1
Freedom and the Phenomenology of Agency
Martine Nida-Rümelin, University of Fribourg (Switzerland)
Published in Erkenntnis, 83 (1), 61-87, 2018.
1. Introduction
In contemporary philosophy of agency, it is considered a central task to account for the
difference between actions and other events. But there is, according to the view here
presented, a more fundamental distinction to be drawn: the one between active behavior
(bodily or mental events brought about in a sense to be explained by the subject concerned)
and mere happenings (bodily or mental changes the subject at issue passively undergoes).
According to the view here proposed, the capacity to behave in an active manner is not
restricted to the human domain and might already have occurred with the emergence of
simple forms of consciousness in early stages of biological evolution.1
It is hard to deny that we all share a vivid understanding of the distinction between changes
that happen to a subject and changes the subject actively brings about. But how do we form
this understanding and what is it based upon? According to the view here proposed our main
cognitive route to the difference between activity and passivity is phenomenological: we
understand what it is to be active on the basis of our awareness of being active while being
active in our own doings.
In daily life we experience our own doings as actively brought about by ourselves; they seem
to be generated in a way which involves that we, the experiencing being we are, actively
contribute to their occurrence. Analogously, we experience the behavior of others (of human
2
subjects and of non-human animals we take to be conscious) as actively brought about by
them. I will briefly present an argument for the following conclusions:
(C1) Experiences of our own present behavior as active and perceptions of the behavior of
other conscious subjects as active are (in large part) veridical. In other words: conscious
subjects are active in their behavior in the way in which they appear to be active in those
experiences.
(C2) A behavior which is active in the relevant sense (brought about by the subject concerned
in the sense at issue) is not causally determined by previous events.
The argument for these conclusions will be sketchy, it is in need of further elaboration and it
is not the main theme of the present paper. I will focus here on a different issue: I would like
to explore how these conclusions, if true, can help us to get clear about the old puzzle about
freedom and determination.
One central ingredient of the view which will emerge is this: the much-discussed apparent or
genuine tension between free agency and determination has been miss-localized. The
supposed incompatibility of free action and determination has nothing in particular to do with
freedom; it is rather due to the fact that all action (be it free or unfree) is active behavior.
Active behavior, as will be argued below, is incompatible with microphysical determination
but it is compatible with determination in the sense of there being no metaphysically possible
alternative to the way the agent acts in a given case. This distinction will prove helpful for
3
developing a better understanding of the various competing core intuitions underlying the
debate about freedom and determination.
2. Agentive and perceptual experiences of behavior as active
The following description cited from T. Horgan & Tienson [2003] is an excellent way, I find,
to ‘point’ to that specific aspect:
“..What is behaving like phenomenologically, in cases where you experience your own
behavior as action? Suppose that you deliberately perform an action—say, holding up
your right hand and closing your fingers into a fist. As you focus on the
phenomenology of this item of behavior, what is your experience like? To begin with,
there is of course the purely behavioral aspect of the phenomenology—the what-it’slike of being visually and kinesthetically presented with one’s own right hand rising
and its fingers moving into clenched position. But there is more to it than that, of
course, because you are experiencing this bodily motion as your own action. In order
to help bring into focus this specifically actional phenomenological dimension of the
experience, it will be helpful to approach it a negative/contrastive way, via some
observations about what the experience is not like. For example, it is certainly not like
this: first experiencing an occurrent wish for your right hand to rise and your fingers to
move into clenched position, and then passively experiencing your hand and fingers
moving in just that way. Such phenomenal character might be called the
phenomenology of fortuitously appropriate bodily motion. It would be very strange
indeed, and very alien. Nor is the actional phenomenological character of the
4
experience like this: first experiencing an occurrent wish for your right hand to rise
and your fingers to move into clenched position, and then passively experiencing a
causal process consisting of this wish’s causing your hand to rise and your fingers to
move into clenched position. Such phenomenal character might be called the passive
phenomenology of psychological state-causation of bodily motion. People often do
passively experience causal processes as causal processes, of course: the collision of a
moving billiard ball with a motionless billiard ball is experienced as causing the latter
ball’s subsequent motion; the impact of the leading edge of an avalanche with a tree in
its path is experienced as causing the tree to become uprooted; and so on. But it seems
patently clear that one does not normally experience one’s own actions in that way—
as passively noticed, or passively introspected, causal processes consisting in the
causal generation of bodily motion by occurrent mental states. That too would be a
strange and alienating sort of experience.
How, then, should one characterize the actional phenomenal dimension of the act of
raising one’s hand and clenching one’s fingers, given that it is not the phenomenology
of fortuitously appropriate bodily motion and it also is not the passive phenomenology
of psychological event-causation of bodily motion? Well, it is the what-it’s-like of self
as source of the motion. You experience your arm, hand, and fingers as being moved
by you yourself—rather than experiencing their motion either as fortuitously moving
just as you want them to move, or passively experiencing them as being caused by
your own mental states. You experience the bodily motion as caused by yourself.“
In the cited passage a preliminary account of how things appear in agentive experiences with
the relevant aspect is proposed: the agent is under the impression of causing him- or herself
the relevant physical event (the movement of the hand). At the same time the passage has a
5
different function: it aims at attracting attention to a specific feature or aspect of agentive
experience. It thereby tries to establish shared reference among the author and the reader to a
particular phenomenal aspect of normal human agentive experience. It is the second function
of the text which is most relevant for my present purposes. Despite a number of objections
one might raise against the contrasting characterization and against the particular formulation
of the supposed content of the experience, the passage is admirable, I find, in the way it
attracts attention to a specific aspect of agentive experience.2 For most readers, I believe, it is
successful in establishing shared reference to that omnipresent aspect of the way it is like to
act. In the following I will assume that this is so.
What is called in the cited passage “the experience of self as source” is precisely what I mean
saying that we experience our own behavior as actively brought about by ourselves. I prefer
the latter terminology for the following reason: Agentive experience with respect to one’s
own behavior and perceptual experience concerning the behavior of others have the very same
kind of content. Therefore, we need to introduce a terminology that allows us to describe that
common content in a natural manner. Describing that content saying that some piece of
behavior appears to be actively brought about by the subject concerned (ourselves in the
agentive case, the perceived other subject in the perceptual case) allows us to do so. By
contrast, to say that we perceive “other selves as source” would be a quite unhappy way to put
the point since it would misleadingly suggest that we see other selves. Furthermore, it seems
quite important to me to realize that there is a close relation here between the way our own
behavior is given to us (in acting or in doing something) and the way the behavior of others is
given to us (in observing them as they do things) which should be kept in mind and
underlined already by the terminology one chooses.
6
Here are a few more examples of agentive experiences with the aspect of ‘experiencing one’s
own behavior as active’. Movements done without any conscious intention and in an
inattentive manner like moving one’s legs while listening to a talk are experienced,
nonetheless, as brought about by ourselves. Complex movements such as dancing, even if
done in a totally unplanned manner and in a way one experiences as not consciously
controlled, are experienced as actively brought about by oneself. Some elements of our mental
life are experienced as actively brought about by ourselves. This is typically so for conscious
decisions taken on the basis of deliberation. (By contrast, mental events such as thought
contents suddenly popping up in one’s mind are not experienced as actively brought about by
oneself.) Quick reactions without reflection to a suddenly perceived danger (for instance
while driving a car) are experienced as actively brought about even though they are not
experienced as done for reasons that are present to the person in the moment of the reaction
and even though they are experienced as ‘directly triggered’ in some sense by the perception
of danger.
Here are a few examples of perceptual experiences of active behavior in others: when a
person you talk to suddenly smiles in an amused manner then you see the smile as an active
behavior of that person, the person you are confronted with seems to be actively involved in
the way that smile comes about. The smile does not look to you like the result of
microphysically determined inner neural and muscular processes. It looks as if done by the
person in a way which excludes such microphysical determination, or so I would like to
suggest. Similar observations apply to seeing animals in their behavior. You see the bird as if
actively moving its head when it turns its gaze towards you and you see the squirrel, the
experiencing subject you are confronted with on such an occasion, as running up the tree in an
7
active manner, where that active manner involves, according to the way things appear to you,
that it is the squirrel itself who actively contributes to its running.
3. Veridicality conditions of experiences: terminology and presuppositions
Before starting to present a few more specific claims about the phenomenology of agency and
the phenomenology of perception it will be helpful to introduce some terminology and to
make several theoretical presuppositions explicit. Experiences as the term will be understood
here are instantiations of experiential properties by experiencing subjects.3 Experiential
properties can be characterized as follows:
Definition 1
A property P is an experiential property iff (a) it can only be instantiated by experiencing
subjects and (b) its instantiation by a subject S partially consists in what it is like for S to have
property P.
Experiential properties in the sense of that definition need not be exhausted by what it is like
to have them. For instance, having a headache is an experiential property which is not
exhausted by what it is like to have it since having a headache involves having a feeling with
a particular kind of cause, or so at least one may plausibly argue. Experiential properties in a
strict sense (as opposed to the broad sense just defined above) are experiential properties such
that having them is exhausted by what it is like to have them. To be acting is an experiential
property in the broad but not in the strict sense. It is something like for the subject who acts to
8
be acting but the fact that the subject is acting does not consist in what it is like for the subject
to act.
It is characteristic of many experiences that the subject at issue is under the impression that
certain things are the case. For instance, in being visually presented with a tree the subject is
under the impression of there being a tree with specific properties in front. If there is in fact
no tree in the subject’s environment, then the experience is not veridical: it does not present
the world as it actually is. Veridicality of an experience may be defined as follows:
Definition 2 (veridicality):
An experience of type E is veridical iff the way the world appears to be to the subject in
having the associated experiential properties is the way the world actually is.
The above definition presupposes that for every experience type E there are associated
experiential properties such that each occurrence of an experience of type E consists in the
instantiation of those experiential properties by some experiencing subject. An experience is
veridical just in case its associated veridicality conditions (in the sense of the definition
below) are fulfilled.
Definition 3 (veridicality conditions):
The conditions C constitute the veridicality conditions of a given experience type E iff in a
case where an experience of that type E is veridical this is so in virtue of the satisfaction of
those conditions C.
9
I will be assuming in what follows that phenomenal kinds of experiences can be described by
the veridicality conditions that are common to all members of that type. I do not thereby
subscribe to the stronger claim that phenomenal properties can be reduced to intentional
properties. This stronger claim can be formulated within the terminology chosen here in the
following way: for every experiential property P there is a specification of veridicality
conditions CP such that having property P consists in being under the impression that the
conditions CP are fulfilled. Even if one explicitly rejects the possibility of such a reduction one
may still accept that one can at least partially describe in many cases what it is like to have a
certain experiential property by describing what appears to be the case to someone who has
that property. Since (a) phenomenal kinds of experiences are individuated by the associated
experiential properties and (b) experiential properties can be described (even though not fully
captured) by what appears to be the case to someone having the property and (c) the
veridicality conditions of an experience specify what appears to be the case for someone
having the associated experiential properties, it follows that one can describe phenomenal
kinds of experiences by reference to the associated veridicality conditions.
For instance, one can describe the specific aspect of the experiential property of acting which
has been called here “the experience of one’s own behavior as active” by specifying how
things appear to be to the agent in acting (and in thereby undergoing an experience with that
aspect). It seems phenomenologically obvious that these veridicality conditions concern the
way the behavior comes about; they concern the way the behavior is generated. The same
applies quite obviously to the perceptual case. When you see the squirrel as actively
contributing to its bodily movements then those movements appear to be generated in a
specific way. To specify the veridicality conditions of these experiences is to specify what
appears to be the case to the subject undergoing such experiences. I will assume here and I
10
hope that this will seem obvious to most readers: the conditions that must be satisfied by a
given behavior for the experience of that behavior as active to be veridical are the same for
experiencing one’s own behavior as active (in the agentive case) and for experiencing the
behavior of others as active (in the perceptual case).
4. The veridicality conditions of experiences of behavior as active and the nature of being
active
I would like to summarize the view her to be explored by the slogan that conscious animals
are genuinely active in their behavior and I will call it the GAA view accordingly (derived
from “genuinely active animals”). To add “genuinely” in its characterization is meant to point
to the fact that being active is understood here in a specific sense. I don’t mean to call a
behavior active for the simple reason that internal states of the animal contribute substantially
to its occurrence. I mean to call it active only if there is a sense in which the animal as such
brings the behavior about and this precisely in the way which renders our everyday
experiences of our own behavior as active and the behavior of other animals as active
veridical.
But why should one assume that to be active is to fulfill the veridicality conditions of the
relevant experiences of being active? Here is the motivation: Our primary cognitive access to
what it is to be active is experiential: we understand what it is to be active via our agentive
and perceptual experiences of being active. If those experiences are all illusionary, then there
is no such thing as active behavior. It is therefore justified to introduce the phenomenon of
being active (the phenomenon referred to by “active behavior” if there is such a phenomenon)
11
by stipulation as the condition which renders experiences of being active veridical. Accepting
this stipulation implies that the way we experience items of behavior to be generated when we
experience them as active puts constraints on the very nature of the phenomenon we talk
about using the term “active behavior”. If, for instance, to experience an item of behavior as
active involves experiencing it as not caused by previous events, then active behavior (if it
exists) is not caused by previous events.
To determine the correct description of the veridicality conditions of a given type of
experience is not a trivial task at all nor is it obvious how one should proceed to find an
adequate description in a given case.4 There is no room here to weigh different possible
proposals against each other for the case here at hand of agentive and perceptual experiences
of behavior as active. I will simply work with the following suggestion and leave defending it
against objections to a different occasion:
(PH1) In experiencing ourselves as active in behavior B, we experience the behavior as
brought about by ourselves in a way which excludes that the behavior is causally determined
by previous events (such as occurrent desires or wishes or by the brain processes ‘realizing’
them).
(PH2) In experiencing the behavior of other animals as active, we experience their behavior as
brought about by them in a way which excludes that their behavior is causally determined by
previous events.
(PH1) should not be misunderstood as claiming that our own mental states and other events
such as physical processes in our brain appear to play no role in the generation of our own
12
behavior. To the contrary one should of course admit that in many cases of agentive
experience we are not only aware in a phenomenally manifest manner of actively contributing
to the realization of certain movements but rather also aware in a phenomenally manifest
manner of what motivates us to actively do what we do. It follows from (PH1) that the
relevant experiences are veridical only if motivation is distinct from event causation. In other
words: for a conscious person to be motivated by reasons must not be equated with the
relevant item of behavior being causally determined by events such as realizers of the relevant
representation of reasons in the brain. According to (PH1) the agentive experience of being
active is illusionary if for an item of human behavior to be motivated by certain
considerations is for that item to be caused by appropriate brain processes some of which are
the physiological basis of the relevant conscious considerations. Rather, if these experiences
are veridical, then something like this must be an adequate description of rational human
behavior: the person at issue actively brings about behavior B in light of certain
considerations. Even if these considerations are so compelling that the person has no other
choice given her values and convictions the behavior the person brings about actively is not
causally determined be previous events.
Similar remarks apply to the content of perceptual experiences of behavior as active. (PH2)
should not be misunderstood as claiming that seeing the squirrel as actively involved in its
running includes the impression that the squirrel’s fear does not play any role. To the
contrary, it may on a given occasion be part of the content of such a perceptual experience
that you see the squirrel as actively bringing about its hectic running because it is frightened
by your presence. (PH2) only implies the following: if your perception of the squirrel is
veridical, then, yes, it runs because it is frightened, but the “because” here at issue must not be
understood as stating a simple event-causal link such as the fear or its basis in the brain
13
mechanically causing (together with other brain processes) the running movements. To say it
in a vivid manner: According to (PH2) you see the squirrel’s movement in a way which
excludes that the squirrel is a biological mechanism. According to the way you see it, the
squirrel is a conscious active individual in a sense that excludes that it is a biological robot, a
conglomeration of cells the behavior of which is microphysically determined.
The GAA view assumes that our experiences of behavior as active are in the overwhelming
majority of paradigmatic cases veridical. It states, in other words, that in the large majority of
paradigmatic cases the veridicality conditions associated to experiences of behavior as active
are satisfied. In order to make the view explicit one has to characterize the veridicality
conditions at issue. In line with what has been said so far, I propose the following claim about
the veridicality conditions for experiences of behavior as active (it makes no difference if the
experience is agentive or perceptual):
V: An item of behavior B fulfills the veridicality conditions of experiences of behavior as
active if and only if B is brought about by the subject concerned in such a way that B is not
causally determined by previous events.
It seems safe to assume that a bodily movement which is causally determined by previous
events is microphysically determined. It therefore follows from V that no microphysically
determined behavior fulfills the veridicality conditions of experiences of behavior as active.
The GAA view may now be characterized as follows: in the vast majority of paradigmatic
cases of human and non-human behavior which are experienced as active the right hand side
of the bi-conditional formulated in V is satisfied. The behavior is generated in the way it
14
seems to be generated: it is actively brought about by the subject in a way which excludes that
it is causally determined by previous events and in a way which excludes that it is
microphysically determined.
The above characterization is only a minimal description of the GAA view about which a lot
more could be said. For the purposes of the present paper it is crucial to see that the GAA
view allows for and even requires distinguishing two senses of determination: causal
determination of concrete occurrences of items of behavior by previous events on the one
hand and metaphysical determination of the kind of behavior realized at a given occasion on
the other. The way a person acts may be metaphysically determined in the sense that there is
no metaphysically possible counterfactual situation in which the same relevant preconditions
are fulfilled and yet the person acts otherwise. And yet, according to the GAA view, even if a
person’s way of acting is metaphysically determined the person’s act is not causally
determined by previous events. Such situations of metaphysical determination can be
adequately described in retrospect as follows: it was within the causal powers of the person to
act otherwise but there was no metaphysical possibility that she would do so. This claim may
appear paradoxical at first sight but it will, I hope, gain some plausibility for the reader when
illustrated below in several cases. The distinction between causal and metaphysical
determination here at issue will be crucial for the resolution of the puzzle about freedom and
determination proposed in the last five sections of this paper.
Why should we accept the GAA view? Here is the answer I would like to propose: If what has
been said about the veridicality conditions of experiences of behavior as active is correct, then
the only alternative to the GAA view is an illusion theory. Omnipresent experiences
concerning our own behavior and the behavior of others would have to be illusionary. When,
15
for instance, you see the smile of a person as brought about by her, then this is (if the GAA
must be rejected) strictly speaking a mere illusion. If, under the influence of some bad drug,
you were to see the smile as a mechanistically caused facial change then, if the GAA is false,
your experience of the smile would be veridical. If you see a squirrel as a conscious individual
bringing about its running in an active manner, then, strictly speaking, you are, again, a victim
of illusion. In reality, the squirrel is (if the GAA is false) a microphysically determined
system; it is what one may properly call a biological robot. According to such an illusion
theory the experience of being actively involved is an illusion created in us by certain brain
mechanisms and the perceptual experience of others as active is a projection of that illusion
onto others we are presented with in perceptual experience.
Is the illusion theory credible at all? That much should be clear: if there was a person who
perceived others in the way which would be veridical according to the illusion theory, then he
or she would live in a regrettable situation. One would consider his or her experience as
pathological and would have deep pity given the sad impoverishment of his or her subjective
world. This does not show that the illusion theory is false but it does show that accepting it is
a high price to pay. We should be ready to pay such a price only if compelling reasons can be
given to the effect that the GAA view is unacceptable. Those reasons can only be scientific
reasons. Are there such reasons? I am convinced there are not, but this is a big issue which
cannot be discussed here.
The argument sketched here for the GAA view can be attacked in a number of ways:
(1) One may argue that there are no experiences of being active or that their veridicality
conditions have been miss-described.
16
(2) One may argue that there are compelling scientific reasons for accepting that those
veridicality conditions are never fulfilled and go for the illusion theory.
(3) One may argue that the illusion attributed to us by the illusion theory is not as radical and
fundamental as has been suggested by the above description and that it is not so hard to accept
that we are, in that respect, permanently the victim of illusion.
I don’t believe that any of these objections is in the end successful. But I cannot even start to
answer them here. Instead, I will explore the view about freedom and determination which
emerges if we assume for the moment, for the sake of argument, that the GAA view is correct.
Before doing so it will be helpful to put the GAA view in the context of the contemporary
landscape of available theories about agency. The reader will have recognized elements of
what has been called the thesis of agent causation and some will wonder about the relation
between such much-discussed views and the one here proposed. So let me briefly clarify this
relation before I finally start talking about freedom.
5. The GAA view and agent causation
The GAA view is a close relative of the agent causation view (called the ACV in what
follows). According to the ACV there is a specific kind of causation at work in free human
action. While normal causation relates events as causes and effects, that special kind of
causation relates individuals (a person, an agent) to events (e.g. bodily movements or changes
in the brain). The person itself is considered to be the cause of the event at issue.5 The ACV
view is not standardly motivated by any phenomenological observations about how things
appear to be in agentive or perceptual experience; it is standardly motivated by theoretical
considerations about moral responsibility and human freedom. Yet, when pressed to say what
17
agent causation is supposed to be some authors claim that we are familiar with it on the basis
of our own action.6 If one is attracted by agent causation theories at all, then one will naturally
assume that it is the first person experience of bringing one’s own movements about which
gives us access to what it is for an agent to cause an event in the relevant sense of agent
causation. This is, I take it, what makes the two views, the GAA view and the ACV close
relatives. They both owe their intuitive attractiveness in great part to the way things appear to
be in agentive experience.
However, in order to motivate the ACV by the assumption that agentive experiences of being
active are veridical one would have to make a strong claim about their veridicality conditions.
Instead of the claim V proposed in the preceding section one would have to say this:
V’: The veridicality conditions of agentive experiences of behavior as active are fulfilled if
and only if the behavior is caused by the subject (in the specific metaphysical sense stated by
agent causation theories).
V’ implies V but an argument would be required to show that V implies V’. The GAA view
only incorporates V and is therefore weaker and thereby less problematic. It is open for the
possibility that ultimately some version of the agent causation view must be accepted. But
there are other possible accounts (one of them briefly sketched below) of what it is to be
active in one’s behavior compatible with V that are not committed to the metaphysical thesis
that subjects (agents) are causes which might in the end prove superior for theoretical and
empirical reasons.7
Related to the difference just explained the following advantages of the GAA view compared
to the ACV view merit to be pointed out:
(1) It has been argued that the ACV is inacceptable for the following reason: contrary to
events individuals are not dated. But how can an event which is dated (it happens at a certain
18
moment) have a cause which is not dated (it is not, in the relevant sense, located in time)?8
The GAA view as characterized so far may be elaborated saying that for a behavior to be
active is for it to fulfill the following condition: the subject at issue is actively involved in the
generation of the behavior. If, for instance, the behavior takes place in the time interval
[m1,m2] then for that behavior to be active involves that the subject at issue is active in that
behavior in a time interval including [m1,m2]. No specific metaphysical claim about what it
is to be active in a given temporally extended behavior is implied by that description. (In
particular, as already stated before, it is not implied that the subject is, literarily, the cause of
that behavior.)
(2) The ACV is often presented in a way which invites the idea that the agent intervenes in a
punctual or instantaneous manner, thereby triggering one thing to happen instead of another.
The picture invited is that, when lifting my arm to vote, for instance, I cause some initial brain
event to happen which then further develops all by itself, so to speak, and causes my arm to
move. This picture is, however, not the one invited by phenomenology as will be clear by
some reflection and it is dubious for independent reasons. - The picture invited by the GAA
view is quite different. In agentive experiences we appear to be actively involved in the
generation of the whole movement while it is executed. We do not seem to instantaneously
trigger the movement at its very beginning. Therefore, since being active is, by stipulation,
what renders these experiences veridical, and the GAA view states that they are veridical,
actively moving one’s arm involves that the subject is active in the generation of the physical
event during the whole period of time in which it happens.
Besides these two differences it will be clear by now that there are further points where the
GAA view and the ACV diverge:
19
(3) While the ACV restricts the phenomenon of agent causation to the human realm or even
to the special case of free human action the GAA view claims that active behavior is
widespread in the animal kingdom and present as well in human and non-human behavior that
one normally does not classify as action.
(4) The ACV view is standardly motivated by theoretical considerations about freedom and
responsibility. By contrast, the GAA view is motivated by phenomenological observations
about how we experience ourselves in our active behavior and about how we perceive others
in theirs.
6. Resolution of the problem about freedom – description of its central elements
From the perspective of the GAA view the famous problem about freedom and determinism
presents itself in a new manner. It turns out that puzzling and famous problems dissolve.
Furthermore, using the GAA view one can isolate, for two standard responses, for
compatibilism and for libertarianism, what it is about them that makes them intuitively
appealing and what their insights are. Within the GAA view, an account of human freedom
can be developed which unites those insights. It will be helpful to start with an overview of
how the GAA view manages doing that.9
According to the compatibilist there is no genuine conflict between the thesis of human
freedom and the claim that all human behavior is microphysically determined. This claim is
unacceptable for a proponent of the GAA view according to which all active behavior is
generated in a way which is incompatible with micro-physical determinism. So with respect
to this element the proponent of the GAA view sides with the libertarian. However, the
20
motivation given within the GAA view for denying the compatibility of free action and
micro-physical determinism is different. The libertarian motivates the relevant incompatibility
claim by some strong version of the so-called PAP principle (the principle of alternative
possibilities) according to which free action requires that relevantly different possibilities are
open and up to the agent in moments of free choice so that he or she could have acted
otherwise under the very same external and internal conditions. Contrary to this the proponent
of the GAA view rejects the PAP principle and argues that free action is incompatible with
microphysical determinism not in virtue of being free but simply in virtue of being an instance
of active behavior.
The proponent of the GAA view can and should deny the version of the PAP principle
endorsed by libertarians and concede to the compatibilist that there are many cases of
genuinely free action where the agent could not have acted otherwise and that free action is
quite typically determined by the reasons available to the agent in the moment of choice in the
following sense: given those reasons and all other relevant conditions satisfied at the moment
of choice there was no psychological and no metaphysical possibility that the agent would act
differently. To admit this is compatible – within the GAA view - with the denial of
microphysical determination of the relevant piece of behavior. The GAA theorist can
distinguish two relevant senses of determination of an instance of human behavior
(psychological or even metaphysical determination on the one hand and microphysical
determination on the other) and use this distinction to integrate the following claims: (1) in
many cases of free action the relevant behavior is psychologically or metaphysically
determined. (2) In no case of (free) action (and in fact, in no case of active behavior), the
relevant item of behavior is microphysically determined. By integrating (1) the GAA view
can preserve an important part of the compatibilist intuition; by integrating (2) the GAA view
21
can preserve an important part of the libertarian intuition. - Let us now have a closer look at
how the GAA view can integrate the compatibilist core intuition without thereby abandoning
the libertarian core intuition.10
7. Psychological determination
The core idea of the libertarian view may be formulated as follows: in cases of free action the
person determines which of various future courses of events will be realized. In such cases the
following condition holds: there is a moment m before the choice such that there are
nomologically possible future continuations of the actual course of events until moment m in
which the person acts differently from the way she actually acts and that are yet exactly like
the real course of events with respect to all relevant conditions obtaining before and at
moment m. For instance, when a person raises her arm in order to vote for a candidate and
thereby acts freely, then – according to the libertarian core idea - it was still nomologically
possible (that is compatible with the laws of nature) at some moment m briefly before she
took her decision that she would not raise her arm; it was possible that she acts otherwise (and
thereby moves otherwise) under the very same internal and external conditions obtaining at
moment m. More specifically, the libertarian does not want the agent’s decision to be
determined by the prevailing psychological factors and wishes to defend the intuition that in
the relevant cases of free choice the person can decide in various different ways under exactly
the same psychological conditions (same beliefs, same values, same character etc.). The
libertarian intuition thus includes that free actions are never psychologically determined: if an
act is free, then the person could have acted otherwise under the very same psychological preconditions. This is where the libertarian goes wrong. Many actions (or choices) that should be
22
considered as free are psychologically determined. Nonetheless a core intuition behind the
libertarian view can be preserved and explicated within the GAA view.11
The notion of psychological determination will play a central role in the following discussion.
In order to contrast the GAA view with the libertarian view it will be helpful to use a strong
notion of psychological determination of a person’s action which can be explained, roughly,
in the following way: under the same psychological conditions it was metaphysically
impossible that the person acts otherwise. To be more precise, the relevant notion of
psychological determination must be relativized to a moment m in time along the lines of the
following definition:
Definition (psychological determination at a given moment m):
S realizes action A at moment m’; m is prior to m’.
B is psychologically determined at m (or: determined by the psychological conditions
obtaining at m) iff:
S realizes action A at moment m’ in all metaphysically possible counterfactual situations in
which
(a) S is at m’ in the same objective decision situation as in the real world (with respect to all
conditions relevant for what S does at m’).
(b) S has, at m’, the same psychological properties as far as they are relevant to what S does at
m’.
(c) All other conditions obtaining between m and m’ that are relevant to what S does at m’ are
the same as in the real world insofar as they are independent of S’s self-generated
psychological development between m and m’.
23
Condition (c) excludes cases in which an external event such as a stone falling on the person’s
head prevents her from realizing A at m’. If such possible situations where quantified over in
the above definition then an action realized in the real world would count as not
psychologically determined if it is metaphysically possible that an external event of the kind
just mentioned prevents the person from acting in the way she would have acted had the event
not occurred. It is however necessary to restrict the conditions mentioned in (c) to those that
are independent of S’s self-generated psychological development between m and m’ to avoid
another problem. An act is not psychologically determined at moment m if (for instance) the
agent’s active direction of attention makes a difference for what he or she does at m’ and if it
is not metaphysically excluded at m that she directs her attention in this specific way (the
GAA view allows for that possibility). Such a case which otherwise would be a
counterexample to the definition is excluded by condition (c).12
With these clarifications we can now turn to the way in which the GAA view can incorporate
the compatibilist core intuition. The basic idea will be this: while microphysical determination
is not compatible with free action since it is not even compatible with being active, an action
can be free and yet psychologically determined in the sense just defined.
8. Obvious choices
The libertarian view has a serious problem with situations of obvious choices. It is
characteristic of such situations that it is immediately obvious to the agent what it is he or she
24
should do and that the agent has no reason and no motivation not to do what appears to be the
thing to do in the situation at hand. Here are four examples of that kind:
Example 1: While Anton is sitting on a river beach he observes a two year old boy who is
playing next to the river. The parents’ attention is caught by a conversation with friends.
There are no other people on the beach. Suddenly the boy stumbles and falls into the water.
Anton immediately understands the situation. He jumps up, hurries to the river and saves the
little boy grasping his arm and pulling him out.
Example 2: Beatrice is a teacher of mathematics. Every Monday morning Beatrice stands up
at 8.00 and leaves her home to go to the school in her neighborhood in order to start teaching
at 9.00. This is what she does on Monday, April 11, 2016. She doesn’t think about whether or
not she will go to school today. It is obvious to her as she wakes up that this is the thing to do.
She realizes her plan without any deliberation.
Example 3: Christopher must undergo a surgery. He must choose between two possible ways
for the medical doctors to proceed. After having done what he could do to gain all relevant
information within reasonable limits of time, Christopher is convinced that the first procedure
is more expensive, more painful and more risky than the second. There are no other relevant
differences as far as Christopher knows between the two procedures. Christopher takes the
obviously rational decision in favor of the first option.
Example 4: Daniela is part of a political committee which must decide by majority vote who
of two candidates will be assigned a responsible position. Candidate A is, in Daniela’s view, a
reasonable person who is well suited for the job. Candidate B is a person with sympathies for
25
neo-Nazi groups and is likely as far as Daniela knows to use the power associated with the
position in a morally problematic manner. It is obvious for Daniela that she should vote for
candidate A and so in the relevant moment she does so by raising her arm.
With plausible additional assumptions all four cases are such that a third person who knows
the agent and the situation well enough could predict with certainty (setting aside intervening
factors that prevent the person from acting or that change the situation in some relevant
manner) what the agent will do. Furthermore plausible additional assumptions make it even
metaphysically impossible that the person acts otherwise than she actually does. Let us
assume that Anton has a realistic perception of the danger for the boy and of the likelihood
that the boy will die if he doesn’t intervene and let us assume furthermore that Anton is a
normal rational person. Under these psychological preconditions together with the assumption
that nothing prevents Anton from acting, it is simply impossible that Anton does not act in
order to save the child. The psychological preconditions do not determine how exactly he
executes the action; they do not determine in what way he jumps up, with how many steps he
runs to the river and which of the boy’s arms he grasps in order to pull him out. But it is
impossible that he acts in a way which does not fall under the type “trying to save the boy”. In
every counterfactual course of events in which Anton does not try to save the child in the
same objective situation, either some event occurs before he can do what he intends to do (in
contradiction to condition c in the definition of psychological determination) or Anton has
suddenly become crazy, or he has very different values, or he is suddenly befallen of an
irrational fear of drowning himself etc. Under the conditions at issue, a person who is
psychologically like Anton in all relevant aspects will try to save the child. It is
metaphysically impossible (not compatible with the nature of Anton’s psychological states)
that a person psychologically like Anton does not in that situation act like Anton.13
26
Analogous observations apply to Beatrice. Let us assume that Beatrice is a teacher who likes
her profession and feels responsible for her pupils. Her lesson for that particular day is already
well prepared. She is looking forward to her work with the group of young people. No
unusual event or new information on that particular morning gives her any reason to depart
from the original plan. Once again it seems clear: in that particular situation and if nothing
unusual happens before the plan is realized, a person who is psychologically just like Beatrice
in all mentioned respects will of course go to school and teach. Again, it is not determined by
those preconditions in what way Beatrice realizes the plan. But it is determined by those
preconditions that she does something which falls under “going to school in order to teach
mathematics”. Under those psychological conditions (and the other two conditions mentioned
in the definition of psychological determination) it is metaphysically impossible that Beatrice
acts otherwise because acting otherwise is incompatible with the very nature of the
psychological properties we have been assuming Beatrice to instantiate at the relevant
moment in time.
Likewise it is metaphysically impossible that Christopher does not choose the first options if
he is rational and has normal human preferences. It is incompatible with what it is to be
rational and with what it is to have the relevant preferences to choose the second option. A
person who chooses the second option in the very same objective situation thereby shows that
she has different preferences or lacks rationality. So: relative to an appropriately chosen
moment before the decision, there is no metaphysically possible situation fulfilling the three
conditions in the definition of psychological determination in which Christopher acts
otherwise.
27
In Daniela’s case too we can easily introduce assumptions about her motivation, her beliefs,
preferences and value attitudes and about her capacity to judge and to act rationally which
make it metaphysically impossible that a person who is psychologically like her votes in the
very same objective situation for the Nazi-candidate instead of voting for candidate A. If in a
considered counterfactual situation which is like the real situation in all respects mentioned in
(a) and (c) in definition 2, Daniela does not votes for candidate B then the considered situation
must be one in which Daniela is psychologically different from how she is in the real world
(perhaps she has different political convictions, perhaps she has different information, or she
has been threatened etc.).
I conclude that it is easy to elaborate the above four examples in such a way that they are all
examples of psychological determination in the sense defined above. In each of these cases
there are moments long before the person acts such that it is psychologically determined
relative to those moments that the person acts in the way she does. But aren’t those examples
all typical cases of free action? Let us go through each of these examples once more with the
question about freedom in mind.
Anton decides in the light of the reasons available to him. He does not deliberate because the
situation is clear and the act required must be executed immediately. He acts in accordance
with his values and convictions; he does exactly what he would have decided to do had he
taken time for deliberation. He is praiseworthy for his quick reaction. Anton’s act is a typical
case of free action in the sense of ‘freedom’ required for moral responsibility.
I see two potential objections against the claim that Anton’s action is to be qualified as free in
the relevant sense. Someone may urge that Anton’s quick response is triggered by emotion.
28
As a normal and caring person, so someone may argue, Anton is shocked by his perception of
danger for the boy and he reacts out of that sudden emotion. Acting immediately out of an
uncontrolled sudden emotion, so the opponent may insist, is not a case of free action. If Anton
is praiseworthy, so the opponent may continue, this is not for his action or for his decision to
act in that way but rather for his character and emotional dispositions.
It may be true that most people who perceive a child in serious danger will immediately react
with a strong emotion and will then perhaps act, in some sense to be clarified, out of that
emotion. Should we conclude that the act is not free? One should not allow oneself to be led
to this conclusion by an inadequate picture of what it is to react out of a sudden emotion. The
inadequate picture I have in mind may be described like this: sudden emotions are something
that happens to the person. Acts out of a sudden emotion are automatic reactions; they are not
under the person’s control. I agree that sudden emotions happen to us and are not actively
brought about by the person concerned. It does not follow, however, that acts out of emotion
are automatic responses. If one fully appreciates what it is to be active one will insist that acts
out of sudden emotions are active behavior. The horrified person who immediately acts in
order to save the child moves actively and does so with a specific intention. Furthermore,
what she does is not out of control. She has a clear intention and she realizes that intention as
quickly and effectively as she can. She does exactly what she considers to be the right thing to
do for her in the situation at hand and we may assume her to be fully aware of that fact while
she is acting. Strong emotion does not turn the person into a microphysically determined
system where no genuine activity occurs and they do not cause the person to execute
movements quite independently of her preferences and convictions. To talk of ‘automatic
responses’ in that context is quite beside the point.
29
There is a tendency to think of strong emotion as ‘taking over control’ thereby depriving the
person of her control over her own behavior. This tendency is surely based on an
oversimplified view, however, about the relation between rationality and emotion. I do not
wish to deny that emotions sometimes keep us from hesitating when we should hesitate and
from deliberating when we should deliberate. And perhaps in extreme cases of strong emotion
we cannot be considered responsible for not having hesitated and for not having deliberated
and the resulting act might rightly be considered unfree in such cases. But Anton’s case, if we
assume him to act out of emotion, is not of that kind. He should not hesitate since the situation
was clear enough and we may well assume that he is clearly aware of that fact when he
immediately jumps up to save the child. Despite the role of emotion in Anton’s action we can
plausibly attribute the immediacy of his reaction to his rational insight about the objective
situation: he just sees without any further reflection that no time must be lost and he acts
accordingly. It would have been a bad mistake had Anton started to deliberate about what he
should do. No deliberation was necessary to understand what must be done and this fact too
can be assumed to be immediately evident to Anton on the basis of his perception of the
situation. Anton’s perception of the situation rationally justifies his immediate act. If there is a
strong emotion of fear for the child involved, then this does not prevent his reaction from
being rational and free. If there is such an emotion involved it plausibly helps Anton to
correctly perceive the situation in the way he does.
For those who disagree despite these considerations with the claim that acts out of strong
emotion can be rational and free in the relevant sense Anton’s example can be modified. It is
plausible that most people in Anton’s situation are terrified by the thought that the child might
die; but obviously this is not necessarily so. We can therefore simply stipulate that Anton is
not influenced by strong emotion and that he acts on the basis of rational insight. To make this
30
a plausible situation we can add that Anton immediately recognizes that there is no serious
risk for the child if he quickly intervenes.
A second objection might be that Anton’s quick reaction cannot count as a free action
precisely because he reacts so rapidly. He does what he sees must be done but he does it
without deliberating about different options. He does not form any preceding intention; he
chooses by acting or so one may argue. But should we admit that such rapid reactions cannot
be free actions? Does free action require a preceding process of conscious pondering of
various alternatives? The answer must be negative. Two intuitions, both misguided, may
motivate a positive reply. First, one might think of such quick reactions as ‘automatic’. But
they are not: they are actively brought about by the subject concerned. Second, one might
think that free action requires rationality and that such quick responses cannot count as
rational since they do not involve any deliberation. But why should we accept that rational
action requires deliberation? Anton does not deliberate since he immediately sees that there is
not deliberation required, he immediately sees that to start deliberating would be a mistake
and he immediately sees what the result of such deliberation would have to be. In such a
situation where it is obvious that immediate action is rationally and morally required, to
hesitate in order to think would rather show a lack of rationality. The claim that the absence of
deliberation renders the action arational in a way which precludes freedom has, furthermore, a
counterintuitive consequence: a less experienced person may not immediately understand the
situation and therefore hesitate about what to do. He or she may perhaps call for the parents
and wait a moment for their reply thereby losing precious seconds. Anton’s quick reaction
manifests his superior practical competence and his superior capacity to quickly recognize the
relevant features of a given situation. So the claim at issue implies that the action of a less
competent person who, contrary to Anton, is unable to quickly recognize the relevant features
31
of the situation would be acting rationally while this cannot be said of Anton in virtue of his
superior capacities. Such a result should make one pause. It casts serious doubt on the
theoretical assumptions which imply it.
I conclude that Anton’s action – when supplemented with appropriate assumptions about its
motivation – is free in the relevant sense of freedom. However, as explained earlier, Anton’s
action is psychologically determined: there are no metaphysically possible counterfactual
courses of events in which – in the relevantly same situation concerning external conditions
and concerning Anton’s psychological properties – Anton does not save the child. In short: it
is metaphysically impossible that Anton acts otherwise than he does in the so specified
situation. Anton’s case is a counterexample to the following simple version of the so-called
PAP-principle: for an act to be free it must be possible that the person acts otherwise in the
very same situation.
At this point, the following libertarian intuition may immediately come to mind and raise
doubts about the result obtained: isn’t it obvious that it was up to Anton to remain seated?
Isn’t it clear that both options where open and up to him? And isn’t it obvious that Anton is
under the impression that it is within his causal powers to act otherwise? And if this
impression is an illusion – as the result obtained seems to suggest – don’t we have to say then
that Anton did not act freely after all? I share the intuition behind those questions but the
conflict between that intuition and the result obtained is only apparent. This is what I would
like to explain next.
According to the GAA view, there is a clear sense in which – despite the fact that Anton’s act
is psychologically determined – all the following claims about Anton are nonetheless correct:
32
The option not to save the child is within Anton’s causal powers. He can actively move in a
way which would be an action of that kind, he knows that he can and he is in a phenomenally
manifest way aware of this capacity. But he does not exercise this capacity since the option
has no attraction for him at all. There is no reason for him to let the child die. He has no
rational, moral and no other motivation for not doing what he takes to be the right thing to do
in the situation at hand. Despite the fact that it is within his causal powers not to save the child
he does not use those causal powers simply because he has no reason to do so.
Here is a way in which one might interpret what has just been said which is not intended:
Anton has the bodily capacity to remain seated. However, given his psychological condition it
is impossible for him to remain seated in the situation described. It is true that Anton can act
otherwise only in the following sense: there is a movement which Anton has the general
capacity to execute which is, in his particular situation, an action of letting the child die.
Given his knowledge about the situation and his other attitudes and values it is, however,
impossible for Anton to execute that movement in that concrete situation.14
This way to describe Anton’s situation is however utterly inadequate according to the GAA
view here proposed. Anton not only has the general capacity to move in that particular way,
rather he has the causal power to actively bring that movement about in the particular
situation in which he is. He is not deprived of that causal power by his awareness of the
reasons speaking against that option. He still has the relevant causal power and he is aware of
having that causal power. He may at the same time be aware of the fact that he is
psychologically determined to save the child in the sense explicated: he may be aware of the
fact that – given his convictions and his attitudes towards human life – it is simply impossible
that he will act otherwise. But the content of this awareness is in no conflict with the plausible
33
simultaneous awareness of Anton that it is possible for him – in the sense of being within his
causal powers – not to save the child. A natural way to express this difference in ordinary
language is perhaps the formulation just chosen in the previous sentences: It is possible for
Anton to act otherwise but it is not possible that Anton acts otherwise. The libertarian mistake
and the truth in the libertarian view can then be stated, briefly, as follows: the libertarian
rightly insists that for an agent’s act to be free it must be possible for the agent to act
otherwise. But he mistakenly concludes that, therefore, for an agent’s act to be free it must be
possible that the agent acts otherwise.
But how can there be a difference, as just suggested, between the following claims C1 and
C2?
(C1) It is possible that agent A does X in situation S and
(C2) It is possible for the agent A to do X in situation S.
According to the GAA view this question has a quite simple answer and the difference is not
mysterious as it might seem at first sight. (C1) is a claim about metaphysical possibilities and
thereby a claim about which actions are and which actions are not compatible with the nature
of the psychological states of person A in situation S. (C2) is a claim about the causal powers
of the person concerned in the situation S to bring about movements which constitute various
actions in the situation at hand. The difference between (C1) and (C2) is due to the fact that
psychological properties, in general, exclude courses of action as impossible in a way which
has nothing to do with the restriction of causal powers. It is impossible that Anton does not
save the child because Anton happens to have a perception of the situation, attitudes towards
the value of life and beliefs about what he can do in the situation at hand which make it
34
obvious for him that jumping up in order to save the child is the thing to do. He is therefore
motivated to do so and he has no motivation not to do so; being a rational agent he uses his
causal power to bring about a series of movements which is – in those circumstances – a
saving of the child. But the reasons available to Anton influence his behavior only in virtue of
his capacity to actively bring about those movements (with the relevant intention in the light
of those reasons). Anton’s reasons do not by themselves cause the movement of Anton’s
limbs, nor do any mental events (supposedly the recognition of those reasons) cause those
movements. It is Anton who makes happen (actively brings about) what happens, not any
events happening inside his body or brain. Despite all those things happening inside his body
or brain and despite his awareness of the reasons speaking in favor of jumping up to save the
child, Anton is not deprived of his causal power to behave and thereby act otherwise; he still
has that power, he simply doesn’t act otherwise because he is rational and has no reason to act
otherwise; therefore, he does not act otherwise in any metaphysically possible situation in
which he has those psychological properties since those properties are incompatible by their
nature with not trying to save the child.
Given the above discussion of Anton’s case it will be quite obvious how the other examples
can be used within the GAA view to argue against the libertarian thesis that free action
requires the possibility that the person could have acted otherwise. Beatrice acts in accordance
with her long term decisions about the kind of life she wishes to lead or so we may assume.
She is in no way forced to go to school on every Monday in order to teach mathematics. To
do so is what she wants to do. Intuitively it would be odd to say that she does not act freely.
Someone whose theoretical account of freedom implies that Beatrice is not free in those
actions might try to save his or her theory arguing that Beatrice is just acting out of habit and
actions done out of habit are not free. Again (like in the case of emotion), the idea that actions
35
done by habit are not free may have to do with the thought that they are automatic. But here
again the GAA theorist will insist that to think so is a mistake. Actions done by habit are still
active behavior and so they should not be qualified as automatic. Another way to argue that
Beatrice does not act freely would be to say that actions done out of habit cannot be free
because they are arational since done without previous deliberation.
But is there any good reason to suppose that previous deliberation is required for an act to be
free? There does not seem to be any such reason. To see this let us suppose that Beatrice is
aware of the reasons speaking strongly in favor of going to school in order to teach. Even if
she acts out of habit those reasons may well be present to her each Monday morning when she
prepares herself to leave the house. She may well be aware of having accepted that duty and
she may be looking forward to teaching. She executes the complex behavior of preparing
herself for the lesson and of leaving in order to go to school in the light of those reasons
which, as we may assume, are present to her while she acts in a phenomenally manifest
manner. Since those reasons are so compelling, she does not even start to consider other
options such as staying at home on her sunny balcony in order to read an interesting book. It
would be odd to assume that in order for her act to be free she must have doubts about what to
do. Compare Beatrice with her colleague Beat who is much less committed to his duties, who
dislikes teaching and who is otherwise in a comparable situation. Each Monday morning he
hesitates a moment while still lying in bed about whether he should go to school or rather take
a day off. Only after a few minutes of pondering the various options open to him he finally
decides to go teaching. I cannot see any plausibility in the assumption that Beat is free in his
action while Beatrice is not free in hers in virtue of the difference between them which is that
Beat has to think about what to do while Beatrice knows it immediately and therefore can skip
the deliberation process.
36
All these considerations speak in favor of the claim that Beatrice is acting freely in the
relevant sense when she goes to school every Monday morning in order to teach mathematics.
But every friend who knows Beatrice well enough can predict with certainty that Beatrice will
act in that manner. And again it seems clear that the very nature of Beatrice’s psychological
states is incompatible with a different behavior under the circumstances described. So
Beatrice’s action is psychologically determined and we must conclude – contrary to the
libertarian view - that psychological determination does not exclude freedom.
It has been argued against the libertarian view that the freedom libertarians claim people to
enjoy is nothing but the capacity to act against reason. The argument may be put as follows:
the libertarian insists that, for a rational choice to be free, it must be possible for the agent to
act otherwise and so, in that case, against reason. But if this is what distinguishes (among
rational actions) those that are free from those that are not free then it is hard to see why
freedom should be valuable.15 In order to respond to this objection the libertarian must insist
that there is more to libertarian freedom than just the capacity to act otherwise. But if he
wants to insist that a person who acts rationally could have acted otherwise under the very
same circumstances, then it is difficult to see how he can answer the challenge.
The GAA view can avoid this problem in a way which does duty to the libertarian basic
intuition. The GAA view rejects the libertarian claim that a choice is free only if there was an
open possibility that the person chooses otherwise and yet preserves the intuitive core of the
libertarian intuition that a rational act is free only if the person has the capacity to act
otherwise. That capacity must be interpreted, according to the GAA view, in the following
way: it is within the person’s causal powers to act otherwise. According to the GAA view
37
there is no contradiction between (a) it being within the causal powers of a person to act
otherwise in given circumstances and (b) it being psychologically and metaphysically
excluded that the person uses that capacity in those circumstances.16
Let us finally turn to the examples involving Christopher and Daniela. A theorist who wishes
to defend the view that freedom excludes psychological determination might try once again to
undermine the thesis that Christopher and Daniela act freely by suggesting that they are in
some way compelled to act as they do. Without going into any details about such a further
description of the two examples it is clear, however, that both examples can be supplemented
in a way such that no potentially freedom undermining factors play any role. Both,
Christopher and Daniela decide, or so we can stipulate, in a non-emotional and well-reflected
manner on the basis of well-founded information. Given their respective preferences and
beliefs and given their respective rationality it is once again predictable for a well-informed
observer how they will decide and it is incompatible with the very nature of the psychological
properties they instantiate that they act differently under the very same conditions. Both
examples are well suited to illustrate the general point: in any situation in which one of the
options available to a given rational agent is clearly preferable (given the preferences and
beliefs and all other relevant psychological properties of the person concerned) to all other
available options, it is metaphysically excluded that the person will act otherwise than she
does under exactly those circumstances. The thesis that freedom excludes psychological
determination therefore implies that the choice of the rationally best alternative is never free if
the chosen alternative is clearly the best one in the light of the reasons available to the person.
This consequence strikes me as unacceptable. Since there does not seem to be any way to
deny that such cases are psychologically determined and yet are typical cases of free choice
the libertarian idea that freedom implies the possibility that the person acts otherwise under
38
the very same circumstances must be abandoned. According to the GAA view the intuitive
tendency to nonetheless insist on the contrary thesis is due to a confusion between what is
possible for an agent to do (what is within the agent’s causal powers in the concrete
circumstances at issue) and what is possible that the person does in those circumstances (what
is compatible with the nature of her psychological properties).
So far it may seem as if the GAA view is friendlier to the compatibilist than to the libertarian.
But this impression will vanish once one considers what the proponent of the GAA view has
to say about easy choices and about tough choices. Let us start with the latter.
9. Tough choices and easy choices
Sophie’s choice in the film and in the novel “Sophie’s choice” is a particularly telling and
horrible example of a tough choice.17 Sophie is forced by members of the Gestapo to decide
who of her two children, an older daughter and a younger son, will be murdered and who of
them will survive. She saves the boy. For the purposes of the discussion which follows let us
consider the example as if it was actual and not just fictional.
According to the compatibilist standard view, if Sophie decides to save the boy, then it must
be possible, in principle, to explain why she does so. Perhaps her love for the boy is deeper or
his younger age motivates her choice. According to the standard compatibilist view a
contrasting explanation must in principle be available, in other words: if, in a considered
counterfactual situation, Sophie decides to save the daughter rather than the boy, then – if all
external conditions are alike - there must be a difference concerning Sophie, presumably
39
concerning her psychological properties, that explains why she acts differently in that
counterfactual situation. The libertarian disagrees. According to the libertarian, Sophie’s
choice need not be psychologically or otherwise determined. 18 The libertarian will typically
say that the case might well be such that it is possible (in all relevant senses: nomologically,
psychologically and metaphysically possible) that Sophie saves the girl in exactly the same
situation.
With respect to Sophie’s case and other tough choices, the GAA view sides with the
libertarian. Using the above distinction between ‘possible that’ and ‘possible for’ we may say
this: within the GAA view the claim is well motivated that Sophie’s situation can be such that
it is possible for her to save the girl (it is within her causal powers) and it is possible that she
saves the girl in exactly the same situation with respect to all relevant factors (it is
metaphysically possible, compatible in particular with the nature of her psychological states)
that she chooses otherwise in the very same situation.
Within the GAA view it is not surprising and not mysterious if a person who does not see any
reason to prefer one of two available options takes an arbitrary choice just by actively taking
a decision or by actively realizing the behavior which is the realization of one possible act
rather than of the other. Sophie is aware that she must take a decision. She has, let us suppose,
no preference with respect to these two horrible options. Therefore, at some point, she just
reaches out for the boy and thereby communicates how she decided. It was possible that she
reaches out for the girl and it was possible for her to reach out for the girl. In metaphysically
and nomologically possible circumstances she arbitrarily reaches out for the girl. The
objection that there must be a relevant psychological difference between these two cases
which explains why she saves the daughter in the counterfactual situation and the son in the
40
real world has no force against the GAA theorist. The understanding proposed by the GAA
theorist of what it is to be active in one’s behavior precisely includes the subject’s capacity to
arbitrarily realize one of two open options in a case where reason in a broad sense which
includes emotional experience, attitude and perception delivers no verdict about what to do.
To put it in more abstract terms: the GAA view proposes an account of what it is to be active
in one’s behavior according to which genuinely arbitrary choices are possible; and genuinely
arbitrary choices do not require contrasting explanations (this is in fact what it is for a choice
to be genuinely arbitrary).19 Therefore, to argue against the GAA view using the assumption
that contrasting explanations of different courses of action must always be available is to beg
the question against the GAA view.
One might be tempted to think that the compatibilist is right and the libertarian wrong about
Sophie’s case having in mind the following reason: it is hard to believe that a person in such a
serious and deeply disturbing situation would take a genuinely arbitrary choice. Humans in
such serious situations will rather bring themselves into a state of mind where one of the
possible choices appears in a better light than the other. But to reject the libertarian thesis
about the case for that reason would be to interpret the libertarian in an unnecessarily strong
and uncharitable way. The libertarian need not and should not insist on the possibility that the
choice is psychologically underdetermined until the very last moment. He or she should rather
defend a weaker thesis: there are moments m before the choice such that with respect to m the
act is not psychologically determined in the sense of the above proposed definition. To say
this of Sophie, for instance, about a moment a few seconds before she reaches out for the boy
does not exclude that Sophie actively sets up her mind between that moment and her later
choice thereby arbitrarily giving, for instance, more weight to one kind of consideration than
to another. In such a case it may be that Sophie’s choice is not psychologically determined at
41
a certain moment m a few seconds before she acts and yet is psychologically determined a
little later as a result of Sophie’s own active and not psychologically or otherwise determined
intervention.
Perhaps tough choices are seldom or never taken by just arbitrarily choosing ‘in the last
moment’ by actively realizing one of the options available. But there are other choices, easy
choices, where it is quite plausible to assume that this is often precisely what happens. Easy
choices concern different options in cases where nothing of any importance depends on which
option is realized. Suppose you like ginger ice cream and you also like lemon ice cream and
you have no preference. At some point when ordering ice you must decide and you choose in
a genuinely arbitrary manner. You utter “ginger” instead of “lemon” at the right moment.
There can be an explanation of your choice. Perhaps you decide as you do due to some
psychological factor you are unaware of. The GAA view only insists that there need not be
such an explanation and, as noted earlier, the view that there need not be such an explanation
is well-motivated within the GAA view. I take this element of the GAA view to speak in its
favor. We often experience our own choices as genuinely arbitrary. Perhaps this is, in many
cases, an illusion. However, if a theory implies that the impression of arbitrary choices is
illusionary without any exception and even necessarily so then this provides reason to reject
that theory.
These considerations about tough and easy choices complete my argument for the following
claim: the GAA view integrates the true core of the compatibilist theory and the true core of
the libertarian theory while avoiding the weaknesses of both. In this sense the GAA view
provides a ‘synthesis’ of the two competing theses. If the synthesis here proposed can be
42
successfully defended within the GAA view and if no alternative to the GAA view can
provide a similar synthesis, then this provides a strong argument for the claim that the GAA
view is correct: conscious animals are genuinely active; they are not microphysically
determined in their behavior.
10. Concluding Remark
In the present paper I briefly sketched a phenomenological argument and I elaborated an
indirect theoretical argument in favor of the GAA view. But even the best development of
these arguments are unlikely to convince those who reject the GAA view for reasons based on
what they take to be established by empirical science. Further defending the GAA view will
have to involve answering a number of scientifically motivated doubts and objections. Such
an argument will have to show:
(1) There is at present no well-established scientific knowledge which excludes the truth of
the GAA view.
(2) Possible future scientific development may lead to empirical results speaking in favor of
the GAA view.
The philosophical opponent is right in claiming that any argument for the GAA view remains
unsatisfying and incomplete if not supplemented by convincing reasons in favor of (1) and,
even better, in favor of (2) as well.
43
But there is a similar scientifically motivated objection that should be seen to be based on
unjustified expectations. The objection I have in mind might be put like this: we have no idea
of how and where the conscious subject might actively intervene on the level of physical
processes happening in the brain. As long as no plausible model of how that might work is
provided the GAA view (just like the ACV) need not be taken seriously. This kind of
objection is, however, ill-founded. It should be obvious that such a model cannot be
developed without detailed knowledge about the brain. A philosopher should remain silent
about how that might work and must leave the development of such a theory to empirical
science. 20
References
Baierlé, Emmanuel (2016), The Phenomenology of Choice, PHD Thesis (University of
Fribourg, Switzerland).
Beckermann, Ansgar (2006), “Neuronale Determiniertheit und Freiheit”. In K. Köchy and D.
Stederoth (eds), Willensfreiheit als interdisziplinäres Problem. Freiburg and Munich:
Alber, 289-304.
Broad, Charlie D. (1953), “Determinism, Indeterminism and Libertarianism”, Ethics and the
History of Philosophy, edited by C.D. Broad: 195-217.
Chisholm, Roderick M. (1964), “Human Freedom and the Self”, Robert Kane (ed.), Free Will,
Blackwell.
Garrett, Michael (2013), “Freedom and Unpredictability”, Inquiry 56 (6): 666-680.
Horgan, Terry (2007), “Agentive Phenomenal Intentionality and the Limits of Introspection”,
Psyche 31 (1), 1-29.
Horgan, Terry (2011), “From Agentive Phenomenology to Cognitive Phenomenology: A
Guide for the Perplexed”, in Tim Bayne & Michelle Montague (eds.), Cognitive
Phenomenology, Oxford University Press.
44
Horgan, Terry & Tienson, John & Graham, George (2003), “The Phenomenology of First
Person Agency”, in Sven Walter & Heinz-Dieter Heckmann (eds.), Physicalism and
Mental Causation. The metaphysics of mind and action, Imprint Academics.
Keil, Geert (2014), Willensfreiheit und Determinismus, Stuttgart, Reclam Taschenbuch.
Fischer, John Martin & Kane, Robert & Pereboom, Derk & Vargas, Manuel (2007), Four
Views on Free Will, Great Debates in Philosophy, Series editor: Ernest Sosa,
Blackwell Publishing.
O’Connor, Timothy (1996), “Why agent causation?”, Philosophical Topics 24, 143-158.
Siegel, Susanna (2012), The contents of visual experience, Oxford University Press.
Nida-Rümelin, Martine (2007), “Doings and Subject Causation”, Erkenntnis 67 (2) , special
issue edited by A. Newen, V. Hoffmann, M. Esfeld, Mental Causation, Externalism,
and Self-Knowledge: 255-272.
Nida-Rümelin, Martine (2016a), “The experience property framework – a misleading
paradigm”, Synthese, special issue: Trends in Philosophy of Language and Mind,
edited by Hanoch Ben-Yami, 1-27.
Nida-Rümelin, Martine (2016b), “Active Animals and Human Freedom”, in Hans Rott et al.
(ed.), Festschrift for Wolfgang Spohn, 339-378.
Nida-Rümelin, Martine (in preparation), “Conscious Individuals. Sketch of a Theory”, under
contract with Oxford University Press.
Nida-Rümelin, Julian (2005), Über menschliche Freiheit, Stuttgart.
O’Connor, Timothy (2002/2010), “Free Will“,The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall
2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),
URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/freewill/>.
Pauen, Michael (2004): Illusion Freiheit?, Frankfurt am Main.
45
Steward, Helen (2012a), “The Metaphysical Presuppositions of Moral Responsibility”, The
Journal of Ethics 16 (2), 241-271.
Steward, Helen (2012b), A Metaphysics for Freedom, Oxford University Press.
Spohn, Wolfgang (2012), “Der Kern der Willensfreiheit”, In Vernunft und Freiheit: Zur
praktischen Philosophie von Julian Nida-Rümelin, edited by Dieter Sturma, 71-90.
Wolf, Susan (1990), Freedom within Reason, Oxford University Press.
1
A similar view is proposed by Helen Stewart in [2012a] and [2012b]. However, contrary to
the position here proposed she claims that agency in the relevant broad sense here called
‘active behavior’ requires a ‘two-way-power’ in a sense which implies the metaphysical
possibility of more than one course of action.
2
See for critical remarks on the description given here chapter 8 in my forthcoming book
“Experiencing subjects. Sketch of a theory”.
3
The claim that issues about phenomenal consciousness should be approached in terms of
experiential properties and not, as it is usually done, in terms of supposed qualitative
properties of events called ‘experiences’ is elaborated and defended in M. Nida-Rümelin
[2016a].
4
The methodological issue about how one may determine the content of experiences which
does duty to phenomenology while at the same time taking into consideration theoretical
constraints is discussed in Susanna Siegel [2012], chapter 3 and in Terry Horgan [2007].
5
The agent causation view is famously defended in Chisholm [1964]. More recent work
defending the view has been developed by Timothy O’Connor (see, for instance, O’Connor
[1999]).
6
Chisholm [1964] section 9 may be read along these lines.
7
In earlier publications (M. Nida-Rümelin [2007] and [2016b]) I claimed that the behavior
being caused by the subject (subject causation) constitutes the veridicality conditions of the
46
experiences at issue. I now think that this was too quick. I owe this insight to discussions with
Emmanuel Baierlé, Franziska Müller, Jacob Naito and Julien Bugnon.
8
The objection is due to Broad [1953]. For comments on the objection see Horgan [2007], p.
326 and Keil [2009], p. 85.
9
For a detailed presentation and elaboration of the various responses to the problem about
freedom and determination see J.M. Fisher et al [2007] and T.O’Connor [2002/2010]. In the
German-speaking discussion the compatibilist position is defended among others by Ansgar
Beckermann [2005], Wolfgang Spohn [2012] and Michael Pauen [2004] while different
versions of a libertarian view are defended by Geert Keil [2009] and Julian Nida-Rümelin
[2005].
10
I would like to thank my partner Max Drömmer and our son Korbinian Nida-Rümelin for
extended discussions about the topic of this talk during a stay in Sardinia in September 2015
which helped me a lot to elaborate the details of the view here presented.
11
I oscillate between talking of free choices and of free actions in what follows but this does
not harm in the present context.
12
For more detailed explications of condition (c) in the above definition compare M. Nida-
Rümelin [2016c], section 7.
13
I am not using “psychological states” or “psychological properties” in the way proposed by
David Chalmers (1997) where the psychological – as opposed to the phenomenal – is defined
by causal role. Experiential properties are, as I use the term here, a subclass of psychological
properties.
14
An analysis along these lines is proposed in Emmanuel Baierlé [2016].
15
Such an argument may be found in Susan Wolf (1990, p. 57). On the basis of the reasoning
just mentioned she asks with respect to libertarian freedom: “Why should one want an ability
one never wants to exercise?...Why should one mind if (…) one is inescapably sane?” Under
47
the title “the rational cost problem” this difficulty for the libertarian is discussed in detail in
Michael Garrett (2013).
16
One might think that the objection here at issue can be reformulated against the view just
sketched saying that there is no value in having the causal powers to act against reason since it
is a bad thing to make use of that power. But this new version of the argument has no force
against the GAA view for the following reasons: First, according to that view, having the
causal powers to act in various ways in a given situation is a general feature of action and
does not distinguish free action from unfree action. Second, the proposal makes intelligible
the sense in which an act is up to the agent (in a sense necessary for acts in general and free
acts in particular) and ‘being up to the agent’ in that sense is arguably a necessary ingredient
of valuable freedom.
17
The film Sophie's Choice with Meryl Streep in the role of Sophie came out in 1982 and was
directed by Alan J. Pakula, who adapted William Styron's homonymous novel.
18
The libertarian will deny that Sophie’s choice is nomologically determined in the usual
sense: it cannot be deduced from adequately chosen previous conditions plus the laws of
nature that the choses (or acts) as she does.
19
For further elaboration of this point compare M. Nida-Rümelin [in preparation] chapter 8.
20
The view here presented has in great part developed in discussion with my collaborators
Emmanuel Baierlé, Franziska Müller and Jacob Naito in the context of our research project
“Philosophy and Phenomenology of Agency” (1.10.2010-31.1.2014, project reference:
PDFMP1-132455). I would like to thank the Swiss National Science Foundation for its
support which gave us the very gratifying opportunity to pursue these issues within
philosophy of agency over several years in personal research, in the context of regular group
meetings and in international conferences.