Lasse Nielsen
Palacký University, Olomouc, Czech Republic.
Reconstructing Thought Experiments in Personal Identity
Abstract | Thought experiments are abundant in the topic of personal identity theory as well as
in metaphysics in general. While many of them serve to illustrate and guide us through complicated
theories and explain difficult to grasp terms, others are irrelevant and muddle the very discussion
they aim to clarify. By building upon the work of John D. Norton and Kathleen V. Wilkes, this
paper sets out to establish a formula for a good thought experiment. The paper outlines Norton’s
theory that all thought experiments can be reconstructed into arguments. His work in this subject
refers mainly to thought experiments in science, but the aim of this paper will be to apply his theory
of reconstruction to thought experiments in metaphysics. Along with Norton, the work of Kathleen
V. Wilkes and her critique of fission thought experiments will likewise be taken into consideration.
The paper concludes that for a thought experiment to be successful it must make sense as an
argument, after the impossibilities have been eliminated.
Keywords | Thought experiments - Personal identity – The Self – The elimination thesis.
In a paper from 1991 entitled “Thought Experiments in Einstein´s Work”, John D. Norton first
proposed the idea that all thought experiments can be seen as arguments. This idea sprang from
the reasoning that as an empiricist philosopher of science, he could not accept that a thought
experiment can replace an actual experiment. Norton elaborates on this in his paper from 1996
titled “Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?”, arguing that a thought experiment
does not involve any new empirical data. A thought experiment can help us see a concept in a new
way, but it is all based on past knowledge gained from experience.1 There is no difference then,
except for the form, between a thought experiment and an argument. All thought experiments can
therefore be reconstructed into arguments. Norton calls this the reconstruction thesis: “All thought
experiments can be reconstructed as arguments based on tacit explicit assumptions. Belief in the
outcome-conclusion of the thought experiment is justified only insofar as the reconstruction
argument can justify the conclusion”.2 According to Norton then, we would be justified in
believing a thought experiment if it can justify the conclusion when reconstructed into an
argument.
Norton states that thought experiments are arguments which: “(i) posit hypothetical or
counterfactual states of affair, and (ii) invoke particulars irrelevant to the generality of the
conclusion”.3 Point (i) is fairly obvious but (ii) is particularly interesting. Norton claims that there
are elements within a thought experiment that have no impact on the conclusion of that argument.
John D. Norton, “Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?,” Canadian Journal of
Philosophy 26, no. 3 (1996): 334.
2
Ibid., 339.
3
Ibid., 336.
1
1
Norton argues that it is possible to remove these from the argument. He calls this claim the
“elimination thesis”.4
The elimination thesis in its entirety states: “Thought experiments are arguments which contain
particulars irrelevant to the generality of conclusions. Thus, any conclusion reached by a good
thought experiment will also be demonstrable by an argument which does not contain these
particulars and therefore is not a thought experiment”.5
Transferring this to the field of metaphysics, it could then be argued, that for a thought
experiment to be successful it must be able to separate the impossibilities from the conclusion. An
unsuccessful thought experiment, in contrast, fails because it bases the conclusion on the
counterfactual element itself. In other words, the element that would normally be cut away with
the elimination thesis is used as a premise in the argument. This leaves us with an argument that
has a conclusion which rests on nonfactual premises. Because of this, the conclusion of the thought
experiment cannot be applied to the real world. To illustrate the point, let us look at a very wellknown thought experiment by Derek Parfit. In his book Reasons and Persons from 1984, Parfit
constructs a thought experiment in which he enters a teletransporter:
“I enter the Teletransporter. I have been to Mars before, but only by the old method, a spaceship journey taking several weeks. This machine will send me at the speed of light. I merely have
to press the green button. Like others, I am nervous. Will it work? I remind myself what I have
been told to expect. When I press the button, I shall lose consciousness, and then wake up at what
seems a moment later. In fact I shall have been unconscious for about an hour. The Scanner here
on Earth will destroy my brain and body, while recording the exact states of all of my cells. It will
then transmit this information by radio. Travelling at the speed of light, the message will take three
minutes to reach the Replicator on Mars. This will then create, out of new matter, a brain and body
exactly like mine. It will be in this body that I shall wake up. Though I believe that this is what
will happen, I still hesitate. But then I remember seeing my wife grin when, at breakfast today, I
revealed my nervousness. As she reminded me, she has been often teletransported, and there is
nothing wrong with her. I press the button. As predicted, I lose and seem at once to regain
consciousness, but in a different cubicle. Examining my new body, I find no change at all. Even
the cut on my upper lip, from this morning's shave, is still there.
Several years pass, during which I am often Teletransported. I am now back in the cubicle,
ready for another trip to Mars. But this time, when I press the green button, I do not lose
consciousness. There is a whirring sound, then silence. I leave the cubicle, and say to the attendant:
‘It's not working. What did I do wrong?’ ‘It´s working’, he replies, handing me a printed card. This
reads: ‘The New Scanner records your blueprint without destroying your brain and body. We hope
that you will welcome the opportunities which this technical advance offers.’ The attendant tells
me that I am one of the first people to use the New Scanner. He adds that, if I stay for an hour, I
can use the Intercom to see and talk to myself on Mars. ‘Wait a minute’, I reply, ‘If I´m here I can't
also be on Mars’. Someone politely coughs, a white-coated man who asks to speak to me in private.
We go to his office, where he tells me to sit down, and pauses. Then he says: ‘I´m afraid that we're
having problems with the New Scanner. It records your blueprint just as accurately, as you will
see when you talk to yourself on Mars. But it seems to be damaging the cardiac systems which it
scans. Judging from the results so far, though you will be quite healthy on Mars, here on Earth you
John D. Norton, “Thought Experiments in Einstein´s Work”, in Thought Experiments in Science and
Philosophy, ed. Tamara Horowitz and Gerald Massey (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991), 131.
5
Ibid., 131.
2
4
must expect cardiac failure within the next few days.’ The attendant later calls me to the Intercom.
On the screen I see myself just as I do in the mirror every morning. But there are two differences.
On the screen I am not left-right reversed. And, while I stand here speechless, I can see and hear
myself, in the studio on Mars, starting to speak.”6
Parfit’s point with this thought experiment is to demonstrate that what matters in cases such as
these is not identity in a strict one to one relation, but rather survival of personal identity. In the
first section of the thought experiment, Parfit sketches out an easy to follow the teletransportation
situation, resulting in a non-branching teletransportation. He then describes the same situation with
a twist. We are now asked to imagine the machine malfunctioning, leaving us with a copy and the
original existing at the same time (a branching form of identity). We have already accepted,
according to Parfit, that teletransportation is survivable in terms of identity. We are left with an
intuitive feeling that both these Parfit persons are identical to the one that entered the
teletransporter. Parfit therefore concludes that a strict one to one identity is not what matters, since
we would intuitively argue that Parfit has survived the teleportransportation, despite now having
taken a branching form of identity.
Reconstructing the thought experiment we find, hidden within, an argument which runs
something like this:
Premise 1: Personal identity is a one to one relation.
Premise 2: Teletransportation is as good as survival.
Premise 3: Teletransportation is not a one to one relation.
Conclusion: Survival does not require a one to one relation of personal identity.
In order for us to accept the conclusion of Parfit’s argument, we would have to accept the second
premise, that teletransportation is as good as survival. Yet because this premise is not factual, we
should not accept it. An argument based on hypothetical premises cannot yield a non-hypothetical
conclusion. We would not be able to apply the elimination thesis to this argument since the
impossibilities are what the conclusion rests upon.
Parfit argues that we can transfer the intuitive beliefs we have, to cover actual cases.7 It is hard
to see how one would go about applying this thought experiment to any genuine situation. We are
not presented with this type of teleporter problem in any aspect of real life. We simply do not know
how any sort of teleportation can alter our view of identity and merely imagining it will not allow
us to gain insight into any element of real life. By creating an obscure sci-fi example, Parfit has
muddled the waters of the discussion. The premises are nonfactual, and his thought experiment
therefore fails.8
Wilkes speaks of a similar issue with fission thought experiments. 9 For Wilkes, the main
problem with thought experiments of this type is that they often suffer from a reality problem. This
does not mean that a thought experiment has to be 100 percent realistic. Wilkes argues that
although a thought experiment can have some impossible element in it, that impossible element
cannot be the one which is the focus of the experiment. When Einstein posed the thought
6
Derek Parfit, Reason and Persons (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 199-200.
Ibid., 200.
8
It is important to note that the scope of this paper is not to debate Parfit’s theory about identity and
survival, but to analyses the thought experiment he uses.
9
By fission thought experiment, I here mean all the thought experiments that deal with people splitting
or changing body, either through operations, teleportation or unnamed magical processes.
3
7
experiment, where he postulates himself flying next to a beam of light, the impossible act –
Einstein flying at the speed of light – in no way changes the properties light has, and the thought
experiment was therefore a successful one. When we, on the other hand, introduce person splitting
we are changing the very thing we want to investigate because splitting changes the properties of
identity.10
Making Einstein’s thought experiment into an argument; it is apparent why Wilkes argues that
this thought experiment works.
Premise 1: According to Maxwell’s theory of electrodynamics, light, relative to something else
at the speed of light, would be rendered as a stationary oscillatory field.
Premise 2: A stationary oscillatory field is an impossibility when dealing with light.
Conclusion: Maxwell’s theory is mistaken.
The element of fiction, Einstein traveling at the speed of light looking at what will occur, can
be eliminated from the argument without changing the conclusion; “Thus we need to ensure that
what is imagined could be realized in some possible world; or that if it could not be, this
impossibility is not ‘relevant’ to the derivation of the conclusion.”11We can apply this to the
splitting example above. We see that the premise (when split in two) cannot be eliminated from
the argument since it is what the conclusion is based on.
Inspired by Norton and Wilkes, a formula can be created for what makes a good thought
experiment in personal identity:
A thought experiment is valid insofar as it makes sense as an argument, after the impossibilities
have been eliminated.
The main point with this formula is not only to sort out the logical from the illogical thought
experiments, but also to eliminate the irrelevant thought experiments. This means all the
experiments that do not allow themselves to be applied to the present way we view a given term.
A thought experiment must be able to lend itself to our real world notion of the use of a concept.
Another issue that comes up in Wilkes book is the problem of imagination. Wilkes argues that
is it not so easy to imagine a possible world where these thought experiments are supposed to take
place. To imagine a possible world where people regularly receive a new body would, according
to Wilkes, involve too many unknowns for us. How would we know what the result of such a
process would be if the background of the possible world where this takes place is not adequately
described?12 To explain the point more clearly, we can look at an actual scientific experiment.
Here we rightly assume that all the background information is set against our real world, and that
all the factors that change are isolated factors which do not influence any other aspect of the world.
With a transplant thought experiments, however, there are far too many unknowns. Our ability to
imagine the thought experiment is impaired by the lack of detail. We do not know which factors
remain the same, and which will be altered based on the setting of the thought experiment. Beck
criticizes Wilkes on this point in his paper. He argues that the background of a thought experiment
is irrelevant as long as it deals with the concepts we also deal with. He argues that Wilkes misses
the mark because what we look for in a thought experiment is our notion of the concept of “person”
10
Kathleen V. Wilkes, Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 2001), 8- 9.
11
Ibid., 12.
12
Ibid., 9.
4
and how the scenario applies to it: “What we are after is our concept, not the concept that people
in the society would use.”13 It seems, however, that Beck has missed a key point of Wilkes
argument. Wilkes is arguing that the process of imagining the thought experiment is impossible
due to its lack of detail. How does one imagine a world where people split at will? This is not
something that is easy to imagine, let alone conclude anything from.
It could be argued that the thought experiment, even if it could be imagined, would fail none
the less. Becks argument is that we can learn something about our concept of identity and persons
by engaging in the thought experiment, but the issue that causes us to reconsider our concept of
person and identity, is an issue that only happens in this very special place. It is in all probability
true that if one were to find one’s self in such a world, identity and person may have different
necessary and sufficient conditions. Living there might force us to reconsider the way we see
personal identity. We do not live there, however. We do not engage in people splitting as they do
in this possible world. We cannot therefore apply what the people do in their world to the real one.
It is difficult to see how this thought experiment can bring us anything of value. It is the same issue
we run into when we look at the thought experiment carried out by Parfit mentioned earlier. Beck
argues that a thought experiment such as this need only be plausible enough to illustrate the
weakness in an opposite theory. It does not play the role of evidence, and it therefore does not need
to be as well established as if it were used as actual confirmation. “But performing the task of
offering a counter-example – as a refuter – to a claim of necessity has no such onerous
requirements. It need only present conditions, as minimal as you like, in which we have a case in
which we can apply a concept in the way the theory in question implies we can’t.”14 Many thought
experiments are used as counter-examples and some are put to good use. The problem is again the
same. The premises must be factual. It is very damaging to a theory like Animalism to have people
splitting and functioning normally, but what good is that counter-example if we do not accept the
premise that people split? Animalism may suffer in a world where people split, but in this world,
the thought experiment does not damage the theory. It is thus an unsuccessful thought experiment
because we cannot apply it to the world we live in. To our formula then, we must add the condition
that for a thought experiment to succeed, it must be described to a degree that makes it possible
for us to imagine the setting.
If thought experiments can be reconstructed into arguments, then why do we then use thought
experiments instead of arguments? This is a good question. Norton points out that it is easier for
us to use a thought experiment than to navigate very complicated arguments.15 We are often
dealing with some very theoretical and difficult concepts, and a thought experiment can help us
get our thoughts in order. It can thus be an exploitational tool. It can also help set the scene for the
argument, making it more convincing by way of explaining some background. We must, however,
be careful. If we forget the limitations of the thought experiment, we lead ourselves astray. We
end up confusing the issue with fiction rather than fact as Wilkes points out.16 The reconstruction
and elimination theses are ways for us to check the validity of our thought experiments.
Simon Mark Beck, “Transplant Thought-Experiments: Two Costly Mistakes in Discounting
Them,” South African Journal of Philosophy 33, no. 2 (2014): 192.
14
Ibid.194
13
John D. Norton, “Thought Experiments in Einstein´s Work”, in Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy,
ed. Tamara Horowitz and Gerald Massey (Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1991), 131
15
16
Kathleen V. Wilkes, Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 2001), 43.
5
A thought experiments is only valid if:
i.
ii.
iii.
it can be reconstructed into an argument,
the impossible parts of the argument can be eliminated,
the background is described in a way that enable us to easily imagine the setting.
The setting of the thought experiment itself can be as impossible as one wishes, as long as it
does not hinder our capacity to imagine the situation. If we hold our thought experiments to this
standard we will reduce the confusions we face in discourse in the topic of personal identity. This
is by no means an easy process. There is a reason thought experiments are preferred over
conventional argumentation. If we are in doubt, however, about whether a thought experiment
succeeds, we can apply the formula above.
Lasse Nielsen
Department of Philosophy
Katedra filozofie
Filozofická fakulta UP
Křížkovského 12
771 80 Olomouc
E-mail:
[email protected]
6