Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2019
…
6 pages
1 file
The defining character of the mental is first person experience, which is simultaneously utterly familiar and deeply mysterious. The core of the mystery is consciousness, which is, for each of us, the centre of our understanding of the world. In this talk I address some of the difficulties of attempting to make sense of this intractable problem, and suggest that it may be illuminated when viewed through the lens of neuroepistemology.
Synthesis Philosophica, 2008
This paper proposes that the ‘problem of consciousness’, in its most popular formulation, is based upon a misinterpretation of the structure of experience. A contrast between my subjective perspective (A) and the shared world in which I take up that perspective (B) is part of my experience. However, descriptions of experience upon which the problem of consciousness is founded tend to emphasise only the former, remaining strangely oblivious to the fact that experience involves a sense of belonging to a world in which one occupies a contingent subjective perspective. The next step in formulating the problem is to muse over how this abstraction (A) can be integrated into the scientifically described world (C). I argue that the scientifically described world itself takes for granted the experientially constituted sense of a shared reality. Hence the problem of consciousness involves abstracting A from B, denying B and then trying to insert A into C, when C itself presupposes B. The problem in this form is symptomatic of serious phenomenological confusion. No wonder then that consciousness remains a mystery.
2019
Philosophers have usually dealt with the problem of consciousness but, in the last decades, neurobiologists have undertaken the daunting task to address it scientifically. In particular, to answer how the brain produces consciousness. Here we question whether it actually does so, seeking to articulate the precise relation between neural activity and subjective experience. There is no doubt that they are intimately related. However, we argue that the thesis of parallelism (that consciousness tells no more than what is going on in the brain, but only in a different language), rather than enunciating an empirical fact, betrays a philosophical commitment. In addition, such equivalence between mental and cerebral states can be shown to lead to self-contradictions (the brain produces the world with itself in it; the brain, as an object in conscious experience, gives rise to conscious experience). Our approach endorses an integration of philosophical and scientific efforts where the scient...
Dualist and Reductionist theories of mind disagree about whether or not consciousness can be reduced to a state of or function of the brain. They assume, however, that the contents of consciousness are separate from the external physical world as-perceived. According to the present paper this assumption has no foundation either in everyday experience or in science. Drawing on evidence for perceptual projection in both interoceptive and exteroceptive sense modalities, the case is made that the physical world as-perceived is a construct of perceptual processing and, therefore, part of the contents of consciousness. A finding which requires a Reflexive rather than a Dualist or Reductionist model of how consciousness relates to the brain and the physical world. The physical world as-perceived may, in turn be thought of as a biologically useful model of the world as described by physics. Redrawing the boundaries of consciousness to include the physical world as-perceived undermines the conventional separation of the 'mental' from the physical', and with it the very foundation of the Dualist-Reductionist debate. The alternative Reflexive model departs radically from current conventions, with consequences for many aspects of consciousness theory and research. Some of the consequences which bear on the internal consistency and intuitive plausibility of the model are explored, e.g. the causal sequence in perception, representationalism, a suggested resolution of the Realism versus Idealism debate, and the way manifest differences between physical events as-perceived and other conscious events (images, dreams, etc.) are to be construed.
Bioethics, 1990
Psychology, 1:3, 1988. Fuller arguments on the basic position are to be found there but no hint of the moral implications.
This paper presents an enquiry into the essential nature of phenomenal consciousness and its relation to the neural correlates of consciousness in the brain (NCCs). It first combines critical accounts of current ideas about the nature of NCCs themselves and about what constitutes phenomenal consciousness. This is followed by an examination of how these two may be related with a particular focus on pointing out the defects in the currently most popular hypothesis in this field namely the Identity Theory. The conclusion is that we need a better theory.
In A.E. Cavanna, A. Nani, H. Blumenfeld & S. Laureys (Eds) The Neuroimaging of Consciousness, 2013
This chapter reviews some of the central theoretical challenges confronting the search for the brain basis of consciousness and develops a conceptual framework for tackling these challenges. At the heart of the search for the neural basis of consciousness is the notion of a neural correlate of consciousness. Identifying the neural correlates of consciousness requires that we acknowledge the various aspects of consciousness, for each of the aspects of consciousness raises its own set of methodological challenges. We examine the question of whether an account of the neural correlates of consciousness can be used to ascribe consciousness to creatures that lack the capacity to report their experiences, and we ask whether it is possible to go beyond the neural correlates of consciousness by providing neurally-based explanations of consciousness.
It is commonplace for both philosophers and cognitive scientists to express their allegiance to the “unity of consciousness”. This is the claim that a subject’s phenomenal consciousness, at any one moment in time, is a single thing. This view has had a major influence on computational theories of consciousness. In particular, what we call single-track theories dominate the literature, theories which contend that our conscious experience is the result of a single consciousness-making process or mechanism in the brain. We argue that the orthodox view is quite wrong: phenomenal experience is not a unity, in the sense of being a single thing at each instant. It is a multiplicity, an aggregate of phenomenal elements, each of which is the product of a distinct consciousness-making mechanism in the brain. Consequently, cognitive science is in need of a multi-track theory of consciousness; a computational model that acknowledges both the manifold nature of experience, and its distributed neural basis.
Advances in Cognitive Psychology, 2018
In view of the unresolved mind-brain problem, we examine a number of prototypical research attitudes regarding the question, how the mental and the neuronal realms are related to each other, both functionally and ontologically. By discussing neurophilosophical and neuropsychological positions, the mind-brain problem can be recast in terms of a structural relation between methodological and content-related aspects. Although this reformulation does not immediately lead to a solution, it draws attention to the necessity of searching for a new way of balancing separating and integrating elements regarding content as well as method. As a relatively unknown alternative in this context we investigate an approach by the philosopher Rudolf Steiner. It comprises a firstperson method, along with the theoretical background of what has come to be known as the mirror metaphor-an analogy for the brain as a necessary but not a sufficient basis for mental activity. Through a first-person study, this approach is scrutinized using volitionally controlled perceptual reversals. The results allow for a phenomenological distinction of processual phases which can be summarized as engaging and disengaging forms of mental activity. Finally, we initiate a discussion in view of related philosophical concepts and give an outlook on the next possible research steps.
The sequence of topics in this BBS reply roughly follows that of the target article. The latter focused largely on experimental studies of how consciousness relates to human information processing, tracing their relation from input through to output. The discussion of the implications of the findings both for cognitive psychology and philosophy of mind was relatively brief. The commentaries reverse this emphasis, and so, correspondingly, does the reply. Sections 1.1 to 1.9 begin with details of the empirical findings (Underwood, Inhoff, Mangan, Van Gulick, Shevrin, Dagenbach, Spiegel, Rey, Lloyd, Wagstaff, Block, Carlson, Mandler, Libet, and Keane). Sections 2 & 3 deal with general comments about the laboratory-based approach of the review (Kinsbourne, Reznick & Zelazo, Bowers, and Foulkes) and the status of subjective reports (Gregson, Economos, Gray, and Lloyd). Sections 4 to 6 discuss the nature of "conscious processing," beginning with differences between conscious and nonconscious processing in section 4 (Wilson, Bowers, Carlson, Block, and Inhoff), followed by a detailed treatment of the relation of consciousness to focal-attentive processing in sections 5.1 to 5.4 (Mandler, Baars, Carlson, Rey, Mangan, Klein, Van Gulick, and Block) and a further discussion of what is meant by a "conscious process" in section 6 (Van Gulick, Dretske). Sections 7 to 9, deal with broad philosophical and theoretical implications, starting (in 7.1 to 7.3) with the mistaken assumption (of Baars, Block, Lloyd, Mangan, Van Gulick, Kinsbourne, Corteen, Rey, and Hardcastle) that I support epiphenomenalism, and the problems of dualist-interactionism (MacKay, and Mangan) and reductionism (Sloman, Hardcastle, Rey, and Stanovich). Section 8 gives a fuller account of "first-person" vs "third-person" perspectives (Stanovich, Schaeken & d'Ywalle, Shevrin and Gardiner), and section 9, of "complementarity." 9.1 replaces the privileged status of "third-person" accounts with a more balanced view of the two perspectives (Lloyd) and 9.2 moves on to a proposed resolution of the paradoxes surrounding the causal interactions of consciousness and the brain (Libet). A "complementary" account is given of the relation of consciousness to its neural correlates in 9.3 (Economos, Koch & Crick, Van Gulick, and Navon) and, finally, of the role of consciousness in evolution in 9.4 (Mangan, Corteen, Klein, editorial, andSchaeken & d'Ywalle).
International Journal of Multidisciplinary, 2023
Failure Pedagogies: Learning and Unlearning What it Means to Fail, 2020
XIX Jornadas de Patrimonio Cultural de la Región de Murcia [celebradas en] Cartagena, Alhama de Murcia, La Unión y Murcia, 7 de octubre al 4 de noviembre 2008, 2008
O patrimônio em trânsito e processo: territórios, sujeitos e atuações na sociedade / Elis Regina Barbosa Angelo et al. (org.). Porto, Portugal : Editora Cravo, 2024
Autodesk Autocad versus Autodesk Mechanical, 2020
Tradition Transformed: Tibetan Artists Respond, 2010
Hydrology and Earth System Sciences
2015 18th International Conference on Information Fusion (Fusion), 2015
, in M. Amodio-L. Arcari-R. Pierobon, Segni di coabitazione negli spazi urbani dell’Oriente romano (I-VI sec. d.C.). Atti del Convegno Internazionale (Napoli, 22-23 gennaio 2015), La Parola del Passato. Rivista di Studi Antichi, v. LXXI/1-2, 2016
Filosofia em rede: filosofia em tempos de pandemia, 2021
IEEE Transactions on Magnetics, 2000
International Journal of Cardiology
Advances in Intelligent Systems and Computing, 2012
Journal of management in medicine, 1999
Journal of Combinatorial Designs, 2005