Topoi
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-019-09635-8
Introduction: Individual Concepts in Language and Thought
Tadeusz Ciecierski1 · Paweł Grabarczyk2
© Springer Nature B.V. 2019
Individual concepts are concepts of individuals of a particular, arbitrary kind: particular persons, buildings, cities,
particles, planets, numbers, sets, functions, qualities, events,
processes or anything to which we can attribute properties.
That is, individual concepts are devices for speaking and
thinking about particular entities no matter what the ontological status of the entity is. What makes a concept individual rather than of individuals? Answers to this questions
may follow Leibniz’s observation that ‘some concepts do
completely determine an actual or possible individual, distinguishing it in one respect or another from every other possible individual’ (Mates 1989: p 62).1 This initial and basic
characterisation, however, is oblivious to several important
philosophical distinctions and controversies; it suffers also
from ambiguities connected with the word ‘concept’.
The first important distinction that has to be taken into
the account here is the one between the psychological and
non-psychological meaning of ‘concept’ (in fact, we should
rather write ‘meanings’ as there are many psychological and
non-psychological uses of the word in the philosophical, psychological and linguistic literature). Although some authors,
despite Frege’s warning, occasionally equivocate between the
two meanings,2 while others attempt to reduce concepts in
the second sense to concepts in the first sense,3 the difference should be clear and uncontroversial. Concepts in the
psychological sense or, as some prefer, mental representations, are constituents of mental states and (possibly) elements of the body of knowledge actually employed in higher
cognitive processes.4 Concepts in the non-psychological
sense, on the other hand, are entities accessible intersubjectively that may be used to classify thoughts and expressions
* Tadeusz Ciecierski
[email protected]
Paweł Grabarczyk
[email protected]
1
Institute of Philosophy, University of Warsaw, Warsaw,
Poland
2
IT University of Copenhagen, Copenhagen, Denmark
as content-identical, content-similar, and so forth. As such,
they may be the results or products of acts of theorising, or
the inputs and outputs of procedures such as explication.
The phrase ‘individual concept’—in its contemporary
(non-Leibnizian) sense—was coined by Rudolf Carnap5 and
used solely in the non-psychological and linguistic sense. For
Carnap, individual concepts were intensions of individual
expressions: constants, descriptions and individual variables.
Carnap applied this category (like all the others that were relevant for his method of extension and intension) solely to artificial languages he called semantic systems. One may assume,
1
Mates adds to this: ‘such concepts are called by Leibniz “complete
individual concepts”. Thus, a complete individual concept contains
every attribute of every individual that can fall under it; it resolves
every question that could be raised about such an individual—that
is, it determines exactly one possible individual’ (Mates 1989, pp.
62–63). Here Mates takes the uniqueness of some attribute of x as
tantamount to a total collection of every attribute x has. However, the
properties distinguishing x from every other possible individuals does
not have to be total and complete. To distinguish ‘complete individual
concepts’ and regular ‘individual concepts’ we might use the terminology coined by Edward Zalta and speak (in the former case) about
the blueprints of individuals (cf. Zalta 1983, p. 35).
2
Susan Carey writes, for instance, that concepts are ‘units of
thought, the constituents of beliefs and theories’ (Carey 2011, p. 5).
It is, however, clear that concepts qua constituents of beliefs are not
concepts qua constituents of theories conceived as the results or products of theory construction.
3
Cf. Margolis and Laurence (2007).
4
It is rather likely that this category is far from being homogenous
(cf. Machery 2010).
5
Carnap (1947). ‘We have earlier found entities which seemed suitable as intensions of designators of other types; for sentences, propositions; for predicators, properties or relations; for functors, functions.
Thus, in these cases, the intensions are those entities which are sometimes regarded as the meanings of the expressions in question; and,
in the case of predicators and functors, the intensions are concepts of
certain types. Now it seems to me a natural procedure, in the case of
individual expressions, likewise to speak of concepts, but of concepts
of a particular type, namely, the individual type. Although it is not
altogether customary to speak here of concepts in this sense, still it
does not seem to deviate too much from ordinary usage. I propose
to use the term “individual concept” for this type of concept.’ (pp
40–41).
13
Vol.:(0123456789)
T. Ciecierski, P. Grabarczyk
however, that this category can be applied to languages more
broadly and to individual expressions of natural languages,
such as proper names, descriptions and indexical singular
terms (like deictically used personal pronouns). Given this
we may consider the following claim or hypothesis:
(Carnap Thesis) Every individual expression (of a possible language L) has an intension. The intension of an
individual expression is an individual concept.
But what exactly are individual concepts in this sense?
Carnap’s initial explanation appealed to notions such as
L-equivalence and the linguistic counterparts of possible
worlds called state-descriptions. Contemporary practitioners of intensional logic will express Carnap’s idea by saying that individual concepts are functions from possible
worlds to individuals (or more broadly: from circumstances
of evaluation to individuals). Thus interpreted, individual
concepts were used by authors like Scott and Montague in
their inquiries into intensional semantics.6
Depending on what particular individual expression is at
stake, such functions may be constant or variable. If they are
constant, we may say that the corresponding expressions are
rigid. If we think that the functions are constant and total,
we may say that the corresponding expressions are Kaplan
rigid. On the other hand, if they are constant but partial, we
may say that they are Kripke rigid.7 Neither Kaplan rigidity
nor Kripke rigidity should be confused with direct reference.
Neither implies that the reference of an expression is direct
in the sense of not requiring identifying properties or modes
of presentations to mediate between individual expressions
and their referents. This can best be seen in the case of rigid
definite descriptions (e.g. ‘the president of the USA in 1918
in LEIBNIZ’ where ‘LEIBNIZ’ is the name of the world
we live in) which are not directly referential, but which may
be Kaplan rigid if a certain semantic treatment of descriptions is assumed—that is, the one that takes descriptions to
be referential terms while assuming that the corresponding
individual concepts have no value in the worlds where the
individual in question (Woodrow Wilson) does not exist.
There is definitely an interpretation of the notion of the
individual concept (in terms of individuating qualities or
descriptive modes of presentation) and the interpretation of
the notion of direct reference that might result in the refutation of the Carnap thesis if some individual expressions are
directly referential (and it is very likely that some, like proper
names or indexicals, are). This is what Kaplan had in mind
when he wrote that if there are directly referential terms, then
the ‘proposition expressed by a sentence containing such a
term would involve individuals directly rather than by way
of the individual concepts or manners of presentation I had
been taught to expect’ (Kaplan 1989: p 483).
However, other interpretations of the notion of the individual concept are possible and it is far from being certain
that the Carnap thesis is inconsistent with the observation
that some individual expressions are directly referential.
Carnap nowhere explained the idea of the individual concept in terms of individuating qualities or descriptive modes
of presentation, and this clearly enables the interpretation
that it as nothing more than a description of specific modal
behaviours of expressions of certain categories. In this spirit,
Abbott (2011) has recently suggested that constant individual concepts might be very useful in the analysis of empty
proper names and specific uses of indefinite descriptions,
while variable individual concepts might be useful in the
analysis of nonspecific uses of indefinite descriptions.
If the propositional content (of a certain sentence or utterance) contains an individual as a constituent (this usually
means that the sentence or utterance in question contains a
directly referential term that refers to that individual) numerous authors will call it a singular proposition. However, if
we agree that Carnap’s notion of the individual concept is
not inconsistent with direct reference, we may also think of
singular propositions as ones that contain rigid individual
concepts as constituents.
All in all, the basic problems connected with the Carnap
thesis and the linguistic interpretation of the notion of individual concept are: (i) possible explications of the latter,
in terms of manners of presentation, descriptive and nondescriptive de re senses (cf. McDowell 1984), kinds of constructions (cf. Tichy 1986) or encoding and exemplification
(Zalta 1983); (ii) the issue of its applicability to particular
classes of expressions or uses of expressions (e.g. proper
names, indexicals, definite and indefinite descriptions, fictional names and de se and non-de se attitude reports); and
(iii) the problem of the modal behaviour of individual concepts that correspond to particular expressions or uses of
expressions—that is, is this individual concept (or kind of
individual concept) Kaplan rigid, Kripke rigid or non-rigid?
The second important distinction regarding the idea of
the individual concept is that one must distinguish between
theories of concepts that attempt to treat concepts in the
non-psychological sense as the basis for a joint classification
of thoughts and expressions and an alternative theories that
enable disjointed classifications of the two. The former can
be viewed as friendly towards the so-called homogeneity
hypotheses,8 according to which there exists a single kind
6
For a relatively recent application of the idea, see Aloni (2005),
which discusses various frameworks that are philosophically rather
controversial as being committed to the idea of contingent identity.
7
Cf. Steinman (1985).
13
8
See Weber (2012). This kind of stance is implicitly taken by philosophers who argue for object-dependent thoughts by appealing to
direct reference (cf. Adams et al. 1999, p. 47).
Introduction: Individual Concepts in Language and Thought
of entity that is (or plays the role of) both mental and linguistic content. Homogeneity enables direct application of
the categories worked up in the theories of language (like
intension, singular proposition or general proposition) to
intentional states or attitudes. The opposite view, for heterogeneity, should work up its own category of singularity as
a property of intentional states. One possibility (not reserved
for proponents of heterogeneity) is to use the notions introduced in the debate concerning mental representations (i.e.
concepts in the psychological sense).
In the domain of mental representations, the close counterpart of the notion of singular proposition is the concept of
the object-dependent thought. This concept was introduced
by Gareth Evans, who held that:
there are thoughts we have about particular objects
which we simply could not have if those objects did
not exist. For example, an internal state of a subject
can be ascribed the content that this table is round only
if there is a particular object it is about, on which it is
causally dependent. There is no neutral or existenceindependent specification of this content to which we
can retreat if the subject is hallucinating. If there is no
object (whether or not the subject believes there is),
there is no content—no thought. (Evans 1985, p. 402)9
As Evans suggested, object-dependent thought is usually explained in terms of two slogans: Change the object,
change the thought and No object, no thought (cf. Corazza
2004). The debate around object-dependent thoughts
mostly revolves around the question of whether psychological generalisations or laws involving object-dependent
thoughts are possible (cf. Noonan 1991; Adams et al. 1999;
Corazza 2004), the related issue of the connection of the
view to internalism in the philosophy of mind (cf. Adams
et al. 1993) and the (also related) question about the role of
object-dependent thoughts in causing actions (and the role
of the concept in theories that attempt to explain actions).
It is rather a popular view that one should not believe in the
existence of object-dependent thoughts unless they manifest themselves in actions and unless the concept of objectdependent thought plays a role in action description and
action explanation.
9
Elsewhere, Evans explicates the notion in terms of informational
connection: ‘Consequently, demonstrative thoughts about objects,
like “here”-thoughts, are Russellian. If there is no one object with
which the subject is in fact in informational “contact”—if he is hallucinating, or if several different objects succeed each other without
his noticing—then he has no Idea-of-a-particular object, and hence
no thought. His demonstrative thought about a particular object relies
upon the fact of an informational connection of a certain kind, not
upon the thought or idea of that connection; and hence it is unconstruable, if there is no object with which he is thus connected’ (1982,
p. 173).
Even if object-dependent thoughts exist, it is neither
likely that all singular mental representations are object
dependent, nor that the latter category is homogenous.
In particular, philosophers are very interested in the class
of indexical attitudes (and their representations) such as
beliefs about ‘where one is, when it is, and who one is’
(Perry 1979: p 5). Beliefs of the last kind are known in the
literature as de se beliefs. Authors such as Feit and Capone
(2013) distinguish here ‘the psychological problem of de
se’. The challenge here is to ‘identify the content of a given
de se belief’ and to distinguish it from the content of beliefs
that are not de se (Feit and Capone 2013). They also single
out the linguistic problem of de se (what is the semantic
value of ‘I’, ‘s/he herself’ or self-oriented long-distance
reflexives in belief clauses) and the generality problem
identified by Geach (‘How can distinct people share the
same de se belief?’). The linguistic problem of the de se
belongs properly to the class of issues connected with nonpsychological understanding of individual concepts, while
the psychological problem of de se belongs to the class of
issues connected with psychological understanding of individual concepts. However, because the authors interested in
the latter problem assume homogeneity, they may consider
the issue to also be closely connected with the semantics
of de se reports.
Because the main distinction between concepts in the
psychological and non-psychological sense applies to concepts in general, it might be directly employed to particular
kinds of concept—concepts of individuals of an arbitrary
ontological category included. The distinctions sketched
above give us the following rough and initial scheme:
INDIVIDUAL CONCEPTS
In the psychological sense
(Mental representations of individuals)
Tools for classifying expressions/utterances
In the non-psychological sense
(=?)
Tools for classifying mental states
The papers presented in this issue consider the notion
of individual concepts in all three distinguished senses and
address the majority of problems described above.
This issue starts with two papers centring on the debate
between descriptivism and anti-descriptivism. In ‘Names,
descriptions and causal descriptions. Is the magic gone?’,
Marti discusses critically the idea of causal descriptivism
(cf. Kroon 1987; Lewis 1997)—the view arising partially in
reaction to the observation that anti-descriptivism regarding
proper names does not offer an explanation of the referential
connection between a name and its bearer. The main idea
behind causal descriptivism is building information about
the causal communicative chain that connects the referent of
13
T. Ciecierski, P. Grabarczyk
N with a particular utterance of N into the reference-fixing
description. Marti argues that causal descriptivism—contrary
to its initial promises—does not provide the required explanation of the referential link, so it offers no better theory in
that respect than the new theory of reference.10 The paper
also contains remarks about the anti-descriptivism of Ruth
Barcan Marcus and about the general explanatory demands
concerning the nature of naming relation.
In ‘Descriptivism without quotation’ Franken presents
the idea of inter-nominal descriptivism. This view arises
in opposition to quotational versions of descriptivism—
that is, views that assume that the descriptive contents of
names always involve their quotations (the author interprets causal descriptivism as a theory committed to this
view). Franken sketches a descriptivist theory that is free
from this assumption. First, he proposes that all particular
proper names of natural languages (or rather: their uses
in contexts) are in fact particular realisations of a single
abstract proper name (referred to as ‘NAME’). He proposes thinking of particular names (or their uses) as analogous to particular uses of indexicals and about the abstract
proper name as analogous to an indexical type. Uses of
names, according to the Franken, have no meaning that
can be properly attributed only to the NAME and which
is analogous to Kaplanian character. Following Kapitan
(2016), he distinguishes between executive and interpretative modes of presentations for expressions—that is, the
one that is executed by the speaker and the other (token,
reflexive one) that is executed by the person who interprets
the utterance. The character of a NAME is, therefore, a
pair of the two kinds of modes of presentation that directly
refer to particular tokens of a NAME. Franken defines both
modes of presentation for NAME and closes the paper
with a discussion of the problems inter-nominal descriptivism must face.
The next paper in the volume, ‘Proper Names, Rigidity, and Empirical Studies on Judgments of Identity Across
Transformations’, by Dranseika et al., is a critical excursion into meta-psychology that analyses the popular mode
of inference used in studies of folk judgements of objects’
identity across transformations. The authors are especially
interested in the studies of folk opinions regarding scenarios
without identity assumptions—that is, the ones where the
studied subjects are asked whether the object’s identity is preserved when central transformations take place. The strategy
involves three steps: (i) the descriptions of the transformation
scenario, (ii) the investigation checking whether the studied
subjects treat pre-transformational and post-transformational
10
As Marti stresses, however, it is a mistake to attribute to all new
reference theorists a single view consisting in commitment to a particular kind of truth-conditional contribution of singular terms.
13
entities as identical and (iii) drawing conclusions on the basis
of answers to (ii) about the relevance of certain criteria as
folk criteria of identity across transformations. The authors
are especially interested in the strategy of taking uses of
proper names of objects as criteria for assessing the results
obtained at stage (ii) of the study. They defend the view that
the assumption of the rigidity of names—used in the justification of the strategy—cannot help in assuring that the
conclusions drawn from the experimental studies are correct.
First, the use of the assumption does not preclude the possibility that a proper name is used differently by the studied
subject. Second, the authors claim that the use of the rigidity
assumption in the experimental study is always committed to
the empirical (and empirically controversial) claim that a particular expression is used rigidly. Third, they argue that the
use of the assumption to draw conclusions about the attitudes
of the subjects involves ‘a significant and possibly irreducible
amount of circularity and indeterminacy’. The problem discussed in the paper has interestin relationship to the problem
of the substitution of co-referential terms in non-intensional
contexts (cf. Poller 2016).
In ‘Truth Without Reference: The Use of Fictional
Names’, de Ponte et al. address the issue of reconciling two
intuitive observations: that fictional names have no referents
and that statements that contain them in many cases seem to
have truth value. The authors are especially interested with
parafictional statements—that is, statements about fictional
states of affairs made outside fiction by actual persons (like
‘Holmes and Watson were friends.’ or ‘Poirot was Belgian.’
as uttered in regular conversations). The analysis provided in
the paper is inspired by critical referentialism (Perry 2012)
and is based on two concepts: the concept of network and the
concept of notion. First, the authors distinguish three (interdependent) components of the truth conditions of all statements containing singular terms: the existential condition,
the reference condition and the satisfaction condition. The
first consists in the statement that a particular object exists,
the second (dependent on the first) is the statement that the
use of a singular term refers to that object and the third one
is the statement that the object in question has the property
attributed to it in the statement. Second, the authors elaborate the reference condition by building into it the concept
of a network of conditional co-reference (coco-reference),
namely that a particular use of a name is normally associated
with the intention of using it in accordance (co-referring)
with some of its earlier uses. Normally the speaker presupposes that the later use refers if the earlier use refers (hence
conditional co-reference). This enables the speaker to create (or enter) the entire network of conditional co-reference
and (normally) refer to the origin of that network, that is
refer to the object that is at the beginning of the network.
So, given a name n, an utterance u (containing n) we might
formulate the reference condition as stating that there exists
Introduction: Individual Concepts in Language and Thought
a coco-reference network Nn (containing n) exploited in the
utterance of u that has a particular object (mentioned explicitly in the existence condition) as its origin. Every network
can be associated with a notion—that is, a cluster of information (and misinformation) about an individual that is the
origin of the network; more generally, notions are clusters of
information and misinformation concerning individuals we
think and talk about. Every use of a proper name therefore
has a corresponding notion-network structure. However, fictional uses of names (occurring in parafictional statements)
are specific since their networks end in blocks. They are
also generally not purported to refer to their origin. They
therefore differ from other kinds of empty uses of names
that might be purported to refer to their supposed origins
(‘Vulcan’ is historical example of this sort, but regular fictional names might also be used in this non-fictional sense
by persons who take them to be non-fictional). The authors
therefore suggest that, properly understood, the parafictional
statements are in fact statements about notions and networks
(and not about non-existent referents of fictional names).
This requires a change in the (elaborated) existential conditions, reference conditions and satisfaction conditions of
statements. For instance, the conditions for the statement (A)
‘Poirot was Belgian’ become:
(Existential Condition) The notion nPoirot exists.
(Reference Condition) There exists an originless network NPoirot such that the use of ‘Poirot’ in ‘Poirot
was Belgian’ exploits NPoirot and NPoirot ends in the
notion nPoirot.
(Satisfaction Condition) the notion nPoirot includes the
idea of being a Belgian.
While the conditions for (B) ‘Poirot was a ballet dancer’ are:
(Existential Condition*) The notion nPoirot exists.
(Reference Condition*) There exists an originless network NPoirot such that the use of ‘Poirot’ in ‘Poirot was
a ballet dancer’ exploits NPoirot and NPoirot ends in the
notion nPoirot.
(Satisfaction Condition*) the notion nPoirot includes the
idea of being a ballet dancer.
Since the corresponding satisfaction conditions respectively
are and are not met, we might treat the parafictional statement (A) as true and the parafictional statement (B) as false.
The authors supplement this approach with additional analysis of uses of (ordinary) empty names and negative existential statements, exploiting the view that such statements do
not have existential and satisfaction conditions.
The problem of fiction is also the topic of the next paper.
In ‘How to Pick Out a Dragon: Fiction and the Selection
Problem’, Haraldsen discusses the relationship between
possibilism and the so-called selection problem. Possibilism (about fictional objects) claims that fictional entities
are merely possible objects (existing in some possible worlds
but not in the actual one). Haraldsen defends the view that
possibilism cannot be questioned on the basis of purely
semantic considerations and that, if it is incorrect, this is
so rather due to metaphysical (and non-semantic) reasons.
This conflicts with the opinions of authors such as Thomasson (1999), Sainsbury (2010) and Kripke (2011). According to these authors, the main challenge to possibilism is
the selection problem: the issue of reconciling three claims
presupposed by possibilists. The first (uniqueness) is that,
for a particular fictional object f (Sherlock Holmes, Hercule
Poirot, the city of Utopia, etc.) there is at most one f (at
most one Sherlock Holmes, Hercule Poirot, Utopia etc.).
The second (multiplicity) is that there are many f-candidates
in distinct possible worlds—that is, objects that satisfy the
entire descriptive content associated with f (there are many
Sherlock Holmes-candidates, Hercule Poirot-candidates or
Utopia-candidates, etc.). The third (arbitrariness) is that we
have no criteria for selecting one of the f-candidates (and not
others) as the entity being f. Haraldsen defends the view that
we may successfully fix the reference of a particular fictional
name in the process of arbitrary selection (by stipulation)
and that story-telling might be conceived of as narrowing
down the set of possible worlds in which the selected individual exists by attributing more and more properties to it.
Haraldsen also defends the view that the sketched possibilist
account is consistent with the causal theory of reference.
The next paper in the issue, by Moldovan, concerns the
case of non-denoting descriptions. According to the referential treatment of definite descriptions (originating with
Frege and Strawson), statements like (M1) ‘The present king
of France is sitting in that chair’ and (M2) ‘The present king
of France is not sitting in that chair’ lack truth values. At
the very same time they are, respectively, intuitively false
and true. Referentialists are, therefore, expected to have a
pragmatic explanation of the intuition in question. Moldovan criticises existing pragmatic explanations of this sort
of intuition (following von Fintel 2004; Yablo 2006) while
also offering his own explanation. The pragmatic approach
of von Fintel assumes the strategy of epistemic revision and
the rejection or acceptance of utterances based on revision.
The idea is that one has a disposition to judge utterances like
M1 to be false due to reasons independent of the fact that
the description is non-denoting. Roughly speaking, (M1) is
judged to be false because even if the present king of France
did exist, he is not actually sitting in that chair. Moldovan
provides counterexamples to this explanation: he argues that
the strategy has problems with correct predictions in cases of
certain utterances that are intuitively false (one of his examples is: ‘The natural satellite of the Moon is a component
of the Solar System’) while having a more general problem
with explaining the intuitions of truthfulness in cases like
(M2). He also criticises the theoretical motivation behind the
13
T. Ciecierski, P. Grabarczyk
approach that is committed to either interpreting the epistemic revision in terms of accommodation or interpreting it
in terms of belief revision. He argues that neither of the two
interpretations is tenable. He argues that Yablo’s alternative analysis also gives erroneous predictions and cannot be
treated as theoretically superior to von Fintel’s. In presenting
his own explanation, Moldovan agrees in spirit with von
Fintel’s diagnosis that utterances like M1 are judged to be
false due to reasons independent of the fact that the description is non-denoting. However, he proposes that these reasons are the result of taking certain (contextually relevant)
entailments of utterances to be the basis of modus tollens
reasoning that results in the rejection of the original sentence
(and in attributing falsehood to that sentence). Moldovan’s
proposal enables the analysis of problematic cases.
Is content (or at least some of its aspects) transparent to
language users? The answer to this question bears an interesting relation to the discussion regarding the content of sentences and utterances that contain empty singular terms. As
pointed out by Hodgson, the notion of content transparency
is ambiguous, because it may actually refer to three separate things. According to the strongest interpretation, users
should be able to detect differences in the contents of expressions. According to the weaker version, the only ability users
are expected to have is the ability to detect differences in
the structure of the content of expressions. According to
the weakest version of the transparency thesis, it is only the
structural type (e.g. the difference between singularity and
generality) of content that has to be detectable by competent users of the language. The first option (transparency
of content) is, as Hodgson points out, highly implausible.
Hodgson also refutes the weaker senses of transparency. He
argues that differences in the structure of content may not be
detectable due to the existence of unarticulated constituents.
He also formulates a challenging dilemma for the proponents
of structural transparency: they have to provide justification
for their claim free of petitio principii. He closes the paper
with a criticism of the positive arguments for transparency.
The next paper in the collection, by Sean Crawford, concerns the content of thoughts and utterances containing
perceptual demonstratives (PD) and the applicability of the
notion of object dependency to such thoughts and utterances.
Crawford proposes an in-between position between theories
committed to the object dependency of PD and the ones
committed to the object independency of PD; he argues for
the property-dependent theory of perceptually demonstrative thoughts and utterances—that is, the view that thinks
of the content of perceptual demonstrative thoughts as constituted by the observable properties of objects (not as constituted by their essences or identities). Once we combine
this idea with the view according to which hallucinations
are not treated as bona fide perceptions, we can arrive at
the following conclusion: contents of hallucinations are
13
neither object nor property dependent, as hallucinations do
not provide us either with objects or with properties that we
can—they involve only the phenomenal side of the experience, not the actual perception of anything (in this respect
the property-dependent theory is close to the No object, no
thought motto of object-dependency theorists). The difference between Crawford’s account and object-dependency
theories becomes noticeable once we look at a different
set of problematic cases: phenomenal duplicates. In some
situations, the perceiver may have a phenomenally identical perception coming from a numerically different object.
According to theories that posit object-dependent content,
in such situations the content must be different. The solution
suggested by Crawford is much more convincing, because
the duplicate objects can be said to contain the same set of
properties, so the content of the corresponding thought is
the same.
Another solution that aims at an ‘in-between’ position can
be found in the paper by Voltolini, who frames his proposal
as an opposition the existing ideas found in Crane (2013).
According to Crane, the tension between the idea that some
expressions have their content fixed by objects to which
they refer can be mitigated by the distinction between what
the expressions refer to and what they purport to refer to.
According to this idea, expressions that fail to refer can still
retain their content, as they still function ‘as if’ they were
referring to singular objects (as opposed to properties, sets
or universalia). Content, therefore, can be said to be fixed
more by how the referring mechanism is designed than by
what it actually refers to. The phenomenal side is an important aspect that Crane adds to the mix here: the fact that
these expressions ‘feel’ identical as expressions that successfully refer to singular objects plays an important role.
Voltolini argues that these new additions to the notion of
singular expressions are not necessary and that a similar
solution can be provided by a simpler theory that does not
demand a new notion of the singular thought. He proposes
the differentiation between the notion of ‘reaching’ the target and ‘constituting’ the target. Using a helpful analogy
to mereological sets, he points out that, just as we do not
expect parts constituting the mereological whole to ‘reach’
it (whatever it would mean in this context), we do not have
to expect the expression to reach the object that constitutes
it. Whether this counter-proposition really does not presume
a new notion of singular thought may be arguable, but it is
definitely an interesting new take on the subject.
From the intuitive, non-critical standpoints it seems
obvious that it should be possible for various agents to
perform the same type of action. This common intuition is
both reflected in our speech when we talk about different
people doing ‘the same thing’, as well as in our folk-psychological practices of action explanation (as is explicitly
assumed in Geach generality problem mentioned above).
Introduction: Individual Concepts in Language and Thought
Yet, as is pointed out by Verdejo, the connection between
actions and their intentional explanation involving de se
beliefs makes this intuition—which Verdejo spells out in
terms of public action requirement—somewhat dubious.
The reason for it is that if de se attitudes are agent dependent and if actions depend on these attitudes then, one may
argue, we are committed to action explanations that are
agent specific. To solve this problem, Verdejo distinguishes three possible levels at which action-explanation
can be conducted—the agent-independent, agent-bound
and agent-specific levels. The difference between the second and third (the first is not useful in dealing with the
problem, because it relates only to actions that are not
tied to de se beliefs) is that, whereas agent-specific actions
demand a particular user to be connected to an action—as
such, they cannot be shared amongst many agents—the
category of agent-bound actions do not presume anything
specific about the agent. According to Verdejo, the proper
locus of action explanation (involved especially in the
well-known Perry cases of actions connected with de se
attitudes) that is consistent with the public action requirement can be located at the agent-bound level. Taking this
into account indicates the constraints both for proponents
of essentially indexical action explanations (they have to
account somehow for the shareability of actions) as well
as for philosophers friendly towards the possibility of
impersonal action explanations (they have to take into the
account the insights from Perry cases).
In the last paper of this volume, Dobler addresses
the problems posed by so-called ‘Travis cases’. Travis
cases show us that the phenomenon of context sensitivity extends far beyond the typical examples of personal
pronouns and demonstratives and can be replicated even
in some of the most ‘innocent’ circumstances of predication. An example of such a situation might be the answer
to the question ‘Is the grass in the garden green?’ delivered by two people: a decorator who painted the grass
so it looks green and the botanist who wishes to study
the grass. The problem that this example poses is that the
same expression seems to change its truth value depending
on the speaker, although it does not seem to contain any
singular expressions that are typically responsible for such
shifts. Dobler presents a new take on this problem and
suggests that what changes in these cases is not the truth
condition of the sentence, but its acceptance conditions.
The main idea behind this approach is that users accept or
reject sentences or utterances in the context of some of the
goals they have in mind. This causes users to selectively
ignore some of the circumstances that, given different
goals, would have made them accept the utterances. To
return to our example: the botanist ignores the fact that
the grass looks green, because it is irrelevant from the
perspective of her goal—the botanical study of grass. The
downside of this solution is that Dobler has to assume an
error theory according to which the users reject sentences
that they know to be true. Dobler argues, however, that
this consequence is not particularly problematic. Although
Dobler does not use this example, her solution seems to be
corroborated by some of the expressions users invoke in
Travis-like cases. For example, it would be quite natural
for the botanist to say ‘It is technically true that the grass
is green, but it is not green’.
Acknowledgements We would like to thank all of the authors for
the high quality of their contributions, the reviewers for their deep
and accurate reviews and the Topoi team for all their help during the
long editorial process. We would also like to mention that some of
the papers in this collection have been presented at the first Context,
Cognition and Communication Conference held at the University of
Warsaw in June 2016.
References
Abbott B (2011) Support for individual concepts. Linguist Philos Invest
10:23–44
Adams F, Stecker R, Fuller G (1993) Thoughts without objects. Mind
Lang 8:90–104
Adams F, Stecker R, Fuller G (1999) Object-dependent thoughts, perspectival thoughts and psychological generalization. Dialectica
53:47–59
Aloni M (2005) Individual concepts in modal predicate logic. J Philos
Logic 34:1–64
Carey S (2011) Precis of the origin of concepts. Behav Brain Sci
34:113–124
Carnap R (1947) Meaning and necessity. University of Chicago Press,
Chicago
Corazza E (2004) Reflecting the mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Crane T (2013) The objects of thought. Oxford University Press,
Oxford
Evans G (1982) The varieties of reference. Oxford University Press,
Oxford
Evans G (1985) Collected papers. Clarendon Press, Oxford
Feit N, Capone A (2013) The problem of de se attitudes. In: Feit N,
Capone A (eds) Attitudes de se. Linguistics, epistemology, metaphysics. CSLI Publications, Stanford
Kapitan T (2016) Indexical duality: a Fregean theory. Rivista internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 7:303–320
Kaplan D (1989) Demonstratives. In: Almong J, Wettstein H, Perry
J (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Kripke S (2011) Philosophical troubles: collected papers, vol 1. Oxford
University Press, Oxford
Kroon F (1987) Causal descriptivism. Australas J Philos 65:1–17
Lewis D (1997) Naming the colours. Australas J Philos 75:325–342
Machery E (2010) Doing without concepts. Oxford University Press,
Oxford
Margolis E, Laurence S (2007) The ontology of concepts—abstract
objects or mental representations? Nous 41:561–593
Mates B (1989) The philosophy of Leibniz. Oxford University Press,
Oxford
McDowell J (1984) De re senses. Philos Q 34:283–294
Noonan H (1991) Object-dependent thoughts and psychological redundancy. Analysis 51:1–9
Perry J (1979) The problem of the essential indexical. Nous 13:3–21
13
T. Ciecierski, P. Grabarczyk
Perry J (2012) Reference and reflexivity. CSLI Publications, Stanford
Poller O (2016) All the superheroes’ names. Studia Semiotyczne
30(2):11–44
Sainsbury M (2010) Fiction and fictionalism. Routledge, London
Steinman R (1985) Kripke rigidity versus Kaplan rigidity. Mind
94:431–442
Thomasson A (1999) Fiction and metaphysics. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge
Tichy P (1986) Constructions. Philos Sci 53:514–534
von Fintel K (2004) Would you believe it? The king of France is
back! (Presuppositions and truth-value intuitions). In: Reimer M,
Bezuidenhout A (eds) Descriptions and beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford
13
Weber C (2012) Eternalism and Propositional Multitasking: in defence
of the Operator Argument. Synthese 189(1):199–219
Yablo S (2006) Non-catastrophic presupposition failure. In: Thomson
JJ, Byrne A (eds) Content and modality: themes from the philosophy of Robert Stalnaker. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Zalta E (1983) Introduction to axiomatic metaphysics. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to
jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.