Philosophy of Law: A Very Short Introduction
Very Short Introductions are for anyone wanting a stimulating
and accessible way in to a new subject. They are written by experts, and have
been published in more than 25 languages worldwide.
The series began in 1995, and now represents a wide variety of topics
in history, philosophy, religion, science, and the humanities. Over the next
few years it will grow to a library of around 200 volumes – a Very Short
Introduction to everything from ancient Egypt and Indian philosophy to
conceptual art and cosmology.
Very Short Introductions available now:
ANARCHISM Colin Ward
ANCIENT EGYPT Ian Shaw
ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY
Julia Annas
ANCIENT WARFARE
Harry Sidebottom
THE ANGLO-SAXON AGE
John Blair
ANIMAL RIGHTS David DeGrazia
ARCHAEOLOGY Paul Bahn
ARCHITECTURE
Andrew Ballantyne
ARISTOTLE Jonathan Barnes
ART HISTORY Dana Arnold
ART THEORY Cynthia Freeland
THE HISTORY OF
ASTRONOMY Michael Hoskin
Atheism Julian Baggini
Augustine Henry Chadwick
BARTHES Jonathan Culler
THE BIBLE John Riches
THE BRAIN Michael O’Shea
BRITISH POLITICS
Anthony Wright
Buddha Michael Carrithers
BUDDHISM Damien Keown
BUDDHIST ETHICS Damien Keown
CAPITALISM James Fulcher
THE CELTS Barry Cunliffe
CHOICE THEORY
Michael Allingham
CHRISTIAN ART Beth Williamson
CHRISTIANITY Linda Woodhead
CLASSICS Mary Beard and
John Henderson
CLAUSEWITZ Michael Howard
THE COLD WAR Robert McMahon
CONSCIOUSNESS Susan Blackmore
CONTEMPORARY ART
Julian Stallabrass
Continental Philosophy
Simon Critchley
COSMOLOGY Peter Coles
THE CRUSADES
Christopher Tyerman
CRYPTOGRAPHY
Fred Piper and Sean Murphy
DADA AND SURREALISM
David Hopkins
Darwin Jonathan Howard
THE DEAD SEA SCROLLS
Timothy Lim
Democracy Bernard Crick
DESCARTES Tom Sorell
DESIGN John Heskett
DINOSAURS David Norman
DREAMING J. Allan Hobson
DRUGS Leslie Iversen
THE EARTH Martin Redfern
EGYPTIAN MYTH Geraldine Pinch
EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY
BRITAIN Paul Langford
THE ELEMENTS Philip Ball
EMOTION Dylan Evans
EMPIRE Stephen Howe
ENGELS Terrell Carver
Ethics Simon Blackburn
The European Union
John Pinder
EVOLUTION
Brian and Deborah Charlesworth
FASCISM Kevin Passmore
FEMINISM Margaret Walters
FOSSILS Keith Thomson
FOUCAULT Gary Gutting
THE FRENCH REVOLUTION
William Doyle
FREE WILL Thomas Pink
Freud Anthony Storr
Galileo Stillman Drake
Gandhi Bhikhu Parekh
GLOBAL CATASTROPHES
Bill McGuire
GLOBALIZATION
Manfred Steger
GLOBAL WARMING
Mark Maslin
HABERMAS
James Gordon Finlayson
HEGEL Peter Singer
HEIDEGGER Michael Inwood
HIEROGLYPHS Penelope Wilson
HINDUISM Kim Knott
HISTORY John H. Arnold
THE HISTORY OF TIME
Leofranc Holford-Strevens
HOBBES Richard Tuck
HUMAN EVOLUTION
Bernard Wood
HUME A. J. Ayer
IDEOLOGY Michael Freeden
Indian Philosophy
Sue Hamilton
Intelligence Ian J. Deary
ISLAM Malise Ruthven
JOURNALISM Ian Hargreaves
JUDAISM Norman Solomon
Jung Anthony Stevens
KAFKA Ritchie Robertson
KANT Roger Scruton
KIERKEGAARD Patrick Gardiner
THE KORAN Michael Cook
LINGUISTICS Peter Matthews
LITERARY THEORY
Jonathan Culler
LOCKE John Dunn
LOGIC Graham Priest
MACHIAVELLI Quentin Skinner
THE MARQUIS DE SADE
John Phillips
MARX Peter Singer
MATHEMATICS Timothy Gowers
MEDICAL ETHICS Tony Hope
MEDIEVAL BRITAIN
John Gillingham and Ralph A. Griffiths
MODERN ART David Cottington
MODERN IRELAND Senia Pašeta
MOLECULES Philip Ball
MUSIC Nicholas Cook
Myth Robert A. Segal
NATIONALISM Steven Grosby
NIETZSCHE Michael Tanner
NINETEENTH-CENTURY
BRITAIN Christopher Harvie and
H. C. G. Matthew
NORTHERN IRELAND
Marc Mulholland
PARTICLE PHYSICS Frank Close
paul E. P. Sanders
Philosophy Edward Craig
PHILOSOPHY OF LAW
Raymond Wacks
PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE
Samir Okasha
PLATO Julia Annas
POLITICS Kenneth Minogue
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
David Miller
POSTCOLONIALISM
Robert Young
POSTMODERNISM
Christopher Butler
POSTSTRUCTURALISM
Catherine Belsey
PREHISTORY Chris Gosden
PRESOCRATIC PHILOSOPHY
Catherine Osborne
Psychology Gillian Butler and
Freda McManus
QUANTUM THEORY
John Polkinghorne
THE RENAISSANCE Jerry Brotton
RENAISSANCE ART
Geraldine A. Johnson
ROMAN BRITAIN Peter Salway
ROUSSEAU Robert Wokler
RUSSELL A. C. Grayling
RUSSIAN LITERATURE
Catriona Kelly
THE RUSSIAN REVOLUTION
S. A. Smith
SCHIZOPHRENIA
Chris Frith and Eve Johnstone
SCHOPENHAUER
Christopher Janaway
SHAKESPEARE Germaine Greer
SIKHISM Eleanor Nesbitt
SOCIAL AND CULTURAL
ANTHROPOLOGY
John Monaghan and Peter Just
SOCIALISM Michael Newman
SOCIOLOGY Steve Bruce
Socrates C. C. W. Taylor
THE SPANISH CIVIL WAR
Helen Graham
SPINOZA Roger Scruton
STUART BRITAIN John Morrill
TERRORISM Charles Townshend
THEOLOGY David F. Ford
TRAGEDY Adrian Poole
THE TUDORS John Guy
TWENTIETH-CENTURY
BRITAIN Kenneth O. Morgan
THE VIKINGS Julian D. Richards
Wittgenstein A. C. Grayling
WORLD MUSIC Philip Bohlman
THE WORLD TRADE
ORGANIZATION
Amrita Narlikar
Available soon:
AFRICAN HISTORY
John Parker and Richard Rathbone
ANGLICANISM Mark Chapman
CHAOS Leonard Smith
CITIZENSHIP Richard Bellamy
Derrida Simon Glendinning
EXISTENTIALISM
Thomas Flynn
THE FIRST WORLD WAR
Michael Howard
FUNDAMENTALISM
Malise Ruthven
HIV/AIDS Alan Whiteside
HUMAN MIGRATION
Khalid Koser
INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS
Paul Wilkinson
JAZZ Brian Morton
MANDELA Tom Lodge
NEWTON Robert Iliffe
PHOTOGRAPHY Steve Edwards
PSYCHIATRY Tom Burns
RACISM Ali Rattansi
THE RAJ Denis Judd
ROMAN EMPIRE
Christopher Kelly
For more information visit our web site
www.oup.co.uk/general/vsi/
Raymond Wacks
PHILOSOPHY
OF LAW
A Very Short Introduction
1
3
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford o x 2 6 d p
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide in
Oxford New York
Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi
New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press
in the UK and in certain other countries
Published in the United States
by Oxford University Press Inc., New York
© Raymond Wacks 2006
The moral rights of the author have been asserted
Database right Oxford University Press (maker)
First published as a Very Short Introduction 2006
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,
without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press,
or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate
reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction
outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,
Oxford University Press, at the address above
You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Data available
ISBN 0–19–280691–2
978–0–19–280691–8
1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2
Typeset by RefineCatch Ltd, Bungay, Suffolk
Printed in Great Britain by
Ashford Colour Press Ltd., Gosport, Hampshire
Preface
Brevity is a virtue not normally associated with the law, let alone its
practitioners. Nor does its literature avoid the hefty and the long.
Law books are weighty; and tomes on legal philosophy also incline
to the stout and substantial. Perhaps this is an inescapable vice.
Indeed, my own recent student text, Understanding Jurisprudence:
An Introduction to Legal Theory (Oxford University Press, 2005)
tips the scales at almost a pound-and-a-half, or 600 grams, and
runs to nearly 400 pages.
This series, however, obliges its authors to slim down, to compress,
to abridge – without oversimplifying the subject of the book.
Distilling the essentials of the philosophy of law is, needless to say,
an ambitious, though I hope not an entirely quixotic, task. The
purpose of this slender volume is to provide the general reader with
a lively and accessible guide to the central questions of legal
philosophy in its quest to illuminate the frequently elusive concept
of law, and its relation to the universal questions of justice, rights,
and morality.
I am deeply indebted to Stephen Guest, Professor of Legal
Philosophy at University College, London, who read the complete
manuscript and made several helpful comments and suggestions.
He must not, of course, be indicted as co-defendant for any
misdemeanours I may have committed in these pages.
The staff of Oxford University Press have, as always, been a pleasure
to work with. I am particularly grateful to Marsha Filion, James
Thompson, Deborah Protheroe, and Jane Robson.
For her love, encouragement, and support, I owe a heavy debt of
gratitude to my wife, Penelope, whose word is law.
Contents
List of illustrations x
Introduction
1
2
3
4
5
6
xii
Natural law 1
Legal positivism 18
Law as interpretation 40
Rights and justice
Law and society
52
75
Critical legal theory
References
108
Further reading 111
Index
118
92
List of illustrations
1
Same-sex marriages
offend the principles of
natural law.
2
© William B. Plowman/Getty
Images
2 The Nuremberg trials
convicted the defendants
of ‘crimes against
humanity’.
11
© Hulton Archive/Getty Images
3 Legal segregation and
discrimination reached
their high-water mark
under apartheid.
13
© 2006 TopFoto.co.uk
4 Jeremy Bentham: the
Luther of legal
philosophy?
20
© Ann Ronan Picture Library/
HIP/TopFoto.co.uk
5 Bentham regarded
English judges as partial,
corrupt, and
capricious.
21
© Corporation of London/HIP/
2006 TopFoto.co.uk
6 H. L. A. Hart: the father
of modern legal
positivism.
27
© Joseph Raz
7 Hans Kelsen attempted
the ethical cleansing of
legal theory.
33
© Ullstein Bild
8 For Ronald Dworkin law
is an interpretive process
that protects rights.
41
© UPPA 2006 TopFoto.co.uk
9 Nelson Mandela: icon of
the quest for freedom and
justice.
56
10
Racial prejudice was
particularly violent in the
American South.
57
14
© 2006 TopFoto.co.uk
11
© Ullstein Bild/dpa
The goddess of justice
atop the ‘Old Bailey’ in
London.
60
© Ian Britton/FreeFoto.com
12
Marx and Engels expose
the relationship between
law and economics.
84
John Rawls’s theory of
‘justice as fairness’ is
highly influential.
69
15
The American civil rights
movement secured racial
equality under the
law.
108
Courtesy of the Library of
Congress
© Jane Reed/Harvard University
Gazette
13
Burning at the stake.
Primitive societies,
Durkheim shows,
practised cruel
punishments.
77
© Stapleton Collection/Corbis
The publisher and the author apologize for any errors or omissions
in the above list. If contacted they will be pleased to rectify these at
the earliest opportunity.
Introduction
The law is rarely out of the news. It frequently stimulates
controversy. While lawyers and politicians celebrate the
virtues of the rule of law, reformers lament its shortcomings,
and cynics question its professed equivalence with justice. Yet
all recognize the law as a vehicle for social change. And few
doubt the central role of law in our social, political, moral, and
economic life.
But what is this thing called law? Does it consist of a set of universal
moral principles in accordance with nature (see Chapter 1)? Or is it
simply a collection of largely man-made, valid rules, commands, or
norms (Chapter 2)? Does the law have a specific purpose, such as
the protection of individual rights (Chapter 3), the attainment of
justice (Chapter 4), or economic, political, and sexual equality
(Chapter 6)? Can the law be divorced from its social context
(Chapter 5)?
These are merely some of the questions that lie in wait for anyone
attempting to uncover the meaning of the concept and the function
of law. And they permeate the landscape of the philosophy of law
with its generous frontiers. Charting this vast territory is a daunting
assignment. I can hope, in these pages, to identify only the most
prominent features of its topography. To this end, I have placed the
emphasis upon the leading legal theories, for they provide the
xii
optimum introduction to both classical and contemporary
jurisprudential thought.
This approach is in no way intended to devalue the strategy that
seeks to elucidate the abundant conceptual and definitional
problems that beset much of legal philosophy. Indeed, Chapter 4 is
devoted to two of the most significant and difficult of them: rights
and justice. Other taxing matters confronted by jurists include the
doctrine of precedent (under which courts are themselves bound
to follow decisions of higher tribunals), the question of whether
there is a moral duty to obey the law, the concept of legal
personality, the complexities of causation and liability, and various
theories of punishment. All have a place within legal theory’s large
territory, but, though some are considered indirectly in the
following chapters, they lie beyond the modest objectives of these
pages.
Legal theory is a far cry from legal theatre. Yet even the
sensationalist criminal trials – real or manufactured – that have
xiii
Introduction
Though this book promises a very short introduction to the
philosophy of law, I use this phrase interchangeably with ‘legal
theory’, ‘legal philosophy’, and ‘jurisprudence’. Strictly speaking,
however, ‘jurisprudence’ concerns the theoretical analysis of law at
the highest level of abstraction (e.g. questions about the nature of a
right or a duty, judicial reasoning, etc, and are frequently implied
within substantive legal disciplines). ‘Legal theory’ is often used to
denote theoretical enquiries about law ‘as such’ that extend beyond
the boundaries of law as understood by professional lawyers (e.g.
Marxist approaches to legal domination). The ‘philosophy of law’, as
its name implies, normally proceeds from the standpoint of the
discipline of philosophy (e.g. it attempts to unravel the sort of
problems that might vex moral or political philosophers, such as the
concepts of freedom or authority). But contemporary writers tend
to pay little attention to these nice distinctions; the terrain of
modern legal philosophy contains few fences.
Philosophy of Law
become regular television fare, encapsulate features of the law that
characteristically agitate legal philosophers. They spawn awkward
questions about moral and legal responsibility, the justifications of
punishment, the concept of harm, the judicial function, due
process, and many more. The philosophy of law, it is easy to
demonstrate, is rarely an abstract, impractical pursuit.
No society can properly be understood or explained without a
coherent conception of its law and legal doctrine. The social, moral,
and cultural foundations of the law, and the theories which both
inform and account for them, are no less important than the law’s
‘black letter’. Among the many topics within legal theory’s capacious
confines is that of the definition of law itself. It stands to reason
that, before we can begin to explore the nature of law, we need to
clarify what we mean by this often elusive concept. We can barely
begin our analysis of the law and legal system without some shared
understanding of what it is we are talking about. A constructive first
step is to distinguish between descriptive and normative legal
theory.
Descriptive legal theory seeks to explain what the law is, and why,
and its consequences. Normative legal theories, on the other hand,
are concerned with what the law ought to be. Put differently,
descriptive legal theories are about facts, normative legal theories
are about values. There are three principal types of descriptive legal
theory. First, there is the ‘doctrinal’ approach which propounds a
theory to elucidate a particular legal doctrine. For example,
freedom of expression might be justified by decisions of the courts
on the limits of free speech. Doctrinal legal theory seeks to answer
questions such as ‘can these cases be elucidated by some underlying
theory?’ Secondly, descriptive legal theory may be ‘explanatory’; it
attempts to explain why the law is as it is. Marxist legal theory, for
example, is ‘explanatory’ in this sense, for it offers an account of law
as expressing the interests of the ruling class (see Chapter 5). A
third form of descriptive legal theory concerns the consequences
that are likely to follow from a certain set of legal rules. For example,
xiv
the economic analysis of law (see Chapter 4) might gauge the likely
costs of imposing a regime of strict liability on the manufacturers of
motor vehicles.
Normative legal theory, on the other hand, is concerned with values.
A normative theory may, for instance, seek to establish whether
strict liability of manufacturers of motor vehicles ought to be
adopted in order to protect consumers. Would it be fair or just to do
so? Normative legal theories thus tend inevitably to be associated
with moral or political theories. In pursuing an evaluation of the
law, normative legal theories might be either ‘ideal’ or ‘non-ideal’.
The former relate to what legal rules would create the best legal
system if it were politically achievable. The latter presuppose an
assortment of constraints on the choice of legal rules, such as the
difficulty of enforcing such rules.
It will also be seen (in Chapter 3) how normative and descriptive
theory may be grafted together to yield a hybrid species of legal
philosophy. In Ronald Dworkin’s theory of ‘law as integrity’, for
example, there is an amalgamation of the goals of descriptive
doctrinal theory and normative theory. By claiming that a theory of
law should both ‘fit’ and ‘justify’ the legal materials, his theory of law
as an interpretative concept appears to allow descriptive doctrinal
theory to coalesce with normative theory.
xv
Introduction
But there is no clear-cut distinction between these two categories of
legal philosophy. A normative theory may rely on a descriptive
theory to obtain its purchase. Thus it is hard to sustain the
normative theory of utilitarianism (see Chapter 4) without a
descriptive account of the consequences of the application of a
specific rule. How would a utilitarian know whether rule X causes
the greatest happiness (result Y) without a description of these
consequences? Similarly, a descriptive legal theory may, on the basis
of predictions about the likelihood of success of, say, law reform, put
a brake on the normative legal theory that gave birth to the
improvement.
Philosophy of Law
We live in a troubled, inequitable world. Perhaps it has always been
so. In the face of wickedness and injustice, it is not difficult to
descend into vague oversimplification and rhetoric when reflecting
upon the proper nature and function of the law. Analytical clarity
and scrupulous jurisprudential deliberation on the fundamental
nature of law, justice, and the meaning of legal concepts are
indispensable. Legal theory has a decisive role to play in defining
and defending the values and ideals that sustain our way of life.
xvi
Chapter 1
Natural law
‘It’s just not right.’ ‘It’s not natural.’ How many times have you heard
these sorts of judgements invoked against a particular practice or
act? What do they mean? When abortion is pronounced immoral,
or same-sex marriages unacceptable, what is the basis of this
censure? Is there an objectively ascertainable measure of right and
wrong, good and bad? If so, by what means can we retrieve it?
Moral questions pervade our lives; they are the stuff of political,
and hence legal, debate. Moreover, since the establishment of the
United Nations, the ethical tenor of international relations,
especially in the field of human rights, is embodied in an increasing
variety of international declarations and conventions, many of
which draw on the unspoken assumption of natural law that there is
indeed a corpus of moral truths that, if we apply our reasoning
minds, we can all discover.
Ethical problems have, of course, preoccupied moral philosophers
since Aristotle. The revival of natural law theory may suggest that
we have, over the centuries, come no closer to resolving them.
‘The best description of natural law’, according to one leading
natural lawyer, ‘is that it provides a name for the point of
intersection between law and morals.’ Its main claim, put simply, is
that what naturally is, ought to be. In his widely acclaimed book,
1
Philosophy of Law
1. Homosexuality, same-sex ‘marriages’, and marital infidelity offend
the principles of natural law.
Natural Law and Natural Rights, John Finnis asserts that when
we attempt to explain what law is, we make assumptions,
willy-nilly, about what is ‘good’:
It is often supposed that an evaluation of law as a type of social
institution, if it is to be undertaken at all, must be preceded by a
value-free description and analysis of that institution as it exists in
fact. But the development of modern jurisprudence suggests, and
reflection on the methodology of any social science confirms, that a
theorist cannot give a theoretical description and analysis of social
facts, unless he also participates in the work of evaluation, of
understanding what is really good for human persons, and what is
really required by practical reasonableness.
This is a trenchant foundation for an analysis of natural law. It
proposes that when we are discerning what is good, we are using our
intelligence differently from when we are determining what exists.
In other words, if we are to understand the nature and impact of the
2
natural law project, we must recognize that it yields a different
logic.
The Roman lawyer, Cicero, drawing on Stoic philosophy, usefully
identified the three main components of any natural law
philosophy:
True law is right reason in agreement with Nature; it is of universal
application, unchanging and everlasting. . . . It is a sin to try to alter
this law, nor is it allowable to attempt to repeal any part of it, and it
is impossible to abolish it entirely. . . . [God] is the author of this
law, its promulgator, and its enforcing judge.
Aristotle devoted less attention to natural law than to the
distinction between natural and conventional justice. But it was the
Greek Stoics, as mentioned above, who were particularly attracted
to the notion of natural law, where ‘natural’ meant in accordance
with reason. The Stoic view informed the approach adopted by the
Romans (as expressed by Cicero) who recognized, at least in theory,
that laws which did not conform to ‘reason’ might be regarded as
invalid.
The Catholic Church gave expression to the full-blown philosophy
of natural law, as we understand it today. As early as the 5th century,
St Augustine asked, ‘What are States without justice, but robber
3
Natural law
This underlines natural law’s universality and immutability, its
standing as a ‘higher’ law, and its discoverability by reason (it is in
this sense ‘natural’). Classical natural law doctrine has been
employed to justify both revolution and reaction. During the 6th
century bc, the Greeks described human laws as owing their
importance to the power of fate that controlled everything. This
conservative view is easily deployed to justify even iniquitous
aspects of the status quo. By the 5th century bc, however, it was
acknowledged that there might be a conflict between the law of
nature and the law of man.
Philosophy of Law
bands enlarged?’ But the leading exposition of natural law is to be
found in the writings of the Dominican, St Thomas Aquinas (1225–
74), whose principal work Summa Theologiae contains the most
comprehensive statement of Christian doctrine on the subject. He
distinguishes between four categories of law: the eternal law (divine
reason known only to God), natural law (the participation of the
eternal law in rational creatures, discoverable by reason), divine law
(revealed in the scriptures), and human law (supported by reason,
and enacted for the common good).
One aspect of Aquinas’s theory has attracted particular attention
and controversy. He states that a ‘law’ that fails to conform to
natural or divine law is not a law at all. This is usually expressed as
lex iniusta non est lex (an unjust law is not law). But modern
scholars maintain that Aquinas himself never made this assertion,
but merely quoted St Augustine. Plato, Aristotle, and Cicero also
uttered comparable sentiments, yet it is a proposition that is most
closely associated with Aquinas who seems to have meant that laws
which conflict with the requirements of natural law lose their power
to bind morally. A government, in other words, that abuses its
authority by enacting laws which are unjust (unreasonable or
against the common good) forfeits its right to be obeyed because it
lacks moral authority. Such a law Aquinas calls a ‘corruption of law’.
But he does not appear to support the view that one is always
justified in disobeying an unjust law, for though he does declare that
if a ruler enacts unjust laws ‘their subjects are not obliged to obey
them’, he adds guardedly, ‘except, perhaps, in certain special cases
when it is a matter of avoiding scandal’ (i.e. a corrupting example to
others) or civil disorder. This is a far cry from the radical claims
sometimes made in the name of Aquinas, which seek to justify
disobedience to law.
By the 17th century in Europe, the exposition of entire branches of
the law, notably public international law, purported to be founded
on natural law. Hugo de Groot (1583–1645), or Grotius as he is
generally called, is normally associated with the secularization of
4
natural law. In his influential work, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, he asserts
that, even if God did not exist, natural law would have the same
content. This proved to be an important basis for the developing
discipline of public international law. Presumably Grotius meant
that certain things were ‘intrinsically’ wrong – whether or not God
decrees them; for, to use Grotius’s own analogy, even God cannot
cause two times two not to equal four!
Aquinas is associated with a fairly conservative view of natural law.
But the principles of natural law have been used to justify
revolutions – especially the American and the French – on the
ground that the law infringed individuals’ natural rights. Thus in
America the revolution against British colonial rule was based on
an appeal to the natural rights of all Americans, in the lofty words of
the Declaration of Independence of 1776, to ‘life, liberty and the
pursuit of happiness’. As the Declaration puts it, ‘We hold these
truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they
are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights.’
Similarly inspiring sentiments were included in the French
Déclaration des droits de l’homme et du citoyen of 26 August 1789
which refers to certain ‘natural rights’ of mankind.
Natural law was applied in the form of a number of contractarian
theories that conceive of political rights and obligations in terms of
5
Natural law
Natural law received a stamp of approval in England in the 18th
century in Sir William Blackstone’s Commentaries on the Laws of
England. Blackstone (1723–80) begins his great work by declaring
that English law derives its authority from natural law. But,
although he invokes this divine source of positive law, and even
regards it as capable of nullifying enacted laws in conflict with
natural law, his account of the law is not actually informed by
natural law theory. Nevertheless, Blackstone’s attempt to clothe the
positive law with a legitimacy derived from natural law drew the fire
of Jeremy Bentham who described natural law as, amongst other
things, ‘a mere work of the fancy’ (see Chapter 2).
a social contract. It is not a contract in a strict legal sense, but
expresses the idea that only with his consent can a person be
subjected to the political power of another. This approach remains
influential in liberal thought, notably John Rawls’s theory of justice
(see Chapter 4).
Philosophy of Law
Natural rights: Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau
Although Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) is usually remembered for
his dictum that life is ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short’, he
actually said, in his famous work, Leviathan, that this was the
condition of man before the social contract, i.e. in his natural state.
Natural law, he contends, teaches us the necessity of selfpreservation: law and government are required if we are to protect
order and security. Under the social contract, we must therefore
surrender our natural freedom in order to create an orderly society.
Hobbes’s philosophy is thus somewhat authoritarian, placing order
above justice. In particular, his theory (indeed, his self-confessed
objective) is to undermine the legitimacy of revolutions against
(even malevolent) government.
For Hobbes every act we perform, though ostensibly kind or
altruistic, is actually self-serving. Thus my donation to charity is
actually a means of enjoying my power. An accurate account of
human action, including morality, must, he argues, acknowledge
our essential selfishness. In Leviathan he wonders how we might
behave in a state of nature, before the formation of any government.
He recognizes that we are essentially equal, mentally and
physically: even the weakest – suitably armed – has the strength to
kill the strongest. This equality, he suggests, generates discord. We
tend to wrangle, he argues, for three main reasons: competition (for
limited supplies of material possessions), distrust, and glory (we
remain hostile in order to preserve our powerful reputations). As a
consequence of our propensity toward disagreement, Hobbes
concludes that we are in a natural state of perpetual war of all
against all, where no morality exists, and all live in constant fear.
6
Until this state of war comes to an end, all have a right to
everything, including another person’s life. Hobbes argues that,
from human self-interest and social agreement alone, one
can derive the same kinds of laws that natural lawyers regard
as immutably fixed in nature. In order to escape the horror of
the state of nature, Hobbes concludes, peace is the first law
of nature.
The second law of nature is that we mutually divest ourselves of
certain rights (such as the right to take another person’s life) so as to
achieve peace. This mutual transferring of rights is a contract and is
the basis of moral duty. He is under no illusion that merely
concluding this contract can secure peace. Such agreements need to
be honoured. This is Hobbes’s third law of nature.
Hobbes supplements his first three laws of nature with several other
substantive ones such as the fourth law (to show gratitude toward
those who comply with contracts). He concludes that morality
consists entirely of these laws of nature, which are arrived at
through the social contract. This is a rather different interpretation
of natural rights from that championed by classical natural law. But
his account might be styled a modern view of natural rights, one
that is premised on the basic right of every person to preserve his
own life.
7
Natural law
He acknowledges that since we are selfish we are likely, out of selfinterest, to breach contracts. I may break my agreement not to steal
from you when I think I can evade detection. And you are aware of
this. The only certain means of avoiding this breakdown in our
mutual obligations, he argues, is to grant unlimited power to a
political sovereign to punish us if we violate our contracts. And
again it is a purely selfish reason (ending the state of nature) that
motivates us to agree to the establishment of an authority with the
power of sanction. But he insists that only when such a sovereign
exists can we arrive at any objective determination of right and
wrong.
Philosophy of Law
John Locke (1632–1704) portrays life before the social contract as
anything but the nightmare described by Hobbes. Locke claims
that, before the social contract, life was paradise – save for one
important shortcoming: in this state of nature, property was
inadequately protected. For Locke, therefore (especially in Two
Treatises of Civil Government), it was in order to rectify this flaw in
an otherwise idyllic natural state that man forfeited, under a social
contract, some of his freedom. Suggestive of Aquinas’s fundamental
postulates, Locke’s theory rests on an account of man’s rights
and obligations under God. It is an intricate attempt to explain
the operation of the social contract and its terms. It is
revolutionary (Locke accepts the right of the people to overthrow
tyranny), and it famously emphasizes the right to own property:
God owns the earth and has given it to us to enjoy; there can
therefore be no right of property, but by ‘mixing’ his labour with
material objects, the labourer acquires the right to the thing he has
created.
Locke’s perception of private property strongly influenced
the framers of the American constitution. He has therefore
been both celebrated and reviled as the progenitor of modern
capitalism.
The social contract, in his view, preserved the natural rights to life,
liberty, and property, and the enjoyment of private rights: the
pursuit of happiness – engendered, in civil society, the common
good. Whereas for Hobbes natural rights come first, and natural law
is derived from them, Locke derives natural rights from natural law
– i.e. from reason. Hobbes discerns a natural right of every person
to every thing, Locke argues that our natural right to freedom is
constrained by the law of nature and its directive that we should not
harm each other in ‘life, health, liberty, or possessions’. Locke
advocates a limited form of government: the checks and balances
among branches of government and the genuine representation in
the legislature would, in his view, minimize government and
maximize individual liberty.
8
Natural law plays a less important role than the social contract in
the theory of Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–78). More metaphysical
than Hobbes and Locke, Rousseau’s social contract (in his Social
Contract) is an agreement between the individual and the
community by which he becomes part of what Rousseau calls the
‘general will’. There are, in Rousseau’s view, certain natural rights
that cannot be removed, but, by investing the ‘general will’ with
total legislative authority, the law may legitimately infringe upon
these rights. Indeed, if government represents the ‘general will’, it
may do almost anything. Rousseau, while dedicated to participatory
democracy, is also willing to invest the legislature with virtually
untrammelled power by virtue of its reflecting the ‘general will’.
He is thus a paradox: a democratic totalitarian.
The fall and rise of natural law
David Hume (1711–76) in his Treatise of Human Nature first
observed that moralists seek to derive an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’: we
cannot conclude that the law should assume a particular form
merely because a certain state of affairs exists in nature. Thus the
following syllogism, according to this argument, is invalid:
All animals procreate (major premise)
Human beings are animals (minor premise)
Therefore humans ought to procreate (conclusion).
9
Natural law
The waning influence of natural law theory, especially in the 19th
century, resulted from the emergence of two formidable foes. First,
as we shall see in the next chapter, the ideas associated with legal
positivism constitute resilient opposition to natural law thinking.
Secondly, the idea that in moral reasoning there can be no rational
solutions (so-called non-cognitivism in ethics) spawned a profound
scepticism about natural law: If we cannot objectively know what is
right or wrong, natural law principles are little more than
subjective opinion: they could, therefore, be neither right nor
wrong.
Philosophy of Law
Hume sought to show that facts about the world or human nature
cannot be used to determine what ought to be done or not done.
Some contemporary natural lawyers, while admitting that the
above syllogism is indeed false, deny that classical natural law
attempted to derive an ‘ought’ from an ‘is’ in this manner, as we shall
see below.
The 20th century witnessed a renaissance in natural law theory.
This is evident in the post-war recognition of human rights and
their expression in declarations such as the Charter of the United
Nations, and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the
European Convention on Human Rights, and the Declaration of
Delhi on the Rule of Law of 1959 (see Chapter 4). Natural law is
conceived of not as a ‘higher law’ in the constitutional sense of
invalidating ordinary law but as a benchmark against which to
measure positive law.
The Nuremberg war trials of senior Nazi officials regenerated
natural law ideals. They applied the principle that certain acts
constitute ‘crimes against humanity’ even if they do not violate
provisions of positive law. The judges in these trials did not appeal
explicitly to natural law theory, but their judgments represent an
important recognition of the principle that the law is not necessarily
the sole determinant of what is right.
Another significant development was the enactment of
constitutional safeguards for human or civil rights in various
jurisdictions (e.g. the American Bill of Rights and its interpretation
by the United States Supreme Court).
Legal theory has also advanced the cause of natural law theory. Lon
Fuller’s ‘inner morality of law’ (see below), H. L. A. Hart’s
‘minimum content of natural law’ (see Chapter 2), and most
importantly, the writings of contemporary natural lawyers such
as John Finnis (see below) have played a major role in this
revival.
10
2. The Nuremberg trials of Nazi war criminals applied the principle that certain acts constitute ‘crimes
against humanity’ even though they do not offend against specific provisions of positive law.
Lon Fuller: the ‘inner morality of law’
Philosophy of Law
The American jurist, Lon L. Fuller (1902–78) famously developed a
secular natural law approach that regards law as having an ‘inner
morality’. By this he means that a legal system has the specific
purpose of ‘subjecting human conduct to the governance of rules’. It
follows that in this purposive enterprise there is a necessary
connection between law and morality.
Fuller recounts the ‘moral’ tale of a fictional King Rex and the eight
ways in which he fails to make law. He goes wrong because (1) he
fails to achieve rules at all, so that every issue must be decided on an
ad hoc basis; (2) he does not publicize the rules that his subjects are
expected to observe; (3) he abuses his legislative powers by enacting
retroactive legislation (i.e. on Tuesday making unlawful those acts
that were lawful on Monday); (4) his rules are incomprehensible;
(5) he enacts contradictory rules or (6) rules that require conduct
beyond the powers of the affected party; (7) he introduces such
frequent changes in the rules that his subjects cannot adjust their
action; and (8) he fails to achieve congruence between the rules as
announced and their actual administration.
Ill-fated King Rex bites the dust because he disregards Fuller’s eight
principles:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
Generality
Promulgation
Non-retroactivity
Clarity
Non-contradiction
Possibility of compliance
Constancy
Congruence between declared rule and official action.
Fuller concludes that where a system does not conform to any one
of these principles, or fails substantially in respect of several, it
12
could not be said that ‘law’ existed in that community. But, though
he insists that these eight principles are moral, they appear to be
essentially procedural guides to effective lawmaking. Some,
however, would argue that they implicitly establish fairness
between the government and the governed and therefore exclude
evil regimes.
The general view, however, is that compliance with Fuller’s eight
‘desiderata’ certifies only that the legal system functions effectively,
and hence, since this cannot be a moral criterion, an evil regime
might just as easily satisfy the test. Indeed, it is arguable that, in
pursuit of efficacy, a wicked legal system might actually seek to fulfil
Fuller’s principles. Certainly, the rulers of apartheid South Africa
Natural law
3. The legal enforcement of racial segregation and discrimination
reached its high-water mark in apartheid South Africa.
13
sought to comply with procedural niceties when enacting and
implementing its obnoxious laws.
Contemporary natural law theory: John Finnis
Philosophy of Law
The Aquinian tenets of natural law have been revived and
meticulously explored by the Oxford legal theorist, John Finnis
(b. 1940), most accessibly and comprehensively in his book,
Natural Law and Natural Rights. It represents a significant
restatement of classical natural law doctrine, especially its
application of analytical jurisprudence to a theory that, as we shall
see, is normally regarded as its opposite.
It is important to grasp the purpose of Finnis’s enterprise. He
rejects David Hume’s conception of practical reason, which
maintains that my reason for undertaking an action is merely
ancillary to my desire to attain a certain objective. Reason informs
me only how best to achieve my desires; it cannot tell me what I
ought to desire. Finnis prefers an Aristotelian foundation: what
constitutes a worthwhile, valuable, desirable life? And his menu
contains what he calls the seven ‘basic forms of human flourishing’:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
Life
Knowledge
Play
Aesthetic experience
Sociability (friendship)
Practical reasonableness
‘Religion’
These are the essential features that contribute to a fulfilling life.
Each is universal in that it governs all human societies at all times,
and each has intrinsic value in that it should be valued for its own
sake and not merely to achieve some other good. The purpose of
moral beliefs is to provide an ethical structure to the pursuit of
these basic goods. These principles facilitate our choosing among
14
competing goods and enable us to define what we are permitted to
do in pursuing a basic good.
To flourish as human beings, we require these basic goods, though
one could easily add to this list. Note that by ‘religion’, Finnis does
not mean organized religion, but the need for spiritual experience.
These seven basic goods are combined by Finnis with the following
nine ‘basic requirements of practical reasonableness’:
The active pursuit of goods
A coherent plan of life
No arbitrary preference among values
No arbitrary preference among persons
Detachment and commitment
The (limited) relevance of consequences: efficiency within reason
Respect for every basic value in every act
The requirements of the common good
Following one’s conscience.
These two inventories together comprise the universal and
immutable ‘principles of natural law’. Finnis demonstrates that this
position accords with the general conception of natural law
espoused by Thomas Aquinas. Nor, he claims, does it fall victim to
non-cognitivist attack by Hume (see above) – for these objective
goods are self-evident; they are not deduced from any account of
human nature. So, for example, ‘knowledge’ is self-evidently
preferable to ignorance. And even if I refute this view, and claim
that ‘ignorance is bliss’, I would willy-nilly be acknowledging that
my argument is a valuable one, and hence that knowledge is indeed
good, thereby slipping into the trap of self-refutation!
The overriding rationale of natural law theory thus seems to be, as
Finnis says, to establish ‘what is really good for human persons’. We
cannot pursue human goods until we have a community. And the
authority of a leader derives from his serving the best interests of
that community. Hence, should he enact unjust laws, because they
15
Natural law
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
militate against the common good, they would lack the direct moral
authority to bind.
Appealing to the concept of the common good, Finnis develops also
his conception of justice. Principles of justice, he contends, are no
more than the implications of the general requirement that one
ought to foster the common good in one’s community. The basic
goods and methodological requirements ought to thwart most
forms of injustice; they generate several absolute obligations with
correlative absolute natural rights:
There is, I think, no alternative but to hold in one’s mind’s eye some
pattern, or range of patterns, of human character, conduct, and
interaction in community, and then to choose such specification of
Philosophy of Law
rights as tends to favour the pattern, or range of patterns. In other
words, one needs some conception of human good, of individual
flourishing in a form (or range of forms) of communal life that
fosters rather than hinders such flourishing. One attends not merely
to character types desirable in the abstract or in isolation, but also to
the quality of interaction among persons; and one should not seek to
realize some patterned ‘end-state’ imagined in abstraction from the
processes of individual initiative and interaction, processes which
are integral to human good and which make the future, let alone its
evaluation, incalculable.
This passage captures the spirit of Finnis’s conception of natural
rights. It includes the right not to be tortured, not to have one’s life
taken as a means to any further end, not to be lied to, not to be
condemned on knowingly false charges, not to be deprived of one’s
capacity to procreate, and the right ‘to be taken into respectful
consideration in any assessment of what the common good
requires’. The concept of justice is further examined in Chapter 4.
Finnis insists that the first principles of natural law are not
deductively inferred from anything at all, including facts,
speculative principles, metaphysical propositions about human
16
nature or about the nature of good and evil, or from a teleological
conception of nature. Aquinas, according to Finnis, makes it clear
that each of us ‘by experiencing one’s nature, so to speak, from the
inside’ grasps ‘by a simple act of non-inferential understanding’ that
‘the object of the inclination which one experiences is an instance of
a general form of good, for oneself (and others like one)’. For
Aquinas, to discover what is morally right is to ask, not what is in
accordance with human nature, but what is reasonable.
The central claims of natural law are rejected by legal positivists
who deny that that the legal validity of a norm necessarily depends
on its substantive moral qualities. This standpoint is considered in
the next chapter.
Natural law
17
Chapter 2
Legal positivism
Imagine a powerful sovereign who issues commands to his subjects.
They are under a duty to comply with his wishes. The notion of law
as a command lies at the heart of classical legal positivism as
espoused by its two great protagonists, Jeremy Bentham and John
Austin. Modern legal positivists adopt a considerably more
sophisticated approach to the concept of law, but, like their
distinguished predecessors, they deny the relationship proposed by
natural law, outlined in the previous chapter, between law and
morals. The claim of natural lawyers that law consists of a series of
propositions derived from nature through a process of reasoning is
strongly contested by legal positivists. This chapter describes the
essential elements of this important legal theory.
The term ‘positivism’ derives from the Latin positum, which refers
to the law as it is laid down or posited. Broadly speaking, the core of
legal positivism is the view that the validity of any law can be traced
to an objectively verifiable source. Put simply, legal positivism, like
scientific positivism, rejects the view – held by natural lawyers –
that law exists independently from human enactment. As will
become clear in this chapter, the early legal positivism of Bentham
and Austin found the origin of law in the command of a sovereign.
H. L. A. Hart looks to a rule of recognition that distinguishes law
from other social rules. Hans Kelsen identifies a basic norm that
validates the constitution. Legal positivists also often claim that
18
there is no necessary connection between law and morals, and that
the analysis of legal concepts is worth pursuing, and distinct from
(though not hostile to) sociological and historical enquiries and
critical evaluation.
Nor do positivists necessarily subscribe to the proposition, often
ascribed to them, that unjust or iniquitous laws must be obeyed –
merely because they are law. Indeed, both Austin and Bentham
acknowledge that disobedience to evil laws is legitimate if it would
promote change for the good. In the words of the foremost modern
legal positivist H. L. A. Hart:
[T]he certification of something as legally valid is not conclusive of
the question of obedience, . . . [H]owever great the aura of majesty
or authority which the official system may have, its demands must in
the end be submitted to a moral scrutiny.
For Hart, as well as Bentham, this is one of the major virtues of legal
positivism.
19
Legal positivism
The highest common factor among legal positivists is that the law as
laid down should be kept separate – for the purpose of study and
analysis – from the law as it ought morally to be. In other words,
that a clear distinction must be drawn between ‘ought’ (that which
is morally desirable) and ‘is’ (that which actually exists). But it does
not follow from this that a legal positivist is indifferent to moral
questions. Most legal positivists criticize the law and propose means
to reform it. This normally involves moral judgements. But
positivists do share the view that the most effective method of
analysing and understanding law involves suspending moral
judgement until it is established what it is we are seeking to
elucidate.
Philosophy of Law
4. Jeremy Bentham: the Luther of legal philosophy?
Law as commands: Bentham and Austin
The prodigious writings of Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832) constitute
a major contribution to positivist jurisprudence and the systematic
analysis of law and the legal system. Not only did he seek to expose
the shibboleths of his age and construct a comprehensive theory of
law, logic, politics, and psychology, founded on the principle of
20
utility, but he essayed for reform of the law on almost every subject.
His critique of the common law and its theoretical underpinnings
are especially ferocious. Moved by the spirit of the Enlightenment,
Bentham sought to subject the common law to the cold light of
reason. He attempted to demystify the law, to expose, in his
characteristically cutting style, what lay behind its mask. Appeals to
natural law were nothing more than ‘private opinion in disguise’ or
‘the mere opinion of men self-constituted into legislatures’.
The indeterminacy of the common law, he argued, is endemic.
Unwritten law is intrinsically vague and uncertain. It cannot
provide a reliable, public standard which can reasonably be
Legal positivism
5. Bentham regarded English judges as partial, corrupt, and
capricious.
21
Philosophy of Law
expected to guide behaviour. The chaos of the common law had to
be dealt with systematically. For Bentham this lay, quite simply, in
codification. Legal codes would significantly diminish the power
of judges; their task would consist less of interpreting than
administering the law. It would also remove much of the need for
lawyers: the code would be readily comprehensible without the help
of legal advisers. Unlike the Continental system of law that has long
adopted Napoleonic codes based on Roman law, codification in the
common law world remains a dream.
John Austin (1790–1859) published his major work, The Province of
Jurisprudence Determined, in 1832, the year of Bentham’s death. As
a disciple of Bentham’s, Austin’s conception of law is based on the
idea of commands or imperatives, though he provides a less
elaborate account of what they are. Both jurists stress the subjection
of persons by the sovereign to his power, but Austin’s definition is
sometimes thought to extend not very much further than the
criminal law, with its emphasis on control over behaviour. His
identification of commands as the hallmark of law leads him to a
more restrictive definition of law than is adopted by Bentham who
seeks to formulate a single, complete law which sufficiently
expresses the legislative will.
But both share a concern to confine the scope of jurisprudential
enquiry to accounting for and explaining the principal features of
the law. In the case of Austin, however, his map of ‘law properly so
called’ is considerably narrower than Bentham’s, and embraces two
categories: the laws of God and human laws. Human laws (i.e. laws
set down by men for men) are further divided into positive laws or
laws ‘strictly so called’ (i.e. laws laid down by men as political
superiors or in pursuance of legal rights) and laws laid down by men
not as political superiors or not in pursuance of legal rights. Laws
‘improperly so called’ are divided into laws by analogy (e.g. laws of
fashion, constitutional, and international law) and by metaphor
(e.g. the law of gravity). Laws by analogy, together with laws set by
men not as political superiors or in pursuance of legal right, are
22
merely ‘positive morality’. It is only positive law that is the proper
subject of jurisprudence.
Bentham is best known as a utilitarian (see Chapter 4) and law
reformer. But he insisted on the separation between what he called
‘expositorial’ and ‘censorial’ jurisprudence. The former describes
what is, the latter what ought to be. Austin was no less categorical in
preserving this division, but his analysis is narrower in both its
compass and purpose than Bentham’s.
Austin, on the other hand, builds his scheme of a legal system on the
classification of rights; he is not troubled by a search for a ‘complete’
law. Also, in his pursuit to provide a plan of a comprehensive body
of laws and the elements of the ‘art of legislation’, Bentham
expounds a complex ‘logic of the will’. Austin seeks to construct a
science of law rather than engage himself in Bentham’s art of
legislation. And while Bentham sought to devise means by which
arbitrary power, especially of judges, might be checked, Austin was
less anxious about these matters.
The central feature of Austin’s map of the province of jurisprudence
is the notion of law as a command of the sovereign. Anything that is
not a command is not law. Only general commands count as law.
And only commands emanating from the sovereign are ‘positive
laws’. Austin’s insistence on law as commands requires him to
exclude customary, constitutional, and public international law
from the field of jurisprudence. This is because no specific sovereign
23
Legal positivism
Though both adhere to a utilitarian morality, and adopt broadly
similar views on the nature and function of jurisprudence and the
serious inadequacies of the common law tradition, there are several
important differences in their general approach to the subject. In
particular, Bentham pursues the notion of a single, complete law
which adequately expresses the will of the legislature. He seeks to
show how a single law creates a single offence defined by its being
the narrowest species of that kind of offence recognized by the law.
can be identified as the author of their rules. Thus, in the case of
public international law, sovereign states are notoriously at liberty
to disregard its requirements.
Philosophy of Law
For Bentham, however, commands are merely one of four methods
by which the sovereign enacts law. He distinguishes between laws
which command or prohibit certain conduct (imperative laws) and
those which permit certain conduct (permissive laws). He argues
that all laws are both penal and civil; even in the case of title to
property there is a penal element. Bentham seeks to show that laws
which impose no obligations or sanctions (what he calls ‘civil laws’)
are not ‘complete laws’, but merely parts of laws. And, since his
principal objective was the creation of a code of law, he argued that
the penal and civil branches should be formulated separately.
The relationship between commands and sanctions is no less
important for Austin. Indeed, his very concept of a command
includes the probability that a sanction will follow failure to obey
the command. But what is a sanction? Austin defines it as some
harm, pain, or evil that is conditional upon the failure of a person to
comply with the wishes of the sovereign. There must be a realistic
probability that it will be inflicted upon anyone who infringes a
command. There need only be the threat of the possibility of a
minimal harm, pain, or evil, but unless a sanction is likely to follow,
the mere expression of a wish is not a command. Obligations are
therefore defined in terms of sanctions: this is a central tenet of
Austin’s imperative theory. The likelihood of a sanction is always
uncertain, but Austin is driven to the rather unsatisfactory position
that a sanction consists of ‘the smallest chance of incurring the
smallest evil’.
The idea of a sovereign issuing commands pervades the theories of
both Bentham and Austin. It is important to note that both regard
the sovereign’s power as constituted by the habit of the people
generally obeying his laws. But while Austin insists on the
illimitability and indivisibility of the sovereign, Bentham, alive to
24
the institution of federalism, acknowledges that the supreme
legislative power may be both limited and divided by what he calls
an express convention.
For Austin, to the four features of a command (wish, sanction,
expression of a wish, and generality) is to be added a fifth, namely
an identifiable political superior – or sovereign – whose commands
are obeyed by political inferiors and who owes obedience to no one.
This insistence on an omnipotent lawgiver distorts those legal
systems which impose constitutional restrictions on the legislative
competence of the legislature or which divide such power between a
central federal legislature and lawmaking bodies of constituent
states or provinces (such as in the United States, Canada or
Australia). Bentham, on the other hand, acknowledges that
sovereignty may be limited or divided, and accepts (albeit
reluctantly) the possibility of judicial review of legislative action.
Moreover, by insisting that the sanction is an indispensable
ingredient in the definition of law, Austin is driven to defining duty
in terms of sanction: if the sovereign expresses a wish and has the
power to inflict an evil (or sanction) then a person is under a duty to
act in accordance with that wish. The distinction between a ‘wish’
and the ‘expression of a wish’ resembles the distinction between a
bill and a statute.
Austin’s association between duty and sanction has attracted
25
Legal positivism
Austin’s contention that ‘laws properly so called’ be confined to the
commands of a sovereign leads him to base his idea of sovereignty
on the habit of obedience adopted by members of society. The
sovereign must, moreover, be determinate (i.e. the composition of
the sovereign body must be unambiguous), for ‘no indeterminate
sovereign can command expressly or tacitly, or can receive
obedience or submission’. And this results in Austin famously
refusing to accept as ‘law’ public international law, customary law,
and a good deal of constitutional law.
Philosophy of Law
considerable criticism, though it may be that he was merely seeking
to show – in a formal sense – that, where there is a duty, its breach
normally gives rise to a sanction. In other words, he is not
necessarily seeking to provide an explanation for why law is obeyed
or whether it ought to be obeyed, but rather when a legal duty
exists. Nevertheless, he unquestionably accords unwarranted
significance to the concept of duty. The law frequently imposes no
direct duty, such as when it facilitates marriage, contracts, and wills.
We are not under any duty to carry out these transactions, but they
are plainly part of the law. H. L. A. Hart calls them ‘powerconferring rules’ (see below).
The less dogmatic approach of Bentham allows that a sovereign’s
commands constitute law even in the absence of sanctions in the
Austinian sense. Law, according to Bentham, includes both
punishments (‘coercive motives’) and rewards (‘alluring motives’),
but they do not define what is and what is not law.
Bentham and Austin laid the foundations for modern legal
positivism. But their ideas have been considerably refined,
developed, and even rejected, by contemporary legal positivists. The
remainder of this chapter outlines the approaches of its three
leading protagonists: H. L. A. Hart, Hans Kelsen, and Joseph Raz.
Law as social rules: H. L. A. Hart
H. L. A. Hart (1907–92) is often credited with charting the
precincts of modern legal theory by applying the techniques of
analytical, and especially linguistic, philosophy to the study of law.
His work illuminates the meaning of legal concepts, the manner in
which we deploy them, and the way we think about law and the
legal system. What, for example, does it mean to have a ‘right’?
What is a corporation or an obligation? Hart claims that we cannot
properly understand law unless we understand the conceptual
context in which it emerges and develops. He argues, for instance,
that language has an ‘open texture’: words (and hence rules) have a
26
number of clear meanings, but there are always several ‘penumbral’
cases where it is uncertain whether the word applies or not. His
book, The Concept of Law, published in 1961, is a classic of legal
theory and has served as a catalyst for many other jurists around the
world.
Hart’s positivism is a far cry from the largely coercive picture of law
painted by Bentham and Austin. Hart conceives of law as a social
Legal positivism
6. H. L. A. Hart: the father of modern legal positivism.
27
phenomenon that can be understood only by describing the actual
social practices of a community. In order for it to survive as a
community, Hart argues, there need to be certain fundamental
rules. He calls these the ‘minimum content of natural law’. They
arise out of our human condition which manifests the following
essential features:
Philosophy of Law
‘Human vulnerability’: We are all susceptible to physical attacks.
‘Approximate equality’: Even the strongest must sleep at times.
‘Limited altruism’: We are, in general, selfish.
‘Limited resources’: We need food, clothes, and shelter and they
are limited.
‘Limited understanding and strength of will’: We cannot be relied
upon to cooperate with our fellow men.
These human frailties require the enactment of rules to protect
persons and property, and to ensure that promises are kept. But,
though he employs the shibboleth ‘natural law’, he does not mean
that law is derived from morals or that there is a necessary
conceptual relationship between the two. Nor is he saying that this
minimum content of natural law ensures a fair or just society. Hart
disengages his legal positivism from both the utilitarianism (see
Chapter 4) and the command theory of law championed by Austin
and Bentham. In the case of the latter, his rejection is based on the
view that law is more than the decree of a gunman: a command
backed by a sanction.
The nucleus of Hart’s theory is the existence of fundamental rules
accepted by officials as stipulating procedures by which the law is
enacted. The most important of these he calls the rule of
recognition which is the fundamental constitutional rule of a legal
system, acknowledged by those officials who administer the law as
specifying the conditions or criteria of validity which certify
whether or not a rule is indeed a rule.
Law, in Hart’s analysis, is a system of rules. His argument is as
28
The existence of a legal system requires that two conditions must be
satisfied. First, valid obligation rules must be generally obeyed by
members of society, and, secondly, officials must accept the rules of
change and adjudication; they must also accept the rule of
recognition ‘from the internal point of view’.
As already pointed out, Hart rejects Austin’s conception of rules as
commands, and the notion that rules are phenomena that consist
merely in externally observable activities or habit. Instead he asks
us to consider the social dimension of rules, namely the manner in
which members of a society perceive the rule in question, their
attitude towards it. This ‘internal’ aspect distinguishes between a
rule and a mere habit.
Thus, to use his example, chess players, in addition to having
similar habits of moving the Queen in the same way, also have a
29
Legal positivism
follows. All societies have social rules. These include rules relating
to morals, games, etc., as well as obligation rules that impose duties
or obligations. The latter may be divided into moral rules and legal
rules (or law). As a result of our human limitations, mentioned
above, there is a necessity for obligation rules in all societies. Legal
rules are divisible into primary rules and secondary rules. The
former proscribe the use of violence, theft, and deception to which
human beings are tempted but which they must normally repress if
they are to coexist in close proximity. The rules of primitive societies
are normally restricted to these primary rules imposing obligations.
But as a society becomes more complex, there is obviously a need to
change the primary rules, to adjudicate on breaches of them, and to
identify which rules are actually obligation rules. These three
requirements are satisfied in each case in modern societies by the
introduction of three sorts of secondary rules: rules of change,
adjudication, and recognition. Unlike primary rules, the first two of
these secondary rules do not generally impose duties, but usually
confer power. The rule of recognition, however, does seem to
impose duties (largely on judges). I expand on this point below.
‘critical reflective attitude’ to this way of moving it: they each regard
it as a standard for all who play chess. They exhibit these views in
their appraisal of other players, and acknowledge the legitimacy of
such criticism when they are themselves subjected to it.
Philosophy of Law
In other words, to grasp the nature of rules we must examine them
from the point of view of those who experience them, or who pass
judgement on them. He also employs the concept of a ‘rule’ to
distinguish between ‘being obliged’ and ‘having an obligation’.
When a gunman says, ‘Your money or your life?’ you are obliged to
obey, but, says Hart, you have no obligation to do so – because no
rule imposes an obligation on you.
Having described the nature and purpose of primary rules, Hart
attempts to show that every legal system incorporates secondary
rules of three kinds. The first he calls rules of change. These
facilitate legislative or judicial changes to both the primary rules
and certain secondary rules (e.g. the rule of adjudication, below).
This process of change is regulated by secondary rules that confer
power on individuals or groups (e.g. Congress or Parliament) to
enact legislation in accordance with certain procedures. Rules of
change also confer power on you and me to alter our legal status
(e.g. by making contracts, wills, etc.).
Secondly, there are rules of adjudication that confer authority on
individuals, such as judges, to pass judgment mainly in cases of
breaches of primary rules. This power is normally associated with a
further power to punish the wrongdoer or compel the wrongdoer to
pay damages.
Thirdly, there is the rule of recognition which determines the
criteria by which the validity of all the rules of a legal system is
decided. As pointed out above, unlike the other two types of
secondary rules, it appears, in part, to be duty-imposing: it requires
those who exercise public power (particularly judges) to follow
certain rules. Hart maintains that rules are valid members of the
30
legal system only if they satisfy the criteria laid down by the rule of
recognition. Comparing it to the standard metre bar in Paris (the
definitive standard by which a metre was once measured), the
validity of the rule of recognition cannot be questioned. It is neither
valid nor invalid, but is simply accepted as the correct standard.
A legal system exists, according to Hart, only if valid primary rules
are obeyed, and officials accept the rules of change and
adjudication. In Hart’s words:
The assertion that a legal system exists is . . . a Janus-faced
statement looking both to obedience by ordinary citizens and to the
acceptance by officials of secondary rules as critical common
standards of official behaviour.
What is necessary is that there should be a critical reflective attitude
to certain patterns of behaviour as a common standard, and that this
should display itself in criticism (including self-criticism), demands
for conformity, and in acknowledgements that such criticism and
demands are justified, all of which find their characteristic
expression in the normative terminology of ‘ought’, ‘must’, and
‘should’, ‘right’ and ‘wrong.’
This ‘internal’ dimension of rules thus distinguishes social rules
from mere group habits. By accepting secondary rules, officials need
not approve of them. Judges in an iniquitous legal system may
detest the rules they are required to apply, but by accepting them
they satisfy Hart’s conditions for a legal system to exist.
Hart concedes that where a legal system fails to receive general
approval, it would be both morally and politically objectionable. But
31
Legal positivism
You and I, as ordinary members of society, do not need to accept
the primary rules or the rule of recognition; it is necessary only
that the officials do so from ‘an internal point of view’. What does
this mean? Hart’s answer is as follows:
these moral and political criteria are not identifying characteristics
of the notion of ‘legal system’. The validity of a legal system is
therefore independent from its efficacy. A completely ineffective
rule may be a valid one – as long as it emanates from the rule of
recognition. But to be a valid rule, the legal system of which the rule
is a component must, as a whole, be effective.
Philosophy of Law
Law as norms: Hans Kelsen
Hans Kelsen (1881–1973), in his complex ‘pure theory of law’,
expounds a subtle and profound account of the way in which
we should understand law. We should do so, he insists, by
conceiving it to be a system of ‘oughts’ or norms. Kelsen does
concede that the law consists also of legal acts as determined by
these norms. But the essential character of law derives from norms
– which include judicial decisions and legal transactions such as
contracts and wills. Even the most general norms describe human
conduct.
Influenced by the great 18th-century philosopher, Immanuel Kant,
Kelsen accepts that we can understand objective reality only by the
application of certain formal categories like time and space that do
not ‘exist’ in nature: we use them in order to make sense of the
world. Similarly, to understand ‘the law’ we need formal categories,
such as the basic norm – or Grundnorm – which, as its name
suggests, lies at the base of any legal system (see below). Legal
theory, argues Kelsen, is no less a science than physics or chemistry.
Thus we need to disinfect the law of the impurities of morality,
psychology, sociology, and political theory. He thus propounds a
sort of ethical cleansing under which our analysis is directed to the
norms of positive law: those ‘oughts’ that declare that if certain
conduct (X) is performed, then a sanction (Y) should be applied by
an official to the offender. His ‘pure’ theory thus excludes that which
we cannot objectively know, including law’s moral, social, or
political functions. Law has but one purpose: the monopolization of
force.
32
Legal positivism
7. Hans Kelsen attempted the ethical cleansing of legal theory.
Kelsen’s concept of a norm entails that something ought to be,
or that something ought to happen – in particular, that a person
ought to behave in a specific way. Hence both the statement ‘the
door ought to be closed,’ and a red traffic light constitute norms. To
be valid, however, a norm must be authorized by another norm
33
Philosophy of Law
which, in turn, must be authorized by a higher legal norm in the
system. Kelsen is intensely relativistic: he repudiates the idea that
there are values ‘out there’. For him all norms are relative to the
individual or group under consideration.
The promotion of social order is achieved by governments enacting
norms that determine whether our conduct is lawful or unlawful.
These norms, argues Kelsen, provide sanctions for failure to comply
with them. Legal norms therefore differ from other norms in that
they prescribe a sanction. A legal system is founded on state
coercion; behind its norms is the threat of force. This distinguishes
the tax collector from the robber. Both demand your money. Both,
in other words, require that you ought to pay up. Both exhibit a
subjective act of will, but only the tax collector’s is objectively valid.
Why? Because, says Kelsen, the subjective meaning of the robber’s
coercive order is not interpreted as its objective meaning. Why not?
Because no basic norm is presupposed according to which one
ought to comply with this order. And why not? Because the robber’s
coercive order lacks the ‘lasting effectiveness without which no
basic norm is presupposed’. This demonstrates the essential
relationship in Kelsen’s theory between validity and effectiveness,
which is discussed below.
His model of a legal system is therefore a succession of
interconnected norms advancing from the most general ‘oughts’
(e.g. sanctions ought to be effected in accordance with the
constitution) to the most particular or ‘concrete’ (e.g. Charles is
contractually bound to mow Camilla’s grass). Each norm in this
hierarchical system draws its validity from another higher norm.
The validity of all norms is ultimately based on the basic norm.
As the validity of each norm depends on a higher norm whose
validity depends in turn on another higher norm, we eventually
reach a point of no return. This is the basic norm or Grundnorm.
All norms emanate from this norm in escalating levels of
‘concreteness’, including the very constitution of the state. Since,
34
by definition, the validity of the basic norm cannot depend on any
other norm, it has to be presupposed. Without this
presupposition, Kelsen claims, we cannot understand the legal
order. The basic norm exists, but only in the ‘juristic
consciousness’. It is an assumption that makes possible our
comprehension of the legal system by the legal scientist, judge, or
lawyer. It is not, however, selected arbitrarily, but by reference to
whether the legal order as a whole is ‘by and large’ effective. Its
validity depends on efficacy. In other words, the validity of the
basic norm rests, not on another norm or rule of law, but is
assumed – for the purpose of purity. It is therefore a hypothesis, a
wholly formal construct.
35
Legal positivism
The nature of the basic norm is illustrated by Kelsen’s religious
analogy in which a son is instructed by his father to go to school. To
this individual norm, the son replies, ‘Why should I go to school?’ In
other words, he asks why the subjective meaning of his father’s act
of will is its objective meaning, i.e. a norm binding for him – or,
which means the same thing, what is the basis of the validity of this
norm. The father responds, ‘Because God has commanded that
parents be obeyed – that is, God has authorized parents to issue
commands to children.’ The son retorts, ‘Why should one obey the
commands of God?’ He is, in Kelsenian terms, asking why the
subjective meaning of this act of will of God is also its objective
meaning – that is, a valid norm or, which amounts to the same
thing, what is the basis of the validity of this general norm. The only
possible answer to this is: because, as a believer, one presupposes
that one ought to obey the commands of God. This is the statement
of the validity of a norm that must be presupposed in a believer’s
thinking in order to ground the validity of the norms of a religious
morality. It constitutes the basic norm of a religious morality, the
norm that grounds the validity of all the norms of that morality – a
‘basic’ norm, because no further question can be raised about the
basis of its validity. The statement is not a positive norm – i.e. not a
norm posited by a real act of will – but a norm presupposed in a
believer’s thinking.
The basic norm is intended to have two major functions. First, it
assists us in distinguishing between the demands of a robber and
those of the law. In other words, it enables us to regard a coercive
order as objectively valid. Secondly, it explains the coherence and
unity of a legal order. All valid legal norms may be interpreted as a
non-contradictory field of meaning.
Kelsen frames the basic norm as follows:
Coercive acts ought to be performed under the conditions and in the
manner which the historically first constitution, and the norms
created according to it, prescribe. (In short: One ought to behave as
Philosophy of Law
the constitution prescribes.)
The basic norm, as a purely formal construct, has no specific
content. Any human conduct, Kelsen says, may be the subject
matter of a legal norm. Nor can the validity of a positive legal order
be denied merely because of the content of its norms.
Since Kelsen argues that the effectiveness of the whole legal order is
a necessary condition of its validity of every norm within it, implicit
in the very existence of a legal system is the fact that its laws are
generally obeyed. In The Pure Theory of Law he puts the matter
bluntly: ‘Every by and large effective coercive order can be
interpreted as an objectively valid normative order.’ But this is
problematic. How can we know whether laws are actually being
observed or disregarded? How do we test whether the law is, in
Kelsen’s phrase, ‘by and large’ effective? Many would say that the
efficacy or otherwise of a legal order is an empirical matter,
something we can witness or observe. But the pure theory spurns
‘sociological’ enquiries of this kind.
Kelsen also eschews any consideration of the reasons why the law
might be effective (its rationality, goodness, etc.). If the validity of a
legal order requires the effectiveness of its basic norm, it follows
that when that basic norm of the system no longer attracts general
36
support, there is no law. This is what happens after a successful
revolution. The existing basic norm no longer exists, and, Kelsen
says, once the new laws of the revolutionary government are
effectively enforced, lawyers may presuppose a new basic norm.
This is because the basic norm is not the constitution, but the
presumption that the altered state of affairs ought to be accepted in
fact.
Kelsen’s ideas have been cited by a number of courts in countries
which have experienced revolutions: Pakistan, Uganda, Rhodesia,
and Grenada.
Law as social fact: Joseph Raz
Raz argues, however, that the law is autonomous: we can identify its
content without recourse to morality. Legal reasoning, on the other
hand, is not autonomous; it is an inevitable, and desirable, feature
of judicial reasoning. For Raz, the existence and content of every
law may be determined by a factual enquiry about conventions,
institutions, and the intentions of participants in the legal system.
The answer to the question ‘what is law?’ is always a fact. It is never
a moral judgement. This marks him as a ‘hard’ or ‘exclusive’
positivist. ‘Exclusive’ because the reason we regard the law as
authoritative is the fact that it is able to guide our behaviour in a
way that morality cannot do. In other words, the law asserts its
37
Legal positivism
The writing of the Oxford philosopher, Joseph Raz (b. 1939) does
not lend itself to simple synopsis. As a leading ‘hard’ or ‘exclusivist’
legal positivist, Raz maintains that the identity and existence of a
legal system may be tested by reference to three elements; efficacy,
institutional character, and sources. Law is thus drained of its moral
content, based on the idea that legality does not depend on its moral
merit. ‘Soft’ positivists, like H. L. A. Hart, reject this view, and
acknowledge that content or merit may be included or incorporated
as a condition of validity. They are therefore also called
‘incorporationists’.
primacy over all other codes of conduct. Law is the ultimate source
of authority. Thus, a legal system is quintessentially one of
authoritative rules. It is this claim of authority that is the trademark
of a legal system.
Raz identifies three principal claims made by positivists and
attacked by natural lawyers:
Philosophy of Law
The ‘social thesis’: that law may be identified as a social fact,
without reference to moral considerations.
The ‘moral thesis’: that the moral merit of law is neither absolute
nor inherent, but contingent upon ‘the content of the law and the
circumstances of the society to which it applies’.
The ‘semantic thesis’: that normative terms such as ‘right’ and
‘duty’ are not used in moral and legal contexts in the same way.
Raz accepts only the ‘social thesis’ on the basis of the three accepted
criteria by which a legal system may be identified: its efficacy, its
institutional character, and its sources. From all three, moral
questions are excluded. Thus, the institutional character of law
means simply that laws are identified by their relationship to
certain institutions (e.g. the legislature). Anything – however
morally acceptable – not admitted by such institutions is not law,
and vice versa.
Raz actually postulates a stronger version of the ‘social thesis’ (the
‘sources thesis’) as the essence of legal positivism. His major
justification for the sources thesis is that it accounts for a primary
function of law: the setting of standards by which we are bound, in
such a way that we cannot excuse our non-compliance by
challenging the rationale for the standard.
It is mainly upon his acceptance of the social thesis, and his
rejection of the moral and semantic theses, that Raz assembles his
case against a general moral obligation to obey the law. In reaching
this conclusion, he repudiates three common arguments made for
38
the moral authority of law. First, it is often argued that to
distinguish, as positivists do, between law and other forms of social
control, is to neglect the functions of law; and because functions
cannot be described in a value-free manner, any functional account
of law must involve moral judgements – and so offend the social
thesis. Raz argues that, while law does indeed have certain
functions, his own analysis of them is value-neutral.
39
Legal positivism
Nor, secondly, does Raz accept that the content of law cannot be
determined exclusively by social facts: so, for example, since courts
unavoidably rely on explicitly moral considerations, they creep into
determinations of what the law actually is. Although Raz concedes
that moral concerns do enter into adjudication, he insists that this is
inevitable in any source-based system. But it does not, in his view,
establish a case against the sources thesis. Finally, it is occasionally
argued that what is distinctive about the law is that it conforms to
the ideal of the rule of law, the belief that no one is above the law.
Surely, some contend, this demonstrates that the law is indeed
moral. Raz attempts to refute this proposition by arguing that,
while conformity to the rule of law reduces the abuse of executive
power, it does not confer an independent moral merit upon the law.
For him the rule of law is a negative virtue – for the risk of arbitrary
power is created by the law itself. He thus concludes that, even in a
legal system that is fair and just, there is no prima facie duty to obey
the law.
Chapter 3
Law as interpretation
The foundations of legal philosophy were shaken in the 1970s by the
ideas of the American jurist, Ronald Dworkin (b. 1931) who in 1969
succeeded H. L. A. Hart as Professor of Jurisprudence at Oxford.
The dominance of legal positivism, especially in Britain, was over
the next three decades subjected to a comprehensive onslaught in
the form of a complex theory of law that is both controversial and
highly influential. His concept of law continues to exert
considerable authority, especially in the United States, whenever
contentious moral and political issues are debated. It is unthinkable
that any serious analysis of, say, the role of the United States
Supreme Court, the issue of abortion, or general questions of liberty
and equality could be conducted without a consideration of the
views of Ronald Dworkin. His constructive vision of law is both a
profound analysis of the concept of law and a compelling entreaty in
support of its enrichment.
Among the numerous elements of his sophisticated philosophy is
the contention that the law contains a solution to almost every
problem. This is at variance with the traditional – positivist –
perception that, when a judge is faced with a difficult case to which
no statute or previous decision applies, he exercises a discretion and
decides the case on the basis of what seems to him to be the correct
answer. Dworkin contests this position, and shows how a judge does
not make law, but rather interprets what is already part of the legal
40
Law as interpretation
8. Ronald Dworkin regards law as an interpretive process under which
individual rights are paramount.
materials. Through his interpretation of these materials, he gives
voice to the values to which the legal system is committed.
To understand Dworkin’s key proposition that law is a ‘gapless’
system, consider the following two situations:
An impatient beneficiary under a will murders the testator. Should
he be permitted to inherit?
41
A chess grand master distracts his opponent by continually
smiling at him. The opponent objects. Is smiling in breach of the
rules of chess?
Hard cases
Philosophy of Law
These are both ‘hard cases’ for in neither case is there a
determinable rule to resolve it. This gives legal positivists a
headache, for, as discussed in the last chapter, positivism generally
claims that law consists of rules determined by social facts. Where,
as in these examples, rules run out, the problem can be resolved
only by the exercise of a subjective, and hence potentially arbitrary,
discretion: a lawyer’s nightmare.
If, however, there is more to law than rules, as Dworkin claims, then
an answer may be found in the law itself. Hard cases such as these
may, in other words, be decided by reference to the legal materials;
there is no need to reach outside the law and so to allow subjective
judgements to enter.
The first puzzle mentioned above is drawn from the New York
decision of Riggs v. Palmer in 1899. The will in question was
validly executed and was in the murderer’s favour. But whether a
murderer could inherit was uncertain: the rules of testamentary
succession provided no applicable exception. The murderer should
therefore have a right to his inheritance. The New York court held,
however, that the application of the rules was subject to the
principle that ‘no person should profit from his own wrong’. Hence
a murderer could not inherit from his victim. This decision reveals,
Dworkin argues, that, in addition to rules, the law includes
principles.
In the second dilemma, Dworkin argues, the referee is called upon
to determine whether smiling is in breach of the rules of chess. The
rules are silent. He must therefore consider the nature of chess as a
game of intellectual skill; does this include the use of psychological
42
intimidation? He must, in other words, find the answer that best
‘fits’ and explains the practice of chess. To this question there will be
a right answer. And this is equally true of the judge deciding a
hard case.
Legal systems characteristically generate controversial or hard
cases such as these in which a judge may need to consider whether
to look beyond the strict letter of what the law is to determine what
it ought to be. He engages, in other words, in a process of
interpretation in which arguments that resemble moral claims
feature. This interpretive dimension of law is a fundamental
component of Dworkin’s theory. His assault on legal positivism is
premised on the impossibility of the separation between law and
morals that it proposes.
There are two phases in Dworkin’s conception of legal reasoning.
First he contended in the 1970s that legal positivism is unable to
explain the significance of legal principles in determining what the
law is. In the 1980s Dworkin advanced a more radical thesis that
law was essentially an interpretive phenomenon. This view rests on
two main premises. The first maintains that determining what the
law requires in a particular case necessarily involves a form of
interpretative reasoning. Thus, for example, to claim that the law
protects my right of privacy against the Daily Rumour constitutes a
conclusion of a certain interpretation. The second premise is that
interpretation always entails evaluation. If correct, this would all
but sound the death knell for legal postivists’ separation thesis.
43
Law as interpretation
Thus for Dworkin, law consists not merely of rules, as Hart
contends, but includes what Dworkin calls non-rule standards.
When a court has to decide a hard case it will draw on these (moral
or political) standards – principles and policies – in order to reach a
decision. No rule of recognition – as described by Hart and
discussed in the last chapter – exists to distinguish between legal
and moral principles. Deciding what the law is depends inescapably
on moral-political considerations.
Philosophy of Law
In a hard case the judge therefore draws on principles, including his
own conception of the best interpretation of the system of political
institutions and decisions of his community. ‘Could my decision’, he
must ask, ‘form part of the best moral theory justifying the whole
legal and political system?’ There can only be one right answer to
every legal problem; the judge has a duty to find it. His answer is
‘right’ in the sense that it fits best with the institutional and
constitutional history of his society and is morally justified. Legal
argument and analysis are therefore ‘interpretive’ because they
attempt to make the best moral sense of legal practices.
Dworkin’s attack on legal positivism is crucially founded on his
concern that the law ought to ‘take rights seriously’. Rights trump
other considerations such as community welfare. Individual rights
are seriously compromised if, as Hart claims, the result of a hard
case depends on the judge’s personal opinion, intuition, or the
exercise of his strong discretion. My rights may then simply be
subordinated to the interests of the community. Instead, Dworkin
contends, my rights should be recognized as part of the law. His
theory thus provides more muscle to the defence of individual rights
and liberty than legal positivism can deliver.
In his best-known and most comprehensive work, Law’s Empire,
Dworkin launches a wholesale attack on both ‘conventionalism’ and
pragmatism. The former argues that law is a function of social
convention which it then designates as legal convention. In other
words, it claims that law consists in no more than following certain
conventions (e.g. that decisions of higher courts are binding on
lower ones). Conventionalism also regards law as incomplete: the
law contains ‘gaps’ which judges fill with their own preferences.
Judges, in other words, exercise a ‘strong discretion’.
Conventionalist accounts of law, Dworkin argues, fail to provide
either a convincing account of the process of lawmaking or an
adequately robust defence of individual rights. In Dworkin’s vision
of ‘law as integrity’ (see below), a judge must think of himself not, as
44
the conventionalist would claim, as giving voice to his own moral or
political convictions, or even to those convictions which he thinks
the legislature or the majority of the electorate would approve, but
as an author in a chain of the common law. As Dworkin says,
He knows that other judges have decided cases that, although not
exactly like his case, deal with related problems; he must think of
their decisions as part of a long story he must interpret and then
continue, according to his own judgment of how to make the
developing story as good as it can be.
It is only what Dworkin calls ‘law as integrity’ (see below) that
provides an acceptable justification for the state’s use of force. Law’s
empire, he tells us, ‘is defined by attitude, not territory or power or
process’. Law, in other words, is an interpretive concept addressed
to politics in its widest sense. It adopts a constructive approach in
that it seeks to improve our lives and our community.
Principles and policies
Dworkin’s account of the judicial function requires the judge to
treat the law as if it were a seamless web. There is no law beyond the
law. Nor, contrary to the positivist thesis, are there any gaps in the
law. Law and morals are inextricably intertwined. There cannot
therefore be a rule of recognition, as described in the last chapter, by
45
Law as interpretation
Pragmatists, according to Dworkin, adopt a sceptical attitude
towards the view that past political decisions justify state coercion.
Instead, they find such justification in the justice or efficiency or
other virtue of the exercise of such coercion by a judge. This
approach fails to take rights seriously because it treats rights
instrumentally – they have no independent existence: rights are
simply a means by which to make life better. Pragmatism rests on
the claim that judges do – and should – make whatever decisions
seem to them best for the community’s future, rejecting consistency
with the past as valuable for its own sake.
which to identify the law. Nor does Hart’s view of law as a union of
primary and secondary rules provide an accurate model, for it omits
or at least neglects the importance of principles and policies.
Philosophy of Law
Dworkin claims that, while rules ‘are applicable in an all-or-nothing
fashion’, principles and policies have ‘the dimension of weight or
importance’. In other words, if a rule applies, and it is a valid rule, a
case must be decided in a way dictated by the rule. A principle, on
the other hand, provides a reason for deciding the case in a
particular way, but it is not a conclusive reason: it will have to be
weighed against other principles in the system.
Principles differ from policies in that the former is ‘a standard to be
observed, not because it will advance or secure an economic,
political, or social situation, but because it is a requirement of
justice or fairness or some other dimension of morality’. A ‘policy’,
however, is ‘that kind of standard that sets out a goal to be reached,
generally an improvement in some economic, political, or social
feature of the community’.
Principles describe rights; policies describe goals. But rights are
trumps. They have a ‘threshold weight’ against community goals.
They should not be squashed by a competing community goal.
Every civil case, he argues, raises the question, ‘Does the plaintiff
have a right to win?’ The community’s interests should not come
into play. Thus civil cases are, and should be, decided by principles.
Even where a judge appears to be advancing an argument of policy,
we should interpret him as referring to principle because he is, in
fact, determining the individual rights of members of the
community. Thus, should a judge appeal, say, to public safety, to
justify some abstract right, this should be read as an appeal to the
competing rights of those whose security will be forfeited if the
abstract right is made concrete.
In a ‘hard case’ – like the homicidal beneficiary in Riggs v. Palmer
(above) – no rule is immediately applicable. Thus the judge must
46
apply standards other than rules. The ideal judge – whom Dworkin
calls Hercules – must ‘construct a scheme of abstract and concrete
principles that provides a coherent justification for all common law
precedents and, so far as these are to be justified on principle,
constitutional and statutory principles as well’. Where the legal
materials permit more than one consistent interpretation, Hercules
will decide on the theory of law and justice which best coheres with
the ‘institutional history’ of his community.
Dworkin contends that conventionalism (or legal positivism) is
gravely impaired by arguments concerning the criteria of legal
validity. As we saw in the last chapter, legal positivists are generally
content with the fact that the rule of recognition stipulates that X is
law. The pedigree of a rule is thus conclusive of its validity. But the
basis of legal validity, Dworkin argues, cannot be determined solely
by the standards contained in the rule of recognition. This
constitutes what he calls the ‘semantic sting’ of legal positivism:
positivist arguments about the law are really semantic
disagreements concerning the meaning of the word ‘law’.
But Dworkin argues that the concept of legal validity is more than
mere promulgation in accordance with the rule of recognition.
Semantic theories contest the claim that there are universal
standards that exhaust the conditions for the proper application of
47
Law as interpretation
What if Hercules discovers a previous decision that does not ‘fit’ his
own interpretation of the law? Suppose it is a precedent decided by
a higher court which Hercules lacks the power to overrule? He may,
says Dworkin, treat it as an ‘embedded mistake’, and confine it to
having only ‘enactment force’. This means its effect would be
limited in future cases to its precise wording. Where, however, a
previous judgment is neither overruled nor is regarded as an
embedded mistake, it will generate what Dworkin calls
‘gravitational force’, that is, it will exert an influence that extends
beyond its actual wording: it will appeal to the fairness of treating
like cases alike.
the concept of law. Such theories, Dworkin argues, erroneously
suppose that significant disagreement is impossible unless there are
criteria for determining when our claims are sound, even if we
cannot accurately specify what these criteria are.
Philosophy of Law
Liberalism
His rights thesis is based on a form of liberalism that derives
from the view that ‘government must treat people as equals’. It
may not impose any sacrifice or constraint on any citizen that the
citizen could not accept without abandoning his sense of equal
worth. His analysis of political morality has three ingredients:
‘justice’, ‘fairness’, and ‘procedural due process’. ‘Justice’
incorporates both individual rights and collective goals which
would be recognized by the ideal legislator dedicated to treating
citizens with equal concern and respect. ‘Fairness’ refers to those
procedures that give all citizens roughly equal influence in
decisions that affect them. ‘Procedural due process’ relates to the
correct procedures for determining whether a citizen has violated
the law.
Upon this foundation of political liberalism, Dworkin has launched
numerous forays against, for example, the enforcement by the
criminal law of private morality, the idea of wealth as a value, and
the alleged injustice of positive discrimination.
His purpose is to ‘define and defend a liberal theory of law’. And this
is the mainspring of his assault on positivism, conventionalism, and
pragmatism. None of these theories of law provides an adequate
defence of individual rights. It is only ‘law as integrity’ (see below)
which affords a suitable defence against the advance by
instrumentalism upon individual rights and general liberty.
A key – controversial – component of Dworkinian legal theory is its
claimed affinity to literary interpretation. When we attempt to
interpret a work of art, Dworkin argues, we seek to understand it in
48
a particular way. We try to portray the book, movie, poem, or
picture accurately. We want to establish, as far as we are able, the
intentions of the author in a constructive manner. Why did Henry
James choose to write about these particular characters? What
was his purpose? In answering these sorts of questions, we
characteristically attempt to give the best account of the novel
we can.
Law as integrity
As a constructive interpreter of the preceding chapters of the law,
Hercules, the superhuman judge, will espouse the best account of
the concept of law. And, in Dworkin’s view, that consists in what he
calls ‘law as integrity’. This obliges Hercules to enquire whether his
interpretation of the law could form part of a coherent theory
justifying the whole legal system. What is ‘integrity’? Dworkin offers
the following description of its important elements:
[L]aw as integrity accepts law and legal rights wholeheartedly . . . It
supposes that law’s constraints benefit society not just by providing
predictability or procedural fairness, or in some other instrumental
49
Law as interpretation
Law, claims Dworkin, like a novel or a play, requires interpretation.
Judges are like interpreters of a developing story. They acknowledge
their duty to preserve rather than reject their judicial tradition.
They therefore develop, in response to their own beliefs and
instincts, theories of the most constructive interpretation of their
obligations within that tradition. We should therefore think of
judges as authors engaged in a chain novel, each one of whom is
required to write a new chapter which is added to what the next conovelist receives. Each novelist attempts to make a single novel out
of the previous chapters; he endeavours to write his chapter so that
the ultimate result will be coherent. To accomplish this, he requires
a vision of the story as it proceeds: its characters, plot, theme, genre,
and general purpose. He will try to find the meaning in the evolving
creation, and an interpretation that best justifies it.
way, but by securing a kind of equality among citizens that makes
their community more genuine and improves its moral justification
for exercising the political power it does. . . . It argues that rights and
responsibilities flow from past decisions and so count as legal, not
just when they are explicit in these decisions but also when they
follow from the principles of personal and political morality the
Philosophy of Law
explicit decisions presuppose by way of justification.
The collective application of coercion is defensible only when a
society accepts integrity as a political virtue. This enables it to
justify its moral authority to exercise a monopoly of force. Integrity
is also a safeguard against partiality, deceit, and corruption. It
ensures that the law is conceived as a matter of principle –
addressing all members of the community as equals. It is, in
short, an amalgam of values which form the essence of the liberal
society and the rule of law, or, as Dworkin, has now called it,
‘legality’.
Why do we value the law? Why do we respect those societies that
adhere to the law and, more importantly, celebrate their observance
of those political virtues that characterize states ‘under law’? We do
so, Dworkin suggests in his more recent work, because, while an
efficient government is laudable, there is a greater value that is
served by legality. A concern with the moral legitimacy of the law is
a primary element of Dworkin’s legal philosophy. It is based, in
large part, on the rather imprecise concept of ‘community’ or
‘fraternity’.
A political society that accepts integrity becomes a special form of
community because it asserts its moral authority to use coercion.
Integrity entails a kind of reciprocity between citizens, and an
acknowledgement of the significance of their ‘associative
obligation’. A community’s social practices spawn genuine
obligations when it is a true, not merely a ‘bare’, community. This
occurs when its members consider their obligations as special (i.e.
applying specifically to the group), personal (i.e. flowing between
50
members), and based on the equal concern for the welfare of all.
Where these four conditions are satisfied, members of a bare
community acquire the obligations of a true one.
Dworkin constructs his idea of political legitimacy upon this notion
of a true community. Political obligation, he argues, is an
illustration of associative obligation. To generate political
obligations, a community must be a true community. It is only a
community that supports the ideal of integrity that can be a
genuine, morally legitimate, associative community – because its
choices relate to obligation rather than naked force.
51
Law as interpretation
Comparing the judicial function to the process of literary criticism
accentuates the positive portrayal of law and the fundamental role
of judges within it. And Dworkin’s conception of a political
community as an association of principle is a powerfully attractive
one. It is a condition which few societies will achieve, but to which,
one hopes, many aspire.
Chapter 4
Rights and justice
Legal philosophy is inconceivable without an examination of the
fundamental ideas of rights and justice. Rights, legal and moral,
pervade the law and legal system, and are thus a central concern of
jurisprudence. And the ideal of justice is both a vaunted virtue of
domestic legal systems and, in its claims of universality, aspires to
transcend law itself.
Individuals and groups are nowadays quick to assert their right to
almost anything, and are no less adroit in claiming that their rights
have been violated. Increasing pressure is put on governments and
international organizations to safeguard and advance the rights of
women, of minorities, and of citizens in general. The enactment of
bills of rights in many countries has imposed new duties on courts
to recognize rights that are either explicitly or implicitly protected.
What is a right? Is there a distinction between my rights as
recognized by the law, and rights that I believe I ought to have?
What of the problems generated by the escalating variety of human
rights that individuals demand? Is it appropriate to insist on such
rights when – in the case, say, of the right to work or the right to
education – they entail considerable public expenditure?
While legal theory seeks answers to some of these questions, its
chief preoccupation has been to define the concept of a right, and to
52
develop theories to support or explain the nature of rights, and how
competing rights are to be reconciled.
There are two major theories of rights. The first is known as the
‘will’ theory, and holds that, when I have a right to do something,
what is effectively protected is my choice whether or not to do it. It
accentuates my freedom and self-fulfilment. The second theory,
known as the ‘interest’ theory, claims that the purpose of rights is to
protect, not my individual choice, but certain of my interests. It is
generally regarded as a superior account of what it is to have a right.
Hohfeld
The springboard for any analysis of rights is normally the
well-known analysis by the American jurist, Wesley Hohfeld
(1879–1918). He attempted to elucidate the proposition ‘X has a
right to do R’ which he argued could mean one of four things. First,
it could mean that Y (or anyone else) is under a duty to allow X to
do R; this means, in effect, that X has a claim against Y. He calls this
claim right simply a ‘right’. Secondly, it might mean that X is free to
do or refrain from doing something; Y owes no duty to X. He calls
this a ‘privilege’ (though it is often described as a ‘liberty’). Thirdly, it
could mean that X has a power to do R; X is simply free to do an
act which alters legal rights and duties or legal relations in general
(e.g. sell his property), whether or not he has a claim right or
privilege to do so. Hohfeld calls this a ‘power’. Finally, it might
53
Rights and justice
Those who espouse this theory raise two main arguments against
the will theory. First, they refute the view that the essence of a right
is the power to waive someone else’s duty. Sometimes, they argue,
the law limits my power of waiver without destroying my
substantive right (e.g. I cannot consent to murder or contract out of
certain rights). Secondly, there is a distinction between the
substantive right and the right to enforce it. Thus children clearly
lack the capacity or choice to waive such rights, but it would be
absurd, they say, to argue that therefore children have no rights.
suggest that X is not subject to Y’s (or anyone’s) power to change X’s
legal position. He calls this an ‘immunity’.
Each of these four ‘rights’, Hohfeld argues, has both ‘opposites’ and
‘correlatives’ (i.e. the other side of the same coin) as shown in the
box.
Hohfeld’s scheme of ‘jural relations’
right
privilege
power
immunity
no-right
duty
disability
liability
right
privilege
power
immunity
duty
no-right
liability
disability
Philosophy of Law
Opposites
Correlatives
In other words, to use Hohfeld’s own example, if X has a right
against Y that Y shall stay off X’s land, the correlative (and
equivalent) is that Y is under a duty to keep off the land. A privilege
is the opposite of a duty, and the correlative of a no-right. Hence,
whereas X has a right (or claim) that Y should stay off his land, X
himself has the privilege of entering on the land, or, in other words,
X does not have a duty to stay off.
Claim rights (i.e. rights in the ordinary sense) are, Hohfeld
maintains, strictly correlative to duties. To say that X has a claim
right of some kind is to say that Y (or someone else) owes a certain
duty to X. But to say that X has a certain liberty is not to say that
anyone owes him a duty. Thus, if X has a privilege (or liberty) to
wear a hat, Y does not have a duty to X, but a no-right that X should
not wear a hat. In other words, the correlative of a liberty is a no54
right. Similarly, the correlative of a power is a liability (i.e. being
liable to have one’s legal relations changed by another), the
correlative of an immunity is a disability (i.e. the inability to change
another’s legal relations).
And even where someone owes a duty to someone to do something,
the person to whom he owes such a duty does not necessarily have
any corresponding right. Thus, a teacher has certain duties towards
her students, but this does not necessarily confer any rights upon
them. Similarly, we acknowledge our duties to infants or animals;
yet many would claim that it does not follow from this that they
have rights. On the other hand, an advantage of a theory of rights
based on correlativity is that the claimant of a right to, say,
employment, is compelled to identify the party who is under a
corresponding duty to find him a job!
Rights theory
We live in the age of rights. Human rights, animal rights, moral and
political rights play a leading role in public debate. But in addition
to right-based theories, some moral and legal philosophers adopt
55
Rights and justice
This analysis has been extremely influential, even though it suffers
from certain limitations. All four of Hohfeld’s rights (which, in
modern accounts, are usually called claim rights, liberties, powers,
and immunities) are rights against a specific person or persons. But
it does not seem to be true that, whenever I am under some duty,
someone else has a corresponding right. Or vice versa. Can I not
have a duty without you (or anyone else) having a right that I should
perform it. Thus, the criminal law imposes certain duties on me
(say, to observe the rules of the road), but no specific person has a
correlative right to my performing these duties. This is because it is
possible for there to be a duty to do something which is not a duty
owed to someone. For example, a police officer is under a clear duty
to report offenders; but he owes this duty to no one in particular,
and, hence, it gives rise to no right in anyone.
either duty-based or goal-based theories. The differences between
the three is worth noting, and may be illustrated as follows. You are
opposed to torture because of the suffering of the victim (this is
rights-based), or because torture debases the torturer (duty-based),
or you may regard torture as unacceptable only when it affects
the interests of those other than the parties involved (utilitarian
goal-based).
Philosophy of Law
Ronald Dworkin’s theory of law is underpinned by his rights thesis
(see Chapter 3). Rights are trumps. The right to equal concern and
respect is fundamental to human dignity and to a fair society.
Equality is assigned primacy over liberty. And the ideal of equal
rights has had a spectacular impact in numerous societies; think of
the Civil Rights movement in the 1950s in the United States, and
the collapse of apartheid in South Africa. Constitutional change has
9. Nelson Mandela with the author soon after the ANC leader’s release
from 27 years of imprisonment. A trained lawyer, Mandela’s dedication
to the overthrow of apartheid made him an international symbol of the
struggle against injustice, and a champion of the establishment of
liberty and equality under law.
56
been wrought through the strength of legal and moral argument
based on the relatively uncomplicated concept of human equality.
The concept of human rights has acquired a prominent place in
contemporary political and legal debate today. Turn on the news or
read a newspaper: issues of human rights are ubiquitous. The idea
rests on the claim that each of us as a human being, regardless of
our race, religion, gender, or age, is entitled to certain fundamental
and inalienable rights – merely by virtue of our belonging to the
human race. Whether or not such rights are legally recognized is
irrelevant, as is the fact that they may or may not emanate from a
‘higher’ natural law (see Chapter 1).
10. In the United States the campaign for equality before the law was
protracted and painful. Racial prejudice assumed many forms, but the
American South produced its own violent brand: between 1889 and
1918, 2,522 blacks were lynched, including 50 women.
57
Rights and justice
The acceptance by the United Nations, in the aftermath of the
Holocaust, of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights in 1948,
and the International Covenants on Civil and Political Rights, and
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in 1976, reveals a dedication
by the community of nations to the universal conception and
protection of human rights.
Philosophy of Law
Human rights have passed through three generations. The first
generation were mostly the negative civil and political rights as
developed in the 17th and 18th centuries by English political
philosophers like Hobbes, Locke, and Mill (see Chapter 1). They are
negative in the sense that they generally prohibit interference with
the right-holder’s freedom. A good example is the First Amendment
to the American Constitution, which makes it unlawful for the
legislature to restrict a person’s freedom of speech.
The second generation consists in the essentially positive economic,
social, and cultural rights, such as the right to education, food, or
medical care. The third generation of human rights are primarily
collective rights which are foreshadowed in Article 28 of the
Universal Declaration which declares that ‘everyone is entitled to a
social and international order in which the rights set forth in this
Declaration can be fully realized’. These ‘solidarity’ rights include
the right to social and economic development and to participate in
and benefit from the resources of the earth and space, scientific and
technical information (which are especially important to the Third
World), the right to a healthy environment, peace, and
humanitarian disaster relief.
Justice
The law is frequently equated with justice. Courts are designated
‘courts of justice’, their buildings flamboyantly emblazoned with the
word itself, or its symbolic representations of equity and fairness.
Governments create ministries of ‘justice’ to oversee the
administration of the legal system. Alleged offenders are no longer
charged or prosecuted, but ‘brought to justice’. But caution is
required. The law occasionally deviates from justice. Worse, it may
actually be an instrument of injustice, as in Nazi Germany or
58
apartheid South Africa. Though the law may, in virtuous societies,
aspire to justice, it is mistaken to bracket the two together.
Justice, in any event, is a far from simple concept. Most discussions
of the subject begin with Aristotle’s claim that justice consists in
treating equals equally and ‘unequals’ unequally, in proportion to
their inequality. He distinguished between ‘corrective’ justice
(where a court redresses a wrong committed by one party against
another), and ‘distributive’ justice (which seeks to give each person
his due according to what he deserves). Distributive justice in
Aristotle’s view was chiefly the concern of the legislator. But he does
not tell us what justice actually is.
The significance of impartiality as a key element of justice is often
depicted in material form as Themis, the goddess of justice and law.
She typically clutches a sword in one hand and a pair of scales in the
other. The sword signifies the power of those who occupy judicial
positions; the scales symbolize the neutrality and impartiality with
which justice is served. In the 16th century, artists portrayed her
blindfolded to emphasize justice is blind: resistant to pressure or
influence.
Equality seems helpful in our search for a satisfactory concept of
justice. Treating equals equally and unequals unequally has a
59
Rights and justice
We gain somewhat clearer guidance from the Romans. The Corpus
Juris Civilis is the body of civil law codified under the order of
the Emperor Justinian (c.482–565). Justice is there defined as ‘the
constant and perpetual wish to give everyone that which they
deserve’. And the ‘precepts of the law’ are stated to be ‘to live
honestly, not to injure others, and to give everyone his due’.
These expressions, though fairly general, do contain at least
three important overlapping features of any conception of justice.
It conveys the importance of the individual; secondly, that
individuals be treated consistently and impartially; and, thirdly,
equally.
Philosophy of Law
11. The so-called goddess of justice wears a blindfold, and clutches a
pair of scales in one hand, and a sword in the other. This statue stands
above the Central Criminal Court (the ‘Old Bailey’) in London.
certain appeal – provided we can agree on objectively ascertainable
and relevant grounds for distinguishing between individuals. One
criterion might be their different needs. Elizabeth is rich, James is
poor. Would a reasonable person object to providing resources to
him rather than to her? One might if the cause of James’ poverty is
his profligacy and extravagance. The principle of need is therefore
not without difficulty.
What of desert? Can justice be made to turn on what individuals
deserve? It is often said that someone got his ‘just deserts’,
suggesting that since Doris worked hard, she deserves her
promotion over Boris. But Boris may lack Doris’s drive because he
has to support several dependants and fatigue is an impediment to
60
his commitment to his job. Since he lacks complete control over his
depressing domestic predicament, basing justice on desert could
actually generate injustice!
Justice between individuals is no less problematic than the
challenge of social justice: the establishment of social and political
institutions to slice the cake fairly. Modern accounts of justice are
inclined to focus on how society can most fairly distribute the
burdens and benefits of social life. One especially influential theory
is that of utilitarianism, and its modern alternative, the economic
analysis of law. The rest of this chapter is devoted to considering
this approach to justice. I shall then sketch the main features of
John Rawls’s celebrated theory of ‘justice as fairness’.
Utilitarianism
Nature has placed mankind under the governance of two sovereign
masters, pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we
ought to do, as well as to determine what we shall do. On the one
hand the standard of right and wrong, on the other the chain of
causes and effects, are fastened to their throne. . . . The principle of
utility recognizes this subjection, and assumes it for the foundation
of that system, the object of which is to rear the fabric of felicity by
the hands of reason and of law. Systems which attempt to question
it, deal in sounds instead of sense, in caprice instead of reason, in
darkness instead of light.
The determining factor is thus the outcome of our actions: do they
make us happy or sad? Through the application of a ‘felicific
calculus’, he argued, we can test the ‘happiness factor’ of any action
61
Rights and justice
Justice, according to utilitarians, lies in the maximization of
happiness. Most famously, Jeremy Bentham (whose positivist
theories we examined in Chapter 2) argued that, since in our daily
lives, we strive to be happy and avoid pain, so too should society be
structured to realize this objective:
or rule. Utilitarianism thus looks to the consequences of actions; it
is therefore described as a form of ‘consequentialism’ which must be
distinguished from deontological systems of ethics which hold that
the rightness or wrongness of an action is logically independent of
its consequences – ‘Let justice be done though the heavens fall!’ is
one of its uplifting slogans.
Philosophy of Law
It is important to note that utilitarians distinguish between ‘act
utilitarianism’ (the rightness or wrongness of an action is to be
judged by the consequences, good or bad, of the action itself ) and
‘rule utilitarianism’ (the rightness or wrongness of an action is to be
judged by the goodness or badness of the consequences of a rule
that everyone should perform the action in like circumstances).
Generally, discussions of utilitarianism concern themselves with
‘act utilitarianism’, though legal theorists often appeal to ‘ideal rule
utilitarianism’ which provides that the rightness or wrongness of an
action is to be judged by the goodness or badness of a rule which, if
observed, would have better consequences than any other rule
governing the same action. This form of rule utilitarianism has clear
advantages in circumstances where a judge is called upon to decide
whether the plaintiff should be awarded damages against the
defendant. He must obviously disregard the result of his judgment
on the particular defendant.
Modern utilitarians tend to regard Bentham’s version of hedonistic
act utilitarianism as rather quaint. Nor is there a great deal of
contemporary sympathy for John Stuart Mill’s form of
utilitarianism that distinguishes between higher and lower
pleasures – implying that pleasure is a necessary condition for
goodness, but that goodness depends on qualities of experience
other than pleasantness and unpleasantness. This may be because
both Bentham and Mill appear to substitute their own preferences
for the preferences they believe people ought to have.
Contemporary utilitarians therefore talk of maximizing the extent
62
Evaluating the consequences of our actions
I am stranded on a desert island with no one but a dying man
who, in his final hours, entrusts me with $10,000 which he
asks me to give to his daughter, Rita, if I ever manage to
return to the United States. I promise to do so, and, after my
rescue, I find Rita living in a mansion; she has married a
millionaire. The $10,000 will now make little difference to
her financial situation. Should I not instead donate the
money to charity? As a utilitarian, I consider the possible
consequences of my action. But what are the consequences? I
must weigh the result of my broken promise against the
benefit of giving the $10,000 to an animal welfare charity.
breaking it? If I break my promise, I may be less likely to
keep other promises I have made, and others may be encouraged to take their own promise-keeping less seriously. I
must, in other words, attempt to calculate all the likely consequences of my choice. But a non-consequentialist Kantian
might argue that the reason why I should give the money to
Rita is that I have promised to do so. My action ought to be
guided not by some uncertain future consequence, but by an
unequivocal past fact: my promise. My reply might be that I
do consider the past fact of my promise – but only to the
extent that it affects the total consequences of my action of
giving the money to the charity instead of to Rita. I might
also say that it is absurd to argue that I am obliged to keep
every promise I make.
to which people may achieve what they want; we should seek to
satisfy people’s preferences. This has the merit of not imposing any
conception of ‘the good’ which leaves out of account individual
63
Rights and justice
Would keeping my promise have better consequences than
choice: you may prefer football to Foucault, or Motown to Mozart.
But this approach is afflicted with its own problems; see below.
Philosophy of Law
Utilitarianism has the considerable attraction of replacing moral
intuition with the congenially down-to-earth idea of human
happiness as a measure of justice. But the theory has long
encountered resistance from those who argue that it fails to
recognize the ‘separateness of persons’. They claim that
utilitarianism, at least in its pure form, regards human beings as
means rather than ends in themselves. Separate individuals, it is
contended, are important to utilitarians only in so far as they are
‘the channels or locations where what is of value is to be found’.
Secondly, opponents of utilitarianism claim that, though the
approach treats individual persons equally, it does so only by
effectively regarding them as having no worth: their value is not as
persons, but as ‘experiencers’ of pleasure or happiness. Thirdly,
critics query why we should regard as a valuable moral goal the
mere increase in the sum of pleasure or happiness abstracted from
all questions of the distribution of happiness, welfare, and so on.
A fourth kind of attack alleges that the analogy used by utilitarians,
of a rational single individual prudently sacrificing present
happiness for later satisfaction, is false for it treats my pleasure as
replaceable by the greater pleasure of others. Some have attacked
the assumption at the very heart of utilitarianism: why should we
seek to satisfy people’s desires? Certain desires – e.g. cruelty to
animals – are unworthy of satisfaction. And are our needs and
desires not, in any event, subject to manipulation by advertising? If
so, can we detach our ‘real’ preferences from our ‘conditioned’ ones?
Is it then acceptable for utilitarians to seek to persuade individuals
to prefer Dworkin to Doo Wop? If so, how do we justify doing this?
If we answer that the principle of utility requires us to do it, are we
not suggesting that the felicific calculus includes not only what we
want, but also what we may one day decide we want as a result of
persuasion or re-education?
64
A different point is made by John Rawls who argues that
utilitarianism defines what is right in terms of what is ‘good’. This
means that the theory starts with a conception of what is ‘good’ (e.g.
happiness) and then concludes that an action is right in so far as it
maximizes that ‘good’.
Should we, in any event, seek to maximize welfare? Some consider it
more important that welfare be justly distributed. Another target of
critics is the intractable problem of calculating the consequences of
one’s actions: how can we know in advance what results will follow
from what we propose to do. And how far into the future do – or can
– we extend the consequences of our actions?
The economic analysis of law
Like utilitarianism, those who champion an economic analysis of
law believe that our rational everyday choices ought to form the
basis of what is just in society. Each of us, it is argued, seeks to
maximize our satisfactions – and if it means paying for something
that will achieve this objective, we are generally willing to do so. In
other words, if I want a Ferrari badly enough, I will be prepared to
find the money to buy one.
The leader of this latter-day form of economic hedonism is the
jurist and judge Richard Posner (b. 1939). Although he denies
that he espouses a utilitarian position, Posner maintains that a
good deal of the common law can be explained as if judges were
seeking to maximize economic welfare. In other words, many
legal doctrines are based, often unconsciously, on judicial
attempts to find the most efficient outcome. Judges, Posner
65
Rights and justice
There are obvious difficulties in attempting to weigh my pleasure
against your pain. Similarly, on a larger scale, judges or legislators
will rarely find it easy to choose between two or more courses of
action, and sensibly balance the majority’s happiness against a
minority’s misery.
claims, frequently decide hard cases by choosing an outcome
which will maximize the wealth of society. By ‘wealth
maximization’ Posner means a state of affairs in which goods and
other resources are in the hands of those people who value them
most; that is to say, those who are willing and able to pay more
to have them.
Philosophy of Law
To take a simple example, suppose you buy my copy of this book for
$5. The highest price you were willing to pay was $10. Your wealth
has therefore been increased by $5. Similarly, Posner argues, society
maximizes its wealth when all its resources are distributed in such a
way that the sum of everyone’s transactions is as high as possible.
This is, he claims, is exactly as it should be.
Economic factors, Posner and his so-called Chicago School claim,
explain several doctrinal developments of the law. For instance, in
the law of negligence, liability generally depends on what is most
efficient economically. The common law method is to allocate
responsibilities between those engaged in interacting activities so as
to maximize the joint value, or, what amounts to the same thing,
minimize the joint cost of the activities. This is achieved by
redefining a property right, or by devising a new rule of liability, or
by recognizing a contract right. And Posner analyses several aspects
of the common law in this manner.
Reading Posner’s prodigious writing does require a fair degree of
familiarity with economic theory. In particular, he deploys various
concepts of efficiency, especially that of Pareto optimality, and the
Kaldor-Hicks test. The former (named after the Italian economist
Vilfredo Pareto) describes a situation which cannot be altered
without making at least one person worse off than he was prior to
the change. A change is said to be Kaldor-Hicks efficient when the
increase in value to those who gain exceeds the losses to those who
lose. Both are measured in terms of readiness to pay. He applies also
the concept of ‘diminishing marginal utility’ which refers to the fact
that $1 given to an impoverished beggar would have a major effect
66
on his wealth, whereas to a millionaire $1 would make almost no
difference at all.
The celebrated Coase theorem (named after the economist Ronald
Coase) postulates a situation in which one outcome is the most
‘efficient’. See, for example, the circumstances illustrated in the box
on page 68.
Real life may, however, be more complex than this simple example
suggests. Certain costs would inevitably be incurred in this process.
The straightforward version of the Coase theorem may thus be
stated as follows: where there are zero transaction costs, the
efficient outcome will occur regardless of the choice of legal rule.
More fundamentally perhaps, can wealth maximization plausibly
be equated with justice? It is doubtful whether wealth
maximization is a value – in itself or instrumentally – that a society
would consider worth trading off against justice. Many would doubt
whether increasing social wealth would really improve society, or
suggest that our desires are more complex than Posner claims.
Justice as fairness
A Theory of Justice by John Rawls (1921–2002) is widely regarded
as a tour de force. It expounds the concept of justice as fairness, and
has – justly – become the focal point for contemporary discussions
of the subject.
The idea of justice as fairness may, at first blush, strike you as trite.
67
Rights and justice
What has any of the above to do with justice? It presumes an initial
distribution of wealth which may be wholly unjust. ‘Efficiency’ is an
instrument by which to maintain existing inequalities. In other
words, is the economic analysis of law little more than a particular
ideological predilection that fortifies the capitalist, free-market
system?
A factory emits smoke which causes damage to laundry hung
outdoors by five nearby residents. In the absence of any corrective measures, each resident would suffer $75 in damages,
a total of $375. The smoke damage may be prevented in one
of two ways: either a smoke-screen could be installed on the
factory’s chimney, at a cost of $150, or each resident could be
provided with an electric tumble-drier at a cost of $50 per
resident. The efficient solution is obviously to install the
smoke-screen since it eliminates total damage of $375 for an
outlay of only $150, and it is cheaper than purchasing five
electric driers for $250. Would the outcome be efficient if
the right to clean air were assigned to the residents or if the
Philosophy of Law
right to pollute is given to the factory? In the case of the
former, the factory has three choices: pollute and pay $375 in
damages, install a smoke-screen for $150, or buy five tumbledriers for the residents at a total cost of $250. The factory
would, naturally, install the smoke-screen: the efficient solution. If there is a right to pollute, the residents have three
choices: suffer their collective damages of $375, buy five driers for $250, or buy a smoke-screen for the factory for $150.
They, too, would choose to buy the smoke-screen. The efficient outcome would therefore be achieved regardless of the
assignment of the legal right.
This assumption is based on the view that the residents
would incur no costs in coming together in order to negotiate
with the factory. Coase calls this ‘zero transaction costs’.
But, in dismissing utilitarianism as a means of determining justice,
Rawls rejects the very idea of inequality – even if it secures
maximum welfare. Welfare, he argues, is not about benefits, but
68
Rights and justice
12. John Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness has exerted considerable
influence on the analysis of this difficult concept.
‘primary social goods’ which includes self-respect. In particular, he
contends that questions of justice are prior to questions of
happiness. In other words, it is only when we regard a particular
pleasure as just that we can judge whether it has any value. How can
we know whether the gratification Tom derives from torture
should be counted as having any value before we know whether the
practice of torture is itself just? Put another way, utilitarianism
defines what is right in terms of what is good, while Rawls considers
what is right as prior to what is good.
69
Philosophy of Law
Chapter 1 touched on the social contract theories of Hobbes, Locke,
and Rousseau. Rawls’s theory of justice as fairness is rooted in this
enduring idea. In A Theory of Justice, he expresses the objective of
his project as carrying the social contract to a higher level of
abstraction. To do so, he argues, we are to think not that the original
contract as one to enter a particular society or to set up a particular
form of government, but that the principles of justice for the basic
structure of society are the object of the original agreement. They
are the principles that free and rational persons seeking to further
their own interests would accept in an initial position of equality
as defining the fundamental terms of their association. These
principles regulate all further agreements; they specify the types
of social cooperation and the forms of government that can be
established. This manner of treating the principles of justice he calls
justice as fairness.
He stresses the need to distinguish between people’s genuine
judgements about justice and their subjective, self-interested
intuitions. The inevitable distinction between the two must be
adjusted by re-examining our own judgements so that we ultimately
reach a state of affairs in which our considered intuitions are in
harmony with our considered principles. This is the position of
‘reflective equilibrium’.
Rawls presents an imaginary picture of the people in the ‘original
position’, shrouded in a ‘veil of ignorance’, debating the principles of
justice. They do not know their gender, class, religion, or social
position. Each person represents a social class, but they do not
know whether they are intelligent or dim, strong or weak, or even
the country or period in which they are living. And they have only
certain elementary knowledge about the laws of science and
psychology.
In this state of almost perfect ignorance, they are required
unanimously to choose the general principles that will define the
terms under which they will live as a society. In this process they are
70
motivated by rational self-interest: each seeks those principles
which will give him or her (but they are unaware of their gender!)
the greatest opportunity of accomplishing his or her chosen
conception of the good life. Stripped of their individuality, the
people in the original position will select, says Rawls, a ‘maximin’
principle which is explained by Rawls’s own gain and loss table
(slightly adapted).
I am faced with a choice from a number of several possible
circumstances. Suppose I choose D1, and C1 occurs. I will lose
$700. But if C2 occurs, I will gain $800 and, if I am really fortunate
and C3 occurs, I will gain $1,200. And the same applies in the case
of both decisions D2 and D3. Gain g therefore depends on the
individual’s decision d and the circumstances c. Thus g is a function
of d and c. Or, to express it mathematically g = f (d, c).
Exercising their choice, the people in the original position, as
rational individuals, would also select principles that ensure that
Decisions
Circumstances
C1
C2
C3
D1
−$700
$800
$1,200
D2
−$800
$700
$1,400
D3
$500
$600
$800
71
Rights and justice
What would I choose? The ‘maximin’ principle dictates that I opt
for D3. In this situation the worst that can happen to me is that I
gain $500, and this is clearly better than the worst for the other
actions (in which I stand to lose either $800 or $700).
Philosophy of Law
the worst condition one might find oneself in, when the veil of
ignorance is lifted, is the least undesirable of the available
alternatives. In other words, I will select those principles which, if I
happen to end up at the bottom of the social order, will be in my
best interests. Similarly, Rawls argues, the people in the original
position will choose the following two principles.
[1] Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total
system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of
liberty for all.
[2] Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are
both:
(a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged, consistent with
the just savings principle, and
(b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of
fair equality of opportunity.
The first principle has what Rawls calls ‘lexical priority’ over the
second. In other words, the people in the original position place
liberty before equality. Why? Because of the ‘maximin’ strategy,
described above, no one wants to risk his or her liberty when the veil
of ignorance is lifted – and it is revealed that they are among the
least well-off members of society!
Similarly, each will opt for clause (a) of the second principle, the
so-called ‘difference principle’. This ensures that the worst anyone
could be is ‘least advantaged’ and, if they do end up as members of
this group, they will benefit from this clause. It would be entirely
rational to choose this principle – rather than either total equality or
some form of greater inequality – because of the respective risks of
being worse off or reducing the prospects of improving their lot.
And, in a society that puts liberty above equality, they will be in a
better position to improve their lot. Why? Because various ‘social
primary goods’ (which Rawls defines to include rights, liberties,
powers, opportunities, income, wealth, and especially self-respect)
are more likely to be attained in a society that protects liberty.
72
Rawls argues that the people in the original position will select the
difference principle because neither of its two principal competitors
(the ‘system of natural liberty’ and the idea of ‘fair equality of
opportunity’) offers them the prospect of prosperity should they
turn out to be among the least advantaged. The former corresponds
to an uncontrolled, free-market economy indifferent to wealth
distribution. The people in the original position would jettison this
principle, he claims, because it ‘permits distributive shares to be
improperly influenced by . . . factors so arbitrary from a moral point
of view’. They would regard the accident of being born into an
affluent family as morally irrelevant.
Note that Rawls’s second principle includes two significant
limitations to secure the interests of the least advantaged. First, he
introduces the ‘just savings principle’ which requires the people in
the original position to ask themselves how much they would be
willing to save at each level of the advance of their society, on the
assumption that all other generations will save at the same rate.
Remember that they have no idea which stage of civilization their
society has reached. Consequently they will save some of their
resources for future generations. The second limitation refers to the
fact that jobs should be available to all.
Rawls’s project is a highly ambitious one and, while it has won
enormous praise and generated a huge literature, critics have, not
surprisingly, expressed reservations about several features of his
73
Rights and justice
They would spurn the second arrangement even though it is plainly
preferable to the first. While it rewards natural talent and its
application, this system suffers from a similar deficiency: it attaches
moral relevance to individual talent, but this is no less accidental
than being the offspring of a millionaire. In neither situation, do
accidents of birth have any association with desert. If they choose
the difference principle, however, it guarantees that talented
individuals may increase their wealth only if, in the process, they
also increase the wealth of the least advantaged.
Philosophy of Law
theory. For example, some oppose the very idea of any patterned
distribution of social goods. Others attack the ‘original position’ as
artificial (can people really be wholly stripped of their values?) or as
necessarily producing the result that Rawls postulates: why should
they prefer liberty to equality?
In response to some of this criticism, Rawls published in 1993
another book, Political Liberalism, in which he refines and modifies
a number of his original ideas. I cannot here analyse the plethora of
critical debate, but an important misunderstanding is clarified in
this later work. Rawls explains that ‘justice as fairness’ is not
intended to provide a universal standard of social justice. His theory
is a practical one that pertains to modern constitutional
democracies. His is, in other words, a political and practical – rather
than a metaphysical – conception of justice, philosophically neutral,
that transcends philosophical argument.
In pursuit of what he calls an ‘overlapping consensus’, Rawls posits
his principles of justice as the terms under which members of a
pluralistic, democratic community with competing interests and
values might achieve political accord. His conception of political
liberalism acknowledges that this consensus may be challenged by a
state’s establishment of a shared moral or religious doctrine. But
the community’s sense of justice would prevail over the state’s
interpretation of the public good.
74
Chapter 5
Law and society
So far we have been preoccupied with normative legal theory, and
its endeavours to explain the concept of law, as it were, from within.
That is to say, normative legal theory concentrates on legal doctrine
and the relations between rules, concepts, principles, and other
constructs employed by courts and lawyers engaged in the actual
practice of the law. But there is another approach to legal analysis
that attempts to understand the nature of these phenomena by
reference to the social conditions in which they function. This
sociological approach has exercised a considerable influence, often
unacknowledged, on the philosophy of law.
For example, Hart’s insistence that officials accept the rule of
recognition ‘from the internal point of view’ and his claim that there
should be a ‘critical reflective attitude’ to certain patterns of
behaviour as a common standard (see Chapter 2) echo Max Weber’s
concept of internal legitimation (see below).
A sociological account of law normally rests on three closely related
claims: that law cannot be understood except as a ‘social
phenomenon’, that an analysis of legal concepts provides only a
partial explanation of ‘law in action’, and that law is merely one
form of social control.
Though the genesis of sociological jurisprudence or the sociology of
75
law may be traced back to the trail-blazing writings of Roscoe
Pound and Eugen Ehrlich, this chapter focuses on the two giants of
social theory—Émile Durkheim and Max Weber – whose impact on
jurisprudence has been most profound. I shall also have something
to say about the impact of Karl Marx on thinking about law and the
legal system, as well as about two leading social theorists, Jürgen
Habermas and Michel Foucault, whose writings continue to exert
a considerable influence in certain quarters of contemporary legal
theory.
Philosophy of Law
Émile Durkheim
Among the central preoccupations of Durkheim (1859–1917) is the
question of what holds societies together. Why do they not drift
apart? His answer points to the crucial role of law in promoting and
maintaining this social cohesion. He shows how, as society advances
from religion to secularism, and from collectivism to individualism,
law becomes concerned less with punishment than compensation.
But punishment performs a significant role in expressing the
collective moral attitudes by which social solidarity is preserved.
He distinguishes between what he calls mechanical solidarity and
organic solidarity. The former exists in simple, homogeneous
societies which have a uniformity of values and lack any significant
division of labour. These uncomplicated communities tend to be
collective in nature; there is very little individualism. In advanced
societies, however, where there is division of labour, a high degree of
interdependence exists. There is substantial differentiation, and
collectivism is replaced by individualism. These forms of social
solidarity are, he argues, reflected in the law: classify the different
types of law and you will find the different types of social solidarity
to which it corresponds.
Crime, according to Durkheim, is a perfectly normal aspect of social
life. Moreover, he provocatively suggests, it is an integral part of all
healthy societies. This is because crime is closely connected to the
76
social values expressed in the ‘collective conscience’: an act becomes
criminal when it offends deeply held aspects of this collective
conscience. An action does not shock the common conscience
because it is criminal, rather it is criminal because it shocks the
common conscience.
Punishment is an essential element of his conception of crime: the
state reinforces the collective conscience by punishing those who
offend against the state itself. He defines punishment as ‘a
passionate reaction of graduated intensity that society exercises
through the medium of a body acting upon those of its members
who have violated certain rules of conduct’.
He shows also how punishment as a form of social control is more
intense in less developed societies. As societies progress, the form of
punishment becomes less violent and less harsh. But because
Law and society
13. Primitive societies practised cruel punishments like burning at the
stake. As societies progress, Durkheim argued, the form of punishment
diminishes in its cruelty.
77
punishment results from crime, he identifies an important
correlation between the evolution of crime and the forms of social
solidarity.
Max Weber
Philosophy of Law
The German sociologist Max Weber (1864–1920) trained as lawyer,
and he assigns to the law a central role in his general sociological
theory. Weber’s classification of the types of law is founded on the
different kinds of legal thought, and ‘rationality’ is the key. On this
basis, he distinguishes between ‘formal’ systems and ‘substantive’
systems. The crux of this distinction is the extent to which the
system is ‘internally self-sufficient’, by which he means that the
rules and procedures required for decision-making are accessible
within the system.
His second critical distinction is between ‘rational’ and ‘irrational’:
these terms describe the manner in which the materials (rules,
procedures) are applied in the system. Thus the highest stage of
rationality is reached where there is an
integration of all analytically derived legal propositions in such a
way that they constitute a logically clear, internally consistent, and,
at least in theory, gapless system of rules, under which, it is implied,
all conceivable fact situations must be capable of being logically
subsumed.
Two principal, and related, elements of Weber’s complex theory will
be considered briefly here: his concern to explain the development
of capitalism in Western societies and his notion of legitimate
domination.
In respect of the first problem, he attempts to show that law is
affected only indirectly by economic circumstances. He conceives of
law as being ‘relatively autonomous’, claiming that ‘generally it
appears . . . that the development of the legal structure has by no
78
means been predominantly determined by economic factors’. For
Weber, law is fundamentally related to, but not determined by,
economic factors. Rational economic conduct (‘profit-making
activity’ and ‘budgetary management’) is at the heart of the
capitalist system; this rationalism is facilitated by the certainty and
predictability of logically formal rational law. The presence of this
type of law assists, but does not cause, the advance of capitalism.
Weber regards formally rational law as one of the preconditions of
capitalism because it provides the necessary certainty and
predictability that is essential if entrepreneurs are to pursue
their profit-making enterprises. The achievement of this formal
rationality required, in Weber’s view, the systematization of the
legal order, a systematization which he found remarkably absent
from the English law.
Secondly, the English legal profession was, during the rise of
capitalism, extremely centralized in London, close to the commercial
district known as the City. Moreover, lawyers customarily served as
advisers to businessmen and corporations. This encouraged them to
adjust the law to suit the interests of their commercial clients.
Thirdly, unlike their Continental counterparts, English lawyers
resembled craft guilds in their education, training, and
79
Law and society
How, then, could he explain the emergence of capitalism in
England? This question has troubled many sociologists. Three
possible explanations are offered for this apparent contradiction in
Weber’s work. First, it is clear that, although English law lacked the
systematic order of the Roman law, it was a highly formalistic legal
system. Indeed, Weber characterized such formalism (which
required, for example, civil actions to follow the precise and
exacting procedures of specific writs for specific civil suits) as
irrational. It was this very formalism, Weber says, that produced a
stabilizing influence on the legal system; and it created a greater
degree of security and predictability in the economic market-place.
specialization, which produced a formalistic treatment of the law,
bound by precedent. This led to what Weber calls, following Roman
law, ‘cautelary jurisprudence’: emphasis is laid on drafting
instruments and devising new clauses to prevent future litigation.
This resulted in a close relationship between lawyers and their
(mostly commercial) clients. In other words, this feature of legal
practice compensated for the lack of systematization in the law
itself.
Philosophy of Law
It seems therefore that what Weber is really saying is that England
developed a capitalist economic system, despite the absence of legal
systematization, because other important components of the legal
system engendered it, but that it may have developed even more
rapidly and more efficiently if the common law had been less
irrational and unsystematic.
Weber’s general thesis is that the formal rationalization of law in
Western societies is a result of capitalism interested in strictly
formal law and legal procedure and ‘the rationalism of officialdom
in absolutist States [which] led to the interest in codified systems
and in homogeneous law’. He is not seeking to provide an economic
explanation for this phenomenon, but identifies several factors that
account for the development, including, in particular, the growth of
bureaucracy which established, as we saw above, the basis for the
administration of a rational law conceptually systematized.
In explaining why people believe they are obliged to obey the law
Weber draws his famous distinction between three types of
legitimate domination: traditional (where ‘legitimacy is claimed for
it and believed in by sanctity of age-old rules and powers’),
charismatic (based on ‘devotion to the exceptional sanctity, heroism
or exemplary character of an individual person’), and legal-rational
domination (which rests on ‘a belief in the legality of enacted rules
and the right of those elevated to authority under such rules to issue
commands’). It is, of course, this third type that is a central feature
of Weber’s account of law. And, though the concept of legal-rational
80
On the other hand, in a society dominated by a charismatic leader,
legal thought is formally and substantively irrational, justice is
charismatic, obedience is in response to the charismatic leader, and
in a society that is genuinely dominated by a charismatic leader,
there is no administration at all.
While Weber is widely regarded as the leading sociologist of law, his
detractors have found numerous flaws in his analysis, particularly
in respect of the two theories I have sketched above. It is claimed,
for example, that his account of the process of domination is more
complex than the formal, legal manifestation upon which Weber
focuses. And some find his attempt to explain the rise of capitalism
in England unconvincing.
Karl Marx
While Karl Marx (1818–83) and Friedrich Engels (1820–95) do not
provide a comprehensive or systematic account of law, their social
81
Law and society
authority is bound up with his theory of value (which argues for the
sociologist of law adopting a detached view of his subject), the
important link is between this form of domination and the modern
bureaucratic state. Under the other forms of domination, authority
resides in persons; under bureaucracy it is vested in rules. The
hallmark of legal-rational authority is its so-called impartiality.
But it depends upon what Weber calls the principle of ‘formalistic
impersonality’: officials exercise their responsibilities ‘without
hatred or passion, and hence without affection or enthusiasm.
The dominant norms are concepts of straightforward duty without
regard to personal considerations.’ The importance of Weber’s
sociology of law lies in the correlation between the various
typologies. For example, in a society with legal-rational
domination, the form of legal thought is logical formal rationality:
justice and the judicial process are both rational, obedience is
owed to the legal order, and the form of administration is
bureaucratic-professional.
Philosophy of Law
theory bristles with observations about the relationship between
law and economics (or material conditions). But the law is accorded
an inferior position to economic factors: it is merely part of the
superstructure – along with various cultural and political
phenomena – determined by the material conditions of each
society.
Marxist accounts of law adopt one of two standpoints in respect of
the relationship between base and superstructure and the position
of law. The first has been dubbed ‘crude materialism’ for it argues
that the law simply ‘reflects’ the economic base: the form and
content of legal rules correspond to the dominant mode of
production. This is generally regarded as providing a simplistic and
incoherent explanation of how the law does so. The second view is
known as ‘class instrumentalism’ because it contends that the law is
a direct expression of the will of the dominant class. Its
implausibility resides in the claim that the dominant class actually
has a cohesive ‘will’ of which it is conscious.
Marx’s theory is fundamentally historicist. That is to say social
evolution is explained in terms of inexorable historical forces.
Substituting Hegel’s dialectical theory of history, Marx and Engels
expounded the celebrated concept of ‘dialectical materialism’. It is
‘materialist’ because it claims that the means of production are
materially determined; it is ‘dialectical’, in part, because they
predict an inevitable conflict between those two hostile classes,
leading to a revolution, as the bourgeois mode of production, based
on individual ownership and unplanned competition, stands in
contradiction to the increasingly non-individualistic, social
character of labour production in the factory. The proletariat, they
claim, would seize the means of production and establish a
‘dictatorship of the proletariat’, to be replaced eventually by a
classless, communist society in which law would ultimately be
unnecessary.
The law plays an important ideological role. Individuals develop a
82
consciousness of their predicament. Marx famously declared: ‘It is
not the consciousness of men that determines their being, but, on
the contrary, their social being that determines their consciousness.’
In other words, our ideas are not arbitrary or fortuitous, they are a
result of economic conditions. We absorb our knowledge from our
social experience of productive relations. This provides, in part, an
explanation of the way in which the law maintains the social order
that – as a matter of the ‘natural order of things’ rather than as a
corporately willed desire – represents the interests of the dominant
class.
The Marxist materialist account of law, however, runs into
difficulties when governments enact reformist legislation that
improves the lot of the working class. How can these laws represent
the dominant ideology or interests? One answer given by Marxists
is to describe the state as ‘relatively autonomous’. It maintains that
the capitalist state is not entirely free to act as it pleases in the
interests of the ruling class, but is constrained by certain social
forces. But it will not permit any fundamental challenge to the
capitalist mode of production; it is, at bottom, what Marx and
Engels called ‘a committee for managing the common affairs of the
whole bourgeoisie’.
Since the law is a vehicle of class oppression, it is unnecessary in a
classless society. This is the essence of the argument first implied by
Marx in his early writings, and reaffirmed by Lenin. In its more
sophisticated version, the thesis claims that, following the
83
Law and society
This ‘dominant ideology’ is tacitly assumed to be the natural order
of things through a variety of social institutions. They establish an
‘ideological hegemony’ which ensures that – educationally,
culturally, politically, and legally – this dominant set of values
prevails. This explanation first appears in the prison writings
of the Italian Marxist Antonio Gramsci and is developed to a
high level of sophistication by the French Marxist Louis
Althusser.
Philosophy of Law
14. Marx and Engels, though they do not offer a comprehensive account
of law, provide an analysis of the relationship between law and
economics that has proved both influential and enduring.
proletarian revolution, the bourgeois state would be swept aside
and replaced by the dictatorship of the proletariat. Society, after
reactionary resistance has been overcome, would have no further
need for law or state: they would ‘wither away’.
One problem with this prognosis is its rather bland equation of
law with the coercive suppression of the proletariat. It neglects the
facts that a considerable body of law serves other functions and
that, even (or especially) a communist society requires laws to plan
and regulate the economy. To assert that these are not ‘law’ is to
induce scepticism.
It is important to note that in Marxist legal theory the law is not
regarded as anything special. At the core of historical materialism
is the proposition that law is ‘the result of one particular
kind of society’ rather than that society is the result of the law.
‘Legal fetishism’ is the condition, in Balbus’s words, where
84
‘individuals affirm that they owe their existence to the Law,
rather than the reverse’. Just as there is a form of commodity
fetishism, there is a form of legal fetishism which obscures
from legal subjects the origins of the legal system’s powers
and creates the impression that the legal system has a life of
its own. Many Marxists spurn the legal fetishism which regards
law as a distinct, special, or identifiable phenomenon with
its own unique and autonomous form of reasoning and
thought.
The choice between a ‘consensus’ and ‘conflict’ model of society is
important to our conception of society. Most theories of law, as
we have seen, implicitly adopt a consensus view that perceives
society as essentially unitary: the legislature represents the
common will, the executive acts in the common interest, and the
law is a neutral referee that is administered ‘without fear or favour’
for the common good. There are no fundamental conflicts of
values or interests. Any conflicts that arise do so at the personal
level: Victoria sues David for damages for breach of contract, and
so on.
At the other end of the spectrum is the ‘conflict’ model which sees
society divided between two opposing camps: those who have
property and power and those who do not. Conflict is inevitable.
The situation of individuals is defined by the very structure of the
society: they exist as components of one or other of the two sides.
Law in this representation, far from being a neutral referee, is
85
Law and society
Equally, they reject not only the concept of justice which, in Marxist
terms, is largely dependent upon material conditions, but also the
ideal of the rule of law – the notion of law as a neutral body of rules
safeguarding freedom. To champion the rule of law would be to
accept the image of law as a dispassionate arbiter which is above
political conflict and remote from the domination of particular
groups or classes. Marxists repudiate this ‘consensus’ model of
society.
actually the means by which the dominant group maintains its
control.
Philosophy of Law
What about human rights? Their ever-increasing significance is
clear from Chapter 4. Socialists generally find the very idea of
individual rights (and their connotations of selfishness and egoism)
incompatible with the communitarian philosophy of Marxism.
They therefore explicitly reject the concept and language of rights –
except perhaps when their use advances short-term tactical
objectives. Their argument is that social change does not occur as a
consequence of our moralizing about rights.
Yet in his early writings, Marx maintained that political revolution
would end the separation between civil society and the state. Only
democratic participation would terminate the alienation of the
people from the state. His own vision of socialist rights, or rights
under socialism, seems therefore to spring from his denunciation of
the distinctive characteristics of a capitalist society: the exploitation
and alienation it creates.
Marx distinguishes between ‘rights of citizens’ and ‘rights of man’.
The former are political rights exercised in common with others
and entail involvement in the community. The latter, on the other
hand, are private rights exercised in isolation from others and
involve withdrawal from the community. ‘Not one of the so-called
rights of man’, he declares, ‘goes beyond egoistic man . . . an
individual withdrawn into himself, his private interests and his
private desires’. And, most tellingly, he adds: ‘The practical
application of the right of man to freedom is the right of man to
private property’.
It has been suggested that Marx should not be taken to mean here
that these ‘rights of man’ (equality before the law, security, property,
liberty) are not important; but rather that the very concept of such
rights is endemic to a society based on capitalist relations of
production. This is an awkward contention to sustain, for Marx
86
sought to show that these rights had no independent
significance.
Revolutionary Marxists reject individual rights mainly
because they are an expression of a capitalist economy and
will not be required in a classless, socialist society. This
rejection rests on four objections to rights:
Their legalism. Rights subject human behaviour to the governance of rules.
Their coerciveness. Law is a coercive device. Rights are
tainted for they protect the interests of capital.
Their individualism. They protect self-interested atomized
individuals.
Their moralism. They are essentially moral and utopian, and
hence irrelevant to the economic base.
87
Law and society
Marxists frequently maintain that capitalism is destructive of
genuine individual liberty. Private property, according to Marx,
represents the dominance of the material world over the human
element, while communism represents the triumph of the human
element over the material world. He employed the concept of
‘reification’ to describe the process under which social relations
assume the form of relations between things. In a capitalist
society, he saw this reification as the result of the alienation of
workers from the product of their work: the ‘general social form
of labour appears as the property of a thing’; it is reified through
the ‘fetishism of commodities’. Capitalist relations appear to
protect individual freedom, but equality before the law is merely a
formal property of exchange relations between private property
owners:
But some Marxists regard the view that rights are necessarily
individualistic as too crude. The Marxist historian, E. P. Thompson
(1924–93), repudiates both the Marxist dismissal of all law
as merely an instrument of class rule, and the conception of civil
liberties as no more than an illusion which obscures the realities of
class rule. He argues that law is not simply an instrument of class
domination, but also a ‘form of mediation’ between and within the
classes. Its function is not only to serve power and wealth, but also
to impose ‘effective inhibitions upon power’ and to subject ‘the
ruling class to its own rules’:
[T]he rule of law itself, the imposing of effective inhibitions upon
power and the defence of the citizen from power’s all-intrusive
claims, seems to me to be an unqualified human good. To deny or
Philosophy of Law
belittle this good is, in this dangerous century when the resources
and pretensions of power continue to enlarge, a desperate error of
intellectual abstraction. More than this, it is a self-fulfilling error,
which encourages us to give up the struggle against bad laws and
class-bound procedures, and to disarm ourselves before power. It is
to throw away a whole inheritance of struggle about law, and within
the forms of law, whose continuity can never be fractured without
bringing men and women into immediate danger.
Several Marxist writers have, not surprisingly, condemned
this wholesale acceptance of the rule of law. Some have argued
that to champion restraints on authoritarian rule does not
commit Marxists to a comprehensive exaltation of the rule
of law.
The collapse of the Soviet Union and its satellite states of Eastern
Europe, along with the eclipse of Chinese socialism by state
capitalism, has gravely wounded both Marxist legal theory and
practice.
88
Jürgen Habermas
One of the foremost contemporary German intellectuals, Jürgen
Habermas (b. 1929) is widely revered for the originality of his
philosophy and his perceptive social criticism, though he is not easy
reading. Among his numerous insights, which integrate subtle
cultural, political, and economic analysis, is his view that despite
the inexorable march of ‘instrumental-technocratic consciousness’,
and the domination of the ‘lifeworld’ it brings in its wake, the
capitalist state also presents opportunities for greater
‘communicative action’.
What does this have to do with the law? The answer is complex.
Given that his concept of ‘communicative reason’ is based on the
principles of freedom and equality, it would not be unreasonable to
expect Habermas to embrace some form of liberalism. In doing so,
he distinguishes between ‘law as medium’ and ‘law as institution’.
The former describes law as a body of formal, general rules that
control the state and the economy. The latter inhabits the ‘lifeworld’
and hence expresses its shared values and norms in institutional
form, for example, those parts of the criminal law that touch on
morality. Unlike ‘law as medium’, ‘law as institution’ requires
legitimation. In fact, argues Habermas, in our pluralistic,
fragmented society, these institutions are a potent basis of
normative integration.
89
Law and society
The combined effect of capitalism and a strong, centralized
authority results, he argues, in the ‘lifeworld’ – the sphere of
common norms and identities – being intruded upon. This
generates atomization and alienation (shades of Marx). Because the
‘lifeworld’ is established by processes whose existence depends on
communication and social solidarity, this intrusion undermines the
‘lifeworld’ itself, and reduces the prospects for collective selfdetermination. He nevertheless recognizes the prospects for
rational communicative discourse in respect of facts, values, and
inner experience.
The legitimacy of the law, he contends, depends significantly on the
effectiveness of the process of discourse by which the law is made.
Consequently freedom of speech and other fundamental democratic
rights are central to his theory of ‘communicative action’.
Habermas has provoked a gargantuan literature. He has been
criticized, for example, for the disproportionate confidence he
places in the law as a vehicle for accomplishing social integration.
And some commentators find his suggestion that only those legal
norms are valid to which all persons affected have assented as
participants in rational discourse somewhat fanciful; he appears to
be advocating a form of Athenian democracy!
Philosophy of Law
Michel Foucault
The recondite ideas of influential French thinker Michel Foucault
(1926–84) touch, directly and indirectly, on the role of law in
society. In particular, his unconventional philosophy, or what, in his
later work, he prefers to call ‘genealogy’, attempts to reveal the
nature and function of power. It is, he argues, distinct from either
physical force or legal regulation. Nor is it hostile to freedom or
truth. Instead, he demonstrates how, beginning in the 18th century,
the human body was subjected to a new ‘microphysics’ of power
through the geography of institutions such as factories, hospitals,
schools, and prisons.
Discipline consists of four ‘practices’, each of which engenders
consequences on those who are subjected to it. This control creates
in those who are its subjects an ‘individuality’ that contains four
characteristics: ‘cellular’ (by the ‘play of spatial distribution’),
‘organic’ (by the ‘coding’ of activities), ‘genetic’ (by the
accumulation of time), and ‘combinatory’ (by the ‘composition
of forces’). And discipline ‘operates four great techniques’: it
draws up tables, it prescribes movements, it imposes exercises,
and it arranges ‘tactics’ in order to obtain the combination of
forces. He concludes:
90
Tactics, the art of constructing, with located bodies, coded activities
and trained aptitudes, mechanisms in which the product of the
various forces is increased by the calculated combination are no
doubt the highest form of disciplinary practice.
The application of these methods renders the social order more
controllable. Disciplinary power, additionally, induces us to act in
ways that we come to think of as natural. We are therefore
manipulated and managed by these ‘technologies’: we become
‘docile bodies’ – and, as a result, capitalism is able to advance and
thrive.
His analysis of power leads him to query liberal ideas, and their
preoccupation with centralized state power. Indeed, he regards it as
a means by which liberalism actually furthers the very domination
it seeks to reduce.
Despite the impenetrability of much of his unsettling work,
Foucault’s inventive approach to the practice of disciplinary power
illuminates the darker reaches of social control by shifting attention
away from the institutional operation of the law towards its effect
on each of us as individuals.
91
Law and society
Foucault’s universe is one in which disciplinary power pervades
almost every element of social life, thus the law has no special claim
to primacy. Regulatory government directs policy towards
controlling an assortment of threats to the maintenance of social
order. The law has thus become ‘sociologized’. Formal equality is a
smokescreen behind which lies the power that characterizes the
postmodern state.
Chapter 6
Critical legal theory
Many of the theories outlined in the previous five chapters are
greeted with scepticism by those who adhere to what, in the
broadest sense, may be called critical legal theory. This wing of legal
theory generally spurns many of the enterprises that have long been
assumed to be at the heart of jurisprudence. And it repudiates what
is taken to be the natural order of things, be it patriarchy (in the
case of feminist jurisprudence), the conception of ‘race’ (critical race
theory), the free market (critical legal studies), or ‘metanarratives’
(postmodernism). Each of these spheres of critical thought are
briefly examined in this chapter.
The primary purpose of critical legal theory, it is reasonable to
assert, is to contest the universal rational foundation of law which,
it maintains, clothes the law and legal system with a spurious
legitimacy. Nor does critical legal theory accept law as a distinctive
and discrete discipline. This view, it alleges, portrays the concept of
law as autonomous and determinate – independent from politics
and morality – which it can never be.
The myth of determinacy is a significant component of the critical
assault on law. Far from being a determinate, coherent body of rules
and doctrine, the law is depicted as uncertain, ambiguous, and
unstable. And instead of expressing rationality, the law reproduces
political and economic power. In addition, as many of the adherents
92
of critical legal studies (CLS) claim, the law is neither neutral nor
objective. To achieve neutrality, the law employs several fictions or
illusions. Most conspicuously, it vaunts the liberal ideal of equality
under the rule of law. But this, in the view of CLS, is a myth. Social
justice is a hollow promise.
Critical legal studies
The movement generated mountainous waves, not only in
American law schools, but in their counterparts in Britain, Canada,
Australia, and elsewhere. Yet, despite its contemporary chic, CLS is
often characterized as a latter-day version of the American realist
movement of the 1920s and 1930s. American realism was the name
given to a progressive coalition of lawyers, judges, and scholars that
rejected the formalism of Austin, Bentham, Mill, and Hume, and
presented a more sociological account of the ‘law in action’. They
eschewed what they considered to be the ponderous metaphysics
that preoccupied legal theory, and its fixation with the meaning of
concepts such as commands, rules, norms, or any other construct
that had no foundation in what they regarded as ‘reality’.
American realism was absorbed in empirical questions, especially
those that attempt to discern the sociological and psychological
factors that influence judicial decision-making. Notwithstanding
this pragmatic approach, they were inherently legal positivists.
Thus, while they did not wholly spurn the notion that courts may be
constrained by rules, the realists contended that judges exercise
93
Critical legal theory
CLS emerged in the 1970s in the United States as a broadly leftist
critique of orthodox legal doctrines. Originally, it had three
distinctive features. First, it was situated within legal, as opposed to
political science or sociological scholarship. Secondly, it sought to
tackle the injustices it identified in legal doctrine. Thirdly, it
adopted an interdisciplinary approach, drawing on politics,
philosophy, literary criticism, psychoanalysis, linguistics, and
semiotics to expound its critique of law.
Philosophy of Law
discretion much more frequently than is generally believed. They
denied, of course, the natural law and positivist view that judges are
swayed mainly by legal rules, but for the realists the key factors
determining the outcome of a case were the political and moral
intuitions relating to its facts.
Father of the movement, Oliver Wendell Holmes (1841–1935),
famously declared that the common law ‘is not a brooding
omnipresence in the sky, but the articulate voice of some sovereign
or quasi sovereign that can be identified’. Holmes, as a Supreme
Court Judge, not surprisingly, believed that the law should be
defined by reference to what the courts actually said it was. This is
particularly apparent from his celebrated address, ‘The Path of the
Law’, which he delivered to law students in 1897. He advised them
to distinguish clearly between law and morality: consider what the
law is, not what it ought to be.
Look at the law, he argues, from the position of the ‘bad man’: ‘If
you want to know the law and nothing else,’ he asserted, ‘you must
look at it as a bad man, who cares only for the material
consequences which such knowledge enables him to predict.’
Holmes also thought that legal developments could be scientifically
justified. The ‘true science of law’, he maintained, ‘consists in the
establishment of its postulates from within upon accurately
measured social desires instead of tradition’.
Karl Llewellyn (1893–1962) adopted a so-called functionalist
approach to the law that perceives it as serving certain fundamental
functions, what he calls ‘law-jobs’. He reasoned that law should be
regarded as an engine ‘having purposes, not values in itself’. If
society is to endure, certain essential requirements must be
satisfied; this produces conflict which must be resolved. The central
idea of this functionalist account of law is the ‘institution’ of law
which performs various jobs. An institution is, he says, an organized
activity built around the doing of a job or cluster of jobs. And the
most important job the law has is the disposition of trouble cases.
94
It is true that both American realism and CLS share a sceptical,
anti-formalist view, but CLS cannot properly be regarded as a ‘new
realism’. Though both movements seek to demystify the law, and to
expose its operation as law ‘in action’, CLS does not engage in the
pragmatic or empirical concerns that preoccupied the realists.
Instead, its adherents regard the law as ‘problematic’ in the sense
that it reproduces the oppressive nature of society. Moreover, unlike
the American realists who accepted the division between legal
reasoning and politics, CLS regards it as axiomatic that, in effect,
law is politics; and legal reasoning is no different from other forms
of reasoning. In addition, although the realists sought to distinguish
between legal rules and their actual operation in society, they
generally embraced the neutrality of law and the ideology of
liberalism. CLS denies both.
And they are ‘reified’, a term used by Marx and refined by the
Hungarian Marxist, György Lukács, to refer to the manner in which
ideas become material things, and are portrayed as essential,
necessary, and objective when, in fact, they are contingent,
arbitrary, and subjective. Moreover, legal thought is, following
Freud, a form of ‘denial’: it affords a way of coping with
contradictions that are too painful for us to hold in our conscious
mind. It therefore denies the contradiction between the promise, on
the one hand of, say, equality and freedom, and the reality of
oppression and hierarchy, on the other.
The Brazilian social theorist, Roberto Unger (b. 1947) is an
95
Critical legal theory
Indeed, applying Marxist and Freudian ideas, CLS detects in the
law a form of ‘hegemonic consciousness’, a term borrowed from the
writings of the Italian Marxist, Antonio Gramsci, who observed that
social order is maintained by a system of beliefs which are accepted
as ‘common sense’ and part of the natural order – even by those who
are actually subordinated to it. In other words, these ideas are
treated as eternal and necessary whereas they really reflect only the
transitory, arbitrary interests of the dominant elite.
Philosophy of Law
important source of CLS ideas. The representation of society, he
contends, is infused with the following four beliefs. First, that law
is a ‘system’, and as a body of ‘doctrine’, properly interpreted, it
supplies the answer to all questions about social behaviour.
Secondly, that a special form of legal reasoning exists by which
answers may be found from doctrine. Thirdly, that this doctrine
reflects a coherent view about the relations between persons and
the nature of society. And, fourthly, that social action reflects norms
generated by the legal system, either because people internalize
these norms or actual coercion compels them to do so.
CLS challenges each of these assumptions. First, it denies that law is
a system or is able to resolve every conceivable problem. This is
described as the principle of indeterminacy. Secondly, it rejects the
view that there is an autonomous and neutral mode of legal
reasoning. This is described as the principle of anti-formalism.
Thirdly, it contests the view that doctrine encapsulates a single,
coherent view of human relations; instead CLS maintains that
doctrine represents several different, often opposing points of view,
none of which is sufficiently coherent or pervasive to be called
dominant. This is described as the principle of contradiction.
Finally, it doubts that, even where there is consensus, there is
reason to regard the law as a decisive factor in social behaviour. This
is described as the principle of marginality.
If law is indeterminate, legal scholarship defining what the law is
becomes merely a form of advocacy. If there is no distinct form of
legal reasoning, such scholarship is reduced to political debate. If
legal doctrine is essentially contradictory, legal argument cannot
rely on it, if it is not to result in a draw. And if law is marginal, social
life must be controlled by norms exterior to the law.
Some of the more radical ideas of CLS are difficult to take seriously.
The suggestion, for example, that to counter the hierarchy endemic
to law schools, all its employees – from professors to janitors – be
paid the same salary has not been enthusiastically endorsed, at least
96
by the former group. There is no question, however, that CLS has
played a significant role in illuminating the fissure between rhetoric
and reality. Yet the possibilities of transforming the law seem
frequently to be diluted by the destructive, even nihilistic,
tendencies of some of the more dogmatic adherents of CLS. Many of
its ideas are still influential in the legal academy, though they have
been absorbed, adapted, and refined by the theories that occupy the
remainder of this chapter.
Postmodern legal theory
This attack on the Enlightenment includes a dismissal of the
Kantian concern with individual rights, equality, and justice
characteristic of modernism. But the target is even larger, for the
espousal of these values is not confined to those who champion the
idea of natural rights (see Chapter 1). They are adopted by a good
deal of post-Enlightenment legal theory, including positivism (see
Chapter 2). Drawing on elements of ‘cultural theory’, and the
writings of Michel Foucault (see Chapter 5), Jacques Derrida,
Jacques Lacan (see below), and other – principally French and
German – theorists, postmodernism may also be understood as an
attempt to invalidate, or at least to contest, the methods,
97
Critical legal theory
‘I define postmodern as incredulity toward metanarratives.’ Thus
spake Jean-François Lyotard (1924–98) in his influential
book, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. The
promise of truth or justice held out by the grand ‘metanarratives’ of
Kant, Hegel, Marx, and others has, in our age, been betrayed.
Universal values, ‘master narratives’, are regarded by
postmodernists like Lyotard as superfluous, if not meaningless. The
great historical epochs, developments, and ideas, especially those
associated with the Enlightenment – and the Enlightenment itself –
are treated with profound suspicion. The conventional assumption
that human ‘progress’ is ‘evolving’ toward ‘civilization’ or some other
end is rejected by postmodernists who seek interpretation and
understanding in the personal experience of individuals.
assumptions, and ideas of the analytical Anglo-American
philosophical tradition.
Philosophy of Law
Postmodernist accounts of society, and the role of law within it,
disclose a disillusionment with formalism, essentialism, statism,
utopianism, and even democracy. Nor does the scepticism end here.
Critical theory, whether aesthetic or ethical, seeks to subvert
‘foundational’ ideas of truth. It expresses an impatience with the
modern state’s bureaucratic suffocation of the individual, the
overarching presence of the state, the increasing globalization of
markets, and universalizing of values.
It has also (perhaps inevitably) witnessed a new pragmatism. A
down-to-earth set of goals – economic, ecological, political – is
accompanied by the advocacy of a more inclusive community that
emphasizes the special predicament of women, minorities, the
dispossessed, and the poor. A popular expression (to be found also
among CLS and feminist theorists) is ‘empowerment’. But the
radical postmodern political agenda is a complex one which may
generate confusion or what has been called a ‘multiplication of
ideologies’.
Both the ‘subject’ and the ‘object’ are regarded as fantasies. And the
postmodern concern with the ‘subject’ generates, especially in the
context of the law, some fascinating accounts of the individual as
moral agent, as rights-bearer, or simply as player in the legal
system. Several are explicitly psychological or linguistic, with the
structural psychoanalytical theories of Lacan and the
poststructuralist ideas of Derrida exerting considerable influence,
though, as will be suggested below, they have little utility in our
quest to comprehend the nature of law.
Jacques Lacan
The French psychoanalyst, Jacques Lacan (1901–81) is frequently
described as the architect of postmodern psychoanalytic semiotics.
98
Drawing on the ideas of Freud, Saussure, and Lévi-Strauss, he
argues that the unconscious is structured like a language; it is
therefore crucial to identify the inner workings of that discourse
that takes place within the unconscious – the repository of
knowledge, power, agency, and desire. We do not control what we
say; rather the structure of language is predetermined by thought
and desire. He employs a psychoanalytical, Freudian conception of
the divided human subject – ego, superego, and the unconscious –
to demonstrate that the ‘I’ expressed by language (which he calls the
‘subject of the statement’) can never represent an individual’s ‘true’
identity (which he calls the ‘subject of enunciation’).
Jacques Derrida
The controversial French philosopher Jacques Derrida (1930–
2004) is closely associated with the concept of deconstruction. He
employs the term – which he borrowed from the German
philosopher, Martin Heidegger – to explicate the notion of
différance. This neologism describes the state of interdependence
and difference between hierarchical oppositions. ‘Difference’ is
based on the French word différer, which means both to differ and
to defer. He replaces an ‘e’ with the ‘a’ in différance. The words are
indistinguishable in spoken French.
Based on the semiotics of the Swiss linguist, Ferdinand de Saussure,
Derrida draws a distinction between ‘signifiers’ and ‘signified’.
Saussure distinguished between langue, the deep structure of
99
Critical legal theory
In the first eighteen months of our lives we experience this
disjunction between identity and its representation, and thereafter
it is forever lost. We construct a semblance of individual and social
stability only by fantasy, which cannot be sustained. The subject is
thus divided or decentred. The language of the unconscious is the
arbiter of all experience, knowing, and living. The idea of justice
becomes, in Lacanian terms, a fantasy that camouflages the
unattainable desire of a harmonious community.
Philosophy of Law
linguistic rules, and parole, the set of speech acts made by members
of a linguistic community. The former is, in the understanding of
language, the more important element because it is the system of
relations among various signs that constitutes a language. So, for
example, the word ‘dog’ does not correspond to the creature we
know and love. But we understand it by virtue of its difference from
similar sounds such as ‘bog’, ‘cog’, or fog’. Derrida postulates that,
since the meaning of ‘dog’ emerges from this contest of differences
between signifiers, its meaning – like the meaning of all signifiers –
is infinitely deferred. He concludes that stability can be achieved
only by ‘deconstructing’ language in order to show how the meaning
of one signifier includes within it another signifier (the ‘other’).
Derrida’s undertaking is ambitious: to expose the ‘metaphysics of
presence’ in Western philosophy. By this he means that, in every set
of oppositions, one kind of ‘presence’ is privileged over a
corresponding kind of ‘absence’. Western philosophy, he argues, is
based on the hidden premise that what is most apparent to our
consciousness – what is obvious or immediate – is most real,
foundational, or important.
Derrida’s disquieting deduction is that, since language emerges
from this unstable structure of differences, it will always be
indeterminate. The prospect of establishing the subject of
identity – and hence of an individual right-holder – is consequently
poor.
Though postmodern legal theory has garnered a sizeable following,
one is bound to question whether it greatly assists our
understanding of law. How, for example, can deconstruction
provide a constructive insight into the concept of law? Since, as we
have seen, the legitimacy of the law lies in some conception of
justice, and the language of the law is unavoidably normative, it is
hard to see how Lacanian psychoanalysis or Derrida’s
deconstruction advance our comprehension of legal ideas.
100
Feminist legal theory
Traditional jurisprudence conspicuously overlooked the position of
women. Feminist legal theory has been remarkably successful in
remedying this neglect. It has had a considerable impact, not only
on university law curricula, but on the law itself, for feminist
jurisprudence extends well beyond the purely academic to
comprehensive analysis of the many inequalities to be found in the
criminal law, especially rape and domestic violence, family law,
contract, tort, property, and other branches of the substantive law,
including aspects of public law.
Not surprisingly, in view of its unease about the injustices
experienced by women, feminist writing is often overtly polemical.
‘The personal is political’ was the compelling slogan adopted by
early feminists. It represented in part a denunciation of the
professed radicalism of social movements that failed to address the
routine subjugation of women at home or at work.
Nor, of course, do feminists speak with a single voice. There are at
least five major strands of legal feminism. What follows is an
outline of their diverse perspectives, as well as a summary of the
achievements of the feminist movement in theory and practice.
Liberal feminism
Liberalism prizes individual rights, both civil and political. Liberals
assert the need for a large realm of personal freedom, including
101
Critical legal theory
In recent years, for example, both English and American courts
have abandoned the common law principle that a husband cannot
be prosecuted for raping his wife, despite her refusal to consent to
sexual intercourse. The wife was deemed by the fact of marriage to
have consented. While the judges make no explicit reference to
feminist jurisprudence, its influence may well have played a part in
these decisions.
Philosophy of Law
freedom of speech, conscience, association, and sexuality, immune
to state regulation, save to protect others from harm. Liberal
feminism perceives individuals as autonomous, rights-bearing
agents, and stresses the values of equality, rationality, and
autonomy. Since men and women are equally rational, it is argued,
they ought to have the same opportunities to exercise rational
choices. (This emphasis on equality, as we shall see, is stigmatized
by radical feminists as mistaken, because asserting women’s
similarity to men assimilates women into the male domain, thereby
making women into men.)
The majority of liberal feminists, while conceding that the legal and
political system is patriarchal, refuse to accept the blanket assault
that is a significant, though not universal, item on the radical
agenda. The liberal battleground is the existing institutional
framework of discrimination, particularly in the domain of
employment.
Liberal feminism accentuates equality, while radical feminism is
concerned with difference. Among the most critical anxieties of
liberal feminists is the border between the private and the public
domain. This is largely because women tend to be excluded from
the public sphere where political equality is realized. Likewise, the
private domain of the home and office is the site of the
subordination and exploitation of women. Crimes of domestic
violence normally occur within the home into which the law is often
reluctant to intrude. Liberalism may itself therefore be implicated
in the subjugation of women, according to radical feminists.
Radical feminism
Leading radical feminist Catharine MacKinnon (b. 1946) contests
the idea that, since men have defined women as different, women
can ever achieve equality. Given that men dominate women, she
argues that the question is ultimately one of power. The law is
effectively a masculine edifice that cannot be altered merely by
102
admitting women through its doors or including female values
within its rules or procedures. Nor, the radical position contends, is
reforming the law likely to assist since, in view of the masculinity of
law, it will simply produce male oriented results and reproduce
male dominated relations. In the words of MacKinnon: ‘Abstract
rights . . . authorize the male experience of the world.’
Radical feminism rejects what it regards as the liberal illusion of the
neutrality of the law. It seeks to expose the reality behind the mask
so that women will recognize the need to change the patriarchal
system which subjugates them.
The differences – or dualisms – between the genders, according to Frances Olsen, are ‘sexualized’. Masculine character-
MALE
FEMALE
Rational
Irrational
Active
Passive
Thought
Feeling
Reason
Emotion
Culture
Nature
Power
Sensitivity
Objective
Subjective
Abstract
Contextualised
(Adapted from Frances Olsen, ‘Feminism and Critical Legal Theory: An
American Perspective’ (1990) 18 International Journal of the Sociology of
Law 199.)
Carol Smart denies that the law can produce real equality. Ann
Scales is eloquent in her dismissal of change through the form of
law:
103
Critical legal theory
istics are considered superior.
We should be especially wary when we hear lawyers, addicted to
cognitive objectivity as they are, assert that women’s voices have a
place in the existing system. . . . The injustice of sexism is not
irrationality; it is domination. Law must focus on the latter, and that
focus cannot be achieved through a formal lens.
Christine Littleton advocates ‘equality as acceptance’, which
emphasizes the consequences rather than the sources of difference,
an approach that has obvious legal consequences in respect of equal
pay and conditions of work.
Philosophy of Law
Radical feminism seeks to expose the domination of women by ‘asking
the woman question’ to expose the gender implications of rules and
practices that might otherwise appear to be impartial or neutral.
Postmodern feminism
Postmodernists, we have seen, generally reject the idea of the
‘subject’. And they exhibit an impatience with objective truths such
as ‘equality’, ‘gender’, ‘the law’, ‘patriarchy’, and even ‘woman’.
Indeed, the very idea that things have properties which they must
possess if they are to be that particular thing (i.e. that they have
‘essences’) is repudiated by many postmodernists. This
‘essentialism’ is discerned by postmodern feminists in the approach
of radical feminists such as Catharine MacKinnon who argues that
below the surface of women lies ‘precultural woman’.
Drucilla Cornell and Frances Olsen draw on the work of Jacques
Derrida and Julia Kristeva to construct what Cornell calls an
‘imaginative universal’ which transcends the essentialism of real
experience and enters the realm of mythology. The maleness of
law – the ‘phallocentrism’ of society – is a central theme in
postmodern feminist writing. Katherine Bartlett identifies at least
three feminist legal methods that are used in investigating the legal
process: ‘asking the woman question’, ‘feminist practical reasoning’,
and ‘consciousness-raising’.
104
The first attempts to expose the gender implications of rules and
practices that may appear to be neutral. Feminist practical
reasoning challenges the legitimacy of the norms that, through
rules, claim to represent the community, especially in cases of rape
and domestic violence cases. Thirdly, consciousness-raising seeks to
understand and reveal women’s oppression.
Difference feminism
It argues that equality is a more subtle and complex objective than
liberals allow. Thus Carol Gilligan, a psychologist, demonstrates
how women’s moral values tend to stress responsibility, whereas
men emphasize rights. Women look to context, where men appeal
to neutral, abstract notions of justice. In particular, she argues,
women endorse an ‘ethic of care’ which proclaims that no one
should be hurt. This morality of caring and nurturing identifies and
defines an essential difference between the sexes.
Difference feminism focuses upon the positive characteristic of
women’s ‘special bond’ to others, while radical feminism
concentrates on the negative dimension: the sexual objectification
of women, through, for example, pornography, which MacKinnon
describes as ‘a form of forced sex’.
105
Critical legal theory
Difference (or cultural) feminism is uncomfortable with the liberal
feminists’ attachment to formal equality and gender. This position,
it maintains, undermines the differences between men and women.
Instead, difference feminism endeavours to reveal the unstated
premises of the law’s substance, practice, and procedure by
exposing the miscellaneous kinds of discrimination implicit in the
criminal law, the law of evidence, tort law, and the process of legal
reasoning itself. This includes an attack on, for example, the
concept of the ‘reasonable man’, the male view of female sexuality
applied in rape cases, and the very language of the law itself.
Philosophy of Law
Critical race theory
CRT originated in Madison, Wisconsin, in 1989 as a reaction
against what it saw as the deconstructive excesses of CLS.
Nevertheless, it is no less sceptical of Enlightenment ideas such
as ‘justice’, ‘truth’, and ‘reason’. Its mainspring, however, is the
need to expose the law’s pervasive racism; privileged white,
middle-class academics, in its view, cannot fully uncover its
nature and extent. Those who have themselves suffered the
indignity and injustice of discrimination are the authentic voices
of marginalized racial minorities. The law’s formal constructs
reflect, it is argued, the reality of a privileged, elite, male, white
majority. It is this culture, way of life, attitude, and normative
behaviour that combine to form the prevailing ‘neutrality’ of the
law. A racial minority is condemned to the margins of legal
existence.
CRT diverges most radically from full-blown postmodernist
accounts (see above) in respect of the recognition by at least some of
its members of the importance of conventional ‘rights talk’ in
pursuit of equality and freedom. Its analysis of society and law
therefore seems, in some cases, to be a partial one. This retreat from
the postmodernist antagonism towards rights signifies an apparent
readiness to embrace the ideals of liberty, equality, and justice.
Several CRT adherents, however, evince profound misgivings about
liberalism and the formal equality it aspires to protect, and a
distaste for individual rights and other contents of the liberal
package.
CRT scholarship often draws on ‘auto/biography’ to appraise social
and legal relations. Patricia Williams, for example, amalgamates
legal analysis and personal narrative to criticize legal subjectivity.
CRT regards the hostility of traditional legal scholarship to the
auto/biographical as a method by which to distance the law from
the very social relations, especially racial and gender
discrimination, that it generates.
106
Critical legal theory
15. The American civil rights movement of the 1960s ultimately
achieved its principal objective of racial equality under the law.
An offshoot of CRT pursues the postcolonial thesis that the
dismantling of colonial governments has failed to end the racial
divisions and assumptions of these societies.
107
References
Chapter 1
A. Passerin D’Entrèves, Natural Law (1970), p. 116.
J. Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, pp. 3, 34.
Cicero, De Re Publica 3. 22. 33.
Augustine, City of God, 4. 4.
Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I/II. 96. 4.
Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (1980), pp. 219–20, emphasis
added.
Chapter 2
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (1994), pp. 210, 117, 57.
H. Kelsen, Pure Theory of Law (1967), pp. 201, 217.
‘Hard’ legal positivists maintain that all criteria of legality must be what
Raz calls ‘social sources’, so the determination of whether something
is ‘law’ cannot turn on a norm’s content or substantive value or merit.
The existence of a particular ‘law’, in other words, does not depend
on whether it ought to be the law. ‘Soft positivists’ (or ‘inclusive
positivists’ or ‘incorporationists’), on the other hand, accept that some
principles may be legally binding by virtue of their value or merit,
but morality can be a condition of validity only where the rule of
recognition so stipulates. See Jules Coleman, The Practice of Principle
(2001), and the works listed in the ‘Further reading’ section by
Waluchow, Himma, and Marmor.
108
J Raz, The Authority of Law (1979), pp. 37 ff.
Chapter 3
R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire (1986), pp. 239, 22.
R. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (1978), pp. 116–17.
R. Dworkin, Law’s Empire, pp. 95–6, emphasis added.
Chapter 4
Chapter 5
Nicola Lacey, A Life of H. L. A. Hart: The Nightmare and the Noble
Dream (OUP, 2004), pp. 230–1.
Max Weber on Law in Economy and Society (1954), pp. 5, 62 (shades of
Dworkin?).
M. Weber, The Religion of China (1951), p. 149.
Max Weber on Law in Economy and Society, p. 225.
‘Legal fetishism . . . ’: I am here paraphrasing Balbus, ‘Commodity Form
and Legal Form: An Essay on the ‘‘Relative Autonomy of the Law’’ ’
(1977) 11 Law and Society Review 582.
K. Marx ‘On the Jewish Question’, in D. McLellan (ed.), Karl Marx:
Selected Writings (OUP, 1977).
E. P. Thompson, Whigs and Hunters (Penguin, 1975), p. 266.
109
References
W. N. Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial
Reasoning, ed. W. W. Cook (1964).
Justinian, Corpus Juris Civilis: The first quotation is from book 1, title 1,
paragraph 10 of Justinian’s Digest. The second is from the same
source, book 1, title 2. The author is Ulpian. The translations are
mine.
J. Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation
(1970), ch. 1, para 1.
The desert island example is adapted from Nigel Simmonds, Central
Issues in Jurisprudence (2002), pp. 17–18.
The four criticisms are expressed by H. L. A. Hart, ‘Between Utility and
Rights’, in his Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (1982),
pp. 200–2.
M. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, tr. A. Sheridan (Penguin, 1977),
p. 167.
Philosophy of Law
Chapter 6
‘American realism . . . ’: a similar distrust of metaphysical concepts
reaches its apogee with the Scandinavian realists, whose chief
protagonists include Axel Hägerström (1868–1939), Alf Ross
(1899–1979), Karl Olivecrona (1897–1980), and A. V. Lundstedt
(1882–1955). But, though the American realists are, in general,
pragmatist and behaviourist, emphasizing ‘law in action’ (as opposed
to legal conceptualism), the Scandinavians launch a philosophical
assault on the metaphysical foundations of law; where the Americans
are ‘rule-sceptics’, they are ‘metaphysics-sceptics’. Yet we may
legitimately group the two ‘schools’ together in one important
respect: they both declare war on all absolute values (such as ‘justice’)
and they are both empirical, pragmatic, and, of course, ‘realistic’.
‘four beliefs . . . ’: these are described by David Trubek, ‘CLS and
Empiricism: Where the Action Is’ in a symposium published in
(1984) 36 Stanford Law Review 413.
Marital rape cases: R v. R [1992] 1 AC 599, House of Lords; Smith v.
Smith 85 NJ 193, 426 A 2d 38 (1981).
A. Scales, ‘The Emergence of Feminist Jurisprudence: An Essay’ (1986)
95 Yale Law Journal 1373, 1385.
K. Bartlett, ‘Feminist Legal Method’ (1990) 103 Harvard Law Review
829.
R. Delgado and J. Stefanic, ‘Critical Race Theory: An Annotated
Bibliography’ (1993) 79 Virginia Law Review 461.
110
Further reading
Introduction
Bix, Brian, Jurisprudence: Theory and Context (3rd edn., Sweet &
Maxwell, 2003).
Christie, George C., and Patrick H. Martin (eds.), Jurisprudence: Texts
and Readings on the Philosophy of Law (2nd edn., West Publishing,
1995).
Davies, H., and D. Holdcroft, Jurisprudence: Texts and Commentary
(Butterworths, 1991).
Feinberg, Joel, and Jules Coleman (eds.), Philosophy of Law (7th edn.,
Wadsworth/Thomson Learning, 2003).
Freeman, M. D. A. (ed.), Lloyd’s Introduction to Jurisprudence
(7th edn., Sweet & Maxwell, 2001)
Harris, J. W., Legal Philosophies (2nd edn., Butterworths, 1997).
Hayman, R. L., N. Levit, and R. Delgado, Jurisprudence, Classical and
Contemporary: From Natural Law to Postmodernism (2nd edn., West
Publishing, 2002).
McCoubrey, H., and N. D. White, Textbook on Jurisprudence (3rd edn.,
Blackstone Press, 1999).
Penner, James, David Schiff, and Richard Nobles (eds.), Introduction to
Jurisprudence and Legal Theory: Commentary and Materials
(Butterworths, 2002).
Simmonds, N. E., Central Issues in Jurisprudence: Justice, Law and
Rights (2nd edn., Sweet & Maxwell, 2002).
111
Wacks, Raymond, Understanding Jurisprudence: An Introduction to
Legal Theory (OUP, 2005).
Chapter 1
Philosophy of Law
Finnis, John Natural Law and Natural Rights (Clarendon Press, 1980).
—— (ed.), Natural Law (in 2 vols., International Library of Essays
in Law and Legal Theory, Dartmouth, 1991).
—— ‘Natural Law: The Classical Tradition’ in Jules Coleman &
Scott Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and
Philosophy of Law (OUP, 2002).
Fuller, Lon Luvois, The Morality of Law (rev. edn., Yale University Press,
1969).
George, Robert P., In Defense of Natural Law (OUP, 1999).
Passerin D’Entrèves, Alessandro, Natural Law: An Introduction to
Legal Philosophy (2nd edn., Hutchinson, 1970).
Chapter 2
Austin, John, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined and the Uses
of the Study of Jurisprudence (Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1954).
Bentham, Jeremy, A Fragment on Government; or, A Comment on the
Commentaries (2nd edn., W. Pickering, 1823).
—— An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation,
ed. J. H. Burns and H. L. A. Hart (Athlone Press, 1970).
—— Of Laws in General, ed. H. L. A. Hart (Athlone Press, 1970).
Coleman, Jules (ed.), Hart’s Postscript: Essays on the Postscript to The
Concept of Law (OUP, 2001).
—— The Practice of Principle: In Defence of A Pragmatic Approach
to Legal Theory (OUP, 2001).
George, Robert P. (ed.), The Autonomy of Law: Essays on Legal
Positivism (Clarendon Press, 1995).
Hart, H. L. A., Essays on Bentham: Studies on Jurisprudence and
Political Theory (Clarendon Press, 1982).
—— The Concept of Law (Clarendon Press, 1961); 2nd edn. by P. A.
Bulloch and J. Raz (Clarendon Press, 1994).
Himma, Kenneth Einar, ‘Inclusive Legal Positivism’ in Jules Coleman
112
113
Further reading
and Scott Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and
Philosophy of Law (OUP, 2002).
Jori, Mario (ed.), Legal Positivism (Dartmouth, 1992).
Kelsen, Hans, General Theory of Law and State, tr. Anders Wedberg
(Harvard University Press, 1949)
—— Pure Theory of Law, tr. Max Knight (University of California
Press, 1967).
—— General Theory of Norms, tr. M. Hartney (Clarendon Press, 1991).
—— Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, tr. Bonnie
Litschewski Paulson and S. L. Paulson (Clarendon Press, 1992).
Kramer, Matthew, In Defense of Legal Positivism: Law without
Trimmings (OUP, 1999).
Marmor, Andrei, ‘Exclusive Legal Positivism’, in Jules Coleman and
Scott Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and
Philosophy of Law (OUP, 2002).
Morison, W. L., John Austin (Edward Arnold, 1982).
Postema, Gerald J., Bentham and the Common Law Tradition
(Clarendon Press, 1986).
Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law (OUP, 1979).
—— The Concept of Legal System: An Introduction to the Theory
of Legal System (2nd edn., Clarendon Press, 1980).
—— The Morality of Freedom (OUP, 1986).
—— Ethics in the Public Domain (OUP, 1994).
—— Practical Reason and Norms (OUP, 1999).
—— Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action (OUP,
2000).
—— Value, Respect, and Attachment (Cambridge University Press,
2001).
Tur, Richard, and William Twining (eds.), Essays on Kelsen (Clarendon
Press, 1986).
Waldron, Jeremy (ed.), Nonsense upon Stilts: Bentham, Burke and
Marx on the Rights of Man (Methuen, 1987).
Waluchow, W. J., ‘Authority and the Practical Difference Thesis: A
Defence of Inclusive Legal Positivism’ (2000) 6 Legal Theory 45,
pp. 76–81.
—— Inclusive Legal Positivism (1994).
Chapter 3
Cohen, Marshall (ed.), Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary
Jurisprudence (Duckworth, 1984).
Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously, new impression with a reply
to critics (Duckworth, 1978).
—— A Matter of Principle (Harvard University Press, 1985).
—— Law’s Empire (Belknap Press, 1986).
—— Life’s Dominion: An Argument about Abortion and
Euthanasia (Harper Collins, 1993).
Guest, Stephen, Ronald Dworkin (2nd edn., Edinburgh University
Press, 1997).
Philosophy of Law
Chapter 4
Rights
Dworkin, Ronald, Taking Rights Seriously, new impression with a reply
to critics (Duckworth, 1978).
—— A Matter of Principle (Harvard University Press, 1985).
Hohfeld, Wesley Newcomb, Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied
in Judicial Reasoning, ed. W. W. Cook (Yale University Press, 1964;
also in (1913) 23 Yale Law Journal 28).
Simmonds, N. E., Central Issues in Jurisprudence: Law, Justice, Law
and Rights (2nd edn., Sweet & Maxwell, 2002).
Waldron, Jeremy (ed.), Theories of Rights (OUP, 1984).
White, A. R., Rights (Clarendon Press, 1984).
Justice
Daniels, Norman (ed.), Reading Rawls: Critical Studies on Rawls’
A Theory of Justice (Basil Blackwell, 1975).
Hart, H. L. A., ‘Between Utility and Rights’, in H. L. A. Hart,
Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Clarendon Press,
1982).
Morawetz, Thomas (ed.), Justice (Dartmouth, 1991).
Nozick, Robert, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (Basil Blackwell, 1974).
Polinsky, A. M., An Introduction to Law and Economics (Little, Brown &
Co., 1983).
114
Posner, Richard A., The Economic Analysis of Law (2nd edn., Little,
Brown & Co., 1977).
—— The Economics of Justice (Harvard University Press, 1981).
Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (OUP, 1973).
—— Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press, 1993).
Raz, Joseph, The Authority of Law: Essays on Law and Morality
(Clarendon Press, 1979).
Chapter 5
115
Further reading
Cain, Maureen, and Hunt, Alan, Marx and Engels on Law (Academic
Press, 1979).
Campbell, Tom, The Left and Rights: A Conceptual Analysis of the Idea
of Socialist Rights (Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983).
Collins, Hugh, Marxism and Law (Clarendon Press, 1982).
Cotterrell, Roger, The Sociology of Law: An Introduction (Butterworths,
1984).
—— Law’s Community: Legal Theory in Sociological Perspective
(Clarendon Press, 1995).
Durkheim, Émile, The Division of Labour in Society, tr. George Simpson
(Collier-Macmillan, 1964).
Hunt, Alan, The Sociological Movement in Law (Macmillan, 1978).
Kronman, Anthony R., Max Weber (Edward Arnold, 1983).
Lukes, Steven, and Andrew Scull (eds.), Durkheim and the Law (Martin
Robertson, 1983).
Marx, Karl, Capital, tr. B. Fowkes and D. Fembach (Penguin Books and
Random House, 1976).
Weber, Max, The Religion of China: Confucianism and Taoism, tr. and
ed. Hans H. Gerth (Free Press, 1951).
—— Max Weber on Law in Economy and Society, ed. Max Rheinstein,
tr. Edward Shils and Max Rheinstein (Harvard University Press,
1954).
—— Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, ed.
Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich (Bedminister Press, 1968).
Chapter 6
Philosophy of Law
Realism
Neil Duxbury, Patterns of American Jurisprudence (Clarendon Press,
1995).
Fisher, W. W., M. J. Horwitz, and T. A. Reed (eds.), American Legal
Realism (OUP, 1993).
Llewellyn, Karl N., ‘Some Realism about Realism’ (1931) 44 Harvard
Law Review 1222.
Olivecrona, Karl, Law as Fact (2nd edn., Stevens & Sons, 1971).
Ross, Alf, On Law and Justice, tr. Margaret Dutton (Stevens & Sons,
1958).
Rumble, Wilfred E., American Legal Realism: Skepticism, Reform, and
the Judicial Process (Cornell University Press, 1968).
Twining, William, Karl Llewellyn and the Realist Movement
(Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1973).
Critical legal studies
Boyle, James D. A. (ed.), Critical Legal Studies (Dartmouth, 1992).
Kairys, David (ed.), The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique
(Pantheon Books, 1982).
Kelman, Mark, A Guide to Critical Legal Studies (Harvard University
Press, 1987).
Norrie, Alan (ed.), Closure or Critique: New Directions in Legal Theory
(Edinburgh University Press, 1993).
Unger, Roberto, ‘The Critical Legal Studies Movement’ (1983) 96
Harvard Law Review 561.
—— False Necessity: Anti-Necessitarian Social Theory in the
Service of Radical Democracy (Cambridge University Press, 1987).
Postmodern legal theory
Lacan, Jacques, The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis, tr.
A Sheridan (Penguin, 1979).
Lyotard, Jean-François, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on
Knowledge (Manchester University Press, 1984).
Patterson, Dennis (ed.), Postmodernism and Law (Dartmouth, 1994).
116
Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Basil Blackwell,
1990).
Critical Race Theory
Delgado, Richard, and Jean Stefanic, ‘Critical Race Theory: An
Annotated Bibliography’ (1993) 79 Virginia Law Review 461.
—— (eds.), Critical White Studies: Looking Behind the Mirror (Temple
University Press, 1997).
Harris, Angela P., ‘Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal Theory’
(1990) 42 Stanford Law Review 581.
117
Further reading
Feminist legal theory
Bartlett, Katherine, ‘Tradition, Change, and the Idea of Progress in
Feminist Legal Thought’ (1995) Wisconsin Law Review 303.
Gilligan, Carol, In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s
Development (Harvard University Press, 1982).
Kingdom, Elizabeth F., What’s Wrong with Rights? Problems for
Feminist Politics of Law (Edinburgh University Press, 1991).
Lacey, Nicola (ed.), Unspeakable Subjects: Feminist Essays in Legal and
Social Theory (Hart Publishing, 1998).
MacKinnon, Catharine, Feminism Unmodified: Discourses on Life and
Law (Harvard University Press, 1987).
—— Towards a Feminist Theory of the State (Harvard University
Press, 1989).
Olsen, Frances E., ‘Feminism and Critical Legal Theory: An American
Perspective’ (1990) 18 International Journal of the Sociology of Law
199.
—— (ed.), Feminist Legal Theory (Dartmouth, 1994).
Rhode, Deborah, Justice and Gender: Sex Discrimination and the Law
(Harvard University Press, 1989).
—— ‘Feminist Critical Theories’ (1990) 42 Stanford Law Review
617.
Scales, Anne, ‘The Emergence of Feminist Jurisprudence: An Essay’
(1986) 95 Yale Law Journal 1373.
Smart, Patricia, Feminist Jurisprudence (Clarendon Press, 1993).
Austin compared
commands 20–5
definition of law 23–4
general approaches 20–6
sanctions 24–6
sovereignty 25–6
codification of common law
21–2
essence of utilitarianism
61–2
role of judiciary 21–2
search for determinacy 22
Blackstone, Sir W.
development of natural law
philosophy 5
Index
A
American jurisprudence
Chicago School 68
realism
behavioural view of law
93–4
Holmes 94
Llewellyn 94
Aquinas, St. T.
development of natural law
philosophy 4
starting point for Finnis 15
Aristotle
development of natural law
philosophy 1
justice 59
Austin, J.
Bentham compared
commands 23–5
definition of law 22–3
general approaches 20–6
sanctions 25–6
sovereignty 25
classification of laws 23
conception of legal
positivism based on
commands 23–4
disciple of Bentham 22
disobedience to the law 26
Hart’s rejection of
commands as rules
27–8, 29
C
Capitalism 79–80, 87
Chicago School 66
Choice theory 53
Cicero 3
Coase theorem 67, 68
Codification of common law
21–2
Command theory
Austin and Bentham
compared 20–6
basis of Austin’s conception
of legal positivism 23–5
sovereignty 25–6
Consequentialism
essence of utilitarianism 62
meaning 62
Constitutions
Austin’s conception of legal
positivism 22–3
Contractarian theories
Hobbes 6–7
Locke 8–9
B
Bentham, J.
118
Rawls 70–1
Rousseau 9
Conventionalism 44–5
Cornell, D. 104
Critical legal studies (CLS)
controversial impact 93
development in US 93
fundamental principles 95–7
hegemonic consciousness 95
indeterminacy 96
reification 95
rejection of natural order 95
Critical legal theory
feminist jurisprudence
difference theory 105
liberalism 101–2
postmodernism 104–5
radical theory 102–3
scope and importance 101
human rights 282
postmodernism
Derrida 99–100
Foucault 89–90
hostility to individual
rights 97–8
Lacan 98–9
linguistic analysis of law
98
race theory, critical (CRT)
main themes 106–7
postmodernism 106
scope and importance 106
rejection of natural order
106
Customs
Austin’s conception of legal
positivism 23–4
Bentham’s search for
determinacy 22
D
119
Index
De Groot, H. 4–5
Derrida, J. 99–100, 104
Descriptive legal theory
normative theory
distinguished, xv–xvi
Dialectical materialism 82
Difference feminism 105
Divine law 4
Domination 80–1
Durkheim, E.
functions of punishment
77–8
social solidarity 76–7
social theory 76–8
Duty
correlation with right
54
Raz’s positivism 37–8
Dworkin, R.
attack on Hart’s model of
rules 44–5
constructive interpretation
49–51
hard cases 46–7
law as integrity 49–50
legal theory 40–51
liberalism based on equality
48
literary theory 48–9
non-rule standards 46
one right answer 141
principles and policies 46
relationship between law
and force 49–50
rights as trumps 44–7, 56
special forms of community
50
E
Functionalism
Llewellyn 94
Economic analysis
justice 65–7
Weber’s social theory 79–80
Efficacy 36–7
Ehrlich, E. 76
Engels, F. 81
Equality see Justice;
Liberalism
Eternal law 4
European Convention on
Human Rights 10
see also Human rights
G
Gilligan, C. 105
Gramsci, A. 95
Grundnorm
Kelsen’s theory of legal
positivism 32–7
H
Habermas, J.
‘communicative action’ 89
importance 89
law as medium and
institution
distinguished 89
postmodernism 341, 344
ties with CLS movement 337
Hägerström, A. 110
Hard positivism
soft positivism distinguished
108–9
Hart, H.L.A.
attack on model of rules by
Dworkin 43
classification of commands
27–9
comparisons with Austin
29–30
criticisms of utilitarianism
64, 109
disobedience to the law 19
foundations of legal
positivism 19
legal positivism 18–19
modern theory of legal
positivism
Philosophy of Law
F
Feminist jurisprudence
difference theory 105
feminist jurisprudence
101–5
liberalism
emphasis on equality 102
postmodernism 104–5
scope and importance 101
Fetishism, legal 85
Finnis, J.
Aquinas misconstrued 15
natural rights 16
revival of natural law 10
theory of natural law 14–17
Foucault, M.
importance 90
investigation of power 90–1
postmodernism 90–1, 97
Freud, S. 95
Fuller, L.L.
internal morality of law
12–14
revival of natural law 10
120
acknowledgement of
natural law 28
application of analytical
and philosophical
techniques 26–7
existence of legal system
31–2
‘internal point of view’
31–2
law as a system of rules
28–32
linguistic analysis 26–7
rule of recognition 30–2
secondary rules 30–2
social rules 76–7
‘power-conferring rules’ 26,
30–1
refinement of ideas 18
revival of natural law 10
rights-based theory 55–6
Hobbes, T.
contractarian theory of
natural law 6–7
natural rights 58
Hohfeld, W.N. 53–5
Holmes, O.W.
pioneer of American realism
94
Human rights
revival of natural law 10
scope and importance 52,
55–8
socialism and 86–8
Hume, D.
attack on natural law 9–10
Indeterminacy 21–2, 96
Inner morality
Fuller 12–14
Integrity, law as
Dworkin’s thesis 49–51
Interest theory of rights 53
‘Internal point of view’ 31–2
Interpretive theory
assault on positivism 40,
43–5
constructive approach
48–9
J
I
Ideology 82–3
121
Index
Judiciary
Bentham’s search for
determinacy 21–2
Dworkin’s thesis
assault on
conventionalism 44–5
constructive
interpretation 48–9
hard cases 42–5, 46–7
importance of principles
and policies 45–7
importance of rights 44–6
one right answer 42–3
Justice
Bentham’s search for
determinacy 22
desert 60–1
economic analysis 65–7
Rawls
criticisms 73–4
fundamental principles
67–74
importance 69
original choices 70–3
as interpretation
assault on positivism 44–5
Dworkin’s thesis 40–51
hard cases 46–7
one right answer 42–3
principles and policies
45–7
relationship between law
and force 49–51
special forms of
community 50
meaning and scope, xiii
‘Law as integrity’ 8
‘Law-jobs’ 94
Legal positivism
Austin
classification of laws 22–3
conception based on
commands 23–5
disciple of Bentham 22
Austin and Bentham
compared
commands 20–5
definition of law 23–4
general approaches 20–6
sanctions 25–6
sovereignty 23
Bentham
codification of common
law 21–2
role of judiciary 21–2
search for determinacy 22
Dworkin’s assault 44–5
foundations 18–19
hard and soft approaches
distinguished 108–9
Kelsen’s contribution to
modern theory
efficacy and validity 36–7
Philosophy of Law
rejection of utilitarianism
68–9
revision and refinement
74
rejection by postmodernists
97
scope and importance 52,
58–9
utilitarian approach
essential
consequentialism 61–4
utilitarianism
criticisms 62–5
maximization of wants
62–4
meaning of
consequentialism 62
K
Kaldor-Hicks efficiency test
66–7
Kant, I
influence on Kelsen 32
Kelsen, H.
contribution to modern legal
positivism 32
efficacy and validity
36–7
hierarchy of norms 34–5
‘science of law’ 32
system of norms 32
Kristeva, J. 104
L
Lacan, J. 97, 22–3
Law
Austin and Bentham
compared 22–3
122
Lex iniusta non est lex
obedience to law 4
Liberalism
Dworkin’s thesis 40–51
feminist jurisprudence 102
Habermas’s social theory
89–90
rejection by postmodernists
97
Linguistic analysis of law
modern theory developed by
Hart 26–7
postmodernism 98–100
Littleton, C. 104
Llewellyn, K. 94
Locke, J.
contractarian theory of
natural law 8–9
natural rights 58
Lukàcs, G. 95
Lundstedt, A.V. 110
Lyotard, J-F. 97
M
MacKinnon, C. 102–3, 105
Marxism
descriptive legal theory, xv
distinction between base
and superstructure 81–2
fetishism, legal 85
historical forces 82
ideology 82–3
incompatibility with human
rights 86–8
no law in a classless society
83–4
rejection of rule of law 88
Mill, J.S. 58, 62
123
Index
Grundnorm 34–7
hierarchy of norms 34–5
‘science of law’ 32
system of norms 32
meaning and scope 18–19
modern theory developed by
Hart
acknowledgement of
natural law 28
application of analytical
and philosophical
techniques 26–7
existence of legal system
31–2
‘internal point of view’
31–2
law as a system of rules
28–32
linguistic analysis 26–7
rule of recognition 30–2
secondary rules 30–2
social rules 29
Raz’s contribution to
positivist theory
concept of duty 37–8
‘sources thesis’ 38
Legal realism
American theory
behavioural view of law
93–4
Holmes 94
Llewellyn 94
pioneers 177–9
Scandinavian theory
Olivecrona 110
Ross 110
Legal theory
importance in explaining
society, xiii
O
Morality
see also Natural law
Dworkin’s thesis 43
normative approach, xvi
Raz 38–9
Obedience to law
lex iniusta non est lex 4
sovereignty 24–5
Weber’s social theory
80–1
Olivecrona, K.
pioneer of Scandinavian
realism 110
Olsen, F. 103, 104
Philosophy of Law
N
Natural law
acknowledgement by Hart
28
decline 9–10
meaning and components
1–3
non-cognitivist objections
9–10
philosophical development
development of God-given
principles 3–4
Hobbes 6–7
Locke 8
political application 10
reason as a basis for law
14–17
Rousseau 9
revival in 20th century
10
Finnis 14–17
Fuller 12–14
shared ground with
positivism 28
Non-cognitivism in ethics
decline of natural law
9–10
Finnis 16–17
Normative legal theory
descriptive theory
distinguished, xv–xvi
Nuremberg war trials 10
P
Pareto optimality test 66
Policies
importance in Dworkin’s
thesis 46
Posner, R. 65–7
Postmodernism
Derrida 99–100
feminist jurisprudence
104–5
Foucault 89–90
hostility to individual rights
97–8
Lacan 98–9
linguistic analysis of law
98
race theory, critical 106–7
scope and importance 106
Pound, R.
importance 76
Principles
importance in Dworkin’s
thesis 45–7
Public international law
Austin’s conception of legal
positivism 23
Punishment see Sanctions
124
R
Race theory, critical (CRT)
postmodernism 106
scope and importance 106–7
Rawls, J.
criticisms of utilitarianism
68–9
justice
fundamental principles
58–61
importance 58–9
original choices 70–3
rejection of utilitarianism
68–9
revision and refinement
73–4
Raz, J.
contribution to legal
positivism
concept of duty 37–8
‘sources thesis’ 38
hard positivist approach
37–8
moral obligation to obey the
law 38–9
Realism see Legal realism
Recognition, rule of
criticisms by Dworkin
43
Hart’s rule 30–1
morality 28
Rights
alternative theories
duty and goal based
approaches 55–6
will and interest based
approaches 53
Hohfeld’s analysis 53–5
S
Sanctions
see also Obedience to law
Austin and Bentham
compared 25–6
Austin’s theory of
commands 23–4
125
Index
hostility of postmodernism
97–8
human rights
and socialism 86–8
scope and importance
52
importance in Dworkin’s
thesis 44–7
Marxist theory 86–8
as part of law 44–7
rejection by postmodernists
97–8
scope and importance 52,
55–8
Ross, A.
pioneer of Scandinavian
realism 110
Rousseau, J-J.
contractarian theory of
natural law 9
Rule of law
Marxist rejection 88
Rules
criticisms of Dworkin 43
Hart
law as a system of rules
26–32
rule of recognition 30–2
secondary rules 30–2
social rules 29
Philosophy of Law
Durkheim’s social theory
77–8
Kelsen 32
Secondary rules 30–2
Smart, C. 103–4
Social contractarianism
fundamental principles 70
original choices 70–3
Rawls’ theory of justice
67–74
revision and refinement 74
Social theory
Durkheim
functions of punishment
77–8
social solidarity 76–7
Ehrlich 76
Foucault
importance 90
investigation of power
90–1
Habermas
‘communicative action’ 89
importance 89
law as medium and
institution
distinguished 89
Marxism
distinction between base
and superstructure
81–2
fetishism, legal 85
historical forces 82
ideology 82–3
no law in a classless
society 83–4
rejection of rule of law 88
Pound
importance 76
Weber
criticisms 81
economic forces 79–80
importance 78
legitimate domination
80–1
typology of law 80–1
Soft positivism
hard positivism
distinguished 108–9
Sovereignty
Austin and Bentham
compared 25
Habermas social theory 89
T
Thompson, E.P. 88
U
Unger, R. 95–6
United Nations Charter 57–8
Universal Declaration of
Human Rights 57–8
Utilitarianism
justice
economic analysis 65–7
essential
consequentialism 62
maximization of wants
62–4
meaning of
consequentialism 62
rejection by Rawls 68–9
V
Validity
Kelsen’s theory of legal
positivism 36–7
126
W
legitimate domination 75,
80–1
typology of law 80–1
Will theory 53
Williams, P. 100
Weber, M
criticisms 81
economic forces 79–80
importance 78
Index
127