Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
Gabriel Rockhill
Theory & Event, Volume 23, Number 1, January 2020, pp. 85-119 (Article)
Published by Johns Hopkins University Press
For additional information about this article
https://muse.jhu.edu/article/747096
Access provided at 29 Jan 2020 17:14 GMT from Villanova University
Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
Gabriel Rockhill
Abstract This article examines the force and limitations of genealogy in order to develop a practice of counter-history that is
capable of both overcoming its inherent problems and providing
a more trenchant mode of critico-historical engagement. Using
Foucault’s well-known essay on Nietzsche as its methodological
centerpiece, it begins by elucidating the latter’s powerful contribution to the historical analysis of values, while also foregrounding the quasi-naturalized morality of genealogy that structures it.
Against this backdrop, it examines Foucault’s symptomatological
distinction between two opposed and normativized conceptions
of origin in Nietzsche—Herkunft and Ursprung—in order to both
explicate Foucault’s unique appropriation of Nietzschean genealogy and demonstrate its limits through the striking fact that this
originary textual symptom of “properly Nietzschean” genealogy
does not actually exist in the text. The remainder of the article
draws on certain genealogical resources while challenging the historical order undergirding them in order to propose an alternative
logic of history that takes into account its constitutive multidimensionality and the multiplicity of agencies at work in any conjuncture. It dismantles, in this way, the very framework that renders
historical origins possible, as well as streamlined moral narratives
of genealogical inversion, thereby parting ways with the moralities of genealogy in favor of the politicization of values.
“Alle Wahrheit ist einfach.”—Ist das nicht zweifach eine Lüge?—
—Friedrich Nietzsche
Genealogy and Counter-History
Genealogy works in black and white. It is guided by a structural
opposition that orients its gaze away from the valorized victors in the
limelight toward the long and weighty shadows cast over those who
have lost their historical battles and are sequestered in the darkness.
Rejecting the grandiose narratives of the conquerors, with their ample
dose of self-aggrandizing mythology and its requisite ethereal abstrac-
Theory & Event Vol. 23, No. 1, 85–119 © 2020 Johns Hopkins University Press
86
Theory & Event
tions, it casts light on the vanquished, the downtrodden and the marginalized, while simultaneously elucidating both the actual—in the
sense of wirkliche—history of their demise and the historiographical
legerdemains that have obfuscated it. Genealogies are thus histories of
inversion, in which the world is abruptly turned upside down. What
had appeared to be good is suddenly revealed, in the shadow play of
genealogy, to be bad, and what had been castigated as evil reappears
as good. A shade is cast over the purportedly pristine innocence of the
vanquishers at the same time that those sullied and subjugated by the
battles of history emerge from their caverns of obscurity.
In his now canonical essay on the subject matter, Michel Foucault
demonstrates the power of genealogical inversion and directly performs it himself by situating a figure who had been marginal to standard histories of philosophy at the core of an unprecedented historiographical overturning. Friedrich Nietzsche, he argues, developed a
unique form of history that abandoned the metaphysical quest for an
origin (Ursprung) in favor of a genealogical examination of the archive
and the singular contingency of any origin (Herkunft). This seemingly
insignificant distinction in German between two types of origin is thus
identified, by Foucault, as a symptom of a major methodological inversion.
Foucault’s enactment of genealogy, however, is plagued by a performative contradiction: the symptomatic difference that he identifies
does not actually exist in Nietzsche’s text. In order to develop his genealogy of a genealogy without Ursprung, he thereby constructs an originary discursive distinction out of the blue—like the hypothesis-mongering English genealogists condemned by Nietzsche—revealing
genealogy’s ongoing dependence on certain forms of origin discourse
and ideal significations in order to spin its black and white tales of
dramatic overturning. If genealogy is supposed to be grey in its meticulous engagement with the contingencies of documentary archives, its
stark opposition of values and grand histories of moral inversion often
obfuscate the material nuances of its objects of analysis.
To bring them out and definitively part ways with origin discourse, it is necessary to go to the heart of the historical order governing genealogy in order to identify its limitations and perform a
tectonic shift, which will lead to counter-history. The latter draws on
and radicalizes some of the major contributions of genealogy, while
also overcoming the chronological order of history that structures it,
as well as its proclivity for individual moral inversions rather than collective political transformations. By foregrounding the geographic and
social dimensions of history along with the chronological, and simultaneously insisting on the fact that each of these is multidimensional,
counter-history breaks with the historical order undergirding the very
distinction between epochs and events, and thus the possibility of ori-
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
87
gins—discursive or otherwise—in history. Understanding the past as
a dynamic and multi-agential force field distributed across time, space
and social stratification, counter-history proposes a complex cartography and topography that maps out the multiple agencies at work in
the ongoing political struggles over the immanent formation of values
and their potential collective transformation.
In what follows, I will begin by elucidating Nietzsche’s understanding of genealogy, foregrounding his denaturalization of the dominant system of morality as well as his attempt to resuscitate a more
originary set of values that have been inverted in the very unnatural
history of ‘the West.’ This will prepare the groundwork for examining
Foucault’s failed attempt to excise origins from Nietzsche and genealogy more generally, thereby opening a broader inquiry into both the
force and limitations of genealogy. The article concludes with an outline of the tectonic shift proposed by counter-history, which renders
origins inoperative, dismantles the ideal significations plaguing the
genealogical chiaroscuro of value inversion, and brings to the fore the
ongoing social and political struggles over the immanent constitution
of collective values.
Genealogy of the Prehistorical Origin of Values
In the final note at the end of the first essay of On the Genealogy of
Morality (1887), Nietzsche parenthetically refers to the issues discussed
in the book as problems regarding “the value of all previous valuations [vom Werte der bisherigen Wertschätzung].”1 This subtle distinction
between Wert and Wertschätzung points to a key theme in his analysis:
values—or, at least, the culturally dominant ones—do not simply exist
as such; they are produced through historical acts of valorization.
It is for this reason that he examines the forgotten prehistory
[Vorgeschichte] of values and the “ethical life of convention [Sittlichkeit
der Sitte]” that has forged “humanity” as such by fabricating its
moral armature and its deeply rooted meta-values.2 Prehistory,
which precedes world history and is “the longest period in the history of mankind,” is the “genuine and decisive main historical period
[Hauptgeschichte] that determined man’s character.”3 Nietzsche’s genealogical intervention consists, among other things, in historicizing this
prehistorical archive of meta-values in order to show that they too are
the result of past acts of valuation.
Morality is thus understood to be a historical product whose origin
has been forgotten, and genealogy labors to unearth its prehistory in
order to reveal how our supposed moral nature is only the sedimentation of an imposed second nature. At the same time, genealogy seeks
to create, for some, new habits that overwrite the past with an original second nature that might one day become first nature. It is in this
88
Theory & Event
regard that one aspect of the “critical” use of history described in his
Untimely Meditations (1876) anticipated an important feature of genealogy:
The best we can do is to confront our inherited and hereditary
nature with our knowledge, and through a new, stern discipline
combat our inborn heritage and implant in ourselves a new habit,
a new instinct, a second nature, so that our first nature withers
away. It is an attempt to give oneself, as it were a posteriori, a past
in which one would like to originate [stammen] in opposition to
that in which one did originate.4
This endeavor to transform calcified habits into one’s own creative
palimpsest is rendered particularly difficult, however, due to a fundamental inversion that characterizes the history of values. In On the
Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche juxtaposes an earlier era in which
the nobles or masters boldly affirmed the good as that which they
instinctively did (and denigrated the bad as the opposite), with a more
recent period in which the herd or slaves have sought—through their
powerlessness—to identify the good of the masters with evil itself,
and to redefine the good as the opposite of evil.5 Slave morality has
thereby reversed the values of the nobles and their bitter ressentiment
has succeeded, at least in part, in making this overturning disappear
into oblivion, thereby naturalizing their morality. In other words, the
“moral facts” engrained in modern culture are actually the result of
a past—and present—power struggle and a revaluation of values that
slave morality has endeavored to conceal behind a veil of innocence.
By lifting the veil, Nietzsche seeks to reveal that values are promoted
and fought for qua values-in-struggle—hence the need for a new, heightened revaluation of values.
On the Morality of Genealogy
Nietzsche’s insistence on historical processes and actions does not
keep him from invoking certain stable reference points. The very figures of master and slave, as well as their respective moralities suggest
that there are identifiable “subjects” that can be taken as markers for
specific types of action. Moreover, these two “agents” form a polarized normative and racialized opposition that has dominated history
for centuries according to Nietzsche. In drawing his conclusions in the
first essay of On the Genealogy of Morality, he writes:
The two opposing values “good and bad,” “good and evil” have
fought a terrible battle for thousands of years on earth […]. The
symbol of this fight […] is “Rome against Judea, Judea against
Rome”:—up to now there has been no greater event than this battle, this question, this contradiction of mortal enemies.6
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
89
His corpus is, of course, as variegated as it is complex, and he did not
necessarily maintain a single position throughout. Nevertheless, in his
Genealogy and other similar texts, it is regularly affirmed that there are
only two major groups of people, or two races, and each of them has its
own understanding of morality. This decisive opposition provides the
over-arching evaluative framework for his genealogical account.7 To
a certain extent, the basis for this polarization is to be found in nature
itself.8 In the section of Twilight of the Idols entitled “Morality as AntiNature,” he writes:
I formulate a principle. All naturalism in morality [Moral], that is
all healthy morality, is dominated by an instinct of life […]. Antinatural morality [Die widernatürliche Moral], that is virtually every
morality that has hitherto been taught, reverenced and preached,
turns on the contrary precisely against the instincts of life.9
It is the inversion of the natural hierarchy of masters over slaves that is
instigated by the perverse ressentiment of the latter, leading to what he
calls in The Anti-Christ (1894) a denaturalization of values: “The history
of Israel is invaluable as a typical history of the denaturalizing of natural values [Entnatürlichung der Natur-Werte].”10 This alienation from
nature is what motivates his revaluation of all values and his attempt
to resuscitate or reinvent their originary relation.
It is in this sense that his genealogy could be understood in the
strict sense of the term as an account of the lineage of two distinct
and opposed races of people. It provides us with a linear history of
inversion and decline, in which he strives to trace both races back
to their primordial origins.11 Whereas the masters manifested their
morality instinctively, the slaves are the unnatural ones who, due to
their powerlessness, revolted against the natural order. This rebellion
is ultimately rooted in their own will to power as the sickest animals
of history: those who are so weak that they can only conquer through
their cleverness by inverting master morality and striving to surreptitiously naturalize their own slave morality.
Nietzsche’s normative stringency and his embrace of a linear history of decline are particularly salient in his denigration of modern
socialist and democratic movements, as well as in his condemnation of
major social revolutions. He situates the triumph of modern so-called
democracy in his deep but schematic history of the clash of antithetical values: “Judea once again triumphed over the classical ideal with
the French Revolution: the last political nobility in Europe, that of
the French seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, collapsed under the
ressentiment-instincts of the rabble.”12 He summarizes this setback by
claiming that we need to acknowledge the fact that the herd has won:
“‘The Masters’ are deposed; the morality of the common people has
triumphed.”13
90
Theory & Event
Nietzsche thus advocates for a resuscitation of the originary and
natural relation between nobles and slaves, which has been perverted
by a pernicious historical inversion that defines the very unnatural
history of descent in the “Western world,” and potentially beyond.
Genealogy is the historical practice that—in the service of life—diligently traces out this masked history of moral transposition and the
decadence it has produced. It tells the secret history of nihilism and the
overturning of values that slave morality seeks to obfuscate in order to
pass itself off as natural (rather than historical).
In endeavoring to reveal the true origin of slave morality, genealogy simultaneously seeks to resuscitate the original sovereign power
of master morality that predates this psycho-historical distortion. The
project that Nietzsche describes as moving beyond good and evil is
thus not one of definitively moving outside good and bad, but rather
one of a liberation from the yoke of slave morality through a revival
of the affirmative character of masterly values.14 Genealogy is thus
fundamentally a matter of elucidating the origin of slave morality by
tracing it back to the more originary source of master morality, thereby
contrasting the bad origin of modern morality to the good archi-origin
it seeks to displace.15
In all of these ways, Nietzsche’s discourse remains haunted by
the risks of selective historicism, by which I mean a form of historicism
that selects certain elements that escape the flow of time. Whereas the
values of his enemies are clearly historicized, he at times appears to
juxtapose them to a naturalized, suprahistorical version of his own.
It is thus often as if master morality transcended and structured his
entire genealogy, functioning as the morality of genealogy that is both the
origin and the transcendental frame of his genealogy of morality.
In foregrounding this aspect of his work, the point is not to condemn all of Nietzsche’s writings for ultimately succumbing to a naturalizing genealogy that passes immanent values off as transcendent.
It is rather to highlight a fundamental risk, while also insisting on
the fact that there are other resources in his motley corpus that one
might be able to mobilize against it. For instance, given his insistence
on values themselves being practical acts of valuation, it would be
possible to argue that the values promulgated by Nietzsche himself
are interventionist in the sense that they are the ones that he actively
creates and seeks to impose—rather than naturalize—even if it means
appealing to nature and instinct as a rhetorical strategy. For he often
insists on a form of radical historicism that goes all the way down by
situating human beings themselves and everything they have created
in the flow of time. The natural would thus actually be historical, and
there would be no first nature, but only palimpsestic processes of sedimentation and varying time scales. Moreover, his important critiques
of the hypostatizing power of language suggest that he was intimately
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
91
aware of the ways in which his own discourse could lend itself to
processes of reification that needed to be resisted. We might therefore
want to understand his key notions—master morality, slave morality,
will to power, and so forth—as autophagic concepts that ingest themselves in the very process of being deployed, precisely as if they had no
being but their own becoming. Let us recall, in this regard, the “true but
deadly” doctrines that he announced in his Untimely Meditations: “the
doctrines of sovereign becoming, of the fluidity of all concepts, types
and species, of the lack of any cardinal distinction between man and
animal.”16 Such openings in his work do not eliminate, of course, the
risks and problems that have been highlighted, but rather they show
that his corpus is variegated and his own discourse is sometimes in
productive conflict with itself.
Foucault’s Originary Symptom of Genealogy
In his widely read essay, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” Foucault
asserts that the author of On the Genealogy of Morality made a distinction between two types of origin. Whereas Herkunft refers to a contingent provenance that is unmasked through genealogical excavation,
Ursprung indexes a primordial identity or essence behind historical
appearances. It is this latter notion of origin that, according to Foucault,
Nietzsche the genealogist dismisses as a myth:
A genealogy of values, morality, asceticism, and knowledge will
never confuse itself with a quest for their “origin [origine].” On the
contrary, it will cultivate the details and accidents that accompany
every beginning [commencement]. [...] The genealogist needs history to dispel the chimeras of the origin [origine].17
Foucault wisely embeds this terminological distinction in a series of
important provisos and qualifications. He emphasizes, for instance,
that there are two different uses of the word Ursprung in Nietzsche:
one that is marked and the other that is not. By unmarked he simply
means that Nietzsche occasionally uses it as a term that is more or
less equivalent to similar words like Herkunft, Entstehung, Abkunft, and
Geburt. The word is marked, however, when it is employed in a conceptual opposition or is invoked ironically or deceptively.18 With this
distinction in mind, he turns to the preface of the Genealogy as “one of
the most significant texts for the use of all of these terms, and for the
variations in the use of Ursprung.”19 He claims that Nietzsche begins
by describing his object of analysis as the Herkunft of moral prejudices,
and then he recounts the story of his personal involvement with this
question by describing how he had wondered if God was responsible
for the Ursprung of evil. A little further on, “he evokes the analyses
92
Theory & Event
that are properly Nietzschean [proprement nietzschéennes], which began
with Human, All Too Human. He speaks of Herkunfthypothesen [sic.]
to characterize them.”20 “This use of the word Herkunft,” Foucault
stresses, “is certainly not arbitrary: it serves to designate several texts
in Human, All Too Human devoted to the origin [origine] of morality,
asceticism, justice, and punishment. And yet, in all of these passages,
the word used then had been Ursprung. It is as if, at the moment of the
Genealogy, and at this precise point in the text, Nietzsche wanted to
emphasize an opposition between Herkunft and Ursprung, which he
had not made use of some ten years earlier.”21 Finally, Foucault maintains that Nietzsche reverted to an unmarked use of the term Ursprung
as neutral and equivalent to Herkunft at the end of the preface (and he
remarks in a note that they are used more or less synonymously in a
number of other passages in the Genealogy).
This passing distinction in a brief text provides Foucault with the
opportunity of formulating a provocative and rhetorically dramatic
thesis regarding the originary moment of non-originary genealogy,
which he describes as the meticulous and well-documented investigation into the contingent singularity of events and the dissimulated
or disavowed historicity of that which appears to have no history. It
is opposed to the “metahistorical deployment of ideal significations
and indefinite or undefined teleologies [des indéfinies téléologies].”22 The
genealogist’s objection to origins is thus a refusal to assume that there
is an original essence or truth behind each thing, or that every historical element began in a pristine state of perfection. In turning away
from this metaphysics of history, genealogy scrutinizes both the source
(provenance / Herkunft) and emergence (émergence / Entstehung) of
historical phenomena. Whereas the examination of the source demonstrates the fragmentary heterogeneity at work in the accidental formation of that which appears to be unchanging, the analysis of emergence
reveals the interstitial struggle of forces out of which specific “things”
develop. In both cases, genealogy operates as a wirkliche Historie in the
following senses: i) it reintroduces becoming into that which is purportedly immortal ii) it reveals discontinuous events behind supposed
continuities iii) it analyzes that which is closest to us by cultivating a
profound distance from it iv) it embraces perspectival knowledge in
the dissolution of absolute truth.
In spite of the importance Foucault places on this distinction
between what we might call a good origin (Herkunft or Entstehung)
and a bad origin (Ursprung), a normative difference that frames his
entire argument, the diligent reader familiar with Nietzsche’s preoccupation with origins cannot help but wonder if his genealogy of
genealogy has been thoroughly grey enough, by working through
the contingent singularities of the material body of the text. The first
thing to note is that Nietzsche explicitly uses the terms Herkunft and
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
93
Ursprung as synonyms at precisely the originary watershed moment in
the text where Foucault claims that he opposes them. He opens section
four of the preface by writing: “I was given the initial stimulation to
publish something about my hypotheses on the origin of morality [von
meinen Hypothesen über den Ursprung der Moral] by a clear, honest and
clever, even too-clever little book.”23 This work, Paul Rée’s The Origin
[Ursprung] of the Moral Sensations, provided a perverse back-to-front
form of genealogical analysis criticized by Nietzsche. After a very brief
description of his relationship to Rée’s work, he writes: “as I said [wie
gesagt], I was, at the time [damals], bringing to the light of day those
hypotheses on descent [Herkunfts-Hypothesen] to which these essays
are devoted.”24 This sentence unmistakably refers back to what was
said just a few lines earlier (wie gesagt), in the first phrase of section
four, where he described his initial stimulation to disclose his theories. The expression “hypotheses on descent [Herkunfts-Hypothesen],”
which Foucault wants to identify as the original flash point in the text
where Nietzsche inscribes a crucial and “marked” distinction between
Herkunft and Ursprung, is thus actually an overtly synonymous
rewording of “hypotheses on the origin of morality [Hypothesen über
den Ursprung der Moral].” If the choice of the word Herkunft “is certainly not arbitrary,” as Foucault would have us believe, it is because
it is clearly inscribed within a chain of equivalent formulations that
Nietzsche uses to describe his project.
This synonymous relationship is further reiterated in the opening
line of the following section of the preface, in which he directly refers
back once again to this time [damals] and to “the nature of hypotheses, mine or anybody else’s, on the origin of morality [Ursprung der
Moral].”25 The supposedly originary instant of distinction between
Ursprung and Herkunft actually appears, then, in a tight, grey sequence
of equivalent reformulations in which the terms are used interchangeably. It is surprising, then, that Foucault would go to such great lengths
to distinguish between them, not only by reading over the wie gesagt,
which distinctly links the first two formulations together, but also by
elliptically suggesting that the use of Ursprung in the opening line of
section four was related to a critical dismissal of Rée’s book, when in
fact Nietzsche is obviously talking about his own origin-hypotheses
(as is also evident from the opening line of section five cited above).
This is, however, only the first sign that Foucault’s discursive
origin, meaning the symptomal moment in the text when Nietzsche
“proper”—the “original” Nietzsche—appears in the suddenly marked
use of a term that purportedly demarcates a positive from a negative form of origin, was pulled out of the blue. Just as the HerkunftsHypothesen that Foucault wants to distinguish from hypotheses
regarding an origin (Ursprung) are simply another way of saying
Hypothesen über den Ursprung, the same is true of his supposedly
94
Theory & Event
Figure 1. A line-by-line comparison between key passages in Michel Foucault’s
“Nietzsche, Genealogy, History” and Friedrich Nietzsche’s Preface to On the
Genealogy of Morality. Image by author.
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
95
ironic use of Ursprung to refer to how he had earlier identified God as
the “origin of evil [Ursprung des Bösen].”26 For even after Nietzsche’s
realization that this was slightly misguided, he once again uses the
term Ursprung to refer to what are apparently—in Foucault’s vocabulary—“analyses that are properly Nietzschean”27: “Fortunately I
learnt, in time, to separate theological from moral prejudice and I no
longer searched for the origin [Ursprung] of evil beyond the world.”28
This suggests that he continued to pursue its Ursprung, just not beyond
the world.
As a matter of fact, in the opening line of this section of the preface
(section three), he emphatically refers to the search for an “origin
[Ursprung]” as being so fundamental to his life that it would almost
make sense to call it his “a priori.” What is more, this a priori is described
as being in direct conflict with his age, as well as his lineage or descent
(Herkunft). If anything, then, he intimates, at least in this passing statement, that genealogy breaks with historical tendencies and extant lines
of descent (Herkunft) by undertaking an untimely quest for origins
(Ursprünge):
With a characteristic skepticism to which I confess only reluctantly—it relates to morality and to all that hitherto on earth has been
celebrated as morality—, a skepticism which sprang up in my so
early, so unbidden, so unstoppably, and which was in such conflict
with my surroundings, age, precedents and lineage [Herkunft] that
I would almost be justified in calling it my “a priori,”—eventually
my curiosity and suspicion were bound to fix on the question of
what origin [Ursprung] our terms good and evil actually have.29
It is very telling that Foucault’s mischaracterizations of Nietzsche’s
writings persist throughout his article. In purporting to provide
additional textual evidence for his claims regarding Nietzsche’s use
of Ursprung, he quotes paragraph three of “The Wanderer and His
Shadow,” where Nietzsche actually uses Anfang and Entstehung, but
Foucault surreptitiously leaves the latter term out of his quotation in
order to suggest that the “origin” under discussion is an Ursprung (a
term that Nietzsche does not use in this paragraph). He repeats the
same basic operation in his next quote to imply that Nietzsche was
using Ursprung in Daybreak §49, when the terms employed were actually Abkunft and Anfang. He also references Beyond Good and Evil §242
as an example of his use of Herkunft, but the term is not employed
there (the verb entstehen is). He points to §244 of the same book for
the same reason, even though Nietzsche actually uses both Ursprung
and Herkunft in this passage. He oddly references Genealogy III, §7 in
his discussion of Herkunft, adding an elliptical footnote reference to
Abkunft, which is the term that Nietzsche actually uses in this passage.
In the context of claiming that Nietzsche often associates Herkunft and
96
Theory & Event
Erbschaft, he refers to Daybreak §247, where Herkunft appears, but not
Erbschaft. Finally, in his documentation of Nietzsche’s use of Entstehung,
he refers to Genealogy III, §13, where the term does not appear.30
On the Differential Repetition of the Morality of Genealogy
Ironically, then, Foucault goes to great lengths to find an originary,
value-laden distinction between Herkunft and Ursprung—between
“good” and “bad” origins—that does not, in fact, exist. He is intent
on deceptively inscribing a normative opposition into the material
archive in order to clearly demarcate the wirkliche Historie of genealogy
from the ideal significations and teleologies of the history of origins.
At stake, for him, is the very value of historical research, as well as the
need to valorize genealogy over and against the essentializing tendencies of metaphysical chronicles. It must not be lost on us, then, that
Foucault is telling a history of values, a genealogy of the emergence of
a more valuable mode of history. He is attempting to tease out from the
Genealogy of Morality the morality of genealogy.
According to Foucault, genealogy emerges from the underside of
dominant history, as an untimely accident of sorts, which contests the
value system of metaphysical historiography. The latter valorizes a
long series of intertwined concepts over and against their opposites:
continuity versus discontinuity, totality versus fragmentation, global
versus local, sameness versus difference, spirit versus body, necessity
versus contingency, and so forth. Genealogy is the art of inverting this
morality of history. What the latter identifies as “good,” the former
takes to be “bad” by advancing an anti-essentialist and non-teleological
historiography that privileges and valorizes discontinuity, fragmentation, difference, chance, accident and so on. The morality of genealogy,
in other words, is an anti-morality that overturns the hierarchies of
dominant history. In his opening lecture for his 1976 course “Society
Must Be Defended,” Foucault defined genealogy as follows:
In relation to the project of inscribing knowledges [savoirs] in the
hierarchical order of power, which is characteristic of science,
genealogy would thus be a sort of undertaking aimed at de-subjugating historical knowledges [désassujettir les savoirs historiques]
and rendering them free, meaning capable of opposing and struggling against the coercion of a unitary, formal and scientific theoretical discourse. A reactivation of local knowledges [savoirs]—of
minor knowledges [savoirs], as Deleuze might call them—in opposition to the scientific hierarchization of knowledge [connaissance]
and its intrinsic effects of power: this, then is the project of these
disordered and fragmentary genealogies. In brief, I would say the
following: archaeology would be the appropriate method for the
analysis of local discursivities, and genealogy would be the tac-
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
97
tic that, on the basis of the descriptions of these local discursivities, would bring into play the de-subjugated knowledges [savoirs
désassujettis] that are released.31
It is noteworthy in this regard that the entire normative opposition
between metaphysical historiography and genealogy “as critique” is
summed up in its totality, we might say, in the symptom that Foucault
identifies as the linchpin of his argument regarding Nietzsche. The
manifest distinction between Ursprung and Herkunft (or Entstehung)
is the fragmentary and apparently haphazard detail that indexes
the latent content that is the systemic division between two moralities of history: the meta-historical chronicle that valorizes a unified
chronology of ideal significations, and genealogy that inverts this
framework by elevating the infinitesimal details of local and contingent relations. This little difference is thus one that makes all of the difference precisely because it sums up, in microcosm, the macrocosmic
system of values that frames Foucault’s entire analysis. It is, we might
say, an originary difference because it marks, in a symptomal fragment, the fundamental dividing line that Foucault wants to inscribe
between two different historical systems of value. In endeavoring to
reestablish the “proper use [utilisation propre]” of these key terms, he
seeks to inscribe an originary discursive and normative distinction.
This is indicative of his approach to archives more generally, as
well as of one of his most widespread hermeneutic strategies: symptomatology. Foucault often searches for little differences that signal
macroscopic shifts in a corpus, an archive, an episteme or an era. The
smaller the symptom and the larger the consequences, the more dramatic his metonymic narrative and its rhetorical impact. His analysis of a passing and seemingly unimportant distinction in a few
lines of Nietzsche’s original German text is thus genealogically of the
same family as his interpretation, for instance, of a line in Descartes’
Meditations that is supposed to have signaled an epochal shift in historical understandings of madness, or again his reading of an essay
by the later Kant that purportedly inaugurated event-based thinking
and the “ontology of contemporary reality.” In all three of these cases,
like many others, an infinitesimal textual detail is used as the index
of a historical sea change, an event, thereby capturing the smallest of
differences within the broadest of historical narratives. In spite of all
of his insistence on dispersion, accidents, singularities, and so forth, it
is important to critically examine the extent to which his discontinuist
logic of history and his overwhelming proclivity for massive events
of structural inversion ultimately subsume the details of microscopic
differences within a systematic historiographical armature. The latter
is the site of conceptual subsumption where differences and accidents
are transformed into symptoms and signifiers of a system or systemic
98
Theory & Event
change. In a certain sense, there is no singularity or contingency so
minor or marginal as to escape systemic capture and integration.
Foucault is, in fact, so intent on valorizing infinitesimal differential
symptoms of evental eruptions that, when they do not exist in the grey
of the text, he pulls them straight out of the blue.
This is particularly important in the case of his interpretation of
Nietzsche, and I have elsewhere made similar arguments regarding his
readings of Descartes and Kant.32 As we have seen, Nietzsche is indeed
preoccupied with discovering the origin of good and bad or evil. In
fact, he opens the first essay of the Genealogy by castigating the lack
of historical spirit at work in the historians of morality who identify
the origin of the concept of the good—the term he uses happens to be
Herkunft—with the praise bestowed upon unegoistic acts. He inverts
this thesis by categorically claiming:
The pathos of nobility and distance, as I said, the continuing and
predominant feeling of complete and fundamental superiority of a
higher ruling kind of relation to a lower kind, to those “below”—
that is the origin [Ursprung] of the antithesis “good” and “bad.”33
While purporting to excavate—but in fact discursively constructing—
an originary moment of normative distinction, Foucault argues that
there is no origin in the sense of a true or essential beginning. This
is particularly important since the originary site that he attempts to
isolate in Nietzsche’s text is itself quintessentially non-originary: he is
simply reformulating what he had already said. It is quite literally a
copy, a repetition, a synonymous reworking of what was stated in the
text. The fact that Foucault constructs an ideal normative signification
with no material reality to support his claim at the precise moment at
which he wants to mark the emergence of the wirkliche Historie that
is non-originary genealogy, should give us pause to consider what is
at stake in this performative contradiction. Indeed, Foucault’s origin,
which we might want to qualify as discursive or discontinuist rather
than essentialist, is nearly as abstract as the ones he criticizes, thereby
ironically proving his thesis that the quest for origins—including his
own—is quixotic and misguided.
The Limits of Genealogy
The term genealogy suggests a linear chain of descent. This is precisely one of the reasons why Foucault avoided using it in his early
work. Unlike archaeology, which he defined in 1967 as “the analysis
of discourse in its modality of archive,” a genealogy is a “description
of beginnings [commencements] and what follows.”34 Not unlike a
family tree, historical genealogy identifies clear starting points in the
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
99
social life of a collective and charts out their heritage over time. In this
regard, it maintains a certain proximity to a model of history according
to which a society’s past would be structured like the life of an individual human being (at least according to common sense): it has sharp
beginning and end points.
Foucault acknowledged his personal debt to Nietzschean genealogy early on, but once he began using the term himself, he insisted
on distinguishing it from “genetic analysis by filiation.”35 He wanted
to avoid, at least to a certain extent, linear histories of descent, and
he often pays attention to the unique histories of particular discursive series or practical registers, some of which come into conflict.
Nevertheless, it is important to recognize that his historical research
remains relatively well circumscribed within very specific cultural and
geographic coordinates. France obviously dominates his work, and the
issue of Franco-centrism is an important one. Moreover, the western
European triumvirate of France, Germany and England governs most
of his early and middle writings, whereas ancient Greece and Rome
become increasingly prominent in his later work. His histories are thus
deeply inscribed in what is called the Western world, and more specifically within the contemporary geo-cultural conception of this world
(with its supposed origin in ancient Greece and its modern forms primarily in western Europe).36 It is true that Foucault occasionally provides detailed and delicate accounts of geographic variability across
these regions. However, the governing framework of western Europe
or the West is maintained across his corpus (with a few exceptions,
which themselves arguably sink into forms of orientalism).37 This is
partially what allows him to construct streamlined, and often bi-dimensional narratives of structural inversion. In some general sense, his
historical accounts might be described as genealogies of “a people,”
or what he would later call “ontologies of ourselves.” This should
give us pause to reconsider the racial component of genealogy as it
morphs from Nietzsche’s preoccupation with an originary master race
into Foucault’s attempt to avoid this type of overt racialization while
nonetheless maintaining clear geo-cultural parameters to most of his
analyses.
Foucault not only recognizes but he also sometimes defends the
fact that his writings abide by a particular cultural delimitation. In
his work on prisons, for example, he admits that it is largely centered
on France, even though he did not want to strictly delimit it due to
overlap with developments elsewhere in Europe (or the US).38 His justification for this is that there are limitations to what one person can do.
While this is certainly true, and it would be naive to look to Foucault
for a complete history of the world, we should nonetheless be attentive
to the ways in which the very delimitation of what one person can or
should do is directly embedded within specific sociohistorical and cul-
100
Theory & Event
tural practices of knowledge production. Indeed, one of the lessons of
genealogy according to Foucault himself is that historical knowledge
is forged within institutional power relations, which surely include
the delimitation and modi operandi of disciplines, the hierarchization
of cultures, and the racialization of archives. In this regard, Foucault is
unmistakably participating, in his own unique way, in the institutionalized activity of historical writing as it came to be defined in France
in his day and age. Working within the confines of a specific cultural
territory was, at least for certain historians, the very lingua franca of history itself. In this sense, there was nothing remiss in Foucault’s genealogies of French or Western phenomena. In spite of his splendid appeal
to the “common labor of people who seek to ‘de-discipline’ themselves
[se ‘dé-disciplinariser’],” he was simply conforming, in this aspect of his
theoretical practice, to the norms of the institutionalized discipline of
history.39
This raises a number of crucial methodological questions. To begin
with, it is often assumed that one can meaningfully speak of cultural
units such as France, Germany or the West, as if they made a priori
sense. However, their delimitation has been, and continues to be, a site
of struggle, and the very idea of a relatively unified geographic space
remains highly contestable. The supposed borders of these spaces are
not only porous, but they are often founded on the attempt to impose
limits where there are, in fact, no strict frontiers. This is not simply due
to the movement of people, things and ideas, but also to the regular
interplay of cultural, political, social and economic forces. It is rather
revealing, in this regard, that Foucault—like many of his fellow French
historians—rarely engages with the question of the larger Francophone
world and the spaces of colonization.40 This is particularly striking for
someone who began teaching in France at the height of the Algerian
War, and who was living in Paris, for instance, during the October 1961
massacre of dozens, and likely hundreds, of pro-National Liberation
Front (FLN) protestors, who were shot, beaten by the police and
thrown into the Seine around the city.41 For someone researching the
historical practices of punishment, confinement, governmentality and
biopolitics emanating from the western European world, how could
one justify sidelining and generally ignoring imperialism and colonialism, particularly when its effects were right in front of one’s eyes?
In raising this question, I do not simply mean to suggest that
Foucault should have extended his investigation to “elsewhere,” as if
the colonies were necessarily distinct realities from France (according
to the standard colonial geography, which Foucault himself respects).
Instead, I mean that if we are intent on talking about the geographic
or cultural unit of France, for instance, we need to recognize that it
extends beyond its borders, but also that, within its frontiers, it is
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
101
always already enmeshed with elements from “elsewhere.” “Europe,”
wrote Frantz Fanon, “is literally the creation of the Third World.”42
To separate out and privilege, within supposed French borders, the
cultural spaces of “the French,” is to participate in a colonial logic of
space. Foucault’s massive valorization of the French Revolution as a
watershed moment in history is a case in point, particularly because
he does not make, to my knowledge, a single reference in his published work to the Haitian Revolution, whose world-historical significance is as important as its contribution to reconfiguring the “French
Revolution,” to the point of problematizing these geographic and cultural categories.
It is true, of course, that Foucault sought, to a certain extent, to
dismantle a number of the overarching historical narratives regarding
“the West” “from the inside,” so to speak, by upending structural pillars in established chronicles of reason, truth, subjectivity, sovereignty
and ethics, as well as of practices such as madness, the human sciences,
punishment, sexuality, and so forth. This is, in part, what justified, at
least in his eyes, his focus on the Western world. In doing so, he generally maintained a historical logic of epoch and event, or sequence
and rupture, that nonetheless required presupposing a minimum of
geographic and social homogeneity. To speak of an era with set characteristics, or a break that cuts across the thread of history and introduces a new age or series, one must compress the geographic as well
as the social dimensions of history into a temporal continuum capable
of being broken. While there is certainly some spatial and social variability in his accounts, this tends to be restricted to chronological staggering, the delimitation of series with their own temporalities, or latencies and resistances within history, which do not seriously contest the
general arc of his script.
In fact, given that Foucault shares Nietzsche’s preoccupation with
historical inversion, defining an event as “the reversal of a relation of
forces [un rapport de forces qui s’inverse],”43 his histories often require
that any geographic or social variability be encased within this general historical framework. Although they each have their own unique
patterns and internal configurations, many of his books are organized
around deep structural reversals. These are not properly speaking
dialectical, as Foucault himself was fond of pointing out, but they are
instead discontinuous inversions: what appears one way from our current vantage point is actually turned upside down, or at least seriously
problematized, once we revisit the archive from his perspective. The
historical accounts of these overturnings often constitute, moreover,
anti-morality tales à la Nietzsche by showing that what is generally
considered to be good—if it be the purportedly enlightened liberation of the mad around the turn of the nineteenth century, or modern
102
Theory & Event
forms of so-called humane punishment—is revealed to be inimical in
various ways. Or, on the contrary, what is generally presumed to be
negative—such as sexual repression in the modern age—is shown to
have a productive side: a burgeoning discourse on sex and a “desire to
know.” Although Foucault frequently avoids explicit normative statements in favor of purportedly descriptive claims, it is rarely difficult
to discern in his work a resolute struggle against the slavish morality
of common sense. His histories are fundamentally driven by a revaluation of values.44
His moral diagnoses do not generally lead, however, to political
remedies in the sense of collective projects that seek to transform the
socio-economic order and its system of values.45 Foucault regularly
castigated projects of revolutionary change, particularly in his later
work, and his unquestioned axiology led him to classify them as “totalizing” (which is normatively understood as “bad”). Take, for example,
his definition of genealogy in a well-known 1984 essay on Kant. He
explains that it is a form of critique that “will separate out, from the
contingency that has made us what we are, the possibility of no longer
being, doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think.”46 By way of clarification, he hastily adds:
The historical ontology of ourselves must turn away from all projects that claim to be global and radical. In fact, we know from
experience that the claim to escape from the system of contemporary reality so as to provide the overall programs for another
society, another way of thinking, another culture, another vision
of the world, has actually led only to the replication of the most
dangerous traditions.47
This purported threat of the gulag, which is reaffirmed elsewhere (such
as in his praise of the reactionary writings of the revisionist historian
François Furet and of the nouveau philosophe André Glucksmann), is
what made him skeptical of anti-capitalist movements.48 It is as if there
was a necessary and inevitable historical link—that is assumed rather
than rigorously demonstrated—between mass political mobilizations
on the hard left and violent repression on a grand scale, in part through
a tendency to collapse the multidimensional history of anti-capitalist
revolutionary experiments into a one-dimensional narrative based on
a particular depiction of Stalinism (while also generally ignoring the
global violence of capitalist exploitation and its state orchestrated wars
of repression).49
Some readers of Foucault might point to his unique interest in
the Iranian Revolution in 1978 and 1979 as a potential exception to
this tendency in his work. After all, this was one of the key moments
in his career when he engaged extensively with current events and
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
103
publicly supported a revolutionary movement. While this is certainly
true, it is important to clarify the reasons for this support. To begin
with, it is noteworthy that Foucault showed more interest in a distant
revolution in “the East” than in the Algerian Revolution at his French
doorstep and all of the anti-colonial revolutionary struggles against
imperial France that were taking place during his lifetime. Secondly,
this penchant for exoticism seamlessly merged with a unique form of
orientalism, which is perhaps most visible in his temporal reading of
geography. The promise of Iran was that it held within it a future that
Europe never had, which was actually a future past in the sense that it
showed a remarkable proximity to the past of Europe. There is thus
a form of revolutionary atavism in his interpretation of Iran: he saw
the political spirituality of Europe’s past being reborn in the East, in a
future the West had never had because of modernization (and, presumably, the tragic consequences of its revolutions). It is not the least bit
surprising, then, to see Foucault praising François Furet’s anti-Marxist
Penser la revolution and drawing on it to frame his understanding of
Iran, all the while ignoring the material history of international relations and the role of the Euro-American imperial powers in destroying
Iranian democracy in 1953 and propping up the pro-business, authoritarian government that was overthrown in 1979.50 As a matter of fact,
what interested Foucault in the Iranian Revolution was precisely the
way in which, according to him, it broke with two key aspects of the
Marxist model of revolution (which he claimed was in crisis): class
conflict and a revolutionary vanguard.51 The Iranian Revolution was a
way of resuscitating a political spirituality of the past and reinventing
every facet of existence in order to devise a future with the potential of
leaping beyond the tragic limitations of European modernization and
Marxist class struggle.
The distance that Foucault maintained from anti-capitalist revolutionary politics thus has a lot to do, of course, with his relationship to
Marxism. Although this would require an independent study, Michael
S. Christofferson has provided a useful heuristic outline. Bracketing
his relatively brief and unorthodox adherence to the communist party
during his student years (which Foucault would later describe as a
form of “Nietzschean” communism52), Christofferson maintains that
Foucault generally rejected Marxist analysis prior to 1968 and was only
briefly inclined to engage with it seriously in the early 1970s, before
openly repudiating it once again as of 1975–1976.53 It is in this context
that his relationship to Glucksmann needs to be understood, because
their political evolution followed a similar path, as their “anti-totalitarian” critique of communism bled into an increasing interest in liberalism. In the case of Foucault, which Michael C. Behrent has convincingly situated within an overall shift in certain sectors of the French
intelligentsia, this took the form of a fascination with economic liber-
104
Theory & Event
alism due to its critique of the state and its insistence on freedom.54 In
his analysis of neoliberalism in his lectures on biopolitics in 1978–1979,
Foucault goes so far as to claim that, in contrast to the model of a disciplinary and repressive society, neoliberalism brings with it the idea of
“a society in which there is an optimization of systems of difference, in
which the field is left open to fluctuating processes, in which minority
individuals and practices are tolerated.”55 Moreover, it is true that
Foucault was much less concerned with analyzing economic exploitation, class warfare and revolutionary struggle than providing diagnoses of forms of social marginalization and exclusion.56 Edward Said
has convincingly argued that his microphysics of power, which not
only ignores the macrophysics of global class warfare but has at times
sought to banish it to the dustbin of history,57 is linked to his political
defeatism: “Foucault takes a curiously passive and sterile view not so
much of the uses of power, but of how and why power is gained, used,
and held onto. This is the most dangerous consequence of his disagreement with Marxism, and its result is the least convincing aspect
of his work. Even if one fully agrees with his view [...], the notions of
class struggle and of class itself cannot therefore be reduced—along
with the forcible taking of state power, economic domination, imperialist war, dependency relationships, resistances to power—to the
status of superannuated nineteenth-century conceptions of political
economy.”58 Foucault’s unwillingness to seriously engage with the
question of global class warfare and Western imperialism is, moreover,
one of the reasons why the US National Security State identified him
as an asset.59
In a 1978 interview, Foucault defined himself, in opposition to
those involved in student and worker protests, as a non-active rebel
invested in “silence” and “total abstention.”60 Although he obviously
enjoyed indulging in autobiographical fictions, his direct political
involvement in strong leftist organizing was minor and intermittent
when compared to figures like Jean-Paul Sartre, Daniel Guérin and
Frantz Fanon. While it is true that the events of 1968 had a radicalizing
effect on him, his shift to the hard left in their wake would not last, and
as Didier Eribon has convincingly argued:
One should refrain, above all, from projecting the image of a later
Foucault onto the Foucault of that period [prior to 1968]. His colleagues from that time are in general agreement in placing him
“more to the left,” although this description is not unanimous.
They describe him primarily as someone who was relatively distant from any militant involvement [tout engagement militant],
despite his very real interest in politics. They were all very surprised, to put it mildly, by his swing to the far left and by the radical positions he took in the 1970s. “I never managed to believe
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
105
it really,” says Francine Pariente, who was his assistant for four
years, from 1962 to 1966. One thing is certain: there was nothing to
make them suspect that he would evolve in this direction.61
Moreover, after this moment of apparent radicalization, he returned
to a more distant and dismissive attitude toward political organizing
later in the 1970s. For instance, in the same interview from 1978 quoted
above, he criticized the women’s liberation and gay liberation movements for being organized around sexual categories and demanding
“subordination to specific ideals and objectives.”62 Describing these
movements as forming private and exclusionary clubs, he drew the
following conclusion: “True liberation means knowing oneself [La
véritable libération signifie se connaître soi-même] and can often not be
realized by the intermediary of a group, whichever one it may be.”63
Given this individualist, libertarian tenor of his work, his genealogical anti-morality tales are more keyed to personal, local and partial
modifications than to systemic political changes, particularly those
that are revolutionary and anti-capitalist.64 Care of self, we might say,
generally superseded care of society, at the risk of developing parasitic practices that could only work within given systems rather than
radically reconfigure them. Indeed, he preferred the interstitial work
of the “specific intellectual” who intermittently drew on his particular
areas of expertise to intercede in public debate (rather than being consistently dedicated to collective political organizing).65 In this sense,
he follows Nietzsche in understanding genealogy as a moral project
of historical introspection. Although it might, and often does, contain
certain political elements in its diagnoses, it is generally opposed to—
and normatively codes as “bad”—the systemic remedy of collective
social action. He flatly claimed in a late interview: “I would more or
less agree with the idea that in fact what interests me is much more
morals than politics or, in any case, politics as an ethics.”66
Counter-History and the Politicization of Values
Let us be clear about the stakes of this critical reassessment of
Foucault’s attempt to provide a genealogy of non-originary genealogy
by studying its supposed emergence in Nietzsche. It is not simply a
matter of claiming that Foucault put forth a faulty interpretation of the
author of On Genealogy of Morality. It is that he raised a fundamentally
important question concerning the writing of history by underscoring
the need to develop narratives that are not beholden to origin discourse. In doing so, however, his own essay nonetheless succumbs to
this very discourse, to such an extent in fact that he constructs an ideal
signification devoid of material reality, an Ursprung in his vocabulary
(not Nietzsche’s). This does not mean, then, that he simply provided
106
Theory & Event
a bad commentary subject to scholarly repudiation, but that what he
does with Nietzsche merits close critical scrutiny precisely because it
raises crucial problems that it is unable to solve within the parameters
of genealogy.67
This is one of the reasons why it is important to tease out various dimensions in his work rather than evaluating it en bloc based
on the moral imperative of being for or against Foucault. This type of
variegated hermeneutics situates itself beyond moral binaries and simplistic filial arrangements, and it also foregrounds the dynamic complexity of bodies of work. It is worth noting in this regard that one
of the motivating factors for calling into question the very idea of an
origin is Foucault’s powerful dismantling of the “natural objects” of
history. Rather than understanding history itself as a description of
the changes undergone by particular elements over time, he inverts
the relation between being and time in order to demonstrate that the
beings of the world are in fact the result of time rather than the governing agents of particular histories. This allows him to develop a form
of intransitive history, or a history without objects, a history of actions
and practices that produce “beings,” which are themselves only the
precarious, and ultimately transitory results of temporal processes.
If history is not undergirded by natural objects, it makes perfect
sense that this would call into question the existence of essentialist origins. Foucault’s critique of the metahistorical deployment of ideal significations is crucially important in this regard, as well as his analysis of
history as a site of struggle à la Nietzsche. Understanding the writing
of history as inscribed within a broad series of complex power relations lifts the epistemological veil that often presents history as simply
a descriptive and verifiable account of the objective nature of reality.
Moreover, it draws attention to the ways in which archives themselves
are always already structured by value judgments and culturally dominant narratives. There are thus certain aspects of Foucault’s genealogical project, coming out of Nietzsche, that merit being worked through,
extended and developed.
The persistence of origins in Foucault’s own discourse, however,
points to the failings and limitations of genealogy more generally. By
largely compressing history into its chronological dimension, relying
on relatively homogenous geographic units of analysis whose histories
remain uninterrogated, and generally compressing the multi-agential force fields of social stratification, Foucault tends to remain, like
Nietzsche, within the chronological order of history, which downplays
the complex geographic and social dimensions of historical developments (as well as the multiplicity of agencies operative in any conjuncture). This is precisely what allows for his well-known oracular
pronouncements on the birth or demise of particular historical phenomena.
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
107
If these other dimensions are taken into account, then the very
opposition between continuity and discontinuity, epoch and event,
is rendered inoperative. Unless one compresses and homogenizes—
at least minimally—the geographic and social axes of history, it is
not possible to establish a temporal trajectory that is either broken at
points or uninterrupted. The streamlined logic of descent falls apart, as
well as the bi-dimensional logic of structural inversion, and the very
possibility of a singular commencement crumbles with them. This is
ultimately why it was important to diligently track Foucault’s moves
in his attempt to document an originary moment in the materiality
of Nietzsche’s text. In undertaking a genealogy of the origin of genealogy without origins, Foucault was endeavoring to provide a historical account of his own operative methodology, which he would return
to years later in his essays on Kant and the Enlightenment. In order
to do so, however, he ends up constructing an originary symptom
by subsuming the specificity of Nietzsche’s text into his governing
morality of genealogy and reading him as someone who is opposed to
world-historical totalities (even though Nietzsche provides his reader
with some of the most grandiose and totalizing narratives imaginable). Foucault thereby both overshoots and undershoots his target,
missing—or ignoring—both the grand historical claims made by
Nietzsche and the microscopic differences and contingences that do
not fit within Foucault’s own conceptual and normative framework.
He also reads Nietzsche in a purely hagiographic light, indulging in
the hero history so characteristic of the morality of genealogy, where
the true champions, who are often the vanquished or excluded, can
do no wrong, even if they promote—like Nietzsche—an aristocratic
history of the master race.68 This latter point is particularly important
because Foucault’s unwillingness to criticize Nietzsche’s politics (the
same could be said of Kant’s) reveals important aspects of his own
political orientation, as well as the historical role of genealogy in political struggles.69
Taking into consideration the three dimensions of history requires
a complex cartographic and topographic approach that recognizes that
at each supposed moment in time, there is a plurality of occurrences
across space and society. The notion of a phase is particularly helpful
for engaging with history across these vectors of analysis. Unlike the
concepts of epoch or time period, a phase is always uniquely distributed across time, space and society. It is a dynamic formation that can
spread and recede within and across these dimensions. It develops
in unique foyers, which are not necessarily sequential, contiguous or
even connected. A phase forms a three-dimensional constellation that
morphs over time as a metastatic transformation. Unlike an event or an
originary moment of rupture, a historical metastasis changes in all
three dimensions of history. This does not mean that it cannot intro-
108
Theory & Event
duce a deep reconfiguration, only that this change will inevitably vary
across chronology, geography and social practice.
The variegated mapping of phases and historical metastasis is
an integral part of counter-history. This is not a form of oppositional
chronicle that seeks to simply invert given stories, nor is it an alternative narrative that attempts to construct novel scripts based on the
same basic phenomena. Counter-history reworks the deep structural
givens of historical practice by proposing a different historical order,
by which I mean a distinctive practical mode of intelligibility of history. In this regard, it labors against the geo-cultural parameters and
rampant social homogenization of many established modes of historical writing. It advances a multidimensional account of temporality,
denaturalizes space in order to develop radical geographies attentive
to a multiplicity of overlapping and intersecting spaces, and it puts
forth a multi-agential account of social struggles that significantly
parts ways with the traditional binaries of social theory.70 Moreover,
counter-history contests the implicit ontological parameters that structure the very distinction between the human and social sciences, on the
one hand, and the natural sciences on the other. Not unlike Nietzsche
(but very unlike Foucault), it is critical of the truncated chronology of
history, which is based on an anthropocentric time-scale and the metaphysical assumption of a relatively clear demarcation between human
beings and nature, which gives birth to static ontologies.71
If there are no origins in history, it is because there are complex
force fields of agencies distributed across multiple dimensions. We
might occasionally decide to use the vocabulary of “beginning” and
“end” as useful shorthand for indexing a complex metastatic transformation whose details we do not want to take the time to rehearse.
However, history does not ultimately abide by the logic of streamlined
trajectories, if they be paths of progress, decline, dialectical overturning
or Nietzschean inversion. History is not genealogy in the sense that it
does not follow a single line of descent—even if it is characterized by
internal tensions, reversals, regressions or returns of the repressed—
and it knows no strict commencements or conclusions. As long as one
attempts to avoid origins within genealogy, which Nietzsche defined
in many ways as the historical study of origins,72 one remains locked
within a specific chronological order founded on discreet beginnings
that compress the spatial and social dimensions of history (which is
precisely what allows for the spinning of moral yarns opposing the
good and the bad).
Counter-history works against grand historical morality or
anti-morality tales by resituating values and the battle over them within
a multi-agential force field and a multidimensional history. Nietzsche
and Foucault have powerfully demonstrated that histories are always
value-laden and bound up with power struggles, but they have not
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
109
provided us with a detailed, reflexive account regarding the historical
constitution of the values operative in their own histories. Instead, they
have developed genealogies that rely on values that largely stand outside of and frame their critical gaze, thereby constituting the uncritical
governing normative framework that is used to judge history. Whereas
Nietzsche often appeals to the naturalized values of master morality,
Foucault frequently indulges in an implicit—but no less obvious—
promotion of the transgressive, the disruptive, the marginalized, the
heterogeneous, the accidental, and so forth. In both cases, the morality
guiding genealogy produces a transcendental value history where the
values of genealogy—if it be those of master morality or those of differential contingencies—are not subjected to historical critique precisely because they frame and determine it as its very conditions of
possibility. It is under a gaze structured by these values that history
itself is written as wirkliche Historie, either to propose a revaluation of
the values that have subverted the natural order, or to unearth and
privilege the disruptive singularities that have been suppressed by the
dominant moral narratives. The genealogy of morality depends upon
the governing morality of genealogy.
Counter-history definitively parts ways with transcendental value
history and the implicit moralism that structures so much intellectual
work from behind the scenes. It counters the moralization of history by
developing a multidimensional account that is recalcitrant to categorical moral judgments from a single vantage point within a system of
values that is at least partially de-historicized. In other words, it resituates all values within ongoing collective struggles. Grand narratives
of historical progress, like those of decline, require such a moralizing
point of view and extra-historical reference points insofar as they presume that an extremely complex force field of agencies, distributed
across the three dimensions of history, can be reduced to simple narratives of evolution or devolution based on fixed values (which is not
to say that one cannot, in circumscribed fields of analysis, appeal to
immanent values and speak of advances and retreats in relation to
them). The same is true for other similar proclamations founded on
a single, unchanging logic of dialectics or genealogical inversion that
purports to sum up the totality of historical dynamics, or an expansive
subset thereof. One does not have to look far to find Geist lingering in
these proclamations insofar as the material complexities of the past can
only be reduced to a single internal logic if they are subjected to the
geistig—intellectual and spiritual—sieve of history, which filters out
anything that does not conform to its dictates.
In my book, Counter-History of the Present, for example, one chapter
provides an intransitive counter-history of democracy that begins by
rejecting the widespread contemporary normative blackmail according
to which one can only speak of democracy if one is favorable toward
110
Theory & Event
it. Far from simply being against democracy, however, I demonstrate
how the implicit normative framework undergirding this predominant attitude is at once historically conditioned and obfuscating. It
is in this context that I outline four phases of an intransitive history
of “democracy” in the so-called Western world, while simultaneously
revealing the ways in which this problematic geo-cultural unit is a historical construct bound up with the contemporary history of democracy and its retroactive postulation of a Greek origin.73 I show how,
in ancient Athens, there was a practice of democracy that had little
or nothing to do with modern instantiations, and that this practice
was defined by the rule of an infinitesimal minority of the population
(approximately 2.4%). I also demonstrate how the practice largely disappeared between the end of antiquity and the modern age, a phase
during which the term democracy was generally used to refer to the
ancients. When it did come back into use in order to depict a contemporaneous practice, it was widely employed as a term of denigration
akin to “mob rule.” It is in this light that I examine the predominant
normative framing operative in the Enlightenment by showing how
the major so-called democratic thinkers at the time—including the
purported Founding Fathers—were rabidly opposed to democracy. It
was only in the middle third of the nineteenth century that the term
slowly came to be used in a more positive sense in certain sectors,
but this was largely to refer to the modern republics that had been
founded in the United States, France and elsewhere. The structure of
these republics, which were oligarchic, did not change along with their
name, however. In other words, they were repackaged as democracies as this term was given its contemporary positive valuation, and
this normative shift was part of the modern Euro-American political
project of disguising the elite rule of oligarchic, capitalist republics
invested in colonialism and the slave trade as progressive forms of
democratic integration in which the state increasingly serves the needs
of “the people.” Far from a transcendental value history or a genealogical account of structural inversions in which the author is implicitly or
explicitly aligned with one side of a moral history, this counter-history
of democracy teases out very specific and complex immanent systems
of value that are enmeshed in collective political struggles and cannot
be encased within a single over-arching moralizing tale (because the
values themselves change over time), while also insisting on the fact that
these phases operate in multi-agential force fields unequally distributed across time, space and society.
This does not mean that counter-history shuns value judgments.
On the contrary, it rejects transcendental value history by subjecting
the valuations of genealogy to historical critique, and it shuns covert
methodological moralism in favor of explicit pragmatic interventions
into multi-agential fields of values. In other words, it follows gene-
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
111
alogy in re-situating values in the history of acts of valuation and the
power struggles over them, but it rejects the naturalization or quasi-naturalization of values at work in binary moral histories. This is
precisely how methodological moralism operates: it determines, from
behind the scenes, the practical coordinates of one’s work by making
it subservient to a series of unquestioned preferences that are largely
conditioned by social forces operative in one’s conjuncture.74 Counterhistory, by contrast, subjects these proclivities to socio-historical and
normative critique, thereby reflexively revealing their material histories and identifying interstices and bracing points that could be used
to transform them.
Using these terms heuristically, counter-history allows us to distinguish between transcendent, immanent and interventionist values.
Transcendent values are those that purport to stand above the flow of
time and determine it as if from the outside, and they are the implicit
or explicit reference points for transcendental value histories, meaning
histories determined by a value system that functions as their unquestioned condition of possibility. The radical historicism of counter-history rejects their existence in the name of recognizing that all values
are immanent in the sense that they have been produced over time
by particular collectivities. Their sedimentation in social systems
often produces the illusion that they are transcendent and unchangeable, but one of the roles of counter-history is precisely to resituate
them in sociohistorical fields of struggle, and hence to politicize them.
For counter-history recognizes that immanent values are the result
of repeated interventions on the part of different forms of agency.
Rejecting, then, the abstract conceptual opposition between universalism and relativism, counter-history demonstrates that values do not
stand above history, nor are they simply arbitrary standards relative
to individuals or homogenous social systems. They are contingent in
the precise sense that they have been produced by certain agencies
and imposed with the force of necessity, but they remain within fields
of struggle and could thereby be transformed. This is precisely why
counter-history explicitly undertakes pragmatic interventions into the
immanent fields of values that it maps, in order to promote or construct interventionist values as part of the very real historical project of
emancipatory politics.
It is here that that the morality of genealogy comes into full relief
against the politics of counter-history. The former tends to subsume the
past within a transcendental system of values, and its critical dimension is oriented toward potentially provoking personal awareness and
individual liberation.75 The latter resituates all values within collective
historical struggles over the construction of common worlds, and it
pragmatically intervenes to contribute to the remaking of values. Such
interventions, far from being a matter of simply knowing oneself or
112
Theory & Event
endeavoring to be or think otherwise, are explicitly dedicated to sociopolitical transformation. More specifically, counter-history historically
emerges from the underside of capitalist and colonial historiographies,
and it intervenes to promote and push forward the immanently constituted values of socioeconomic equality against the onslaught of the
modern capitalist world-system. Whereas the morality of genealogy
is oriented toward local and personal changes, and its political orbit
includes strong opponents of equality like Nietzsche and Kant, the
politics of counter-history is invested in an egalitarian social transformation via a radical reconfiguration of the collective imaginaries that
produce the very values that individuals cultivate or reject.
Conclusion
Genealogy produces bi-dimensional histories of descent that are value-laden and marked by originary events of structural inversion.
Counter-history—while drawing on certain resources like intransitive
history, the rejection of ideal significations, and understanding history as a site of struggle—challenges the historical order operative in
genealogy and proposes an alternative logic that takes into account the
multidimensionality of history and the multiplicity of agencies at work
in any conjuncture. Rather than opposing origins, then, it dismantles
the very framework that renders them possible. Instead of moralizing
history from an individual vantage point, it politicizes it by resituating
values within multi-dimensional force fields that it maps and in which
it intervenes. It does not allow values to float above material histories by becoming the transcendental armature used to judge and script
these histories from the outside in terms of black-and-white narratives
of opposition and inversion. Instead, it develops a complex historical
and sociological geography of immanent values while also mobilizing
interventionist values to collectively reconfigure the normative horizons of a world-in-struggle, in which there is no beginning to values,
and there is no end to politics. Counter-history thereby responds to the
moralization of genealogy with the politicization of values.
Notes
1. Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, ed. Keith Ansell-Pearson,
trans. Carol Diethe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 34.
2. Ibid., 36 (translation slightly modified).
3. Ibid., 54 and 83.
4. Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, ed. Daniel Breazeale, trans. R. J. Hollingdale
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 76–77.
5. In The Anti-Christ (1894), Nietzsche writes: “What is good?—All that heightens the feeling of power, the will to power, power itself in man. What is
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
113
bad?—All that proceeds [stammt] from weakness” (Twilight of the Idols and
The Anti-Christ, trans. R. J Hollingdale [London: Penguin Books, 2003], 127).
6. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, 31–32.
7. The values that structure and motivate his genealogy approximate what he
had called in the second of his Untimely Meditations (1874) the “suprahistorical [überhistorisch],” which he defined as “the powers which lead the eye
away from becoming [Werden] towards that which bestows upon existence
the character of the eternal and stable” (ed. Daniel Breazeale, trans. R.J.
Hollingdale [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1997], 120). It is the
suprahistorical and the unhistorical, by which he means “the art and power
of forgetting,” that constitute “the natural antidotes to the stifling of life by
the historical, by the malady of history” (ibid. 120 and 121, my emphasis).
Foucault simplifies the latter’s argument by ignoring the unhistorical and
claiming that he is purely critical of the supra-historical (see “Nietzsche,
Genealogy, History” in The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow [New York:
Pantheon Books, 1984]).
8. In Beyond Good and Evil, he describes valuations as organically rooted
in specific life instincts: “Behind all logic and its seeming sovereignty
[Selbstherrlichkeit] of movement there also stand valuations [Wertschätzungen],
or more plainly spoken, physiological demands for the preservation of a
certain type of life” (Beyond Good and Evil / On the Genealogy of Morality,
trans. Adrian Del Caro; Vol. 8 of The Complete Works of Friedrich Nietzsche,
eds. Alan D. Schrift and Duncan Large [Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press, 2014], 7, translation slightly modified).
9. Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols and The Anti-Christ, 55.
10. Ibid., 147.
11. See, for instance, On the Genealogy of Morality, 15 and 25.
12. Ibid., 33.
13. Ibid., 19. Nietzsche’s virulent rejection of socialism and his racialization
of an inferior slave class to be suppressed in favor of the natural superiority of masters are inscribed, historically, in the colonial-capitalist project of imperial domination elucidated perhaps most clearly by Domenico
Losurdo in War and Revolution: Rethinking the Twentieth Century, trans.
Gregory Elliott (London: Verso, 2015). “Late Nietzsche’s relentless polemic against socialists,” he writes, “must not lead us to forget the motif of the
‘destruction of the decadent races.’ The philosopher expressed the hope
that the ‘‘barbarism’ of the methods’ used by the conquistadors ‘in the
Congo and wherever,’ and an awareness of the need to maintain ‘mastery of barbarians,’ would end up putting paid to the habitual, hateful
‘European sentimentality’” (179–180).
14. “Beyond Good and Evil… at least this does not mean ‘Beyond Good and
Bad’” (On the Genealogy of Morality, 33).
15. Gilles Deleuze cogently writes that “Genealogy means both the value of
origin [origine] and the origin [origine] of values” (Nietzsche and Philosophy,
trans. Hugh Tomlinson [London: The Athlone Press, 1983], 2).
16. Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, 112.
114
Theory & Event
17. Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” 80 (translation slightly modified).
18. To illustrate the latter case, Foucault refers to Daybreak §62, where
Nietzsche clearly uses Entstehung as a synonym for Ursprung, and §102
where he suggests that the shameful Ursprung of morality is to be found
in the judgment that what harms me is evil, and what is useful is good.
He also cites On the Genealogy of Morality, I, §14 where Nietzsche does not
actually use the term (although he does use it in I, §13 to distinguish the
Ursprung of “good” in slave morality from his own account of it).
19. Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” 77 (translation slightly modified).
20. Ibid., 78 (translation slightly modified).
21. Ibid. (translation slightly modified). Of the five passages that Nietzsche
references from Human, All Too Human, three of them do not actually contain the noun Ursprung, and the two that do use the verb entstehen in close
connection with it. Moreover, in order to illustrate his claim, Foucault
furtively highlights in a footnote that paragraph 92 of Nietzsche’s book
was entitled Ursprung der Gerechtigkeit (Origin of Justice). Although this is
true, it was not one of the examples referenced by Nietzsche himself, so it
does not actually support Foucault’s assertion.
22. Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” 77 (translation slightly modified).
23. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, 5.
24. Ibid., 6.
25. Ibid. (my emphasis).
26. Ibid., 4.
27. Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” 78 (translation slightly modified).
28. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, 5.
29. Ibid., 4. In Beyond Good and Evil §32, Nietzsche provides an interesting
sketch of the history of morality centered on a critique of origins
(Herkünfte). A “premoral period” in which the consequences of actions
were alone important and not their origin (Herkunft), was followed by a
long moral era in which the Herkunft of an activity—rather than its consequences—became the source of its value (35). He then imagines and calls
for a third, extra-moral period in which this Herkunft would be overcome.
30. These discrepancies persist in Foucault’s re-visitation of Nietzsche’s
supposed critique of Ursprünge in the lectures that he presented in Rio
de Janeiro in 1973 (“La vérité et les formes juridiques” in Dits et écrits I,
1954–1975. Paris: Éditions Gallimard, 1994, 1406–1514). For instance, he
references The Gay Science §151 as an example of the fact that religion does
not have an Ursprung, only an Erfindung, even though Nietzsche does not
use the latter term and explains that the origin (Ursprung) of religion is
not a metaphysical need but an error in the interpretation of natural phenomena. He also asserts that Nietzsche argues in §353 that there is no
Ursprung of poetry (only an invention), but the text in question is enti-
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
115
tled “The Origin [Ursprung] of Religions” and focuses on the inventions
(Erfindungen) of their founders, with no discussion of poetry.
31. Power/Knowledge, 85 (translation modified). Earlier in the same lecture,
Foucault provided the following definition: “Let us call, if you will, ‘genealogy,’ the coupling of erudite knowledges [connaissances] and local memories, which allows for the constitution of a historical knowledge [savoir]
of struggles and the use of this knowledge [savoir] in contemporary tactics” (ibid. 83, translation modified).
32. See Logique de l’histoire: pour une analytique des pratiques philosophiques.
Paris: Éditions Hermann, 2010, as well as “Comment penser le temps present? De l’ontologie de l’actualité à l’ontologie sans l’être,” Rue Descartes 75
(2012/13): 114–26 (English translations of the latter and one chapter of
the former are available in Interventions in Contemporary Thought: History,
Politics, Aesthetics [Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2016]).
33. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality, 12.
34. Michel Foucault, Dits et écrits, Vol. 1 1954–1969 (Paris: Éditions Gallimard,
1994), 595.
35. Foucault, Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the Collège de France
1977–1978, ed. Michel Senellart, trans. Graham Burchell (New York:
Picador, 2009), 177 (translation slightly modified). In “What Is Critique?”
he juxtaposes genealogy to genesis by defining the former as an attempt
“to restore the conditions for the appearance of a singularity from multiple determining elements of which it is not the product, but rather the
effect” (The Politics of Truth, ed. Sylvère Lotringer, trans. Lysa Hochroth
and Catherine Porter [Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2007], 64, translation
slightly modified).
36. “Foucault,” Gayatri Spivak writes, “is a brilliant thinker of power-in-spacing, but the awareness of the topographical reinscription of imperialism
does not inform his presuppositions. He is taken in by the restricted version of the West produced by that reinscription and thus helps to consolidate its effects” (Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture, eds. Cary
Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg [Champaign, IL: University of Illinois
Press, 1988], 290). Although it is arguable that she mischaracterizes him
as having an “essentialist agenda” and “methodologically presupposing
a Subject-of-power,” her assessment is nevertheless a welcome critique of
his Eurocentrism (ibid. 285 and 289).
37. See, for instance, his interview on Zen in Dits et écrits, Vol. III 1954–1969
(Paris: Éditions Gallimard, 1994), 618–624, as well as his writings on Iran
in Janet Afary and Kevin B. Anderson, Foucault and the Iranian Revolution:
Gender and the Seductions of Islamism (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 2005).
38. For an important critique of his Eurocentrism—among other things—in
his work on prisons, see Angela Davis, The Angela Y. Davis Reader, ed. Joy
James (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 1998). This issue of the geographic parameters of his work is at the center of a 1976 interview entitled
“Questions à Michel Foucault sur la géographie” (Dits et écrits III, 28–40).
He concludes the conversation by admitting that he has changed his mind
116
Theory & Event
because geography should indeed be at the core of his preoccupations.
Unfortunately, it is not clear that he significantly revised his methodology
in his subsequent writings.
39. Dits et écrits. Vol. IV 1980–1988. Paris: Éditions Gallimard, 1994, 19.
40. Edward Said poignantly writes in this regard: “ignoring the imperial
context of his own theories, Foucault seems actually to represent an irresistible colonizing movement that paradoxically fortifies the prestige of
both the lonely individual scholar and the system that contains him. […]
Foucault, perhaps because of his disenchantment with both the insurrections of the 1960s and the Iranian Revolution, swerves away from politics
entirely” (Culture and Imperialism [New York: Vintage Books, 1993], 278).
41. In one of his rare references to the Algerian War, Foucault disingenuously claimed in a 1980 interview that he experienced it as a foreigner
because he was abroad (he returned to France in 1960, and the war did not
end until 1962). Although he asserted that he was against the war, even
though he had rarely discussed it, he added: “But being abroad and not
living directly what was happening in my country, even if clarity was not
difficult for me, I did not have to show much courage; I did not personally
participate in one of the decisive experiences of modern France” (Dits et
écrits IV, 59). As a side note, he did, however, insist in 1971 on the fact that
almost no one ever discussed the 1961 massacre of Algerians in Paris (see
Dits et écrits I, 1954–1975, 1050).
42. Fanon, The Wretched of the Earth, trans. Richard Philcox (New York: Grove
Press, 2004), 58.
43. Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” 88 (translation slightly modified).
44. This is one of the reasons why he maintained a compelling interest in
counter-cultural activities that resist dominant practices within a given
time period, as is the case, for instance, in his account of the counter-discourse of literature in the modern age of the human sciences. Nevertheless,
his social account of history tends to remain bi-dimensional insofar as it
foregrounds a culturally dominant mode, which defines the nature of the
era and its values, and forms of resistance that beckon toward a potential
age to come, or the return of a past age.
45. “The questions I am trying to ask,” stated Foucault in 1983, “are not determined by a preestablished political outlook and do not tend toward the
realization of some definite political project” (The Foucault Reader, 375).
46. Foucault, The Politics of Truth, 114.
47. Ibid. (translation slightly modified).
48. Foucault flatly asserted in the first volume of the History of Sexuality, in
stark opposition to those who have rigorously documented the class war
opposing the owners of the means of production to the mass of workers,
that “power comes from below; that is, there is no binary and all-encompassing opposition between rulers and ruled at the root of power relations, and serving as a general matrix” (trans. Robert Hurley [New York:
Vintage Books, 1990], 94).
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
117
49. For more nuanced, materialist and well-researched accounts of actually existing socialism and its struggles against capitalism, see Domenico
Losurdo’s War and Revolution and Michael Parenti’s Blackshirts & Reds:
Rational Fascism & the Overthrow of Communism (San Francisco, CA: City
Lights Books, 1997).
50. See Foucault, Dits et écrits III, 745. For a rigorous account of the British
and US imperial intervention in Iran, see William Blum’s Killing Hope:
US Military and CIA Interventions since World War II (London: Zed Books,
2014), 64–72.
51. See Foucault, Dits et écrits III, 623.
52. See Didier Eribon, Michel Foucault, trans. Betsy Wing (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1991), 52.
53. See Michael S. Christofferson, “Foucault and New Philosophy” in Foucault
and Neoliberalism, eds. Daniel Zamora and Michael C. Behrent (Cambridge,
UK: Polity Press, 2016), 6–23. Also see Nicos Poulantzas’ detailed assessment of Foucault’s relationship to Marxism in State, Power, Socialism, trans.
Patrick Camiller (London: Verso, 2014).
54. See Michael C. Behrent, “Liberalism without Humanism” in Foucault and
Neoliberalism.
55. Foucault, The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France, 1978–79, ed.
Michel Senellart, trans. Graham Burchell (New York: Palgrave Macmillan,
2008), 259–260.
56. See Nicos Poulantzas’ trenchant and poignant critique of Foucault, in
which he takes him to task for his reduction of the rich, ongoing history of
Marxism to either a simplistic caricature or to the particular Marxism of
the Third International, as well as for his remarkable underestimation of
classes and class struggle in favor of “a vision which dilutes and scatters
power among innumerable microsituations” (State, Power, Socialism, trans.
Patrick Camiller [London: Verso, 2014], 44). Also see Daniel Zamora,
“Foucault, the Excluded, and the Neoliberal Erosion of the State” in
Foucault and Neoliberalism.
57. See, for instance, Dits et écrits I, 1954–1975, 1674.
58. Edward Said, The World, the Text, and the Critic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1983), 221.
59. See my article “The CIA Reads French Theory: On the Intellectual Labor
of Dismantling the Cultural Left” Los Angeles Review of Books, “The
Philosophical Salon” (February 27, 2017) <http://thephilosophicalsalon.
com/the-cia-reads-french-theory-on-the-intellectual-labor-of-dismantling-the-cultural-left/>.
60. Foucault, Dits et écrits III, 670.
61. Eribon, Michel Foucault, 132, translation modified (entire passages were
oddly left out of the English translation).
62. Ibid., 677. Foucault’s reticence to embrace pragmatic political ideals
comes out in his 1971 debate with Noam Chomsky. In his discussion
with Gilles Deleuze in 1972, he uncharacteristically links certain social
struggles to the revolutionary movement of the proletariat (see Language,
118
Theory & Event
Counter-Memory, Practice: Selected Essays and Interviews, ed. Donald F.
Bouchard [Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1986], 216). In some of
his later interviews, Foucault discusses the need to struggle to establish
homosexual lifestyles, advocating for the invention of new cultural forms
and ethical relations (see for instance Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth. The
Essential Works of Foucault, Vol. I, ed. Paul Rabinow, trans. Robert Hurley
and Others [New York: The New Press, 1997], 137–8, 157–60, 163–4).
63. Foucault, Dits et écrits III, 678.
64. In “What Is Critique?” (1978), Foucault sketches a history of the “critical
attitude” by situating it in opposition to the explosion and multiplication
of all of the arts of governing since the fifteenth century. Whereas the latter
is described as a social and institutional project involving religion, law
and science, the latter is defined as “the movement by which the subject
gives himself the right to question truth on its effects of power and question power on its discourses of truth. Well, then!: critique will be the art of
voluntary insubordination [l’inservitude volontaire], that of reflected intractability [l’indocilité réfléchie]. Critique would essentially insure the desubjugation of the subject in the context of what we could call, in a word, the
politics of truth” (The Politics of Truth, 47). It is not surprising in this regard
that Foucault takes a sympathizer with the doctrine of enlightened despotism, Immanuel Kant, as an exemplar for this form of critique since his
reflections on the Enlightenment—at least according to Foucault—manifested this individualist conception of critique in which one “dared to
know” with public reason but obeyed the dictates of the social order when
it came to the private use of reason in a civil post or office. Indeed, Kant
concluded his reflections on the nature of the Aufklärung by praising the
“enlightened” monarch who—backed up by “a numerous and well-disciplined army”—proclaims: “Argue as much as you will, and about what
you will, only obey!” (On History, ed. Lewis White Beck, trans. Lewis
White Beck, Robert E. Anchor, Emil L. Fackenheim [New York: Macmillan
Publishing Company, 1963], 10).
65. See Language, Counter-Memory, Practice, 205–217, as well as Power/
Knowledge, 109–133, where he candidly states the numerous risks run by
the specific intellectual: “Above all, the risk of being unable to develop
these struggles for lack of a global strategy or outside support; the risk too
of not being followed, or only by very limited groups” (130).
66. The Foucault Reader, 375.
67. “I am tired of people studying him [Nietzsche],” Foucault claims in a 1975
interview, “only to produce the same kind of commentaries that are written on Hegel or Mallarmé. For myself, I prefer to utilize the writers I like.
The only valid tribute to thought such as Nietzsche’s is precisely to use it,
to deform it, to make it groan and protest. And if commentators then say
that I am being faithful or unfaithful to Nietzsche, that is of absolutely no
interest” (Power/Knowledge, 53–54). Let us note in passing that Foucault
often relies on a form of double-edged hermeneutics as a highly questionable defense strategy against those who questioned his findings. On
the one hand, he regularly insists that his work is rigorously documented
and maintains an intimate relationship to the archives that he studies. On
Rockhill | Foucault, Genealogy, Counter-History
119
the other hand, as soon as there are discrepancies between his claims and
the archive, he retorts that he wants his books to function as iconoclastic
bombs that ignore scholarly conventions. On his own terms, then, there is
little or no space for material refutation: either he is right, or he does not
care about being right.
68. Foucault’s gloss on Nietzsche’s racial classifications is somewhat misleading insofar as he claims that the traits that he attempts to identify in his
“analysis of Herkunft […] are not the exclusive generic characteristics of
an individual, a sentiment, or an idea, which permit us to qualify them as
‘Greek’ or ‘English’; rather, it seeks the subtle, singular, and subindividual
marks that might possibly intersect in them to form a network that is difficult to unravel” (The Foucault Reader, 81).
69. On this issue, see Domenico Losurdo’s astute critique of Nietzsche and—
by extension—Foucault as theorists of “aristocratic radicalism” whose
“identification of reason with domination” serves as a bulwark against
the rational and scientific critique of class hierarchies, which are thereby
naturalized: “Those (one thinks particularly of Michel Foucault) who have
discovered a more radical critique of domination in Nietzsche than Marx,
who supposedly stopped half-way, as demonstrated by his genuflection
to reason and science, argue in mistaken and misleading fashion. In reality, in the theorist of aristocratic radicalism [Nietzsche], the non-transcendability of conflict through reason ultimately refers to the irreparable
naturalistic rift splitting the human community into masters and slaves,
successes and failures” (Class Struggle: A Political and Philosophical History,
trans. Gregory Elliott [New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2016], 69).
70. I have developed a number of these themes in Radical History & the Politics
of Art (New York: Columbia University Press, 2014).
71. Foucault’s “ontology of ourselves” is an account of how the “being” of
certain Westerners has been modulated by relatively recent historical
developments, rather than an attempt to plumb the temporal depths of
the ontological constitution of “homo sapiens.” In other words, his ontology of historical beings is far from being a historical ontology of those very
beings. On this topic, see my debate with Ádám Takács at the Critical
Theory Workshop / Atelier de Théorie Critique 2016: <https://www.
youtube.com/watch?v=rsoy-TVXWXU>.
72. In Human, All Too Human, Nietzsche describes his “moral dissecting table”
by claiming that “here there rules that science which asks after the origin [Ursprung] and history [Geschichte] of the so-called moral sensations”
(trans. R. J. Hollingdale [Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989],
32).
73. Although I will avoid the repetition of scare quotes in what follows, it
goes without saying that, for counter-history, there are no fixed and natural objects behind history, such as “democracy,” “the West,” etc.
74. On this point, see my essay entitled “Is Difference a Value in Itself?
Critique of a Metaphilosophical Axiology” in Interventions, 117–138.
75. There are at least a few passing references to a “collective” critical attitude
in Foucault’s variegated corpus (see, for instance, The Politics of Truth, 67).