Journal for the History of
Analytical Philosophy
Volume 8, Number 9
Editor in Chief
Audrey Yap, University of Victoria
Editorial Board
Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine
Henry Jackman, York University
Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester
Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts
Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey
Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut
Anthony Skelton, Western University
Mark Textor, King’s College London
Richard Zach, University of Calgary
Editors for Special Issues
Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University
Alexander Klein, McMaster University
Review Editors
Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver
Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University
Design and Layout
Daniel Harris, Hunter College
Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts
ISSN: 2159-0303
jhaponline.org
© 2020 Andreas Vrahimis
The Vienna Circle’s Reception of Nietzsche
Andreas Vrahimis
Friedrich Nietzsche was among the figures from the history of
nineteenth-century philosophy that, perhaps surprisingly, some
of the Vienna Circle’s members had presented as one of their
predecessors. While, primarily for political reasons, most Anglophone figures in the history of analytic philosophy had taken a
dim view of Nietzsche, the Vienna Circle’s leader Moritz Schlick
admired and praised Nietzsche, rejecting what he saw as a misinterpretation of Nietzsche as a militarist or proto-fascist. Schlick,
Frank, Neurath, and Carnap were in different ways committed
to the view that Nietzsche made a significant contribution to the
overcoming of metaphysics. Some of these philosophers praised
the intimate connection Nietzsche drew between his philosophical outlook and empirical studies in psychology and physiology. In his 1912 lectures on Nietzsche, Schlick maintained that
Nietzsche overcame an initial Schopenhauerian metaphysicalartistic phase in his thinking, and subsequently remained a positivist until his last writings. Frank and Neurath made the weaker
claim that Nietzsche contributed to the development of a positivistic or scientific conception of the world. Schlick and Frank
took a further step in seeing the mature Nietzsche as an Enlightenment thinker.
The Vienna Circle’s Reception of Nietzsche
Andreas Vrahimis
Since at least as far back as Lou Andreas-Salomé’s Nietzsche
from 1894, some scholars have detected a “positivist” phase in
Nietzsche’s intellectual development (see Hussain 2004, 365).
This interpretation has been debated in various contexts, the
most recent being an ongoing scholarly debate concerning the
precise nature of Nietzsche’s view of natural science (see, e.g.,
Cohen 1999, Clark and Dudrick 2004, Hussain 2004). This paper will examine an intricately connected topic in the history of
contemporary philosophy, namely the reception of Nietzsche’s
thought by the Vienna Circle. Despite usually avoiding the use
of this etic term as a self-description, the Vienna Circle largely
contributed to shaping the conception of “positivism” at work
in contemporary philosophy, and thereby also the conception at
stake in the aforementioned debates within Nietzsche scholarship. As I will demonstrate in this paper, some of the Vienna
Circle’s leading members had interpreted the later Nietzsche as
a positivist, as engaged in overcoming metaphysics, as an Enlightenment thinker, and as contributing to the formation of a
scientific conception of the world.
Though some of Carnap’s, Neurath’s, and Schlick’s reactions
to Nietzsche have been debated by historians of analytic philosophy,1 and though some comparisons between them have
been attempted,2 so far no comprehensive study of these various
responses has been undertaken. Scholarly focus on individual
1For Carnap, see Allen (2003); Gabriel (2004, 12); Wolters (2004, 28, 32);
Sachs (2011); Mormann (2012); Moreira (2018). For Neurath, see Nemeth
(1992). For Schlick, see Iven (2013a,b).
2For example, Nelson (2018, 324–26) briefly refers to Frank’s and Schlick’s responses to Nietzsche. Ferrari (2016) discusses the differences between Schlick’s
and Carnap’s metaethical views, mentioning that they, as well as Frank, were
influenced by Nietzsche. Mormann (2015, 421) very briefly compares Schlick’s,
figures has sometimes resulted in puzzlement: why, for example, would someone like Carnap (1959a, 80) refer to Nietzsche in
the course of presenting how modern logic allows philosophers
to overcome metaphysics? Such puzzlement is dissolved, as this
paper will show, by taking into account all of the passages in
which Vienna Circle members respond to Nietzsche’s work in
similar ways to Carnap.
In this paper, I will examine Schlick’s, Frank’s, Neurath’s,
and Carnap’s various discussions of Nietzsche throughout their
work. I will demonstrate that the Vienna Circle’s members understood Nietzsche in light of a cluster of interrelated theses.
The most important of these can be formulated as follows:
(N1) Nietzsche was an anti-metaphysical philosopher.
As I will show in what follows, Schlick, Frank, Neurath, and
Carnap all endorsed N1, interpreting Nietzsche as committed
to overcoming metaphysics. A detailed analysis of their articulations of N1, however, shows that they each emphasise different aspects of Nietzsche’s overcoming of metaphysics. We
shall see that Schlick emphasises Nietzsche’s rejection of the
possibility of knowledge of a “supersensible” (Schlick 2013, 228)
world; Frank highlights Nietzsche’s psychological and linguistic critique of metaphysical concepts; like Frank, Neurath links
Nietzsche’s overcoming of metaphysics to his use of psychology,
as well as his critique of Kantian philosophy; Carnap focuses on
Carnap’s, and Neurath’s responses to Nietzsche, only to claim (without adducing further textual evidence) that they are incompatible; nonetheless, despite
the differences Mormann notes, I will demonstrate that there are fundamental points of agreement between all three (and also Frank). Tuusvuori (2000,
159–62, 233, 290–92, 678–80) briefly overviews some of Schlick’s, Neurath’s,
Carnap’s, Frank’s and von Mises’ remarks on Nietzsche, but does not discuss
Schlick’s (at the time unpublished) lecture notes, and does not draw connections between their views. Fischer (1999) only compares Schlick’s and Carnap’s
more well-known mentions of Nietzsche. Except for Mormann (2015), almost
none of these comparisons consider the most extensive treatment of Nietzsche
by any Circle member, namely Schlick (2013).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[1]
Nietzsche’s division of his work between empirical studies and
poetry. This partly reflects disagreements within the Vienna Circle concerning the correct conception of the project of overcoming metaphysics. Clearly there are also substantial differences
between Nietzsche’s and the Vienna Circle’s members’ various
conceptions of metaphysics, as well as their proposed methods
for its overcoming. Although scholars later debated the question of Nietzsche’s commitment to a brand of falsificationism,
(e.g., Clark and Dudrick 2004, Hussain 2004), none of the Vienna
Circle’s members explicitly interpreted him as a verificationist.
Indeed, as I explain in Section 4, Schlick presents Nietzsche as
committed to the thesis that metaphysical statements are false,
rather than, as the Vienna Circle’s verificationism would have it,
meaningless. Thus N1 should be construed broadly as indicating
an overall critical attitude towards the viability of metaphysics,
rather than tied to a specific conception of a method for overcoming metaphysics.
A second thesis which the majority of the abovementioned
Vienna Circle members explicitly upheld is the following:
(N2) Nietzsche’s philosophy was intimately related to the results of specific scientific fields, including most prominently psychology.
Interestingly, in most of the relevant writings by the Vienna Circle, N2 is connected to N1. In other words, Nietzsche’s overcoming of metaphysics is seen as being accompanied by his high
estimation of empirical sciences like psychology and physiology.
As already noted, some of these writings portray Nietzsche as
deploying empirical psychological explanations in support of
the attempt to overcome metaphysics.
The combination of N1 with N2 is further connected with a
third interpretative thesis:
(N3) Nietzsche was a positivist.
Here, I employ the term “positivism” in the very broad sense
found in Schlick’s methodological and epistemological characterisation of Nietzsche. As I will show in Section 4, Schlick explicitly takes Nietzsche to be a “positivist” in the sense of being
committed to the thesis that philosophy has no special method
for acquiring knowledge, above or beyond the empirical methods
of the sciences. If metaphysics is conceived as relying on such
special methods, this means that N3 is connected to, though
it does not necessarily entail, N1.3 Schlick was in fact the only
Vienna Circle member to explicitly defend N3. However, Frank
and Neurath defend the following weaker claim:
(N3*) Nietzsche made significant contributions to the development of a scientific world conception.
In other words, Frank and Neurath, as I will show in Sections 7
and 8, do not make the bolder interpretative claim that Schlick
makes, but instead briefly mention the significance of Nietzsche’s
contributions to the scientific (or “positivistic”: Frank 1970, 232)
outlook that they also championed. That Schlick makes the
bolder claim (N3), while Frank and Neurath limit themselves
to weaker claims (N3*) may be explainable by the fact that, as
we shall see in Sections 2–5, Schlick wrote extensively on the
interpretation of Nietzsche’s oeuvre, while Frank and Neurath
did not. Carnap simply does not comment on this subject.
The fourth interpretative thesis which this paper will explore
is the view that
(N4) Nietzsche was an Enlightenment thinker.
Though closely connected to all the above theses, this view was
explicitly upheld, as we shall see, only by Schlick and Frank. Both
Schlick and Frank understood Nietzsche to be an Enlightenment
thinker insofar as: he rejected metaphysics (N1), he valued the
results of specific sciences (N2), and he was either a positivist
3For example, some varieties of nineteenth-century positivism were not
committed to N1.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[2]
(N3), as Schlick argues, or committed to a scientific conception
of the world (N3*), as Frank claims. As I show in Sections 3–4,
Schlick saw Nietzsche’s early Schopenhauerian metaphysics as
accompanied by a critique of the Socratic culture of the Enligthenment. In Schlick’s view, Nietzsche only became a proponent
of the Enlightenment when he overcame his early metaphysics
and embraced a scientific world conception.
Interestingly, N1–N4 broadly align with the types of philosophical views that the Vienna Circle outwardly presented as
characterising their unified outlook. Inwardly there were, as
most scholars agree, significant disagreements between the Circle’s members (see, e.g., Uebel 2007). Most importantly, though,
they were all agreed that this had something to do with some
brand of verificationism, the manner in which metaphysics was
to be overcome (N1) was conceived in quite distinct ways by
Schlick, Neurath, and Carnap (see, e.g., Uebel 2019). In this paper, I focus on the broad agreement between Vienna Circle members, and will therefore avoid focussing on what are otherwise
incredibly significant differences between their positions.4
Though the Vienna Circle’s members did come to see
Nietzsche as their predecessor in connection to the abovementioned theses, they also objected to specific aspects of Nietzsche’s
ethics. Carnap’s 1929 lecture notes indicate that he discussed
Nietzsche’s association with “aristocratic ethics” and “heroism”
Carnap (1922–33, 33), though the notes are inadequate for further determining Carnap’s position on this topic.5 Despite his
high enthusiasm for Nietzsche’s genius, Schlick, e.g., (1952, 78–
79) remained critical of Nietzsche’s conception of a Herrenmoral.
After Schlick’s death, Waismann (1994a,b) would follow suit in
presenting some scathing criticisms of Nietzsche’s specific view
4My focus on commonalities may come at the expense of an analysis of
Nietzsche’s influence on some of the Vienna Circle’s disagreements concerning
practical philosophy. This has already been explored in Ferrari (2016).
5Moreira (2018, 268) claims that “nothing suggests that Carnap has any
sympathy with these views”.
that the members of a “master race” (1994a, 47) should be exempt from all moral strictures. Nonetheless, it is important here
to specify that such criticisms only concern the positive conception of ethics outlined by Nietzsche. Other aspects of Nietzsche’s
ethics and metaethics, especially his critique of morality, influenced some Vienna Circle members (see, e.g., Mormann 2010,
Ferrari 2016).
The Vienna Circle’s accounts of Nietzsche are at odds with
the vehement rejections of Nietzsche’s thought developed by
other significant figures in the history of analytic philosophy.
The latter were largely a result of Nietzsche’s association with
political positions to which the majority of Anglophone analytic
philosophers were opposed. At the outset of the First World
War, British propaganda had portrayed Nietzsche as responsible
for Germany’s amoral militarism (see Martin 2006). As Akehurst (2010, 18–25, 55–58, 69–70, 96, 101–104) has shown, these
outcries shaped the Anglophone analytic reaction to Nietzsche.
Already during the interwar, Russell would claim that “Hitler’s
ideals come mainly from Nietzsche” (quoted in Akehurst 2010,
1). Russell repeats this claim in his popular History of Western Philosophy (1946, 667, 746), though there he clarifies that Nietzsche
was neither a nationalist nor an anti-Semite (1946, 791–92). The
most direct point of contrast to Nietzsche’s reception by Anglophone analytic philosophers is found in Schlick’s work. In 1914,
Schlick (2013, 77–87) defended Nietzsche against the British propagandists’ charge of militarism, and again during the 1930s
against the far-right militaristic appropriation of Nietzsche (1952,
77–79).6 Another important case in point relates to Neurath,
who in 1944-1945 had co-published with Joseph Lauwerys a series of papers arguing that Plato’s Republic should be banned
from education in post-war Germany, as fascists could use it to
propagate their ideas (see Soulez 2019, Tuboly forthc. b). Their
work predated, and influenced, similar political attacks by Rus6See Wolters (2017, 11–14), Wolters (forthc.); Vrahimis (forthc. a).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[3]
sell and Popper against figures from the history of philosophy.
Yet contrary to Russell (1946), Neurath and Lauwerys’ (1944;
1945) heated polemic against Plato and other philosophers refrained from making political accusations against Nietzsche. Instead, they contained their commentary to a brief chastisement
of Nietzsche’s portrayal of “the resemblance of his own ideas
with those of Frederic II” (Neurath and Lauwerys 1944, 575). By
contrast to Russell and other Anglophone analytic philosophers,
Schlick, and in part Neurath, resisted the far-right’s misappropriation of Nietzsche. There were, however, contrasting opinions
within the Circle.7 Carnap’s 1918 notes indicate that he conceded
the propagandists’ view of Nietzsche, classifying him alongside
Heraclitus and Thrasymachus as an individualistic defender of
“perpetual war”, conceived “as a moral necessity” (Carnap 1918,
17).8 Feigl (1981, 383) also briefly mentions Nietzsche as a militarist in 1952.
It is unlikely that either Carnap or Feigl had read Schlick’s
1914 addendum to his lecture notes, in which he develops detailed objections to Nietzsche’s portrayal as a militarist. In fact,
Schlick’s early work, where we find the most extensive treatment
of Nietzsche’s philosophy by a member of the Vienna Circle, has
until recently been overlooked by scholars.9 Schlick’s defence
of Nietzsche in his Rostock lecture notes was only published in
2013, while most of his early work has not been translated into
English. This in part explains why the Vienna Circle’s reception of Nietzsche, and in particular Schlick’s major contribution
in shaping it, has so far been inadequately studied. This article
aims to rectify this omission.
7This is unsurprising, given the political complexity of the Vienna Circle;
see e.g., Reisch (2005).
8See Moreira (2018, 267–68). As e.g., Wolters (2017, 21) points out, the
evidence suggests that Carnap had initially been an enthusiastic about the
First World War, and only converted to pacifism sometime in 1918.
9See Mormann (2010, 263–64). Exceptions include Stadler (2015, 281); Schleichert (2003); Wolters (2017), Wolters (forthc.); Vrahimis (forthc. a); Tuboly
(forthc. a).
1. Schlick’s Reading of Nietzsche
Among the Vienna Circle’s members, Schlick was clearly the
most avid admirer of Nietzsche’s work (and though the others
may have agreed with him concerning N1–N4, it is unlikely that
they shared his level of enthusiasm). Schlick’s first readings of
Nietzsche date back to 1898, when as a 16-year-old Gymnasium
student he began to be interested in philosophy (Iven 2013b,
55). Like many teenagers after him, he enthusiastically discovered Nietzsche (Iven 2013b, 17–18; 2013a, 55), and swiftly began
reading first Zarathustra and then Die fröhliche Wissenschaft (Iven
2013a, 18). He would later note in his (unpublished) autobiography that during his lifetime no other book would “so shake
and enrapture [him] as much as Zarathustra” (quoted in Iven
2013a, 18, my translation), while elsewhere he thanks Nietzsche
for causing in him “so many tears of high enthusiasm” (quoted
in Iven 2013a, 18, my translation). As Iven (2013b, 61–63) points
out, Schlick’s unpublished manuscripts even contain an undated
prose-poem emulating Nietzsche’s writing style, in which his
protagonist engages in dialogue with Nietzsche’s Zarathustra
character.10
One of the earliest scholarly acknowledgements of Schlick’s
influence by Nietzsche occurs in a 1938 memoir, where Feigl
writes that
Without more accurate biographical reference-points, it is difficult
to establish which influences had the most effect on Schlick’s work.
As regards his philosophy of life, in particular, I would hardly
venture to name anyone apart from Guyau, Nietzsche and Ruskin.
(Feigl 1979, xix–xx)
Feigl goes on to oppose his estimation of Nietzsche’s influence
10In his reminiscences of Schlick, Waismann (1979, xvii) would talk of this
tension between Schlick’s character as a scientist and his poetic inclinations.
Uebel (2020, 144–45) shows that Schlick’s break with Neurath occurred when
Neurath described as “poetry” some of the phrases he employed in describing
Konstatierungen.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[4]
on Schlick’s “philosophy of life” with other influences on his
“theoretical philosophy”. Though the division between these
two aspects of Schlick’s work is not entirely mistaken, the degree
to which Nietzsche influenced Schlick exceeds the boundaries
Feigl’s division sets. As will become clear in our study of sources
unavailable to Feigl at the time, Schlick’s early Nietzschean concerns would continue to shape not only his philosophy of life
and culture, but also his conceptions of ethics and epistemology.
As Mormann (2010, 270–71) and Ferrari (2016) have shown, Problems of Ethics restates in a more sober tone various Nietzschean
themes from Schlick’s earlier Lebensweisheit. As I will show in
Section 6, Nietzsche’s influence is also felt in Schlick’s epistemology, in connection with his consistent account of the value of
knowledge throughout his work. Nietzsche’s influence continues throughout Schlick’s work, from his 1908 Lebensweisheit to
his last unfinished book Natur und Kultur.
In what follows, I will divide my discussion of Schlick’s responses to Nietzsche into two parts. In the first part (Sections 2–
5), I will discuss Schlick’s manner of interpreting Nietzsche, as it
is presented in the course of his 1912-1923 lectures at the University of Rostock. Schlick’s primary task here concerns the exposition of Nietzsche’s thought as he interprets it, without explicitly
connecting it to his own philosophical views. In the second part
(Section 6), I will address the ways in which Nietzsche, now
seen through the prism of the interpretation offered in the Rostock lectures, influenced Schlick’s philosophical work, both in
his early realist phase and after his turn to positivism during his
Vienna years. The interpretation of Nietzsche found in Schlick’s
lectures also sheds some light on other responses to Nietzsche by
the Vienna Circle’s members (which I examine in Sections 7–9).
2. Schlick’s Nietzschean Exposition of Nietzsche
In Nietzsche’s work one can find a unique approach to the historiography of philosophy, which Schlick applies in his historical
study of Nietzsche himself. In various places, Nietzsche (e.g.,
(2002, 6–7); (1996, 109–10)) would analyse philosophical ideas
as resulting from physiological drives, often unconscious, and
explainable by means of physiology (e.g., by reference to dietary
habits). Nietzsche thus conceives of the history of philosophy
as inextricably connected to philosophers’ lives. A Nietzschean
history of philosophy would look to philosophers’ biographies,
not simply for their “valuations”, but also for the drives that
underlie them. Schlick’s Rostock lectures take what can thus be
understood as a Nietzschean approach to the thinker’s life and
work, by presenting one alongside the other.11 In fact, Schlick
(2013, 102–6) justifies his method by arguing that a complete
understanding of Nietzsche’s ideas could only emerge from an
understanding of his life. Thus, for example, aside from a number of other biographical details, Schlick pays close attention to
Nietzsche’s state of health. Schlick uses references to Nietzsche’s
illness in explaining the fact that he spent a phase in which, being
unable to work for extended periods of time, he wrote only fragments (2013, 240–42). Schlick also enters the perhaps unfortunate
debate over whether Nietzsche’s final collapse can be detected
in some of his last works. Schlick (2013, 296) rejects Möbius’
diagnosis that Nietzsche’s pronouncements of his discovery of
the doctrine of Eternal Recurrence (forgetting the origins of this
doctrine e.g., in Stoicism) were a symptom of his mental illness.
Schlick (2013, 317–18) nonetheless thinks that the lack of inhibition and self-praise that characterises Nietzsche’s last works is a
first sign of his subsequent collapse.
Schlick (2013, 99–101, 366–71) makes it clear that he does not
rank Nietzsche among the Great Philosophers, nor does he think
11Schlick’s knowledge of Nietzsche’s life comes from Raul Richter, Arthur
Dews, and Elizabeth Förster-Nietzsche (Iven 2013a, 23); Schlick (2013, 104–5)
states that the latter completely misunderstood her brother’s philosophical
work; see also Iven (2013a, 23, 33–34, 37–38), Iven (2013b, 65–66). For a discussion of the overall Germanophone reception of Nietzsche, see e.g., Aschheim
(1994).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[5]
that this detracts from the value of his work.12 Nietzsche was not
a system-builder, and did not attempt to develop a series of interconnected, coherent, original solutions to the basic problems
of philosophy.13 In most cases, according to Schlick, Nietzsche
simply adopted or reworked positions which had already been
developed in the context of earlier philosophical debates. For
example, as shown in Section 3, Schlick takes Nietzsche to have
started out as a Schopenhauerian, and thus to have simply expanded Schopenhauer’s outlook by applying it to the objects
of his philological studies. When he later overcame his early
Schopenhauerian leanings, many of Nietzsche’s new philosophical positions simply rearticulated views that were originally put
forth by earlier nineteenth-century positivists. The fact, however,
that most of Nietzsche’s answers to the traditional problems of
philosophy are not highly original does not otherwise diminish
Schlick’s appraisal of him. Schlick plainly considers Nietzsche to
be a genius.14 Schlick first of all notes that, even though his positions had already been developed in previous debates, Nietzsche
was a genius insofar as he was able to bring them together, connect them to the philosophy of culture, and articulate them with
unprecedented passion. Schlick has high praise for Nietzsche’s
style, and agrees with his own estimation that he was one of
the greatest innovators in the German language after Luther
and Goethe (2013, 301–2).15 Yet Schlick (2013, 100–1) insists that
Nietzsche should not thereby be understood as being only a
great poet. Although Nietzsche is not a great system-builder, he
is nonetheless immensely significant as a philosopher of culture.
12Nonetheless Schlick (1962, 17) elsewhere names Nietzsche as a “great
thinker”.
13In Natur und Kultur (1952, 78–79), for example, Schlick mentions that he
would obviously not turn to Nietzsche for insights into the philosophy of
mathematics. See also Sachs (2011, 314).
14Schlick had earlier developed an account of genius in Lebensweisheit (2006,
181–84).
15Reichenbach (1978, 15) also privately praises Nietzsche’s style.
Schlick conceives of changes in culture as resulting from gradual processes which may take millennia. Juxtaposed to this,
Schlick talks of those rare few solitary individuals who singlemindedly rise up against the tide in attempting to overcome
their own culture, effecting drastic changes. In 1911, a year before writing his Nietzsche lectures, Schlick had expressed this
idea in what appears to be a criticism of Nietzsche’s conception
of “the transvaluation of values” (1979c, 115). Schlick argues
that Nietzsche’s account of “that great process on which all advances in culture and the conception and quality of life depend”
(1979c, 115) mistakenly sees it in individualistic terms, as a sudden change. Instead, in Schlick’s view, transvaluation
is a constantly advancing process, slowly and inexorably occurring
everywhere, which only occasionally receives a slight change in velocity or direction due to quite exceptional personalities and events,
a change whereby particular epochs of cultural history, or of history
generally, then become separable from each other. (Schlick 1979c,
115).
Interestingly, Schlick’s list of historical “transvaluation-periods”
(1979c, 115) includes, after the Renaissance and the Reformation,
“the dawn of a scientifically grounded world-outlook” (1979c,
115). The same picture of the long durée involved in the transformation of values and cultures is conjured at the outset of
Schlick’s 1912 Nietzsche lectures (2013, 88–91). Here, he concedes that Nietzsche was in fact one of those exceptional figures
who manage to stand above the long historical tide, and effect
drastic changes in their culture (2013, 91–92).
The 1911 text states something also intimated by the 1912 lectures, and which will later be repeated by other Vienna Circle
members in upholding N3*: namely that Nietzsche’s genius is
connected to the emergence of a “scientifically grounded worldoutlook” (1979c, 115). In 1912, Schlick (2013, e.g., 92) highlights
the extent to which Nietzsche’s views, radical for his time, had
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[6]
already come to be commonplace during the twentieth century.16
Schlick (2013, e.g., 325–28) thinks that Nietzsche looked too far
ahead into the future, and thus his efforts were doomed to failure
during his own lifetime.
3. The Tripartite Division of Nietzsche’s Phases: The
Artistic-Metaphysical Phase
Like many of his contemporary Nietzsche scholars influenced
by Andreas-Salomé (2001), Schlick divides Nietzsche’s work into
the following three phases: (i) an early metaphysical phase under the influence of Schopenhauer and Wagner, (ii) an early positivist phase characterised by the overcoming of metaphysics and
an appreciation of science, and (iii) a later development of a
non-metaphysical account of the value of life from within the
strictures of positivism. In what follows, I will elaborate on each
phase as presented by Schlick, beginning with Nietzsche’s early
metaphysical phase.
In intertwining a biographical account with an attempt to comprehend his oeuvre, Schlick begins by describing Nietzsche’s and
his family’s life (2013, 107–20). He then covers Nietzsche’s career as a scholar from a fairly young age (2013, 120–28), e.g., in
establishing a philological study group with his classmates at
the age of 16 (2013, 120–21). He eventually presents Nietzsche’s
early work as tied to his career as a philologist (2013, 128–32).
Schlick also gives an account of how Nietzsche came under the
heavy influence of Schopenhauer (2013, 132–44) and Wagner
(2013, 144–51). Schlick thinks that, by idolizing these men as
his heroes, Nietzsche conjured up an idealized image of his
own self, which inevitably led to disappointment when contrasted with reality (2013, e.g., 209). This disappointment marks
the end of the first phase in Nietzsche’s work. As I explain
16Schlick’s Natur und Kultur (1952, 77–78) highlights the drastic technological
changes from Nietzsche’s day to his own, e.g., in his comparison of Nietzsche’s
conception of war and his contemporary military technology.
in Section 4, Schlick (2013, 139–40) detects a philosophical critique of Schopenhauer as latent quite early on in Nietzsche’s
intellectual development, but presents him as suppressing such
criticisms in his writings until his subsequent overcoming of
Schopenhauerian metaphysics. By contrast, Schlick (2013, 202,
208–11) presents Nietzsche’s disillusionment about Wagner as
something closer to shock effected by Nietzsche’s discovery of
Wagner’s mystical leanings. Nietzsche’s visit to Bayreuth for the
rehearsals of the Ring Cycle in 1876 is presented as the catalyst
for shattering the ideal image of Wagner.
Given the idolization described above, Schlick thinks that
Nietzsche’s philosophical contributions during this period are
not highly original, but rather minute modifications of the
Schopenhauerian outlook. Apart from other minor philological studies, the major work of this artistic-metaphysical phase
is The Birth of Tragedy, which Schlick presents as an application
of Schopenhauer’s insights to an analysis of culture. Nietzsche’s
philosophical outlook towards culture is here characterised by a
deeply critical view of the enlightenment. This is how Schlick
interprets Nietzsche’s understanding of the contrast between
the balancing of the Dionysian and Apollonian in Aeschylus
and Sophocles, on the one hand, and on the other hand Euripides’ Socratic destruction of that balance. Schlick presents
Nietzsche as equating the Enlightenment to Socratic culture.
Schlick thus thinks that the The Birth of Tragedy sees this Enlightenment Socratic culture as guided by a “will to knowledge”,
which Nietzsche denigrates. According to Schlick, Nietzsche’s
goal during his early “romantic” (2013, 205) artistic-metaphysical
phase is to overcome the Socratic-Enlightenment culture. Schlick
clarifies that Nietzsche does not hold that such an overcoming
can be effected through regressing to an ancient Dionysian culture. Rather, Nietzsche proposes that the Enlightenment’s “will
to knowledge” will be overcome through art, and more specifically through what he sees as Wagner’s Schopenhauerian approach to art.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[7]
This topic is further discussed in Nietzsche’s Untimely Meditations. Its essays belong to the artistic-metaphysical phase, since
Nietzsche is still addressing themes and problems that arise from
within a broadly Schopenahauerian framework. Nietzsche, for
example, still attacks the Enlightenment “will to knowledge”,
both in his critique of David Strauss as a Bildungsphilister (Schlick
2013, 185–92), and in his criticisms of the “idle stroller in the
garden of knowledge” as developed in “The Use and Abuse of
History for Life” (Schlick 2013, 192–98). In the last two Meditations, Schlick detects some elements of Nietzsche’s thought
that gradually prepare for the second anti-metaphysical stage.
In “Schopenhauer as educator”, for example, Schlick (2013, 198–
202) sees Nietzsche as portraying an idealized version of his former master’s genius, and this ends up bearing little resemblance
to Schopenhauer himself (Schlick 2013, 198–99). The same applies to his praise of Wagner (2013, 202–203), written right before
Nietzsche’s visit to Bayreuth finalized his disillusionment with
both his heroes. Having bid farewell to both, as Schlick sees it
(2013, 207–209), Nietzsche would move on to his positivist phase.
4. Overcoming Metaphysics: Nietzsche’s Positivist
Turn
Nietzsche’s middle period, according to Schlick (2013, e.g., 204),
thus begins with Nietzsche’s final overcoming of his Schopenhauerian metaphysics. The middle period covers over the production of three important works, Human all too Human, Daybreak, and The Joyful Wisdom (2013, 205). In Schlick’s parallel
biographical account (2013, 211–27, 243–48, 254–60, 266–76), the
anti-metaphysical turn not only coincides, as we have seen, with
a detachment from the influence of his “heroes”, but also with a
period in which Nietzsche’s health rapidly deteriorates. The state
of Nietzsche’s health makes him incredibly sensitive to changes
in climate, and as Schlick notes, Nietzsche continuously seeks
environments where the climatic conditions allow his pains to
pause (2013, 225). Schlick points out that the state of his health
not only will gradually force Nietzsche to abandon his academic
career, but also limits the time-span which he can dedicate to
writing, forcing him to compose short aphorisms.17
Nietzsche’s overcoming of Schopenhauer’s influence, in
Schlick’s account, consists primarily of the liberation of his
philosophical thinking from metaphysics. Schlick (2013, 139–40)
thinks that Nietzsche already formed doubts about Schopenhauerian metaphysics quite early on through the influence of his
reading of Lange (2013, 139–44). Nietzsche had, nonetheless, refused to shake off Schopenhauer’s system until much later in his
career. Schlick finds evidence of this in Nietzsche’s correspondence with Gersdorff in 1866, where he expresses such Langean
criticisms, but still finds ways to answer them. According to
Schlick, Nietzsche had seen that metaphysics “has no scientific
value at all . . . but was to be regarded entirely as art, as conceptpoetry” (2013, 139, my translation). Furthermore, he understood
that
metaphysics cannot be attacked by logical objections either.
“Who wants,” he writes to Gersdorff, 1866, “to refute a movement
by Beethoven, and who wants to accuse Raphael’s Madonna of a
mistake?” (Schlick 2013, 139, my translation)
It is interesting that Schlick reproduced this specific passage
from Nietzsche’s correspondence, in which he clarifies that
artistic modes of expression are not candidates for verification.
Schlick’s lecture notes do not clarify that Nietzsche’s reference to
Beethoven and Raphael is a quote from Lange, but only notes that
Nietzsche came to question Schopenhauer due to his reading of
Lange’s Geschichte des Materialismus. The example of verifying
Beethoven’s music, as we shall see in Section 9, is the precise
example that Carnap (1959a, 80) uses. Though Carnap does attribute this anti-metaphysical attitude to Nietzsche, he cites nei17Schlick too wrote aphorisms, posthumously compiled in Aphorismen
(1962).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[8]
ther Nietzsche’s letter nor Lange’s book. Thus though, as we
shall see, Carnap and Schlick are aligned in seeing Nietzsche
as anticipating the overcoming of metaphysics, it is difficult to
conclusively ascertain whether Carnap was directly influenced
by (Schlick’s knowledge of) Nietzsche’s correspondence, by his
reading of Lange, or by both.18
According to Schlick, Nietzsche’s attempt to defend Schopenhauer’s metaphysics as a kind of Langean “concept-poetry”
eventually falters. Nietzsche frees himself from metaphysics by
rejecting the idea that truth or falsehood can be in any way
relevant to emotional needs (Schlick 2013, 228). According to
Schlick, Nietzsche’s middle phase is marked by a rejection of
metaphysics, defined as any doctrine about a “supersensible”
(2013, 228) world underlying phenomena; this is how Schlick understands Nietzsche’s commitment to N1 above. Defined thus,
metaphysical systems “are not simply unprovable, but surely
false” (Schlick 2013, 228, my translation). In Schlick’s account,
Nietzsche now admits of no other knowledge other than that
given by the senses, and whose truth is discovered by science.
Nietzsche, according to Schlick, is a positivist in the following
sense: he thinks “the methods of thought of the rigorous sciences” (Schlick 2013, 229, my translation) are the only methods of
acquiring knowledge, and that “philosophy has no other method
at its disposal” (Schlick 2013, 229, my translation). Schlick is thus
committed to N3 (and furthermore sees it as intimately connected to N1). In this middle period, according to Schlick (2013,
e.g., 234, 249–50, 261), Nietzsche conceives of knowledge as the
highest good, which is pursued, in a scientific manner, for its
own sake, and which brings joy to the knower (2013, 249–50). In
Schlick’s view, Nietzsche presents metaphysics as an attempt to
“artificially embellish science” (2013, 250, my translation) which
he compares to the attempt to ornamentally beautify nature in
18Concerning Lange’s influence on Carnap, see Gabriel (2004, 10–11);
Wolters (2004, 28–29); see also Sachs (2011, 305–309).
Rococo gardens. He goes on to add:
but just as nature is more beautiful than any garden, so genuine
science is more beautiful than any metaphysic (Schlick 2013, 250,
my translation)19
Thus during the middle phase, Nietzsche’s former enthusiasm
for artistic creation is toned down. Nietzsche’s newly found appreciation of scientific rigour explains his high praise for the
significance of psychology, physiology, and evolutionary biology during both his middle and later phases, and he appeals
to psychological explanations of aesthetic phenomena (Schlick
2013, 230–31). In this way, Schlick presents Nietzsche’s commitment to N3 and N1 as connected to N2. Nietzsche’s Schopenhauerian estimation of Genius is also put on hold (Schlick 2013,
232). By extension, while Nietzsche had previously raised art
above knowledge in attacking the Socratic culture of the Enlightenment, during his middle phase he reappraises this former
rejection. This is evidenced, for example, in the high praise for
Socrates that we encounter in Nietzsche’s work during this phase
(2013, 234–36).20 Thus Schlick is committed to N4, seeing the
later Nietzsche as transformed from a critic of the Enlightenment
to its proponent. As outlined above, Schlick understands how
Nietzsche become a proponent of the Enlightenment in terms
of his overcoming of metaphysics (N1) and the accompanying
positivistic (N3) emphasis on the value of scientific knowledge
(N2).
19Schlick had previously (2006, 115–70) argued that art is a poor imitation
of nature.
20Schlick (e.g., (2008, 376, 379–80, 383); (1938, 395–97); (1962, 18)) himself
also presented Socrates in an analogous way.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[9]
5. From Wissenschaft to Life: Nietzsche’s Third
Phase
In Schlick’s conception of Nietzsche’s three phases, the developments that bring the second phase towards an end merge
organically with the outset of the third phase (2013, 276–77).
In Schlick’s estimation (2013, 277), the change from the second
to the third phase is not one in Nietzsche’s theoretical orientation, but in some of his specific practical valuations. Schlick
(2013, e.g, 240–41, 276–77) insists that Nietzsche does not revert
to his former metaphysical romanticism, and that nothing in
his later work contradicts the basic theoretical principles of his
positivism. Nietzsche remains a committed positivist (N3), and
revises neither his rejection of metaphysics (N1), nor his limitation of the knowable to what is given by the senses (e.g., Schlick
2013, 280–84).
In Schlick’s account, the specific philosophical view which
Nietzsche revises during the shift from the second to the third
phase concerns his estimation of the value of knowledge. While
in the second phase Nietzsche upholds knowledge as an absolute
value, the third phase is characterised by a relativisation of the
value of knowledge. In this third phase, Nietzsche sees the value
of knowledge as determined by the demands of life. Life is now
conceived as an unanalysable, irreducible, absolute value. The
mature Nietzsche sees that knowledge is only a small part of
life; it is valuable only insofar as it ultimately serves life (Schlick
2013, 277–78). (This, as we shall see, is a view which Schlick
will negotiate in his own conception of the value of knowledge.)
Thus, according to Schlick, Nietzsche’s emphasis shifts away
from knowledge and towards value. Nonetheless, Schlick argues
that the correct way to see Nietzsche’s later phase is as a nonmetaphysical attempt to develop this axiological project (what he
calls the “transvaluation of all values”) from within the positivist
theoretical framework that he had already accepted in the second
phase.
Nietzsche’s final period, according to Schlick, emerges with
Zarathustra’s turn to life itself as the highest value, determining and shaping even the will to knowledge. Schlick thinks of
Zarathustra as an unsurpassed masterpiece, in which Nietzsche
reaches a peak of his creative powers that the remainder of his
later works fail to attain. Zarathustra is Nietzsche’s masterpiece
primarily because it reaches a state of equilibrium between the
content and the medium in which it is expressed, namely poetry. Schlick (2013, 300–304) has nothing but high praise for the
exalted language of the book, and presents it as being unquestionably a work of genius. Though Nietzsche’s later attempts
to defend Zarathustra’s outlook in a more systematic manner (in
what he had published of his unfinished The Will to Power) are
clearly works of genius, they pale in comparison to Zarathustra
(2013, 311–12). Schlick argues that in these works Nietzsche fails
to articulate the fundamental insights of Zarathustra precisely because they are attempts to present in a theoretical manner views
that are best expressed poetically (2013, e.g., 278, 311). (As I will
show in Section 9, by contrast to Schlick, Carnap had interpreted
the later Nietzsche’s work as neatly divided between poetry and
empirical studies. Schlick’s 1912 lecture notes nonetheless partly
prefigure Carnap’s similar claims about metaphysics as being the
result of attempts to express in a theoretical medium things that
are best expressed as art or poetry.)
Schlick defends his view that the mature Nietzsche remains a
positivist by opposing metaphysical interpretations of his work.
In other words, Schlick thinks Nietzsche is committed to both
N3 and N1 throughout his middle and later periods. In order
to defend this view, Schlick must show that Nietzsche remains
within the theoretical strictures set out by his earlier positivism.
Schlick is therefore at pains to show that some of Nietzsche’s
concepts that deceptively appear to be metaphysical, such as his
doctrine of eternal recurrence and his view of the Übermensch,
are in fact consistent with his anti-metaphysical (N1) positivism
(N3).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[10]
Schlick argues that the doctrine of eternal recurrence, which
Zarathustra proclaims as a central component of his teaching, is
not a metaphysical idea (2013, 298). Nietzsche’s own positivistic strictures allow this view. The doctrine makes no reference
to a supersensible world beyond experience, but only refers to
something which could not possibly be experienced. Schlick thus
claims that a broader conception of metaphysics, which covers
over anything that could not possibly be experienced, is required
if one is to claim that Nietzsche has fallen back into metaphysics
here. As Schlick (2013, 298) notes, in unpublished documents
Nietzsche made a failed attempt to prove his thesis on the basis of physics and cosmology. Schlick (2013, 298–99) proposes
that the thesis is in fact a kind of speculative naturalistic view,
which remains a possibility that is as yet neither provable nor
unprovable by contemporary physics. It gives rise to no logical
contradiction. Schlick nonetheless questions how such a view
would have any consequence other than being “a symbolic representation of the eternal value of life” (Schlick 2013, 299, my
translation), as it seems to make no empirical difference: to whoever lives it, a life that has already had manifold recurrences will
still be new.
Schlick further rejects the idea that the notion of the Übermensch was originally intended by Nietzsche as a metaphysical
concept. Schlick (2013, 284–85) does concede that Nietzsche was
not consistent in his original non-metaphysical view, and misuses the concept in his some of his less careful last works. Schlick
(2013, 284) interprets Nietzsche’s concept of the “Übermensch”
as an evolutionary biological concept. Schlick (2013, 284) cites
Nietzsche’s first deployment of the concept in Zarathustra, which
he thinks clarifies that humans evolved from apes, and the Übermensch will evolve from humans. Schlick very briefly contrasts
the blind natural evolution of species to the “conscious” (2013,
284) production of the Übermensch through a process of education [“Höherbildungsprocess” (2013, 284)] and even of breeding
[“Höherzüchtung” (2013, 286)].
Schlick’s biological conception of the Übermensch may seem
deceptively close to some form of eugenics (i.e., the attempt to
influence the evolution of the human species by the application
of selective breeding).21 However, what Schlick has in mind is
better clarified in his earlier Lebensweisheit (90), which distinguishes, in Nietzschean terms, between “all-too-human” [Allzumenschliche] and “overhuman” [Übermenschliche] drives. Schlick’s
account here seems merely descriptive, insofar as he defines Allzumenschliche drives as those which are currently being overcome, while Übermenschliche drives are those which will become
more powerful in future humans. In Schlick’s account, education would thus play a role in strengthening or weakening certain
drives, which thereby affect the biological future of the human
species.22 This connects to Nietzsche’s project of the transvaluation of all values, as the affirmation of new values is what
will create, through habituation, the Übermenschliche drives of
the future. This explanation, of course, does not clear Schlick of
all charges, since without further inspection of Schlick’s earlier
writings, his lecture notes remain ambiguous, and could easily
leave their reader with the false impression that he approvingly
interprets Nietzsche as defending eugenics!
21The only explicitly reference to eugenics in Schlick’s work uncritically uses
it as “an example of how the biological development of the genus Homo
Sapiens can be taken up in culture as its own, indeed perhaps as its highest,
mission” (Schlick 1952, 25). See also Bright (2017). As Bright clarifies, though
the Vienna Circle later fought against race science, Schlick retained some racist
attitudes, e.g., speaking of the ‘African savage’ in order to attack the racist view
that they are morally inferior to Europeans.
22One example of this may be glimpsed from Schlick’s (2006, 155–70, 181–85;
1979b) discussions of aesthetics. Schlick envisages a process of adaptation to
the environment which will eventually allow all humans to effortlessly see the
world as beautiful, in the way that only genius artists currently see it.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[11]
6. Nietzsche’s Influence on Schlick
What I have outlined above concerns Schlick’s exposition of
Nietzsche’s thought in his Rostock lectures, i.e., in what is primarily a historically-minded enterprise. Though Schlick (2013)
does defend a number of interesting interpretative theses on
Nietzsche (N1–N4), and does often pause to evaluate some of
his views, he does not directly connect Nietzsche to his own
philosophical positions. In what follows, I will proceed to examine how aspects of Nietzsche’s thought influenced Schlick’s
positions on ethics, epistemology, and his connected conceptions
of play and the meaning of life.
Interestingly, in the Rostock lectures Schlick presents
Nietzsche as a “positivist” at a time when Schlick himself had
not yet become one. Before his conversion to positivism in 1922
through his contact with the Vienna Circle, Schlick had espoused
a brand of realism (usually categorised as either “critical” or
“structural” realism). Schlick’s early work is crucially opposed
to the most prominent positivistic philosophy of science of his
time, i.e., Machian “empiriocriticism”.23 The early Schlick does
subscribe to a broadly Machian (and Nietzschean) conception of
drive-psychology, which I will go on to discuss in more detail.
His major disagreement with Mach concerns not practical, but
theoretical philosophy, and mainly epistemology. Against the
Machian explanation of knowledge by reference to a uniform account of the drive to pleasure, Schlick argues for the autonomy
of Wissenschaft.24 Nonetheless, in reacting against Mach, Schlick
finds an ally in Nietzsche. As will become clear after we further
analyse Schlick’s conceptions of play and the value of “joyful”
knowledge, Schlick will follow Nietzsche into what, in the Rostock lectures, he had designated as the third phase of his oeuvre.
Apart from the Rostock lectures, Schlick’s clearest dialogue
23See also Lewis (1988); Textor (2018).
24See also Vrahimis (forthc. a).
with Nietzsche occurs in his 1908 Lebensweisheit. This peculiar
book offers a clear example of the unresolved tension between
Schlick’s more sober technical work and his poetic leanings.
Schlick’s influence by Nietzsche is displayed not only in numerous doctrines he puts forward, but also in the style of his writing.
Schlick swiftly moves from neurobiological explanations of the
workings of the human brain (2006, e.g., 50–51) to emotional
flourishes, often punctuated by exclamation marks, e.g., on the
meaning of love (2006, 289–332). Schlick’s partly Nietzschean
style has been described as “involuntarily comic” (Mormann
2010, 268) or “purple prose” (Uebel 2020, 144).
As Mormann (2015, 419–20) points out, there were a number of contemporary Germanophone philosophers who had responded to Nietzsche’s Schopenhauerian notion of the “will to
power” by adapting it to their own frameworks, e.g., Vaihinger’s
“will to illusion”, or Rickert’s “will to system”. Schlick similarly
reworks this broadly Schopenhauerian and Nietzschean notion
into his own evolutionary conception of a “will to pleasure”.25
In Schlick’s account, the “will to pleasure” is the drive which
governs all spheres of human activity pertaining to the attainment of practical ends. According to Schlick’s Nietzschean (and
partly Machian) psychology of drives, all values are determined
by such a will.26 We have already seen how Schlick, within this
context, develops an account of the struggle between contesting
drives, in relation to which he interprets the Nietzschean concept
of the Übermensch.
Schlick’s main aim in this book is to formulate a typology of
the ways the “will to pleasure” takes. This drive manifests itself
in different forms, some purely bodily and some mental. Thus,
for example, Schlick (2006, 108–23) distinguishes between mere
civilization, which looks to the satisfaction of bodily needs, and
a kind of utopian Kultur which seeks to effect mental joy, and
25See also Mormann (2010); Ferrari (2016); Vrahimis (forthc. a). On Schlick’s
uses of Schopenhauer, see Textor (2018).
26See Ferrari (2016); Textor (2018).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[12]
ultimately a way of living in harmony with nature.27
Rising above mere bodily needs, the “will to pleasure” develops into a “will to beauty” Schlick (2006, 155–70) that drives art
and aesthetic appreciation, and into the “will to truth” (2006,
170–81) which determines scientific knowledge. Especially in relation to the latter, Schlick (2006, e.g., 170–71) conceived of a
strict separation between two possible ways of approaching an
object in the world, one pertaining to values, the other pertaining
to facts. According to Schlick, values are pertinent to the ways
in which we approach any object in relation to specific practical ends. Such valuations involve no real scientific knowledge
[Wissenschaft]. Knowledge, as Schlick conceives it, has a purely
theoretical character, which presupposes an indifference to the
practical value of the object under examination. Thus, Schlick
thought that Wissenschaft is not subjugated to practical ends, but
is a purely theoretical type of knowledge driven by the “will to
truth”.
Though autonomous from practical goals, the “will to truth”
is not completely disengaged from them. Schlick (2006, 155–
70) has an evolutionary account of the emergence, in various
stages, of the “will to truth” from the “will to pleasure”. Before the emergence of a “will to truth”, humans (like all other
animals) are simply motivated by the drive towards pleasure.
At this stage, according to Schlick, one cannot speak of knowledge, since the drive towards pleasure guides only valuations
for practical purposes. Schlick follows Mach in showing how it
is useful for humans to make predictions conducive to particular practical ends.28 Specific predictions, however successful, are
nonetheless insufficient for Wissenschaft. A further stage is necessary, involving a notion of play (2006, 143–55) that, as we will
27This remains Schlick’s ideal throughout his life, which in Natur und Kultur
he describes in terms of Zeno of Citium’s “ὁμολογουμένως τῇ φύσει ζῆν”
(Schlick 1952, 14).
28See Textor (2018, 114–15).
see, remains central throughout Schlick’s later work.29 Schlick
(2006, 171) imagines a scenario in which all other drives are momentarily satisfied. In such a case, it becomes possible to ask,
for the sake of asking, a question which has no specific practical
application. In Schlick’s account, following adequate habituation, engaging in this kind of questioning can come to provide
pleasure—it becomes a kind of game. The game is not yet Wissenschaft: in playing the game it may not matter whether the right
answer is reached or not (2006, e.g., 173). In Schlick’s conception,
the emergence of Wissenschaft is made possible by a combination
of the ability to make predictions with the ability to enjoy playing
with questions. Playing the game enough times may enable its
players to answer some questions in a manner which has some
predictive power. Wissenschaft gradually emerges as an attempt
to answer some questions for the sake not of a practical goal,
but of finding the truth. While the drive to pleasure in the pursuit of practical ends only leads to further pursuits, there is an
immediate pleasure afforded by the pursuit of truth for its own
sake.
In Schlick’s account, knowledge can only come about through
the playful pursuit of truth.30 He connects this thesis to his critical attitude towards the notion that knowledge is the result
of work. He also presents this as his interpretation of the Nietzchean “joyful wisdom” of life. Schlick endorses Nietzsche’s
criticism of the professionalization of knowledge, and its irreconcilability with the game of pursuing knowledge:
The sensitive Nietzsche, who felt this disharmony perhaps especially in himself, therefore praises, in contrast to this unhappy
practice of erudition, the “joyful Wissenschaft” of the wise.
Wise is he [sic] to whom the contemplation of the world and the
search for truth have bestowed all their blessings . . . which the Play
of the Spirit effuses on all who give themselves to it. (Schlick 2006,
181, my translation)
29See Bonnet (2016).
30See also Bonnet (2016).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[13]
In accordance with the two later phases in Nietzsche’s work that
Schlick detects in his 1912 lectures, we can distinguish between
two ways of understanding this Nietzschean “Wisdom of Life”.31
In his middle positivist period, as Schlick emphasises, Nietzsche
develops a conception of scientific knowledge as an end in itself. What characterises, in Schlick’s account, the shift from the
middle to the later period is, as we have seen, Nietzsche’s relativisation of the value of knowledge, which is seen in terms of
its service to life. In Lebensweisheit, but also in later works (e.g.,
1974, 94–101), Schlick’s epistemology follows Nietzsche into his
third phase. For Schlick, the “will to truth” can only be fulfilled
in making successful predictions about reality (see Bonnet 2016):
Even if science does not draw its conclusions for the purpose of
action, the truth of its propositions can of course . . . only be tested
by the success of actions; the latter are then called experiments.
(Schlick 2006, 173, my translation).
This is a position that Schlick maintained throughout his Vienna
Circle years, for example in his most well-known contribution to
the Protocol-Sentence debate in “The Foundation of Knowledge”
from 1934.32 Here, Schlick more or less summarises his position
from 1908, when he states that
Cognition is originally a means in the service of life. In order to find
his way about in his environment and to adjust his actions to events,
man must be able to foresee these events to a certain extent. . . . Now
in science this character of cognition remains wholly unaltered; the
only difference is that it no longer serves the purposes of life, is not
sought because of its utility. With the confirmation of prediction
the scientific goal is achieved: the joy in cognition is the joy of
verification, the triumphant feeling of having guessed correctly.
And it is this that the observation statements bring about. (Schlick
1959, 222–23)
31The mature Schlick (e.g., (2008)) retains this term to describe his metaphilosophical views.
32See also Uebel (2007); Uebel (2020); Bonnet (2016).
As has been made clear by our discussion so far, the view of
joyful verification Schlick advances here comes from Nietzsche.
It is thus perhaps fitting that the accompanying notion of Konstatierungen has been translated into English as “affirmations”,
carrying the appropriate Nietzschean overtones.33
The influence of Nietzsche on Schlick is also made explicit
in “On the Meaning of Life”. The main thesis of Schlick’s 1927
article is that the meaning of life consists in playful activity undertaken for its own sake. Schlick here presents his view of
the meaning of life as a development of his engagement with
Nietzsche’s response to Schopenhauer on this matter. Schlick’s
account of the meaning of life is based on a rejection of the
Schopenhauerian dictum that life is meaningless (Schlick 1979a,
113).34 Schopenhauer famously framed this contention in terms
of the view of all action as driven by desires that unceasingly
lead to further desires, and so on ad nauseam. Schlick seems to
implicitly accept Schopenhauer’s framing of the question of the
meaning of life, and thus it is in response to this that he searches
for the answer in activity that is undertaken for its own sake.
Schlick claims that Nietzsche’s overcoming of Schopenhauer’s
pessimism was a predecessor to his own view of the meaning
of life. He summarises the gist of the tripartite periodization of
Nietzsche’s work he had discussed in his Rostock lectures, now
seen as three ways of responding to pessimism:
First by the flight into art: consider the world, he says, as an aesthetic
phenomenon, and it is eternally vindicated! Then by the flight into
knowledge: look upon life as an experiment of the knower, and
the world will be to you the finest of laboratories! But Nietzsche
again turned away from these standpoints; . . . henceforth the ultimate value of life, to him, was life itself . . . For he saw that life has
no meaning, so long as it stands wholly under the domination of
purposes. (Schlick 1979a, 113)
Schlick evidently develops the thought which he finds in “the
33See also Uebel (2020, 145).
34On Schlick’s overall response to Schopenhauer, see Textor (2018).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[14]
wisest Nietzsche . . . of Zarathustra” (1979a, 113), explicitly connecting it to his own conception of play. Repeating, in brief, the
outlook he had developed in 1908, Schlick defines play, explicitly
against the ordinary usage of the term (1979a, 115), in terms of
all free activities that “exist for their own sake and carry their satisfaction in themselves” (1979a, 114), rather than existing for the
satisfaction of some other desired end. He presents this insight
as a continuation of the last stage in Nietzsche’s work.
So far, I have argued for a consistent influence by Nietzsche
on some of Schlick’s fundamental views concerning the value
of knowledge and its relation to drive psychology, as well as his
conception of play. Recent scholarship has also outlined some
other aspects of Nietzsche’s influence on Schlick. Ferrari (2016),
for example, shows that Schlick appealed to Nietzschean insights
in rejecting the philosophy of values developed within his contemporary Neo-Kantianism and Phenomenology. Though I will
not further discuss the details of this view in this paper, I should
here note that the same theme will appear in some of his fellow
Vienna Circle’s members’ responses to Nietzsche, to which I now
turn.
7. Philipp Frank on Nietzsche as an Enlightenment
Philosopher
It is highly unlikely that Schlick’s work on Nietzsche was known
by Philipp Frank in 1917 when he wrote “The importance of Ernst
Mach’s Philosophy of Science for our times”. Frank nonetheless
echoes, and even amplifies, Schlick’s view of the second and
third phases of Nietzsche’s work when he interprets Nietzsche,
alongside Mach, as an Enlightenment thinker. Frank prefaces his
discussion of their relation by noting that it concerns “the striking
agreement of his [i.e., Mach’s] views with those of a thinker
for whom he cannot have had any great sympathy, Friedrich
Nietzsche” (Frank 1970, 232).
The main relevant influence on Frank comes from the parallel
between Mach and Nietzsche drawn by Hans Kleinpeter in his
1913 Der Phenomenalismus.35 According to Kleinpeter’s interpretation, which has generally been ignored by Nietzsche scholarship,36 Mach and Nietzsche both developed phenomenalist epistemologies.37 Kleinpeter detects two epistemological principles
which characterise both Nietzsche’s and Mach’s phenomenalism, namely: (a) the view that all knowledge is grounded in
sensations, and (b) the view that all our concepts are mere symbols and thus ““truth” has only a relative meaning” (Gori 2012,
343). In both philosophers’ epistemologies, there is no purely
logical way of reaching out to a true description of the world
without recourse to sensations.38 This, as Kleinpeter saw, meant
that both Nietzsche and Mach were concerned with working out
the consequences of this new anti-metaphysical (N1) “scientific
philosophy” (Gori 2012, 342) (N3*).39
Frank relies on Kleinpeter in proclaiming Nietzsche, after
Mach, to be “the other great enlightenment philosopher of the
end of the nineteenth century” (Frank 1970, 232). Frank uncritically repeats Kleinpeter’s view that their epistemological views
are in agreement, despite other radical disagreements, e.g., in
their very different education, “temperament” (1970, 232), or
“ethical ideals” (1970, 232). Like Schlick, Frank calls Nietzsche
35Frank (1915) had earlier reviewed this book. Though it is unlikely that
Schlick had any influence on Kleinpeter’s interpretation of Nietzsche, or vice
versa, Schlick was certainly aware of Kleinpeter’s book, which he later refers
to (Schlick 1974, 241).
36See Gori (2012, 341); see also Frank (1949, 18).
37See Kleinpeter (1913, 143); see also Gori (2012); (2019, 103–11).
38Gori (2012, 344).
39Though Schlick talks of Nietzsche as a positivist (N3) while Kleinpeter
more narrowly pins down his epistemology to the two phenomenalist principles, both argue that Nietzsche’s thought is concerned with developing a
philosophical view within the bounds of such anti-metaphysical strictures
(N1). Both Kleinpeter and Schlick saw Nietzsche as concerned with the practical implications of the new scientific view of the world N3*.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[15]
“that great master of language” (1970, 232) in quoting, with apparent approval, a series of remarks that show Nietzsche to be a
phenomenalist, in connection to which he rejects as metaphysical
the notion of subjectivity and the distinction between appearance
and reality.40 Frank describes the aphorism “On the Psychology
of Metaphysics” as “Nietzsche’s most significant expression of
the positivistic world conception . . . where he attack[s] with cutting sharpness the employment of very frequently misused concepts” (Frank 1970, 232–33), i.e., the aforementioned metaphysical notions. Frank here clearly accepts both N1 and N3*. Though
he does not explicitly claim that Nietzsche was a positivist, Frank
does briefly note that he contributed to the “positivistic world
conception” (1970, 232). By contrast to Schlick’s extensive defence of the view that Nietzsche was a positivist, Frank’s cursory
employment of the term “positivism” is not enough here to justify attributing to him a full-fledged endorsement of the bolder
view N3. Frank at best seems to say that Nietzsche had positivist
tendencies, and contributed to an overall positivistic outlook.
Frank’s view is thus better understood as an endorsement of the
weaker claim N3*. Similarly to Schlick, Frank ties N3* to N1, insofar as he sees the critique of metaphysics as Nietzsche’s main
contribution to the positivist outlook. Furthermore, Frank selects
a passage from Nietzsche in which his critique of metaphysics
(N1) is based on an appeal to insights from empirical psychology
(N2).
Frank closes his comparison between Nietzsche and Mach by
noting what he calls a “tragic feature” (1970, 233) of the enlightenment, namely that “it destroys the old systems of concepts, but
40Sachs (2011, 311–12) argues that Carnap payed inadequate attention to
Nietzsche’s criticisms of the dichotomy between appearance and reality, which
were incompatible with Carnap’s position. Sachs claims that Carnap saw the
overcoming of metaphysics as relying on the application of modern logic,
which shows us that what appeared to be meaningful was really meaningless.
Frank, by contrast, appreciates Nietzsche’s criticism of the distinction as being
a main part of Nietzsche’s contribution to overcoming metaphysics.
while it is constructing a new system, it is also already laying the
foundations for new misuse” (1970, 233). This is an unavoidable
feature of scientific theory construction, in Frank’s view, given
that it is necessary for theories to employ auxiliary concepts,
which inevitably will eventually be misused. In response to this
phenomenon, it would be possible to attempt to block challenges
to specific scientific views by upholding them as dogmas. But
this would go against the spirit of the enlightenment, as championed by Mach and Nietzsche. As Frank sees it, both philosophers
envision the enlightenment as an ongoing process in which the
truth is perpetually sought but no perpetual truth is ever finally
reached. Frank quotes Nietzsche’s claim that the spirit of the
enlightenment concerns “the will to test, investigate, predict, experiment” (1970, 233), not its inhibition through some purported
attainment of truth. Here again, Frank clearly sees Nietzsche in
terms of N3*. Frank’s reference to experimentation is far from
being an explicit acceptance of N2, yet he does make the weaker
claim that Nietzsche had a high esteem for the methodological
characteristics of empirical science.
When Frank returns to this theme in introducing his 1949
book Modern Science and its Philosophy (in which the 1917 article
is reproduced), he diagnoses that
the great mass of writing on Nietzsche has overlooked the fact that
he was a philosopher of enlightenment in his acute analysis of the
auxiliary concepts of contemporary idealistic philosophy. (Frank
1949, 18)
In this regard, one of Nietzsche’s targets, and the one that Frank
presents as having turned his interest to him, is Kant’s view
of unchanging a priori synthetic conditions for any possible experience. Frank presents Nietzsche as opposed to Kant’s view
that there can be certain knowledge about such conditions, and
which furthermore is not knowledge about experience:
Nietzsche said flippantly that Kant’s explanation is merely equivalent to saying that man can do it “by virtue of a virtue”. Nietzsche
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[16]
accused him of demonstrating by sophisticated and obscure arguments that popular prejudices are right while the scientists are
wrong. (Frank 1949, 9)
Frank’s description of Nietzsche’s critique as “flippant” appears
to signal that he is interested in the general spirit of Nietzsche’s
critique of Kant, rather than its details, which he does not further
discuss. Frank presents Nietzsche as aligned with the Vienna Circle’s overall appraisal of the Scientific World Conception (N3*), as
opposed to Kant’s championing of popular prejudices. Notably,
Frank’s 1917 views are mirrored in von Mises’ 1938 “Ernst Mach
and the Scientific Conception of the World”, where Nietzsche is
summarily presented as a critic of Kant (von Mises 1970, e.g.,
169) who was “in full accord with Mach’s view” (1970, 171).
Frank’s earlier presentation of Nietzsche as an antimetaphysical (N1) enlightenment thinker (N4) may be contrasted to his brief mention of Nietzsche in his well-known
biography of Einstein published in 1947. Frank (1947, 46–47)
quotes a passage from Antonio Aliotta’s 1884 The Idealistic Reaction against Science, in which Nietzsche is presented as part of a
romantic response to a seeming crisis in late nineteenth-century
science. In other words, Aliotta here rejects all of N2, N3, and
N3*. Aliotta sees Nietzsche, like other romantics, as denigrating
rational thought in preference for aesthetic intuition.41 This romantic response to science’s crisis is presented by Frank as an
alternative to positivist and pragmatist responses to the crisis, under which heading he includes, among others, the work of Mach.
Frank notes that the positivist movement had also been perceived
by some as anti-intellectualist, but qualifies such claims by arguing that it “could be characterized as anti-intellectual only in so
far as it warned against occupying the intellect with meaningless problems” (Frank 1947, 47). According to Frank, the antimetaphysical stance of late nineteenth-century positivists like
41As we have seen, this is how Schlick interpreted the first phase in
Nietzsche’s thought, which is overcome by his later phases.
Mach should not be understood as a denigration of the powers
of intellect; it is, instead, a correct estimation of the extent to
which such issues can be meaningfully discussed.
It is unclear why, whereas in 1917 Frank had thought this
would be a good characterisation of Nietzsche’s worldview, he
seems to have changed his mind in 1947, only to repeat his 1917
view in 1949. One possible explanation for this would be that the
later Frank simply revised his early positive views of Nietzsche.
This is further suggested by the fact that, in introducing the 1949
republication of the 1917 text, Frank talks of having been influenced by Nietzsche “at this stage” (1949, 9), possibly implying
that he later overcame this influence. Frank does not specify a
specific date range for the stage, or clarify whether he did change
his mind about Nietzsche’s significance, and for what reason.
Another possible explanation for Frank’s seeming change of
heart may be given by the subject matter of the 1947 book, namely
Einstein’s life. Frank divides Einstein’s philosophical interests
into two categories. On the one hand, there are those philosophical works pertaining to and influencing his scientific work, in
which category Frank includes Mach. On the other hand, there
are other works, including those of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche,
which Einstein read
because they made more or less superficial and obscure statements
in beautiful language about all sorts of things, statements that often
aroused an emotion like beautiful music and gave rise to reveries
and meditations on the world. . . . Einstein read these men, as he
sometimes put it, for “edification” just as other people listen to
sermons. (Frank 1947, 51)
Here Frank is echoing similar remarks made by other Vienna Circle members, e.g., Feigl’s aforementioned remarks on Schlick’s
influences, or more famously Carnap’s remarks on metaphysics,
to which I will turn to in Section 9. Before turning to Carnap,
I will first look at various remarks on Nietzsche made by Otto
Neurath.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[17]
8. Neurath on Nietzsche as Predecessor of the
Vienna Circle
Neurath’s remarks on Nietzsche are quite brief, and might appear especially puzzling if not seen in light of his other Vienna
Circle colleagues’ estimation of Nietzsche (and their varying degrees of commitment to N1–N3*). Yet in light of Schlick’s and
Frank’s earlier appraisals of Nietzsche, it is clear that Neurath is
simply pointing out something that is “in the air”, so to speak, in
Vienna Circle discussions. This practice was in fact quite commonplace in Neurath’s modus operandi. Neurath did not work
within academia, and did not follow common academic citation practices; he would often respond to contemporary debates
without citing the relevant sources.42 This may help explain why
he is convinced of Nietzsche’s importance for the work of the Vienna Circle without necessarily attempting to demonstrate it, or
to refer to relevant works that did so (e.g., Schlick’s, Frank’s, or
Carnap’s).
Neurath presents Nietzsche as a predecessor to the Vienna Circle’s anti-metaphysical stance (N1). This is clear e.g., in his 1935
presentation of the Vienna Circle to a French audience, where
he plainly states that “Nietzsche and his critique of the metaphysicians took an active part in the flourishing of the Vienna
School” (quoted in Moreira 2018, 243). A few pages later, listing
the Vienna Circle’s influences, Neurath names “Mach, Avenarius, Poincare, Duhem, Abel Ray, Enriques, Einstein, Schröder,
Frege, Peano, Hilbert, Russell as well as James and Nietzsche”
(Neurath 1981, 697).43 Neurath does not further qualify his claim
in 1935, but does so in his 1936 introduction to the Vienna Circle’s
ideas:
Nietzsche stressed esteem for “the unpretentious truths”, objecting
to the fascinating errors of metaphysical ages. An evolved civi42See e.g., Uebel (1992, viii–ix); Uebel (2007); Tuboly (2019, 165–67).
43Uebel (2015, 4) compares Neurath’s various lists of influences on the Vienna
Circle, pointing out that Nietzsche and James only appear in this specific list.
lization likes, according to Nietzsche, the modest results found by
means of exact methods which are fruitful for the whole future; and
such manliness [sic], simplicity, and temperance will characterize
not only an increasing number but also the whole of humanity
in the future. Moritz Schlick explained in a similar sense that the
evolution of modern critical thinking is founded on an anonymous
mass of thinkers, especially scientists, and that progress does not
arise from the sensational philosophical systems which form an
endless row, each contradicting the others. (Neurath 1955, 18).
Neurath’s interpretation of Nietzsche here is unorthodox, to
say the least. Along with Voltaire and Schlick, Neurath sees
Nietzsche as championing a culture based on the communal
activity of scientific research, as opposed to revolving around
“individual philosophemes” (1955, 18). Though this seems to go
against the grain of Nietzsche’s individualistic and elitist outlook, I will not here attempt to determine whether Neurath’s
interpretation is plausible. What is perhaps most interesting in
connection to this enquiry is the relation of Neurath’s comments
to Schlick’s interpretation of Nietzsche. As noted in Section 2,
Schlick presents Nietzsche as an individual genius who attempts
to overcome his cultural surroundings, despite the tendency of
such processes of change to be slower than he envisages. On
the contrary, Neurath claims that both Schlick and Nietzsche
are paradigmatic champions of communal efforts, as opposed
to individual genius. Neurath tells us that Schlick understands
that “critical thinking” is not the product of individuals, but
rather the result of accumulated effort. As shown in Section 2,
this is precisely the reason that Schlick gives for his claim that
attempts to single-handedly transvaluate a culture’s values tend
to fail, and also the reason why Schlick thinks Nietzsche was an
exceptional genius who happened to succeed in such an attempt.
Another parallel between Schlick’s, Frank’s (and von Mises
1970), and Neurath’s responses to Nietzsche may be found
in their interpretation of his views as anti-Kantian.44 Neurath
44On Schlick’s anti-Kantian use of Nietzsche, see Ferrari (2016).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[18]
presents Nietzsche’s anti-Kantianism as part of his overall antimetaphysical position. In the context of discussing the separation of specific scientific fields of study from “the motherphilosophy” (Neurath 1955, 10), Neurath notes that although
Kant did in fact subsequently influence many scientists, his work
also had as its effect the hindering of scientific progress in some
fields. Like Frank, Neurath partly attributes this understanding
of Kant to Nietzsche:
The essayist-philosopher Nietzsche showed how much of an antiscientific attitude can be found in Kant’s system, which reduces
the power of science and thus opens the doors to metaphysical and
philosophico-religious speculations. (Neurath 1955, 11)
Thus Nietzsche’s critique of Kantian metaphysics is linked by
Neurath to his favouring of a scientific world conception (N3*).
Neurath had elsewhere (1987, 11) presented psychology as the
last of the sciences to be cut off from philosophy, thus resulting in
the overcoming of metaphysics. Neurath describes Nietzsche’s
contribution to this project as follows:
The last science to have the umbilical cord connecting it to philosophy severed is psychology. And what remains behind is a dead, deaf
mass. If Nietzsche stimulated psychologists in many ways, it was
not by producing a systematic metaphysics, but because he was
able to pursue lines of thought untrammelled by contemporary
academic psychology, which was not interested in, e.g., “resentment”. But even a non-philosopher enjoys that freedom today. The
end of metaphysics is demonstrable precisely in the case of psychology.
(Neurath 1987, 11)
It is thus that Neurath connected Nietzsche’s psychological insights with his overcoming of metaphysics. Nietzsche’s antimetaphysical turn made lasting contributions to empiricallyminded psychology, in Neurath’s view. Accordingly Neurath
elsewhere notes that many of Nietzsche’s “excellent philosophical insights” (1981, 826) contributed both to psychoanalysis and
to what Neurath calls “behaviouristics”. Thus Neurath not only
sees Nietzsche as committed to N2, but also makes sense of this
commitment in reference to N1.
Neurath’s brief comments on Nietzsche are not meant to be
scholarly analyses. Neurath does not attempt to substantiate
them by reference to specific works. Most appear in programmatic statements of the Vienna Circle’s mission. Nonetheless,
Neurath’s brief responses to Nietzsche play an interesting role
in bringing together and unifying different interpretative theses
(N1, N2, N3*) articulated by the Vienna Circle’s members. Neurath quickly outlines how Nietzsche’s anti-metaphysical stance
(N1) was connected to his understanding of psychology (N2), all
in light of an overall commitment to a scientific world conception
(N3*). These are, as I have shown, themes that are addressed by
both Schlick and Frank, and which will also play a part in Carnap’s reception of Nietzsche, to which I now turn.
9. Carnap’s Nietzsche: The Begriffsschrift on the
Desk, Zarathustra on the Bedside Table?
Gabriel summarises the significance of Nietzsche for Carnap (as
well, perhaps, as the Vienna Circle in general) by noting that
“for Carnap, Frege’s Begriffsschrift lies on the desk, so to speak,
and Nietzsche’s Zarathustra on the bedside table” (Gabriel 2004,
12).45 Various scholars have highlighted the fact that Nietzsche’s
influence was significant in the formation of different strands
of the German Youth Movement, in which both Carnap and
Reichenbach had participated.46 The young Carnap was associated with Dilthey’s student Herman Nohl, who had written on
Nietzsche.47
45But see Mormann (2012, 72).
46E.g., Carus (2008, 52–54). Schlick (1979a, 124) favourably compares
Nietzsche to Wyneken, who had led the strand of the Jugendbewegung that
Reichenbach had belonged to; see also Schlick (1962, 13).
47See e.g., Gabriel (2004); Damböck (2012); Nelson (2018, 328).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[19]
Carnap’s philosophical debt to Nietzsche already manifests itself in his 1922 sketch for the Aufbau, titled “Vom Chaos zur Wirklichkeit”.48 The relevant conception of “chaos”, as it appears in
Carnap’s title, is traceable, through various possible paths, back
to Nietzsche.49 Like Schlick, Rickert, Vaihinger, and other early
readers of Nietzsche, Carnap reworks the Nietzschean conception of the “will to power”, which he renders as the “will to
order”.50 Mormann (2016, 117–18, 121–22) has traced the transmission of influence from Nietzsche to Carnap via the NeoKantian Rickert and his critique of Lebensphilosophie during the
early 1920s. Rickert had attempted to tame the Nietzschean conception of the will to power by claiming that in exact philosophy
this manifests itself as a “will to system”.51 Philosophy’s task is
to order the chaotic stream of experiences (what Rickert’s philosophical opponents had called “Lebens”) into a coherent and
comprehensive system. Carnap’s “Vom Chaos zur Wirklichkeit”
has been seen by both Mormann (2006), (2016) and Leinonen
(2016) as engaged in precisely this project, set out by Rickert, in
its attempt to explain how the will to order is the guiding principle of the move from chaos to structured reality. According to
Carnap,
“Reality” is not given to us as something fixed, but undergoes permanent corrections. The epistemologist asserts: it has been built
up on behalf of an accomplishment from an original chaos according to certain order principles that for the time being are instinctive. . . . The will to a new order is responsible for the epistemolog48See e.g., Mormann (2006); Mormann (2012, 73); Mormann (2016, 117–18,
121–22); Leinonen (2016); Moreira (2018, 262–69).
49See Leinonen (2016, 215–16).
50Carnap began writing the manuscript in 1921 and he continued working
on it until 1926. He was introduced to Schlick by Reichenbach in 1923. I have
been unable to ascertain whether the apparent parallels between Carnap’s 1921
and Schlick’s 1908 and 1912 interpretations of Nietzsche could be the result
either of their conversations or of Carnap’s reading of Schlick’s work.
51Mormann characterises this concept as “pseudo-Nietzschean” (2016, 117),
insofar as it distorts Nietzsche’s views.
ical considerations that deal with the fictions of chaos as starting
point and the principles of order that guide the constitution. This
will to order, which intends to overcome the inconsistencies of reality by rebuilding it in a new way, is the irrational starting point of
our theory. (quoted in Mormann 2006, 34)
Mormann (2016, 121–22) thus holds that Carnap’s “will to order” builds on Rickert’s unorthodox (and strictly speaking false)
interpretation of Nietzsche’s conception of the “will to power” as
“will to system”. Contesting Mormann’s account, Carus (2008,
108, 125–27) has interpreted Carnap’s discussion of “chaos” as influenced primarily by Vaihinger.52 In Vaihinger’s view, the original chaos we find in the stream of our experiences is rendered
meaningful by the fictions we impose onto them. As already
noted, like Rickert, Vaihinger also appeals to Nietzsche as a predecessor of his fictionalist account of the “will to illusion”.53 I
will not attempt to resolve this dispute here; for the purposes of
this article, it should suffice to note that, whether it is through
Rickert or Vaihinger, Carnap’s conceptions of “chaos” and the
“will to order” are ultimately traceable back to Nietzsche.54
By contrast to Carnap’s various early sketches from the 1920s,
which contain no references to other works, the Aufbau itself
contains multiple references to Nietzsche.55 One of the central
themes advanced by Nietzsche and upheld by Carnap concerns
the rejection of the Cartesian view of subjectivity. In the various
responses to Nietzsche outlined above, this topic is only mentioned in passing by Frank as an example of Nietzsche’s critique
of metaphysical concepts. Carnap objects to the idea that what
is given must be given to some subject. He quotes the following
passage by Nietzsche as a source for his claim:
52In response, Leinonen (2016, 215–19) has argued in favour of the compatibility of both Rickert’s and Vaihinger’s influence on the early Carnap.
53See also e.g., Gori (2019, 111–18).
54But Moreira (2018, 260–69) portrays Carnap and Nietzsche as being on
opposite political sides, the former advocating order, the latter chaos.
55See also Mormann (2012, 73); Moreira (2018, 245–46).
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[20]
It is merely a formulation of our grammatical habits that there
must always be something that thinks when there is thinking and
that there must always be a doer when there is a deed. (quoted in
Carnap 2003, 105)56
Carnap returns to another aspect of this same theme when he
formulates his views on “the problem of the self” (2003, 261).
This relates to Carnap’s objection against the Cartesian account
of the self: according to Carnap, the “cogito” does not imply the
“sum”. Carnap lists Nietzsche among a series of philosophers
who had via “philosophical introspection . . . reached the same
result” (2003, 261). Carnap parallels Frank’s earlier view on the
topic when he also includes Mach as a source for his view, noting
his agreement with Nietzsche. Carnap also categorises some of
Nietzsche’s anti-Cartesian views concerning the non-existence
of the subject as being in agreement with Avenarius (2003, 261),
Schlick (2003, 105, 261), and Russell (2003, 261).
Carnap (2003, 108–9) nonetheless partly contests the
Kleinpeter-Frank thesis, insofar as he discerns an epistemological disagreement between Mach and Nietzsche when it comes
to the former’s atomistic rendition of phenomenalism. In selecting between the two positions, Carnap favours Nietzsche
over Mach. Carnap’s preference for Nietzsche over Mach parallels a similar view by Schlick (as outlined in Section 6), and in
fact Carnap names Schlick (2003, 108) as one of his allies in his
choice against Mach. In Carnap’s view, Mach naïvely endorses
an atomistic conception of “sensations” which is incompatible
with the latest advances of science. More specifically, Carnap
refers to the results of Gestalt psychology, showing that the primary units of experience are not like Machian “atomic” sensations, but rather combined into unitary wholes. Carnap (2003,
108) refers to Nietzsche as part of a list of thinkers, compiled
by Hans Cornelius, who had defended such views before they
56Waismann (1959, 350) also briefly mentions Nietzsche in connection to the
significance of grammar.
were experimentally demonstrated by psychologists. This overall attitude is similar to the one by Neurath that we have already
examined: both Carnap and Neurath agree about N2, holding
that Nietzsche was an important precursor of later empiricallyminded experimental psychology.
Carnap returns to Nietzsche in his famous remarks in the 1931
article “Overcoming Metaphysics through the Logical Analysis
of Language”.57 Here, Carnap’s overall project is to demonstrate
how, following various failures from previous philosophical
movements (including the ancient skeptics, the modern empiricists, and some strands of Kantian thought), the newly developed
method of logical analysis provides the tools for demonstrating
that metaphysics is cognitively meaningless. Carnap shows how
(i) metaphysical pseudo-concepts without empirical content, and
(ii) metaphysical pseudo-statements can be overcome by his recommended method. According to Carnap, metaphysicians had
hitherto endeavoured to put forth theses that are to be shown to
be either true or false in the course of rational theoretical debate.
However, the content of their expressions is, according to Carnap, what he calls Lebensgefühl, i.e., a kind of emotive attitude
towards life. Carnap thinks that such emotive attitudes should be
expressed in the appropriate medium, which is not theoretical.
Art can provide the most appropriate medium for expressing
Lebensgefühl, since the question of whether a statement is true
or false is irrelevant to artworks. As Dahms (2004) shows, one
of the first articulations of this idea was presented in Carnap’s
lectures at the Dessau Bauhaus.58 There, Carnap admits that
57Whereas Carnap had chosen to use the Nietzschean term “overcoming”
[Überwindung] in his title, in his well-known Language, Truth and Logic, A. J. Ayer
had preferred the phrase “the elimination of metaphysics”, and this was later
used by Arthur Pap in translating the title of Carnap’s paper; see Friedman
(2000, 23); Vrahimis (2013a, 90–91); Vrahimis (2013b, 4); Moreira (2018, 248–49);
Vrahimis (forthc. b).
58In 1929, Carnap (1922–33, 33) briefly mentions Nietzsche’s aristocratic
ethics in his notes for this lecture. In his 1930 notes for 1959a, Carnap (1929–
37, 21) comments on the relation between metaphysics and poetry, noting that
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[21]
after the misguided metaphysicians’ attempts to express their
Lebensgefühl in a theoretical medium have been overcome, the
need for expressing such Lebensgefühl in other media remains.59
Carnap even encouraged the artists and designers in his audience to address this need.60 He thus portrayed the overcoming
of metaphysics as a kind of liberation, freeing Lebensgefühl from
the shackles of theory and allowing freedom for its exploration
within the realm of artistic creation and “the conscious design
of the things of [everyday] life” (quoted in Dahms 2004, 370).
Nietzsche is, according to Carnap, the philosopher who most
clearly saw this well before it could be cemented by logical analysis:
Our conjecture that metaphysics is a substitute, albeit an inadequate one, for art, seems to be confirmed by the fact that the metaphysician who perhaps had artistic talent to the highest degree, viz.
Nietzsche, almost entirely avoided the error of that confusion. A
large part of his work has predominantly empirical content. We find
there, for instance, historical analyses of specific artistic phenomena, or an historico-psychological analysis of morals. In the work,
however, in which he expresses most strongly that which others
express through metaphysics or ethics, in Thus Spake Zarathustra,
he does not choose the misleadingly theoretical form, but openly
the form of art, of poetry. (Carnap 1959b, 80)
The above passage may at first appear puzzling, especially if
read in isolation from other responses to Nietzsche by the Vienna Circle. In the first sentence, Carnap appears to suggest that
Nietzsche is actually a metaphysician.61 This seems to be in tension with what follows, as Carnap goes on to say that Nietzsche
overcomes metaphysics by altogether avoiding its exposition in a
theoretical medium. Should this avoidance not mean, according
to Carnap, that Nietzsche is no longer a metaphysician?
‘Nietzsche clearly separates the two’ (quoted in Moreira 2018, 247).
59See also Carnap (1929–37, 21).
60See Dahms (2004, 369–70); Vrahimis (2012, 70–72). See also Galison (1990);
Potochnik and Yap (2006); Sachs (2011).
61Sachs (2011, 312) and Moreira (2018, 247) reject this as a misreading.
We have already established that both Schlick and Frank had,
in the preceding two decades, already interpreted Nietzsche as
a critic of metaphysics (N1). Schlick, furthermore, had in 1912
already defended the tripartite view of Nietzsche’s phases, according to which, having overcome an initial metaphysical period, Nietzsche became a positivist (N3). This interpretation of
Nietzsche, which was also put forth by various contemporary
Nietzsche scholars, helps us to make sense of Carnap’s remarks.
Carnap is best understood as claiming that Nietzsche had been
a metaphysician, before he subsequently overcame metaphysics
(N1) by dividing his work into either empirically-minded historical and psychological analyses (N2),62 on the one hand, or poetry on the other hand.63 As Schlick, Frank, and Neurath would
agree, this way of overcoming metaphysics puts Nietzsche in
league with the Vienna Circle, as one of their closest predecessors during the late nineteenth century. The Vienna Circle can
now realise the Nietzschean project of overcoming metaphysics
by putting to use the technical means provided by the development of modern logic.
As already shown in Section 5, Schlick had seen Zarathustra
as the epitome of Nietzsche’s work, because it employs a poetic form that is appropriate to the subject-matter. Schlick sees a
decline in Nietzsche’s writing that occurs in later works, which
try to approach in a systematic manner the views initially expressed as poetry in Zarathustra. Once Carnap’s characterisation
of Nietzsche as a metaphysician is clarified in light of Schlick’s
tripartite scheme, i.e., as pertaining to an initial phase which
Nietzsche later overcomes, it becomes clear that Carnap endorses
the view that Zarathustra is not a work of metaphysics. Instead,
Carnap agrees with Schlick that Zarathustra is a work which has
overcome metaphysics. Carnap explicitly understands Zarathus62Sachs (2011, 313) connects this to what he calls Carnap’s and Nietzsche’s
hypermodernism.
63Sachs (2011, 312) questions whether this is a correct understanding of
Nietzsche.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[22]
tra as expressing in the poetic medium what ‘others express
through metaphysics or ethics’ (1959a, 80), i.e., through a theoretical medium. In other words, in Zarathustra Nietzsche has
overcome metaphysics by embracing the use of a non-theoretical
medium for his work. By contrast to Schlick, however, Carnap
omits to mention the fact that Nietzsche returned to a theoretical medium after Zarathustra. As Schlick clearly understood,
Nietzsche’s last works attempted to systematically develop what
he had earlier expressed as poetry. Thus by contrast to Schlick,
Carnap’s all too brief mention of Nietzsche in 1931 selectively
emphasises those aspects of his thought which conveniently
align with his project of overcoming metaphysics.64
Carnap’s final mention of Nietzsche occurs in his 1932 “Psychology in Physical Language”. In the context of discussing “resistance to the thesis of physicalism” (Carnap 1959a, 40), Carnap lists a number of examples in which a new theory causes a
wave of controversy because, to quote Carnap’s Nietzschean vocabulary, “an Idol is being dethroned by it” (Carnap 1959a, 40).
Carnap’s examples include Copernicus’ heliocentrism, Darwin’s
theory of evolution, Marx’s material explanation of causation in
history, and Freud’s notion of unconscious drives. Nietzsche is
listed among these, since as a result of his historico-psychological
analysis “the origins of morals were stripped of their halo” (Carnap 1959b, 40). Carnap’s thesis here is compatible with his earlier division of Nietzsche’s work into poetic art works, on the one
hand, and empirically-minded analyses on the other. Carnap accepts what he sees as Nietzsche’s empirical genealogy of morals
as one among the various ground-breaking theoretical advances
that he mentions. This position again is aligned with the overall
emphasis of N2 by Schlick and Neurath.
64This omission may reflect the overall disagreements between Carnap and
Schlick concerning the scope of the project of overcoming metaphysics, which
I cannot further discuss here. Schlick may have been more willing than Carnap
to go along with Nietzsche’s last works, and their return from poetry to theory.
For further discussions of this, see e.g., Uebel (2020); Tuboly (forthc. a).
Overall, Carnap’s various claims about Nietzsche, as I have
shown here, can best be understood alongside Schlick’s, Frank’s,
and Neurath’s similar statements. There is nothing extraordinary
about Carnap’s suggestion that Nietzsche’s work was relevant
to the Vienna Circle’s project of overcoming metaphysics. It is,
rather, a kind of routine operation by which Carnap, like almost
all other Vienna Circle members, acknowledges the significance
of work that he considers to have anticipated Logical Empiricism.
10. Conclusion
In the above examination of Nietzsche’s reception by the Vienna Circle’s members, I have first of all clarified that the Vienna
Circle’s responses to Nietzsche were overwhelmingly positive.
Their championing of Nietzsche focussed on what I have summarised as a series of specific theses on his work (N1–N4).
As this paper has shown, N1 was explicitly attributed to
Nietzsche by Schlick, Frank, Neurath, and Carnap. Schlick discussed Nietzsche most extensively at a time when he himself
was neither a positivist nor committed to the project of overcoming metaphysics tout-court. Nonetheless, he was sympathetic to
Nietzsche’s overcoming of metaphysics, which he understood
to be the rejection of appeals to a “supersensible” (Schlick 2013,
228) world. Frank sees N1 in terms of Nietzsche’s rejection of
“misused” (Frank 1970, 233) metaphysical concepts, such as the
notion of subjectivity or the distinction between appearance and
reality. Neurath explicitly presents Nietzsche as a precursor of
the Vienna Circle’s proposals for overcoming metaphysics, tying N1 to N2 and N3*, as well as to Nietzsche’s critique of
Kant. Carnap, finally, presents N1 in light of his interpretation
of Nietzsche’s work as split between poetry and empirical research. Thus, while Schlick, Frank, Neurath, and Carnap agree
in subscribing to a version of N1 broadly construed, they each
emphasise different specific aspects of it.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[23]
Of the different responses to Nietzsche by the Vienna Circle,
it is only Schlick who explicitly linked Nietzsche’s turn towards
N1 and N3 to his rejection of Schopenhauer’s early influence on
his work. The others simply focus on Nietzsche’s philosophy
after its turn away from Schopenhauerian metaphysics. Nevertheless, I have shown that Carnap’s remarks on Nietzsche are
best understood in light of the view of Nietzsche’s rejection of
Schopenhauer’s influence that is also put forth by Schlick.
I have also demonstrated that N2 was explicitly acknowledged
by Schlick, Neurath, and Carnap. Frank does not explicitly address N2, but does briefly refer to Nietzsche’s use of psychology
in criticising metaphysics. He also connects Nietzsche’s role as
an Enlightenment philosopher (N4) with his high esteem for the
application of “the will to test, investigate, predict, experiment”
(Frank 1970, 233).
N3, on the other hand, was only explicitly proclaimed by
Schlick. Frank and Neurath uphold its weaker form N3*. Frank
claims that Nietzsche contributed to “the positivistic world conception” (Frank 1970, 232) with his attack on metaphysics, thus
tying N3* to N1. Neurath’s portrayal of Nietzsche as endorsing a
scientific conception of the world, as I have shown, draws various
connections between N1, N2, and N3*. Both Frank and Neurath
praise Nietzsche’s critique of Kant, which they present as having
been a kind of philosophical impediment to the advancement of
a scientific conception of the world.
Finally, this paper has shown that the view that Nietzsche was
an Enlightenment philosopher (N4) was explicitly articulated
by Frank as well as Schlick. As highlighted above, Schlick understood N4 to result from Nietzsche’s turn away from his early
critique of the Enlightenment, and towards an anti-metaphysical
positivist phase. Though the various brief comments by Neurath
do not directly address this view of Nietzsche as an Enlightenment philosopher, he can be said to implicitly subscribe to the
Frank/Schlick interpretation, insofar as he sees him as an ally of
the scientific world conception.
Though most scholarly attention has focussed on Carnap’s response to Nietzsche, it is in various ways an outlier, as we have
seen above. By contrast to Schlick, Frank, and Neurath, Carnap
nowhere explicitly discusses the issue of Nietzsche’s relation
to positivism (N3) or to the scientific world conception (N3*).
Neither does Carnap give any indication as to whether he upholds N4 or not. Carnap’s discussion of Nietzsche’s views on
subjectivity is not paralleled in other Vienna Circle texts, with
the exception of a brief mention by Frank. Nonetheless, as this
article has argued, the relation Carnap sees between Nietzsche
and the overall project of overcoming metaphysics is best understood in light of the reception of Nietzsche by his Vienna Circle
colleagues. The discussion in this article should at least resolve
a certain ongoing puzzlement as to why Carnap closes his 1931
paper with a reference to Nietzsche.
Acknowledgements
I began to write this paper with the intention of presenting it at
the 2020 annual conference of the Society for the Study of the
History of Analytical Philosophy; though the conference was
cancelled due to the COVID-19 pandemic, I would like to thank
the organisers for having accepted the paper (thereby motivating
me to keep working on it). In thinking about some of the ideas
developed in this work, I have benefitted from discussions with,
among others, Mark Textor, Adam Tamas Tuboly, and Christian
Damböck, to whom I owe many thanks. I am grateful to the
anonymous reviewers for their comments on the paper, as well
as to Richard Zach for his contribution as an editor. All errors
are my own.
Andreas Vrahimis
University of Cyprus
[email protected]
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[24]
References
Akehurst, Thomas L., 2010. The Cultural Politics of Analytic Philosophy: Britishness and the Spectre of Europe. London: Continuum.
Allen, Barry, 2003. “Carnap’s Contexts: Comte, Heidegger,
Nietzsche.” In A House divided: Comparing Analytic and Continental Philosophy, edited by C. G. Prado, pp. 33–62. New York:
Humanity Books.
Andreas-Salomé, Lou, 2001. Nietzsche, edited by Siegfried Mandel. Urbana, Ill.: University of Illinois Press.
Aschheim, Steven E., 1994. The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany: 18901990. London, Berkeley, and Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Ayer, A. J., 1959. Logical Positivism. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press.
Bonnet, Christian, 2016. “Schlick et l’origine pratique de la
connaissance.” In Wissenschaft und Praxis. Zur Wissenschaftsphilosophie in Frankreich und Österreich in der ersten Hälfte des
20. Jahrhunderts, edited by Christian Bonnet and Elisabeth
Nemeth, pp. 43–53. Dordrecht: Springer.
Bright, Liam Kofi. “Logical Empiricists on Race.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 65: 9–18.
Carnap, Rudolf, 1918. “Schema für den 9. Rundbrief”. Unpublished manuscript, University of Pittsburgh, Archive for
Scientific Philosophy, https://digital.library.pitt.edu/
islandora/object/pitt%3A31735061847921/viewer.
, 1922–33. “Lectures in Europe (Items 43–54)”. Unpublished manuscript, University of Pittsburgh, Archive for
Scientific Philosophy, https://digital.library.pitt.edu/
islandora/object/pitt%3A31735061812479/viewer.
, 1929–37. “Lectures in Europe (Items 18—29)”. Unpublished manuscript, University of Pittsburgh, Archive for
Scientific Philosophy, https://digital.library.pitt.edu/
islandora/object/pitt%3A31735061812453/viewer.
, 1959a. “Psychology in Physical Language, translated by
George Schick.” In Ayer (1959), pp. 165–98.
, 1959b. “The Elimination Of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language, translated by Arthur Pap.” In Ayer
(1959), pp. 60–81.
, 2003. The Logical Structure of the World and Pseudoproblems
in Philosophy, edited by Rolf A. George. Chicago: Open Court
Classics.
Carsten Klein and Steve Awodey, eds., 2004. Carnap Brought
Home: The View from Jena. Chicago: Open Court.
Carus, André W., 2008. Carnap and Twentieth-Century Thought:
Explication as Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Clark, Maudemarie and David Dudrick, 2004. “Nietzsche’s PostPositivism.” European Journal of Philosophy 12: 369–85.
Cohen, Jonathan, 1999. “Nietzsche’s Fling with Positivism.” In
Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science, edited by Babette E. Babich and Robert S. Cohen, pp. 101–108. Dordrecht:
Springer.
Dahms, Hans J., 2004. “Neue Sachlichkeit in the Architecture
and Philosophy of the 1920s.” In Klein and Awodey (2004),
pp. 357–76.
Damböck, Christian, 2012. “Rudolf Carnap and Wilhelm Dilthey:
‘German’ Empiricism in the Aufbau.” In Rudolf Carnap and the
Legacy of Logical Empiricism, edited by Richard Creath, pp. 67–
88. Dordrecht: Springer.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[25]
Feigl, Herbert, 1979. “Memoir.” In Schlick (1979d), pp. xv–
xxxviii.
Galison, Peter, 1990. “Aufbau/Bauhaus: Logical Positivism and
Architectural Modernism.” Critical Inquiry 16: 709–52.
, 1981. “Validation and Vindication: An Analysis of the
Nature and the Limits of Ethical Arguments.” In Inquiries and
Provocations: Selected Writings 1929–1974, edited by Robert S.
Cohen, pp. 378–92. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Gori, Pietro, 2012. “Nietzsche as Phenomenalist?” In Nietzsches
Wissenschaftsphilosophie, edited by Helmut Heit, Günter Abel
and Marco Brusotti, pp. 345–56. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Ferrari, Massimo, 2016. “Wiener Gefühle. Fragen der Ethik zwischen Schlick und Carnap.” In Wissenschaft und Praxis. Zur
Wissenschaftsphilosophie in Frankreich und Österreich in der ersten Hälfte des 20. Jahrhunderts, edited by Christian Bonnet and
Elisabeth Nemeth, pp. 5–28. Dordrecht: Springer.
Fischer, Kurt Rudolf, 1999. “Nietzsche and the Vienna Circle.” In
Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, and Critical Theory, edited by
Babette E. Babich and Robert S. Cohen, pp. 119–28. Dordrecht:
Springer.
Frank, Philipp, 1915. “[Rezension] Hans Kleinpeter, Der
Phaenomenalismus, Leipzig 1913.” Monatshefte für Mathematik
und Physik 1915: 46–47.
, 1947. Einstein: His Life and Times, edited by George Rosen.
New York: Alfred Knopf.
, 1949. Modern Science and its Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
, 1970. “The Importance of Ernst Mach’s Philosophy of
Science for our times.” In Ernst Mach: Physicist and Philosopher,
edited by Robert S. Cohen and Raymond J. Seeger, pp. 219–34.
Dordrecht: Reidel.
, 2019. Nietzsche’s Pragmatism: A Study on Perspectival
Thought, edited by Sarah De Sanctis. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Hussain, Nadeem J. Z., 2004. “Nietzsche’s Positivism.” European
Journal of Philosophy 12: 326–68.
Iven, Mathias, 2013a. “Einleitung.” In Schlick (2013), pp. 17–52.
, 2013b. “Editorischer Bericht.” In Schlick (2013), pp. 55–76.
Kleinpeter, Hans, 1913. Der Phenomenalismus: Eine naturwissenschaftliche Weltanschauung. Leipzig: Barth.
Lange, Friedrich Albert, 1866. Geschichte des Materialismus: Und
Kritik seiner Bedeutung in Gegenwart. Iserlohn: Baedeker.
Leinonen, Mikko, 2016. “Assessing Rickert’s Influences on Carnap.” In Influences on the Aufbau, edited by Christian Damböck,
pp. 213–32. Cham: Springer.
Lewis, Joia, 1988. “Schlick’s Critique of Positivism.” PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association
1: 110–17.
Friedman, Michael, 2000. A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer,
and Heidegger. Chigago: Court.
Martin, Nicholas, 2006. “Nietzsche as Hate-Figure in Britain’s
Great War: ‘The Execrable Neech’.” In The First World War as a
Clash of Cultures, edited by Fred Bridgham, pp. 147–66. New
York: Camden House.
Gabriel, Gottfried, 2004. “Introduction: Carnap Brought Home.”
In Klein and Awodey (2004), pp. 3–24.
McGuinness, Brian and Joachim Schulte, eds., 1994. Ethics and
the Will. Dordrecht: Springer.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[26]
Moreira, Felipe G. A., 2018. “Overcoming Metametaphysics:
Nietzsche and Carnap.” Nietzsche Studien 47: 240–71.
Part 1, edited by Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap and Charles
Morris, pp. 1–27. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Mormann, Thomas, 2006. “Between Heidelberg and Marburg:
The Aufbau’s Neo-Kantian origins and the AP/CP divide.”
Sapere Aude: Revista de Filosofia 1: 22–50.
, 1981. “Einheitswissenschaft als Empiristische Synthese.”
In Gesammelte philosophische und methodologische Schriften. Volume 2, edited by Rudolf Haller and Heiner Rutte, pp. 825–31.
Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.
, 2010. “Zwischen Weisheit und Wissenschaft: Schlicks
weites philosophisches Spektrum.” Grazer Philosophische Studien 80: 263–85.
, 2012. “Carnap’s Boundless Ocean of Unlimited Possibilities: Between Enlightenment and Romanticism.” In Carnap’s
Ideal of Explication and Naturalism, edited by Pierre Wagner,
pp. 63–78. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
, 2015. “Review of Moritz Schlick: Nietzsche und Schopenhauer
(Vorlesungen).” Journal for General Philosophy of Science 46: 419–
23.
, 2016. “Carnap’s Aufbau in the Weimar Context.” In Influences on the Aufbau, edited by Christian Damböck, pp. 115–36.
Cham: Springer.
Nelson, Eric, 2018. “Dilthey and Carnap: The Feeling of Life, the
Scientific Worldview, and the Elimination of Metaphysics.”
In The Worlds of Positivism, edited by Johannes Feichtinger,
Franz L. Fillafer and Jan Surman, pp. 321–46. Cham: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Nemeth, Elisabeth, 1992. “Nietzsche, Neurath und die Reflexivität der Moderne.” In Philosophie, Psychoanalyse, Emigration:
Festschrift für Kurt Rudolf Fischer, edited by P. Muhr, P. Feyerabend and C. Wegeler, pp. 251–66. Vienna: Universitätsverlag.
Neurath, Otto, 1955. “Unified Science as Encyclopedic Integration.” In International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Volume I.
, 1987. “Unified Science and Psychology.” In Unified Science,
edited by Brian McGuinness, pp. 1–23. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Neurath, O. and J. A. Lauwerys, 1944. “Nazi textbooks and the
future.” The Journal of Education 76: 521–22, 574–76.
, 1945. “Plato’s Republic and German Education.” The Journal of Education 77: 57–59.
Nietzsche, Friedrich W., 1996. On the Genealogy of Morals, edited
by Douglas Smith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
, 2002. Beyond Good and Evil, edited by Judith Norman.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Potochnik, Angela and Audrey Yap, 2006. “Revisiting Galison’s ‘Aufbau/Bauhaus’ in light of Neurath’s philosophical
projects.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37:
469–88.
Reichenbach, Hans, 1978. Selected Writings, 1909–1953. Volume 1,
edited by Maria Reichenbach and Robert S. Cohen. Dordrecht:
Reidel.
Reisch, George A., 2005. How the Cold War transformed Philosophy
of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Russell, Bertrand, 1946. History of Western Philosophy: And its
connection with Political and Social Circumstances from the Earliest
Times to the Present Day. London: Allen and Unwin.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[27]
Sachs, Carl B., 2011. “What Is To Be Overcome? Nietzsche, Carnap, and Modernism as the Overcoming of Metaphysics.” History of Philosophy Quarterly 28: 303–18.
, 1979e. Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers: Volume Two
(1925-1936), edited by Henk L. Mulder and Barbara van de
Velde-Schlick. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Schleichert, Hubert, 2003. “Moritz Schlick’s Idea of NonTerritorial States.” In The Vienna Circle and Logical Empiricism: Re-evaluation and Future Perspectives, edited by Friedrich
Stadler, pp. 49–61. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
, 2006. Lebensweisheit: Versuch einer Glückseligkeitslehre und
Fragen der Ethik, edited by Mathias Iven. Vienna: Springer.
Schlick, Moritz, 1938. “L’École de Vienne et la philosophie traditionnelle.” In Gesammelte Aufsätze 1926–1936. Vienna: Gerold
& Co.
, 1939. Problems of Ethics, edited by David Rynin. New York:
Prentice Hall.
, 1952. Natur und Kultur. Vienna & Stuttgart: Humboldt.
, 1959. “The Foundation of Knowledge, translated by David
Rynin.” In Ayer (1959), pp. 209–27.
, 1962. Aphorismen, edited by Blanche Hardy Schlick. Vienna: Carl Ueberreuter.
, 1974. General Theory of Knowledge, edited by Albert E.
Blumberg. Vienna: Springer.
, 1979a. “On the Meaning of Life.” In Schlick (1979e),
pp. 112–29.
, 1979b. “The fundamental problem of aesthetics seen in an
evolutionary light.” In Schlick (1979d), pp. 1–24.
, 1979c. “The Present Task of Philosophy.” In Schlick
(1979d), pp. 104–18.
, 1979d. Moritz Schlick: Philosophical Papers: Volume One
(1909-1922), edited by Henk L. Mulder and Barbara van de
Velde-Schlick. Dordrecht: Reidel.
, 2008. “The Future of Philosophy.” In Die Wiener Zeit:
Aufsätze, Beiträge, Rezensionen 1926–1936, edited by Johannes
Friedl and Heiner Rutte, pp. 371–90. Dordrecht: Springer.
, 2013. Nietzsche und Schopenhauer, edited by Mathias Iven.
Dordrecht: Springer.
Soulez, Antonia, 2019. “Does Understanding Mean Forgiveness?
Otto Neurath and Plato’s ‘Republic’ in 1944–45.” In Neurath
Reconsidered: New Sources and Perspectives, edited by Jordi Cat
and Adam T. Tuboly, pp. 435–49. Dordrecht: Springer.
Stadler, Friedrich, 2015. The Vienna Circle: Studies in the Origins,
Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism. Dordrecht:
Springer.
Mark Textor, 2018. “Schlick on the Source of the ‘Great Errors in
Philosophy’.” Journal of the American Philosophical Association 4:
105–25.
Tuboly, Adam Tamas, 2019. “Review of Michael Turk, Otto Neurath and the History of Economics.” Review of Radical Political
Economics 52: 164–68.
, forthcoming a. “Making Logical Positivism Less Logical:
The Case of Schlick and von Mises.” In The Socio-Ethical Dimension of Knowledge: The Mission of Logical Empiricism, edited
by Christian Damböck and Adam T. Tuboly. Cham: Springer.
, forthcoming b. “Neurath on Plato-Hitler and the British
Scene of Irritation.” In Proceedings of the Carnap/Neurath ConJournal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[28]
ference. Studien zur Österreichischen Philosophie, edited by Ch.
Damböck, J. Friedl and U. Höfer. Amsterdam: Rodopi–Brill.
Tuusvuori, Jarkko S., 2000. Nietzsche & Nihilism: Exploring a Revolutionary Conception of Philosophical Conceptuality. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Helsinki.
, forthcoming a. “Philosophy (and Wissenschaft) without
Politics?: Schlick on Nietzsche, German Idealism, and Militarism.” In The Socio-Ethical Dimension of Knowledge: The Mission of Logical Empiricism, edited by Christian Damböck and
Adam T. Tuboly. Cham: Springer.
Uebel, Thomas, 1992. Overcoming Logical Positivism from Within:
The Emergence of Neurath’s Naturalism in the Vienna Circle’s Protocol Sentence Debate. Amsterdam: Rodopi.
, forthcoming b. “Language, Truth, and Logic and the Anglophone Reception of the Vienna Circle.” In The Historical and
Philosophical Significance of Ayer’s Language, Truth, and Logic,
edited by Adam Tuboly. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
, 2007. Empiricism at the Crossroads. The Vienna Circle’s Protocol Sentence Debate. Chicago: Open Court.
Waismann, Friedrich, 1959. “How I See Philosophy.” In Ayer
(1959), pp. 345–80.
, 2015. “American Pragmatism and the Vienna Circle: The
Early Years.” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 3(3):
1–35.
, 1979. “Foreword.” In Schlick (1979e), pp. xxiii–xxxiii.
, 1994a. “Ethics and Science.” In McGuinness and Schulte
(1994), pp. 33–52.
, 2019. “Verificationism and (Some of) its Discontents.” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 7(4): 1–31.
, 1994b. “Will and Motive.” In McGuinness and Schulte
(1994), pp. 53–137.
, 2020. “Schlick and Wittgenstein: The Theory of Affirmations Revisited.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 58: 141–66.
Wolters, Gereon, 2004. “Styles in Philosophy: the Case of Carnap.” In Klein and Awodey (2004), pp. 25–40.
von Mises, Richard, 1970. “Ernst Mach and the Empiricist Conception of Science.” In Ernst Mach: Physicist and Philosopher,
edited by Robert S. Cohen, pp. 245–71. Dordrecht: Reidel.
, 2017. “Clash of Cultures? German Philosophers of Science
and the Great War (1914-1918).” Bollettino della Società Filosofica
Italiana, nuova series 220: 7–28.
Vrahimis, Andreas, 2012. “Modernism and the Vienna Circle’s
critique of Heidegger.” Critical Quarterly 54: 61–83.
, forthcoming. “Philosophenkrieger? Wie Carnap & Co.
den Ersten Weltkrieg sahen.” In Logical Empirism, Life Reform,
and the German Youth Movement, edited by Christian Damböck,
Günther Sandner and Meike Werner. Cham: Springer.
, 2013a. “‘Was There a Sun Before Men Existed?’: A. J. Ayer
and French Philosophy in the Fifties.” Journal for the History of
Analytical Philosophy 1(9): 1–25.
, 2013b. Encounters between Analytic and Continental Philosophy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy vol. 8 no. 9
[29]