Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2019
…
20 pages
1 file
If suicide - (perhaps the highest form of self-harm) - goes against the basic human value of life, then correspondingly “unreasonableness” goes against the basic human and irreducible value of “practical reasonableness”, as developed by the Oxford scholar John Finnis. According to this view, practical reasonableness is the type of reasoning that we use to make decisions about how to act and how to order our lives. Also according to this view the other basic values are pursued with the help of this “reasonableness”. There are nine requirements of practical reasonableness that will be briefly tackled during the talk. Alan argues that activities like wars, terrorism, racism, separatism, may well appear as benefitting one individual group (say, a nation) over another and thus appear reasonably practical. However, he argues, that in the short, medium and long term all these activities have serious intrinsic consequences on the perpetrator and obviously on the target, making the whole national and international community unstable. It is in other words, a self-harm situation. Alan will mainly tackle two of these requirements in his talk, namely: the seventh requirement which states that one should never commit an act that directly harms a basic value, even if it will indirectly benefit a different basic value; and the eighth requirement which states that one should look after the common good of the community. Alan will discuss why the aforementioned activities are acts of self-harm, besides of general harm, and why do they go against practical reason, making them “practically unreasonable”. As always there will be more questions asked than answers given. Alan’s aim in this talk is to create a dialogue through which anyone can critically and practically reason about issues. Then practical reasonableness becomes a philosophical tool that can be used to analyse any issue.
The idea of practical reasonableness has been developed by John Finnis as one of the seven basic goods. The other basic goods are pursued with the help of this good. All these goods are objective goods which are self evident and they are not questionable. In order to know whether our decisions are practically reasonable or not Finnis has given nine requirements of practical reasonableness. These nine requirements are- coherent plan of life, non arbitrariness in the preference among values, non arbitrariness among persons, detachment, commitment, limited relevance of consequences, equal value to all the basic goods, following one’s conscience. John Finnis is also against consequentialism or utilitarianism. This project therefore tries to study the idea of practical reasonableness as put forward by Finnis. Aim and Objective: To study the idea of practical reasonableness put forwards by John Finnis. Research Questions:- • What is the idea of practical reasonableness? • What are the requirements of practical reasonableness? • How did Finnis criticized consequentialism? Scope and Limitation: The scope of the project is limited to the idea of practical reasonableness of John Finnis. Review of LiteratureL John Finnis, Natural Law & Natural Rights( Paul Craig, 2nd Edition Oxford University Press 2011) This book is the seminal work of John Finnis where he has discussed in detail his ideas of practical reasonableness. Practical reasonableness according to him is one through which we pursue the other basic goods. In his book he talks about the seven basic goods and practical reasonableness is one of them. He has listed down nine requirements of practical reasonableness. Through these requirements we can actually know if our decisions are practically reasonable or not. According to him consequentialists are not practically reasonable. They always talks about maximizing the net goodness but according to Finnis its not possible. Again what is good for one might be different for others. Conor O’ Mahony, ‘ The Failings of Practical Reasonableness: Another Look at John Finnis’ ( Cork Online Law Review 2002) http://www.corkonlinelawreview.com/editions/2002/2002-5.pdf accessed 10 October 2016This article provides a critique to Finnis’s idea of practical reasonableness. The author has criticized Finnis of giving more importance to practical reasonableness then other goods. Research Methodology: The type of research is qualitative and doctrinal. Secondary sources are taken help of. Websites, blogs and books are taken help of to make the project.
The Journal of Value Inquiry, 2013
In this talk I present a new approach to modeling practical deliberation (deliberation with a choice in view). This approach models deliberation as the intersection of a plurality of deliberational “moving parts”, that consequently can result in a plurality of outputs for the same input. (This can be conceptualized in computational terms as a multi-tape Turing machine, though I shall not be concerned with computational issues in this talk. This talk will take up philosophical issues exclusively.) My approach competes with the expected utility approach to decision making (a single-output approach), and has the potential for quite different powers of prediction. In particular, it has the power to diagnose (by pinpointing precisely) errors of practical judgment, whereas a single-output approach (if and when it’s actually correct) can signal only that a mistake has occurred. The familiar term is “irrationality”, meaning a failure to comply with the axioms chosen by experts—a pronouncement too vague to be of any diagnostic use. The multi-output approach is also in possession of significant resources to diagnose many things now lumped together under the heading of “risk aversion”.
The Journal of Value Inquiry, 2013
The concepts of reasons as supporting elements, of practical reason as a capacity, and of practical reasoning as a process are central in the theory of action. This paper provides a brief account of each. Several kinds of reason for action are distinguished. Practical reason is characterized both as a capacity whose exercise is largely constituted by a kind of responsiveness to reasons and as governed by certain normative principles; and practical reasoning is described as a kind of mental process in which reasons figure as premises and, from those premises, a practical conclusion is drawn. Much of the paper undertakes two related tasks: to distinguish the main kinds of practical reasoning and the associated criteria of assessment and to formulate some important substantive principles of practical reason. These principles yield criteria of several sorts: logical, inferential, epistemic, and material. On the theory presented, although any (non-basic) intentional act can be grounded in practical reasoning, the same acts can be performed for the relevant reason(s) without being so grounded, and in either case their rationality depends on adequate support by the reason(s). One kind of reason is commonly thought to be captured by Kantian hypothetical imperatives. The final sections explore what constitutes a hypothetical imperative and what other principles are needed to account for practical rationality. A major conclusion is that in the domain of practical reason, if there are no categorical imperatives, there are no hypothetical imperatives either. Reasons are central in understanding both practical reason and theoretical reason. But there are many kinds of reasons. Partly because of this, philosophical writing is often unclear about what counts as a reason and about how reasons are connected with various closely related elements. One of these is reason, as a general capacity. A second is reasoning, as an exercise of that capacity. My concern is the practical domain, but much of what I say also applies to the theoretical realm. I begin with the nature of reasons for action, proceed to connect these with practical
Ratio, 2010
This paper seeks a better understanding of the elements of practical reasoning: premises and conclusion. It argues that the premises of practical reasoning do not normally include statements such as 'I want to ϕ'; that the reasoning in practical reasoning is the same as it is in theoretical reasoning and that what makes it practical is, first, that the point of the relevant reasoning is given by the goal that the reasoner seeks to realize by means of that reasoning and the subsequent action; second, that the premises of such reasoning show the goodness of the action to be undertaken; third, that the conclusions of such reasoning may be actions or decisions, that can be accompanied by expressions of intention, either in action, or for the future; and that these are justified, and might be contradicted, in ways that are not only peculiar to them (i.e. in ways that diverge from those found in theoretical reasoning), but are distinctively practical, in that they involve reference to reasons for acting and to expressions of intention, respectively. 1 This paper explores practical reasoning. In particular, it seeks a better understanding of the elements of practical reasoning (premises and conclusion) and their relation. These are large and much debated issues. I shall first focus on the question: 'What are the premises of practical reasoning?' and, towards the end of the paper, will say something about the conclusion of practical reasoning. As will become clear, my discussion is inspired in Elizabeth Anscombe's remarks on practical reasoning in Intention and in her paper 'Practical Inference'. 2 A preliminary point. The term 'practical reasoning', one might think, is ambiguous, for it can be used to refer to the process of practical reasoning, or to the 'content' of that reasoning. I am not convinced by this ambiguity claim. At any rate, by 'practical reasoning' I shall here mean the reasoning that we, as rational agents, engage in. Engaging in such reasoning is taking certain statements as premises and, if all goes well, reaching a 'practical' conclusion, which has those premises as its grounds. So the questions I am concerned with can be put without ambiguity: what kind of statements play the role of premises when we engage in practical reasoning? And what is the conclusion of such reasoning? The premises of practical reasoning 1 I should like to thank John Broome, Alex Neill, Aaron Ridley, Daniel Whiting and participants at seminars where earlier versions of this paper were presented for their comments and suggestions.
Reasons without Rationalism. By Kieran Setiya. (Princeton UP, 2007. Pp. ix + 131. Price £23.95.) 1.
Philosophy & Social Criticism, 2015
My aim in this article is to investigate the epistemic dimension of reasonableness. In the last decades, the concept of reasonableness has been deeply analysed, and yet, I maintain that a strictly epistemic analysis of reasonableness is still lacking. The goal of this article is to clarify which epistemic features characterize reasonableness as one of the fundamental virtues in the political domain. In order to justify political liberalism through a public justification that averts the risk of falling into a dilemma, it is important to establish in advance which are the epistemic constraints that should be respected. My proposal is that a moderate approach in moral epistemology expresses the best scheme available to us – as moral agents constrained by the limit of our rationality – for establishing a normatively binding, and yet realistic, procedure of justification for political institutions and practices.
Advances in Medical Education, 2011
Journal of Geography (Chigaku Zasshi), 1999
Этнографическое обозрение, 2023
Dalla cremazione all'inumazione (?), 2015
Educação & Sociedade, 2024
Alanis Obomsawin: Lifework, 2022
Policy Research Working Papers, 1999
SPEKTRUM INDUSTRI, 2016
Anais do II JITOU, 2014
Ophthalmic Research, 2015
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2012
Journal of Clinical Care and Skills, 2021
Journal of Avian Biology, 2007