Natures, Rights and Political Movements
[a draft chapter for Elia Apostolopoulou and Jose A. Cortes-Vazquez (eds.), The Right to Nature: Social
Movements, Environmental Justice and Neoliberal Natures (Routledge, forthcoming)]
Larry Lohmann
The Corner House
Abstract
Natures are partly composed of rights and rights are partly composed of natures. Every history of natures is a
history of rights, and vice versa. Thus, private property rights in land tend to come with a particular nature
associated with hedges, fences and cadastral surveys. Similarly, the rights to global carbon-cycling capacity that
are today parcelled out to industrialized countries under international agreements are tied to a novel, partly
computer-engendered nature called “the global climate”. Emerging political movements for “rights of nature”
aimed at countering evolving capitalist movements for “rights to nature” need to be aware that such contrasting
regimes of rights/natures are constantly in play, and are being used by all sides, on the “middle ground” that
defines this conflict.
Natures fit for capital
The word nature has a lot of meanings, and they are always changing. For Raymond Williams
(1983, p. 219), it was “perhaps the most complex word in the [English] language”. Distinguishing
nature from what is not nature is an unending struggle. When we grow crops, are we dealing with
nature or something that is not nature? Maize, rice and potatoes have been with us for millennia, we
influencing (creating) them and they influencing (creating) us. When we look at a forest, we are
almost always looking at something that has been shaped by millennia of human burning, planting,
sharing, cultivating and gathering. Are we looking at nature or at something that is not nature? Or at
both? In what circumstances do we even want to ask such questions?
I think about what it is for me to remember my way home. My eyes fall on that familiar rock, I lift
my head and there is that old tree in the distance, and after that there will be two more streets, the
bend in the road and then the building with the butcher shop. Is my memory something that I have
inside me that is separate from nature, or is my memory also in nature – in the pathway, the rock,
the tree and the streets? No need to travel to Melanesia (Strathern, 1980) or the Amazon (Viveiros
de Castro, 1998) to find places or circumstances in which nature/culture bifurcations to which we
may have grown accustomed suddenly look odd.
Nevertheless, our schoolteachers told us that behind all the different things human beings do there is
an unchanging background consisting of things like atoms and energy. Human societies are like
characters in a cartoon. Captain America walks around in the foreground, but the background often
stays pretty much the same from frame to frame. This background, our schoolteachers said, is called
“nature”. So, we’re surprised when we learn that for many Amazonian societies, it is, roughly
speaking, the background that is culture, and what move around in the foreground are natures
(Viveiros de Castro, 1998; Kohn, 2013).
Which raises the question: what are the reasons for dividing nature from society in the peculiar way
that our schoolteachers advocated, and to say that this is the most important distinction there is? In
societies dominated by capital there are in fact many such reasons, probably more than there ever
were before. These reasons tend to be “free-floating” in the sense spelled out by Daniel Dennett
(2018). They don’t presuppose intelligent, intentional prior design, comprehension or even
consciousness. They are unlikely to be reasons that individual capitalists, for example, can be said
to “have”. They don’t necessarily need a Descartes to articulate them. But they’re adaptive for the
accumulative environments that have proliferated especially since the 16th century, which they
continually modify in turn. They are there in the way people and things act (Zizek, 1991; Marx,
1976 [1867]) even if not in what they believe. For example, human beings are divided from land so
that they can be put to work and produce surplus that becomes profit. Various processes result in the
half-successful creation and re-creation of supposedly non-natural humans who can make
commodities out of supposedly non-human natures, which are created and re-created through
similarly half-successful procedures. The bifurcation is then sharpened and generalized globally
through fossil-fuelled mechanization (Huber, 2008) and thermodynamics (Lohmann and Hildyard,
2014; Caffentzis, 2013). Relationships are reconfigured in millions of ways that result in the
emergence, by the 19th century, of relata (Barad, 2007, pp. 136ff.), consisting of real abstractions
(Moore, 2015, pp. 30, 55-56, 197) known as “resources” (potential or actual) and “labour”
(potential or actual), that is, of new forms of non-human and human. For example, when people
move into centres of mechanization, the land they leave behind changes as well as the people
themselves. Farmland changes into large-scale plantations, mineheads or reservoirs. Fertility of the
agricultural fields that remain changes from being a matter of manuring, firing and rotation with
local cultivars towards being more a matter of importing guano from Peruvian islands, saltpeter
from the Atacama, or Haber-Bosch nitrates from gas extracted from new fracking sites in the US.
Each import entails certain kinds of treatment of human beings and land far from the fields where
the new fertilizer itself changes the soil structure. Animals change over time, too. The 19th century
saw a difference in the treatment of horses when they became part of the steam economy (Forrest,
2017), and the 20th century in the treatment of cattle and chickens when they were isolated and
amassed on feedlots and factories, their recourse to commons cut off and their rates of growth
reorganized according to the free-floating rationales of capital. The domestic beast-that-can-betortured was part of a nature that was as artifactual as the mythical, purely wild deer and buffalo of
the “primordial” Americas (Hribal, 2012; Mann, 2006; see also Berger, 2009).
Almost by definition, resources are passive and under threat from society. To survive the threat,
they have to be “managed sustainably” by experts who inhabit an ancestral line that stretches back
at least to the 18th-century European foresters working to keep insular colonial plantations
productive (Grove, 1997). To put it another way, sooner or later many resources have to become as
“renewable” as possible. Alternatively, the “populations” to which resources are counterposed have
to be surveyed, reorganized, “digitized” and trimmed (or expanded). Or certain resources have to be
cut off from contact both with ordinary people, and, to some extent, with individual capitals, and
placed under legislation establishing protected areas or other special reserves. Such actions –
usually undertaken by states – embellish, embroider, elaborate and strengthen existing Cartesian
bifurcations still further, adding their bits to help produce the “nature” and “society” of educated
people, which seem always to have been there and to be “separate from the practices in which they
are brought into being and reproduced” (Mitchell, 2002, p. 296).
These capitalist environmentalisms – together with regulation more generally – tend to generate
their own imaginary featuring powerful managerial agents situated above both nature and society
that can step in to govern their mutual relations. In one limiting case, this even includes fantastical
agents charged with “ending capitalism” while keeping capitalist nature more or less as it is. (For a
contrast between such “global” imaginaries and alternative “spherical” imaginaries, see Ingold,
(2000).) Law, mapping, school curricula, statistics, economics, climatology and other disciplines
and institutions help to stage, produce, format and secure a bifurcation of the world into
implementation and plans, material and discursive, real and abstract, material and technological,
violence and law, “exchange and rules for exchange”, “objects and ideas, nature and culture, reality
and its representation, the nonhuman and the human” (Mitchell, 2002, pp. 10, 82–83). “Biopower”
(Foucault, 2003), in tandem with its more recent complement “geopower” (Yanez, 2018; Bonneiul
and Fressoz, 2016; see also Moore, 2015; Robertson, 2004), add immense detail and density to
these reifications. Maintaining these bifurcations – which are manifested in innovations such as “the
economy” (an object datable very roughly from the 1930s) and “the climate” (a similar object
emerging over a longer period) – is itself, as Timothy Mitchell (2002) argues, key to maintaining
elite power in contemporary capitalist societies. But the reasons for their entrenchment remain freefloating and generally evolutionary and need not invoke either “agency” or “structure”.
A new stage: ecosystem services
A further stage in this history – one of special contemporary interest – is ecosystem services. This
particular new nature, and the “free-floating” reasons for its emergence, have evolved in a context
of crisis afflicting earlier capitalist environmentalisms. Later 20th-century overaccumulation saw
increasing reliance on the production of waste-based consumption as a means of absorbing surplus
(Pineault, 2016; Foster, 2011) at the same time that post-1970 environmental legislation was
promulgated in what amounted to both a symptom and a cause of the “maxing out” (Moore, 2015,
pp. 119–120, 226) of free waste sinks that industrial capital had long relied on. Exchange of
ecosystem services was expressly designed as a way of cheapening that regulation (Lohmann, 2006)
– which from its earliest days had been questioned as a dangerous check on economic growth
(Lane, 2015, p. 28) – or making it more flexible, “reasonable” and streamlined from the point of
view of commercial developers (Robertson, 2004). Instead of reducing their environmental impact
at home, businesses could now comply with environmental norms and laws by buying low-cost
units of environmental compensation (CO2 emissions reduction equivalents, units of bat
conservation, units of watershed quality, internationally transferred mitigation outcomes and so on)
from the other side of the country or the other side of the globe. That helped align regulation more
closely with neoliberal business models in which profit rates had to depend more heavily on crude
dispossession, neo-extractivism, wage reductions, financial engineering and speculation and plunder
of the public sector.
To make this possible, however, non-human nature needed once again to be reconfigured and
reimagined. In addition to the cheap labour and cheap resources that capital had always created and
depended on, nature/society dichotomies were now modified and re-enlisted to accommodate mass
production of tokens whose use-value was to provide cheap, flexible regulatory relief. The
extractive and pollution pipelines that conventional environmental regulation had threatened to
pinch off were repaired by novel, standardized products derived from further, second-order
appropriations of nature. For example, power plants in Europe could “offset” their greenhouse gas
emissions by quantifying and colonizing the photosynthetic capacity of tracts of land in Latin
America, Africa or Asia. Corporations could also mine the future for such units by claiming – via
arcane numerologies paralleling those deployed by the “quants” of the new finance (Lohmann,
2010, pp. 233-237, 242-246) – that their investments in ecosystem services were preventing a
measurably greater increment of environmental degradation from occurring elsewhere, and that
their purchase of these digitized increments of “avoided degradation” would cancel out the
destructiveness of their own activities. The relative cheapness of such units was not – or not entirely
– a given, legislated fact, but emerged largely out of a predictable dynamic of rent-seeking lobbying
and regulatory capture; informal, improvisatory negotiation (Robertson, 2007); and entrepreneurial
competition to find the most efficient means of mass-producing destruction-compensation tokens,
often involving ingenious manipulation of numbers. Prices in carbon markets, for example,
generally start out very low and then decline spectacularly: pollution allowance prices under the
European Union Emissions Trading Scheme have declined by a factor of at least six over its
lifetime, hitting significantly negative figures for many large industries (Pearson, 2010), while
prices of the United Nations carbon offsets used in the scheme have dropped by a factor of more
than 100. Few basic commodities – even those most associated with plummeting prices, such as
coffee – can match this triumph of cost reduction.
The new nature consisting of ecosystem services thus emerged in a context that joined burgeoning
neoliberal responses to profit crisis traceable to stunted growth in labour productivity (Moore, 2015;
Caffentzis, 2013) with a “great acceleration” in environmental destruction (Steffen et al., 2015;
Angus, 2016; Melathopoulos and Stoner, 2015). But its appearance also owed a great deal to – and
is contributing to the further development of – a third factor: the “geopower” mentioned above.
Geopower manifested itself in, for example, post-war ecosystem science and the supercomputerdriven global circulation models (GCMs) that enable and constrain the work of the
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). While the groundwork for both developments
had been laid long before in European colonial science (Anker, 2001) and what James Beniger
(1986, p. vi) calls the 19th-century “control revolution” tied to the emergence of thermodynamic
energy, significant recent factors were post-Second World War systems and cybernetic thinking
influenced by military and nuclear-state preoccupations with command, control, communication,
feedback and means for wholesale mechanization of interpretative labour (Elichirigoity, 1999, pp.
33–36; Edwards, 2013; Haraway, 1991, pp. 62–68; Gane, 2006; Nelson, 2015). GCMs helped paint
an ever more indelible picture of a coherent global climate system “locked into an endless dance of
adaptation” with an external, equally blocklike global social system (Taylor, 2015, p. 39; see also
Carey, 2014 and Fogel, 2004, p. 109), which both responded to and was supposed to control and
manage it (Elichigoity, 1999, p. 37). Ecosystem studies, for their part, came under growing pressure
to develop into an “econoscience” in which “conventional market accounting units and ecosystem
accounting units” would be merged in a way that could make national and international trading in
ecosystem services credible in environmental terms (Boyd and Banzhof, 2007, p. 626). Thus, the
new “nature” defined as ecosystem services included not just species, but also digitized units of
“species-equivalents” that could be exchanged one for another to provide the same services to
society that less information-intensive conventional regulation would have provided, but more
cheaply. It included not just molecules, but also “molecule-equivalents” certified by the IPCC to be
“equally” destabilizing to the climate and thus tradeable for one another according to their “global
warming potentials” (GWPs). For example, it no longer exhausted the definition of a nitrous oxide
molecule to say that it consisted of one nitrogen atom and two oxygen atoms; had certain
distinctive, complex effects on global climate; and so forth. Today, a nitrous oxide molecule is also,
climatologically speaking, 0.003 carbon dioxide molecules, 0.114 methane molecules and 17.953
CFC-11 molecules (IPCC, 2015, pp. 87–88). The subject matters of natural sciences shifted, in
other words, when different species and greenhouse gases began to have to confront each other as
service commodities in the way that linen, in becoming a commodity, had to confront coats, corn
and iron in certain new ways (Marx, 1976 [1867], pp. 132ff.). To become an acceptable candidate
for salvation, capital’s nature itself had to become – in parallel with the human subjects of
Foucault’s biopower – something that geopower was capable of “making live or letting die” as well
as something sovereign corporations or states could “let live or make die” (Foucault, 2003, p. 241;
Ojalammi and Blomley, 2015, p. 53).
The partial reinvention of “nature” in terms of ecosystem services was simultaneously, of course, a
partial reinvention of the “society” counterposed to it under the rule of capital. In the course of
helping capital overcome regulatory blocks to investment, the averaged, “liquid” nature (Buscher,
2014) defined by an expanded set of market-friendly environmental equivalences finds a
counterpart in the averaged, “statistical” person (Heinzerling, 2000) whose fears (Sunstein, 2009)
and suffering can be fluently costed out even while specific individuals or communities succumb to
uncertainty or disease. Under a geopowered regime of environmental services, the neoliberal state
can convert polluting factories, airports or extraction sites into statutorily “non-polluting”
installations that local residents have fewer legal rights to challenge, without having to stem a single
effluent stream. At the same time, new styles of “social” discipline come into play (Osborne, 2015;
Pena-Valderrama, 2016; West, 2006) in the distant locations that produce the offsets that
“neutralize” effluents or extinctions. Each “double grab” performed by an offset (see Re:Common,
this volume) is also double in the sense of amounting to a grab of both “nature” and “society”.
Rights to nature
One element missing from the short history of natures sketched above is rights. Natures are partly
composed of rights and rights are partly composed of natures. Every history of natures is a history
of rights, and vice versa.
For example, the rights of access that form part of the set of relations in which the ecologies of
various common irrigation systems in Asia are suspended are tied to obligations not only to
common welfare but also to spirits of water, rice, and other aspects of the landscape (Chatchawan
and Lohmann, 1991, pp. 102-105). The “bundles of rights” that are commonly held to constitute
private property, by the same token, cannot become a reality without the various “bundles of
powers” that constitute access (Ribot and Peluso, 2003, p. 153). Those powers in turn rely on
technologies that have specific ecological effects. In the modern era, strong private rights over
extensive stretches of land have depended, among other things, on the availability of hedges, fences
and other labour-saving technologies of exclusion and border-construction that have a marked
impact on the face of the landscape and its inhabitants’ relationships (Blomley, 2007). State or
public rights over protected areas also go hand in hand with selectively exclusionary techniques and
the construction of distinctive “wildernesses” (Neumann, 1998; Lohmann, 1999). The mapping of
territories to facilitate the exercise of rights of conquest, ownership or appropriation helps create
putatively null spaces made distinct from the material relationships that formerly constituted them
(Sack, 1986). Rights over the electromagnetic spectrum, too, depend on possession by the state of
technologies to control and generate the relevant aspects of nature. Even the alienable rights to use
your own person that characterize labour power, together with the rest of capital’s social relations,
become generalized globally only through conflict-ridden fossil-fuelled technologies that reshape
non-human as well as human nature (Huber, 2008). The technology-assisted violence associated
with creating and enforcing differential private property rights that thinkers as varied as Norbert
Elias and David Graeber (2015) see as largely “stored behind the scenes of everyday life’’ (Elias
2000 [1939]: 238–239) is a violence that makes not only human but also non-human beings what
they are.
As one may expect from the history of natures sketched earlier in this chapter, novel elaborations of
capitalist nature tend to go hand in hand with the emergence of novel varieties of rights. In the
1940s, for example, it would have seemed outlandish to presume that there could exist rights to
global carbon-cycling capacity that could be parcelled out among nation-states. Yet by the year
2000, when ecosystem services had become an aspect of nature, such rights were legally entrenched
in global environmental policy (Lohmann, 2006), carrying with them all sorts of financial and
environmental consequences. No amount of fences, hedges and cadastral surveys would have been
sufficient to make these rights a reality. They become possible only with, for example, continuous
emissions monitoring systems (Cole, 2002), satellite imaging, new enforcement systems (Rose,
2003) and a supercomputer-powered conception of Earth as a “vast machine” (Edwards, 2013)
endlessly cycling carbon under the controlling eye of nation-states. Just as tradeable wetlanddestruction rights ownable by corporations require the production of mounds of “scientifically
incoherent” data and propositions that can “circulate in the networks of law and economics”
(Robertson, 2006, pp. 375, 377), so, too, ownable rights to use the atmosphere to dump carbon
dioxide in (as well as, perhaps at some point in the future, recognized political rights to
geoengineer) presuppose a nature that processes of highly mechanized interpretation carried out in
part by “intelligent infrastructure” (Jordan, 2018) can “see”, even if others cannot.
The rights to nature referred to in the title of this volume could not have emerged, and could not
continue to emerge today, except through such concrete, science-laden histories. As a rule, rights to
nature as a concept becomes possible only where it becomes possible to recast a wide range of
practices and phenomena as if they were relationships between humans and things – between,
roughly speaking, Cartesian subjects and Cartesian objects, persona and res (Tigar and Levy, 1977,
pp. 268–269) – whether those humans are peasants or corporate heads and whether those things are
rice fields or Ferrel cells pictured in GCMs. Rights to nature, that is, tend to be part of integrated
packages that also include fetishized relata bearing labels such as “resources”, “hectares”, “nature
reserves”, “units of functional lift” or “the global climate”.
The extent to which human rights come out of this same troubled history, while under-explored,
should not be under-estimated. To oversimplify drastically, human rights and the relata that are their
subjects tend to precipitate out of the conflicts and compromises that accompany the emergence of
packages that include natures of a roughly Cartesian, anti-commons type. Just as London’s public
parks are no more (if no less) than a residue of embattled commons (Thompson, 1990, pp. 63, 96–
184) governance of which passed, over decades and centuries, to middle-class and then municipal
organizations (Lefevre, 1910), so, too, a good many of the human rights associated with efforts to
limit sovereign power, institute welfare states, combat racism and so forth contain substantial
residues (if only residues) of commons-based efforts at self-defence following partial dispossession
that have then been reconstituted under other authorities (Linebaugh, 2009; McDermott, 2007). By
the same token, some of the first self-identified environmental justice movements tended to present
themselves by default as advocating equal human rights to nature (unpolluted air, for example), for
the time being leaving latent or inexplicit any underlying opposition to rights to nature (or human
rights) themselves. Many mainstream climate justice intellectuals – including delegates to
international climate change negotiations as well as academics – have followed suit, basing their
work on notions of equal (human) rights to fetishized objects, such as carbon dioxide molecules,
development, climate finance, climate risk or economic growth (for example, Baer et al., 2009;
Roberts, 2001).
Rights of nature on the “middle ground”
More thoroughgoing resistance to the rights-to-nature framework, of course, does exist in many
forms. One form that has become particularly prominent recently are movements for the rights of
nature, more or less explicitly conceived as opposed to capitalistic rights to nature (Ito and Montini,
this volume; see also Republic of Ecuador, 2008, Pecharroman, 2018, Arsel, 2012; cf. Stone, 1974).
What lessons does the story of rights to nature hold for these movements?
One lesson is that whatever rights of nature may be, conflicts will arise when they are interpreted as
rights of any of the abstract natures that have developed under the rule of capital. For example, do
natural resources have rights? That amounts to a strange way of talking insofar as natural resources
are as a rule constituted in a way that serves commodity production and industrial development, and
any rights granted to them would have to be strictly and quantitatively conditioned in order not to
hobble capital accumulation.
Similarly, do ecosystem services have rights? That sounds even stranger. Wage workers have rights,
but what would it mean for capitalist work itself to have rights? And yet that is what ecosystem
services are (Robertson, forthcoming) – the capitalized work of non-humans, organized in part
around the goal of helping to immunize private or public industries against environmental laws that
governments have passed since the later 20th century. If, on the other hand, it is ecosystem service
providers that are held to be the holders of rights of nature, other problems arise. For example, how
will rights of nature be able to challenge capitalistic rights to nature if they are modelled on the
rights wage labourers have had to fight for? Are there to be non-human labour movements and nonhuman labour relations boards? If so, what form would these take?
Perhaps, then, the nature that has rights is commons (see Partridge, this volume). But this is not
really coherent either. If commons are reinterpreted as a species of natural resource management, as
Elinor Ostrom (1990) controversially does, then the difficulties mentioned above with the notion of
“rights of resources” re-emerge. If, by contrast, commons are seen as “those parts of the
environment for which customary law exact[s] specific forms of community respect”, which lie
“beyond [people’s] own thresholds and outside of their own possessions”, which are “not perceived
as scarce”, and to which people “ha[ve] recognized claims of usage, not to produce commodities
but to provide for the subsistence of their households” (Illich, 1983), then the notion of “the rights
of commons” seems peculiar in other ways. One difficulty is that such a notion awkwardly
assimilates “forms of community respect” to a model of negotiation between relata (Barad, 2007,
pp. 136ff.) that emerge from specifically capitalist relationships. This difficulty arises perhaps in its
sharpest form where, as is often the case, commons practices are inextricable from a sense of the
sacred, whether human or non-human. As one indigenous lawyer puts it, because the cosmos is
sacred, to say that it has rights is insulting, like saying that God has rights (Saldamando, 2015).
Thus while “common rights” is a comprehensible, fairly unproblematic term insofar as it
encompasses diverse notions of mutuality, deference and customary respect, “rights of commons” is
less so. Language attributing rights to territorios (in the sense used in indigenous Latin America)
runs into similar contradictions.
Attributing rights to various elements or aspects of nature rather than nature in the round tends only
to complicate the issue. Very roughly, most specific elements or aspects of capital’s natures can be
subsumed under the same categories that apply to the whole: “resource”, “protected object”,
“ecosystem service”. That makes it problematic to propose rights that can be possessed by specific
parcels of land or specific animals, geological formations, deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA) sequences,
rivers or plants, or their various activities, with some humans sometimes a partial exception. Under
some commons regimes, meanwhile, many aspects of nature also remain more or less in the same
framework of the sacred that covers the whole. Yet under other commons or liminal regimes, rights
can be attributed to elements or aspects of nature even if not to the whole. For example, although
animals may in some circumstances be sacred and removed from the realm of rights altogether, they
are also often beings over which humans have rights but that also have their own rights. On the cusp
of the early modern era, animals were not only not yet resources in the contemporary sense;
famously, they were also often even put on trial for various misdeeds and could be defended in
court (St. Clair, 2011). Contemporary animal rights movements are in part a conscious retort – but
one that tends not to invoke the sacred – to the increased industrial resourcification of animals
particularly following the Second World War. Recent defences of the rights of rivers also belong to
this odd, evolving “middle ground” (White, 2011 [1991]) where capitalistic, commons, religious
and rights traditions are all uncertainly in play and subject to ad hoc transformations.
Accordingly, the political difficulties of finding or creating a nature that could be an unequivocal
subject of rights are not likely to be relieved simply by restricting the focus to elements or aspects
of various natures. Should we then just give up this line of enquiry? If “recognizing rights of
nature” is no substitute for – and may even undermine – efforts to support and build on existing
tangles of commons relationships in their millions, and if the real issue is how to stimulate
discussions and other actions directed at more mutually respectful ways of living and being tout
court, perhaps nature talk should simply be dispensed with. Perhaps the concepts both of rights and
of nature are burdened with just too much historical baggage to be usefully retooled as instruments
in struggles opposing rights-to-nature frameworks.
But this is probably too hasty a conclusion. The political reality is that many who participate in
movements that criticize natural resources and ecosystem services continue to feel a need, in current
contexts of public debate, to develop general “oppositional” concepts (Haraway, 1991, pp. 155–
156) of nature that are as abstract, general and simplified as those represented by phrases such as
“natural resources” and “ecosystem services”. Of course, “commons” itself is one such term
(Lohmann and Hildyard, 2014, p. 66), adapting for general use a tradition specific to historical
struggles in Europe and Asia and seldom even called by that name there. However, in addition to
being equally highly contested, “commons” may still be too obscure in the minds of many middleclass activists and academics to be used as an effective lever in official and international debates,
especially since capital has its own free-floating reasons for defending various versions of
“commons” (Caffentzis, 2004, 2013; Federici, 2004). At the same time, the active “middle ground”
(White, 2011 [1991]; see also Liu, 2006, 2000, 1996) where structures of nature as resources or
ecosystem services cannot quite be entrenched by force is currently a lively and fertile site where
new and invented congruences – however ludicrous or equivocal (Viveiros de Castro, 2004) – are
positing different and provisional “natures” that may at least be stepping-off points for future
cooperation and struggle, or moments in a longer process of what Boaventura de Sousa Santos
(2005, 20) calls the “dialogical and political work” of translation among social movements. As a
gesture of kindness offered by commoners and indigenous peoples to potential allies who have
grown up under the sign of “rights to nature”, advocacy of “rights of nature” may still turn out to be
capable of preparing the ground for more radical practices of interpretation and re-interpretation.
References
Angus, I. (2016) Facing the Anthropocene: Fossil Capitalism and the Crisis of the Earth System. New York:
Monthly Review Press.
Anker, Peder (2001) Imperial Ecology: Environmental Order in the British Empire, 1895–1945. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
Arsel, M. (2012) Between ‘Marx and Markets’? The State, the ‘Left Turn’ and Nature in Ecuador. Tijdschrift
Voor Economische En Sociale Geografie 103 (2), 150–163.
Baer, P., Athanasiou, T., Kartha, S. and Kemp-Benedict, E. (2009) Greenhouse Development Rights: A
Proposal for a Fair Global Climate Treaty. Ethics, Place & Environment 12 (3), 267–281.
Barad, K. (2007) Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and
Meaning. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Beniger, J. (1986) The Control Revolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Berger, J. (2009) Why Look at Animals? London: Penguin.
Blomley, N. (2007) Making Private Property: Enclosure, Common Right and the Work of Hedges. Rural
History 18 (1), 1–21.
Bonneiul, C. and Fressoz, J.-B. (2016) The Shock of the Anthropocene: The Earth, History and US, trans. D.
Fernbach. London: Verso.
Boyd, J. and Banzhaf, S. (2007) What are Ecosystem Services? The Need for Standardized Environmental
Accounting Units. Ecological Economics 63, 616–626.
Buscher, B. (2014) Nature on the Move I: The Value and Circulation of Liquid Nature and the Emergence of
Fictitious Conservation. In B. Buscher, W. Dressler and R. Fletcher (eds), NatureTM Inc.: Environmental
Conservation in the Neoliberal Age. Tucson: University of Arizona Press. Pp. 183–204.
Caffentzis, G. (2004) A Tale of Two Conferences: Globalization, the Crisis of Neoliberalism and Question of
the Commons. Presentation at the Alter-Globalization Conference, San Miguel de Allende, Mexico, 9
August.
---------------- (2013) In Letters of Blood and Fire. Oakland: PM Press.
Carey, M. (2014) Science, Models, and Historians: Toward a Critical Climate History. Environmental History
19, 354–364.
Chatchawan T. and Lohmann, L. (1991) The mueang faai Irrigation System of Northern Thailand. The
Ecologist 21 (1), 101-106.
Cole, D.H. (2002) Pollution and Property: Comparing Ownership Institutions for Environmental Protection.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dennett, D.C. (2018) From Bacteria to Bach and Back: The Evolution of Minds. London: Penguin.
de Sousa Santos, B. (2005) The Future of the World Social Forum: The Work of Translation. Development 48
(2), 15–22.
Edwards, P. (2013) A Vast Machine: Computer Models, Climate Data, and the Politics of Global Warming.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Elias, N. (2000 [1939]). The Civilizing Process: Sociogenetic and Psychogenetic Investigations. Trans.
Jephcott, E. Oxford: Blackwell.
Elichirigoity, F. (1999). Planet Management: Limits to Growth, Computer Simulation, and the Emergence of
Global Spaces. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Federici, S. (2004) Caliban and the Witch: Women, the Body and Primitive Accumulation. Oakland:
Autonomedia.
Fogel, C. (2004) The Local, the Global, and the Kyoto Protocol. In S. Jasanoff and M.L. Martello (eds),
Earthly Politics: Local and Global in Environmental Governance. Cambridge: MIT Press. Pp. 103–126.
Forrest, S. (2017) The Age of the Horse: An Equine Journey through Human History. New York: Atlantic.
Foster, J.B. (2011) The Ecology of Marxian Political Economy. Monthly Review 63 (4), 1-16.
Foucault, M. (2003) Society Must be Defended: Lectures at the College de France, 1975-76, trans. D. Macey.
New York: Picador.
Gane, Nicholas (2006) When We Have Never Been Human, What is to be Done?: Interview with Donna
Haraway. Theory, Culture and Society 23 (7–8), 135–158.
Graeber, D. (2015) The Utopia of Rules: On Technology, Stupidity and the Secret Joys of Bureaucracy.
London: Melville House.
Grove, R.H. (1997) Ecology, Climate and Empire: Colonialism and Global Environmental History, 1400–
1940. Cambridge: White Horse Press.
Haraway, D. (1991) Simians, Cyborgs and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. London: Free Association
Books.
Heinzerling, L. (2000) The Rights of Statistical People. Harvard Environmental Law Review 24, 189–207.
Hribal, J. (2012) Animals are Part of the Working Class Reviewed. Borderlands 11 (2), 1-37.
Huber, M. (2008) Energizing Historical Materialism: Fossil Fuels, Space and the Capitalist Mode of
Production. Geoforum 40, 105–115.
Illich, I. (1983) Silence is a Commons. Co-Evolution Quarterly, Winter.
Ingold, T. (2000) Globes and Spheres: The Topology of Environmentalism. In The Perception of the
Environment. New York and London: Routledge. Pp. 209–218.
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) (2015) Climate Change 2014: Synthesis Report.
Contribution of Working Groups I, II and III to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental
Panel on Climate Change. Geneva: IPCC.
Ito, M. and Montini, M. (2018) Nature’s Rights and Earth Jurisprudence – A New Ecologically-based
Paradigm for Environmental Law. This volume.
Jordan, M.I. (2018) Artificial Intelligence – The Revolution Hasn’t Happened Yet. Medium. Available at:
https://medium.com/@mijordan3/artificial-intelligence-the-revolution-hasnt-happened-yet-5e1d5812e1e7.
Kohn, E. (2013) How Forests Think: Toward an Anthropology beyond the Human. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Lane, R. (2015) Resources for the Future, Resources for Growth: The Making of the 1975 Growth Ban. In B.
Stephen and R. Lane (eds), The Politics of Carbon Markets. New York: Routledge. Pp. 27-50.
Lefevre, G. (as Lord Eversley) (1910) Commons, Forests and Footpaths. London: Cassell.
Linebaugh, P. (2009) The Magna Carta Manifesto: Liberties and Commons for All. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Liu, L.H. (1996) Translingual Practice: Literature, National Culture, and Translated Modernity – China,
1900–1937. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
----------- (ed.) (2000) Tokens of Exchange: The Problem of Translation in Global Circulations. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
----------- (2006) The Clash of Empires: The Invention of China in Modern World Making. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Lohmann, L. (1999) Forest Cleansing: Racial Oppression in Scientific Nature Conservation. Sturminster
Newton: The Corner House.
--------------- (2006) Carbon Trading: A Critical Conversation on Climate Change, Privatisation and Power.
Uppsala: Dag Hammarskjold Foundation.
--------------- (2010) Uncertainty Markets and Carbon Markets: Variations on Polanyian Themes. New Political
Economy 15 (2), 225–254.
Lohmann, L. and Hildyard, N. (2014) Energy, Work and Finance. Sturminster Newton: The Corner House.
McDermott, J.F.M. (2007) Producing Labor-power. Science and Society 71 (3), 299–321.
Mann, C.C. (2006) 1491: New Revelations of the Americas before Columbus. New York: Vintage.
Marx, K. (1976 [1867]) Capital, vol. 1. London: Penguin.
Melathopoulos, A.P. and Stoner, A.M. (2015) Critique and Transformation: On the Hypothetical Nature of
Ecosystem Service Value and its Neo-Marxist, Liberal and Pragmatist Criticisms. Ecological Economics
117, 173–181.
Mitchell, T. (2002) Rule of Experts: Egypt, Technopolitics, Modernity. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Moore, J. (2015) Capitalism in the Web of Life: Ecology and the Accumulation of Capital. London: Verso.
Nelson, S.H. (2015) Beyond The Limits to Growth: Ecology and the Neoliberal Counterrevolution. Antipode
47 (2), 461–480.
Neumann, R.P. (1998) Imposing Wilderness: Struggles over Livelihood and Nature Preservation in Africa.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Ojalammi, S. and Blomley, N. (2015) Dancing with Wolves: Making Legal Territory in a More-than-human
World. Geoforum 62, 51–60.
Osborne, T. (2015) Tradeoffs in Carbon Commodification: A Political Ecology of Common Property Forest
Governance. Geoforum 67, 64–77.
Ostrom, E. (1990) Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for Collective Action. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Partridge, T. (2018) The Commons as Organizing Infrastructure: Indigenous Collaborations and Post-neoliberal
Visions in Ecuador. This volume.
Pearson, A. (2010) The Carbon Rich List: The Companies Profiting from the EU Emissions Trading Scheme.
London: Sandbag.
Pecharroman, L.C. (2018) Rights of Nature: Rivers that Can Stand in Court. Resources 7 (1), 13–27.
Pena-Valderrama, S. (2016) Entangling Molecules: An Ethnography of a Carbon Offset Project in
Madagascar’s Eastern Rainforest. PhD thesis, Durham University, Available at:
http://etheses.dur.ac.uk/11475/.
Pineault, E. (2016) Growth and Over-accumulation in Advanced Capitalism: Some Critical Reflections on the
Political Economy and Ecological Economics of Degrowth, paper presented at the 5th Degrowth
conference, Budapest, 31 August.
Re:Common (2018) Offsetting for Whom? This volume.
Republic of Ecuador (2008) Constitution of 2008. Georgetown University Political Database of the Americas.
Available at: http://pdba.georgetown.edu/Constitutions/Ecuador/english08.html.
Ribot, J. and Peluso, N. (2003) A Theory of Access. Rural Sociology 68 (2), 153–181.
Roberts, J.T. (2001) Global Inequality and Climate Change. Society & Natural Resources 14 (6), 501-509.
Robertson, M.M. (2004) The Neoliberalization of Ecosystem Services: Wetland Mitigation Banking and
Problems in Environmental Governance. Geoforum 35, 361–373.
-------------------- (2006) The Nature that Capital Can See: Science, State, and Market in the Commodification
of Ecosystem Services. Environment and Planning D 24, 367–387.
-------------------- (2007) Discovering Price in All the Wrong Places: The Work of Commodity Definition and
Price under Neoliberal Environmental Policy. Antipode 39 (3), 500–526.
-------------------- (forthcoming) Ecosystem Services as Nature’s Workfare. Annals of the Association of
American Geographers.
Rose, C. (2003) Romans, Roads and Romantic Creators: Traditions of Public Property in the Information Age.
Law and Contemporary Problems 66, 89-110..
Sack, R.D. (1986) Human Territoriality: Its Theory and History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
St Clair, J. (2011) Let us Now Praise Infamous Animals. In J. Hribal, Fear of the Animal Planet: The Hidden
History of Animal Resistance. Oakland: AK Press. Pp. 1–20.
Saldamando, A. (2015) Personal communication.
Steffen, W., Broadgate, W., Deutsch, L., Gaffney, O. and Ludwig, C. (2015) The Trajectory of the
Anthropocene: The Great Acceleration. The Anthropocene Review 2 (1), 81–98.
Stone, C.D. (1974) Should Trees Have Standing? Toward Legal Rights for Natural Objects. Los Altos: William
Kaufman, Inc.
Strathern, M. (1980) No Culture, No Nature: The Hagen Case. In C. MacCormack and M. Strathern (eds),
Nature, Culture and Gender. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pp. 174–222.
Sunstein, C.R. (2009) Laws of Fear: Beyond the Precautionary Principle. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Taylor, M. (2015) The Political Ecology of Climate Change Adaptation: Livelihoods, Agrarian Change and
the Conflicts of Development. New York: Routledge.
Thompson, E.P. (1990) Customs in Common: Studies in Traditional Popular Culture. New York: The Free
Press.
Tigar, M. and Levy, M.R. (1977) Law and the Rise of Capitalism. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Viveiros de Castro, E. (1998) Cosmological Deixis and Amerindian Perspectivism. Journal of the Royal
Anthropological Institute 4 (3) 469-488.
-------------------------- (2004) Perspectival Anthropology and the Method of Controlled Equivocation. Tipití 2
(1), 3–22.
West, P. (2006) Conservation Is Our Government Now: The Politics of Ecology in Papua New Guinea.
Durham: Duke University Press.
White, R. (2011 [1991]) The Middle Ground: Indians, Empires, and Republics in the Great Lakes Region,
1650–1815. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, R. (1983) Keywords. London: Penguin.
Yanez, I. (2018) Personal communication.
Zizek, S. (1991) For They Know Not What They Do: Enjoyment as a Political Factor. London: Verso.