleasure that films can
provide – in good measure due to the machinery of cinema, whereby the world of fiction is
doubly imaginary, doubly absent – and the forms of desire they rely on. Metz’ work does not
“criticize” the cinema (as Baudry does), he offers a critique of it (in an almost Kantian sense):
studying the (psychic) conditions of possibility for the pleasure it affords and how they
merge with or juxtapose technical conditions.
AvdO: Metz' interest in the “conditions of possibility” for providing “pleasure,” as you say,
was made possible by cinema's technical aspects; its apparatus, yet in your reflections on
Metz' theory, the technological seems to be outweighed by the psychoanalytical?
ML: If it appears like I’m downplaying the technological, apparatus side of Metz’ work in the
1970s, it’s because I want to avoid mechanistic/deterministic readings of it which I don’t
think properly echo his project. The material aspects of the cinematic signifier reflect desire
and pleasure as much as they dispense it. And in as much as pleasure and desire are what is
at stake in Metz’ psychoanalytic account of the apparatus, I think there are still insights to be
gained from it, even today. Indeed, if one avoids reifying it, avoids the implicit (and in,
naïvely, an almost Hegelian sense) historical scheme posited by Baudry (from Plato, to
Renaissance perspective all the way to cinema, as the only trajectory or lineage for projected
moving images), there is no reason why Metz’ overall perspective couldn’t cross‐pollinate
with some of the more historical and media archaeological work being done today. Do the
same desire and pleasure occur in watching a film on my iPhone or iPad? I think Metz would
argue that they do, for the signifier is equally imaginary there as it is when a traditional
movie screen and projector are used (I know for a fact that Metz watched a lot of films on
13
television and on videotape!). Of course, the sort of pleasure Metz discusses may be harder
to achieve or sustain when the iPhone starts ringing or when emails come in while I’m
watching a film – does this mean that we’re back to a situation akin, if only in this respect, to
that of early film goers likely disturbed by sitting next to the projector? But then again with
so many people nowadays using their smart phones in commercial film theatres, achieving
and sustaining pleasure may be a difficult project there as well…
AvdO: Is the signifier indeed equally imaginary if the screen size and other elements of the
appareil de base and the dispositif are radically changed? What happens when we remove
the traditional movie screen, the projector and its light beam, the dark cinema auditorium?
That certainly is a Metzian question. Of course such a question was not asked in the hey‐day
of classical cinema. But we may indeed wonder. What about film viewers in a train on a
bleak winter day bending over their phones to watch, say THE WIZARD OF OZ? It has struck me
many times that viewers when bending over their phones would suddenly put this typical
soft smile on their faces, as if seeing something innocent and cute. In art history this type of
effect is addressed in relation to miniature art, miniature portrait painting, doll houses etc.
Would miniature artefacts – or IMAX screens, for that matter – exist if they would not affect
viewers? Then: do phones affect the imaginary status of the seen? Do they affect the
imagination of viewers in a radically different way? One can argue that, in the end, they do
not, that is, when viewers have become users who are used to watching like this, to phrase
it tautologically. In other words: the film experience may end up being not all that different
in terms of the imagination for viewers who shift screens habitually.
ML: It is obvious that the phenomenal conditions of film watching on, say, a miniature
screen are different from those offered by mainstream large screen film theatres. One could
claim that there is a loss of impact in image and sound, for instance (however, one could
equally ask whether there are gains “elsewhere” in the experience). The counterpoint, of
course, is that individuals now have home theatres built to recover part of that impact. It’s
difficult to say how Metz would have theorized these changes in the material and perceptual
conditions of viewing films and it’s unfair to him to speculate what his views would be.
However, Metz was not insensitive to technological change in the cinema. In notes that he
took on Rudolf Arnheim’s Film as Art, Metz wrote: “Perhaps, as of 1980, the cinema in its
entirety is dead at the benefit of TV and new media.” Now Metz was very fond of Arnheim’s
work and he devoted an entire seminar to him. Further on in his notes, however, he
critiques Arnheim for failing to consider cinema’s technological evolution:
The blind spot, the closing of the mind is that he [Arnheim] didn’t understand this:
that, because it is technological, the cinema is fatally subject to evolution. The latter
can only lead to improving cinema’s impression of reality, and also render the latter
more automatic. It is true that this eliminates the coarse and childish “signifying
effects” Arnheim loved (=a gigantic shadow used symbolically doesn’t fare well in a
strongly “realistic” film) –, but it is also normal (and this Arnheim also rejected) that,
when a young art develops signifying effects become much more subtle, and, by the
same token, compatible with the complete reproduction of reality, such as the true or
false alternating and repetition effects in Hitchcock that R. Bellour studied. Arnheim
didn’t want to see – simply for a biographical reason, that of a self‐attachment to his
own era – that inseparably linked to the technical progress he abhorred, the
14
anonymous collectivity of filmmakers was becoming ever more clever, ceaselessly
recomposing its margins of creativity.33
Notice, however, that the argument concerning technology here is an aesthetic one. If we
come back to the problem of the apparatus, it’s important to recognize that Metz’ theory of
the dispositif as vehicule of the cinematic signifier is dependent on a number of principles
(especially the specific regime of absence/presence that the cinematic signifier ensures) that
still hold when watching a film on a miniature screen. In short, in Metzian terms, and
keeping in mind that the signifier is not the machine, the real question one should be asking
here is the following: with the proliferation of screens and formats, has the nature of the
cinematic signifier changed?
1
Martin Lefebvre and François Albera, eds.“La filmologie de nouveau,” CINéMAS 19, no. 2‐3 (2009).
Dominique Chateau and Martin Lefebvre, “Dance and Fetish: Metz’ Epistemological Shift,” October
(forthcoming). Parts of this article were presented as a paper in a panel on Christian Metz at the Film
Philosophy Conference in London in September 2012.
3
Martin Lefebvre, “Existe‐t‐il une approche sémiologique de l’esthétique?” 1895, no. 70 (forthcoming). Please
note that all quotations from Metz' manuscript have been translated from the French by Martin Lefebvre,
unless indicated otherwise.
4
“The semiological paradigm and Christian Metz's ‘cinematographic’ thought”
[Le paradigme sémiologique et la pensée ‚‘cinématographique’ de Christian Metz], (conference organized by
the University of Zurich, Film Studies Department, 12–14 June, 2013).
5
Christian Metz, “Le cinéma: langue ou langage” Communications 4 (1964).
6
See online: http://www.reseau‐cinema.ch/fileadmin/files/images/00_news/E‐Flyer‐DGZ.pdf.
7
[Eric de Kuyper and Emile Poppe, eds], Seminar semiotiek van de film. Over Christian Metz. Sunschrift 159
(Nijmegen: SUN, 1980). Sunschrift 158 was devoted to a partial translation in Dutch of Metz’ The Imaginary
Signifier. Moreover, many of Metz’s articles were translated by and published in Versus, the academic film
journal De Kuyper and Poppe founded and edited till late 1992. For an integral digital presentation, see
http://filmarchief.ub.rug.nl/root/Sub‐collecties/Papierenarchief/Filmtijdschriften/
8
Christian Metz, “La grande syntagmatique du film narratif,” in Essais sur la signification au cinema, vol. 1
(Paris: Klincksieck, 1968).
9
Christian Metz, Le Signifiant imaginaire (Paris: UGE, coll. 10/18), 1977, 12, 329, ftn 14.
10
Jean‐Louis Baudry, L’Effet cinéma (Paris: Editions Albatros, coll. Ça cinéma), 1978.
11
Marcelin Pleynet, “économique, idéologique, formel,” Cinéthique no. 3 (1969): 10.
12
Ibid.
13
ibid.
14
Jean‐Louis Baudry, “Effets idéologiques produits par l’appareil de base,” Cinéthique, no. 7‐8 (1970).
15
Jean‐Louis Baudry, L’Effet cinéma, 31, ftn1.
16
See Chateau and Lefebvre, “Dance and Fetish: Metz’ Epistemological Shift.”
2
15
17
The text was originally published in Cahiers du cinéma and Metz refers to it in the opening pages of Le
Signifiant Imaginaire / The Imaginary Signifier. Christian Metz, “A propos de l’impression de réalité au cinéma,”
Cahiers du cinéma, no. 166‐167 (1965).
18
Laura Mulvey, “Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema,” Screen 16, no. 3 (1975).
19
Christian Metz, “Vision binoculaire et vision monoculaire (idéologie et données psycho‐physiologiques,”
(unpublished manuscript, Metz archive at Bibliothèque du film (BiFi), Paris, 1973‐74), the subsequent quotes
are all taken from this manuscript.
20
Christian Metz, The Imaginary Signifier: Psychoanalysis and the Cinema [1977], trans. Celia Britton et al
(London: Macmillan, 1983),74‐76.
21
Ibid.
22
Ibid.
23
Ibid.
24
Ibid.
25
Ibid.
26
For a concise reflection on phenomenological media theories and Merleau‐Ponty, see Lambert Wiesing,
“What are Media?” (chapter in this book).
27
For the whole quote, see “What are Media?” in this book.
28
Metz, Le Signifiant imaginaire, 75.
29
Christian Metz, “Existe‐t‐il une approche sémiologique de l’esthétique?” (unpublished manuscript of a
conference paper, Metz archive at Bibliothèque du film (BiFi), Paris, 1971). The paper will be published in # 70
of 1895.
30
Christian Metz, “Trucages et cinéma,” in Essais sur la signification au cinéma, vol. 2 (Paris: Klincksieck, 1972).
31
In a private email.
32
Christian Metz, (unpublished review, Metz archive at Bibliothèque du film (BiFi).
33
Christian Metz from notes on Rudolf Arnheim’s Film as Art (unpublished notes, Metz archive at Bibliothèque
du film (BiFi), Paris).
16