Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
5 pages
1 file
Locke’s theory of property as found in the Second Treatise of Government was regarded as the cornerstone of classical liberalism (Gough, 1950). His attempt to ground the right to property in natural law was seen to be an important device for asserting the rights of individuals against the state and for limiting the moral authority of the state in a crucial area of human endeavor (Vaughn, 1980). This essay is broadly divided into two parts: the former explaining the justification of private property and the latter evaluating the same. While explaining, we will stick to the time and situation of Locke back in the seventeenth century and while evaluating we shall apply the same in present time and different critiques. While doing this, we shall touch upon Locke’s theory of property, the definitions of property and labour, restrictions and criticisms on the theory, role of government and the evaluation.
In Weinberg & Gordon-Roth (eds.), The Lockean Mind, 2021
This paper critiques Locke's account of private property. After sketching its basic principles as well as how contemporary Lockeans have developed them, I argue that this account doesn't and cannot work philosophically. The main problem is that the account requires the determination of objective value of resources in historical time, but this doesn't exist. I conclude that the ultimate philosophical failure of this tremendously influential kind of account does not entail that it is valueless. Rather, the suggestion is that understanding and overcoming its problems promises one way to overcome more general problems of systemic injustice regarding private property and the environment in our modern world. Introduction 1 Locke's account of private property is perhaps the most influential one in Western legal-political thought. In it, Locke brilliantly rethinks and unifies a set of core old and new intuitions and ideas about justice and property. The old thoughts include how human beings naturally strive (labor) to preserve themselves and humankind as well as the importance of law and reason to capture justice. The new, modern ones include the importance of individual rights, freedom, and equality-ideas Locke combines with his innovative proposal that originally (only) each person has natural political power. The result is an account of just property relations that is consistent with both philosophical anarchism and Locke's own revolutionary political engagement, and, so, with Locke's defense of each individual's natural executive right and a right to revolution. As we will see, I do not think the Lockean account of property ultimately works philosophically, but this doesn't make it less valuable. Locke's insights on their own and as explored by those coming after him empower us to see important complexities and concerns related to our attempt to envision just property relations in modern societies. To make my case, I briefly present the core ideas that make up Locke's account of property as well as some central, well-known lines of objections and contemporary attempts at improving the account. I argue that all Lockean accounts depend on the possibility of identifying an objective way of valuing objects and productive activity in historical time, but that this is in principle impossible. In addition, I argue that this kind of approach faces insurmountable problems with regard to capturing just private property relations once we include trade in our analyses and, even more so, once our access to means becomes dependent on participation in an economy. I then draw attention to a much less studied objection, from Hannah Arendt, that even though Locke famously says that we have a right to "the labor of our body and the work of our hands," he fails to pay attention to the common language as well as an important philosophical distinction between "labor" and "work." I propose that Arendt's objection is important for Locke's own account, later Lockean accounts, as well as Marxist accounts since their theory of the relation of labor to property is derived from Locke.
İSTANBUL ÜNİVERSİTESİ İKTİSAT FAKÜLTESİ MECMUASI, 2007
Locke was a late seventeenth century philosopher who wrote before the industrial revolution, hence, what Locke aimed to justify was the pre-industrial form of property in its personal form. However, Locke's popularity among the nineteenth century liberals suggests that his theory transcended his own time and formed the theoretical basis of a new form of property that gained social character with the changing mode of production. Locke begins with a justification of property right based on one's own labor; however ends up as an apologist of capitalism legitimizing the unlimited accumulation of capital. His labor theory of value plays a crucial role in his chain of arguments. Contrary to Locke, who views property right as an essential part of individual freedom, Marx employs the labor theory of value to argue for the abolition of private property, which he perceives as a source of alienation and a major obstacle for the attainment of individual freedom. By comparing these two thinkers this paper develops a critique of the well known liberal arguments that relate private property rights with political democracy.
American Political Science Review, 1981
And so the battle continues. For over 20 years, since at least the publication of C. B. Macpherson's The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962), political theorists and their students have ranged themselves on one of two sides: those who endorsed the Macpherson thesis that Locke and other seventeenth-century theorists were, intentionally or otherwise, apologists for a fully emergent bourgeoisie, and those who took issue with that position, arguing that Locke and the Levellers were exponents of a liberal constitutionalist position and only indirectly concerned themselves with the promotion of a vaguely discernible bourgeoisie. Today the issue is still unresolved, as witness the shortly-to-be published Agrarian Capitalism by Neal Wood and the present book-which represent the same two opposed positions. Yet another component of the debate has been introduced with the recent literature. That literature on Locke portrays him as a plotter and a pamphleteer even more than as a political theorist. Ashcraft so analyses him as do Dunn, Tully, Schochet and others. In this recent spate of articles and papers we have come to see in Locke a much closer affinity to the Levellers than was ever acknowledged in the literature before. We now know that Locke must have rubbed shoulders with Wildman, giving us the direct link between Locke and the Levellers that was never seen earlier. Tully is one of the few commentators on Locke to have noted this connection, long before the recent literature commented on it. But while admitting such a connection Tully also sees no capitalist appearing or lurking in the wings. Wood finds this hard to accept. As Wood observes: "For Tully if there is one leitmotiv which unites Locke's works it is surely a philosophy of religious praxis. The contribution of the Two Treatises to this unifying theme is the vision of the self-governing political community emboding the egalitarianism of the Levellers like Lilburne and Overton, consisting of small and middling proprietors, all of whom will be able to live in security and relative comfort and enjoy the fruits of their calling." The special emphasis running through Tully's book is the concept of work, labour, exertion. God is the great workman who has enjoined us to labour like Him to increase and multiply the earth and all that He initiated. By His creative powers God has made me, and having made me, He thereby owns me. Therefore, we are not in command of our lives, liberties and souls. We must be kept at liberty-free to glorify Him, to love our neighbour and to subdue His earth. It is on his concept of labour that Tully's argument rests. Rights we learn, both inclusive and exclusive rights, give us our clue to his understanding of common and private property and the nature of ownership. We have, to begin with, an inclusive natural right to the earth and its produce. We also have an exclusive right, that of appropriating and improving the earth and all that it provides. It is the exertion of labour that puts our imprint on these improvements. And we have found out a way to justify our unequal holdings not simply from our tacit consent to the use of money but because in applying our
2022
The paper addresses Locke's political implications in the theory of fiduciary powers presented in the Second Treatise on Government. I proceed by analysing Locke's conception of natural rights in the state of nature as well as his conception of property in accordance with its different articulations (particularly the idea of the private ownership of an acquired object). I reconstruct the logic of the social contract theory and the foundation of the modern bourgeois (liberal) state. The paper concludes by showing the limits of Locke's minimalist conception of the state. It argues that the original placing of the civil society in the state of nature prevents the recognition of a conflictual and dynamical composition of class interests whose mediation is the proper task of politics at the parliamentary level.
This paper critically examines John Locke’s labor theory of property as presented in his Two Treatises of Government. Locke's theory, which justifies property rights through an individual's labor, is historically significant and intuitively appealing. However, this paper identifies several critical issues within Locke’s framework. These include the conditional nature of exclusive ownership, ambiguities in defining what constitutes labor, and complications in property ownership arising from collaborative work and division of labor. Furthermore, the paper highlights how Locke’s theory neglects the concept of associative rights and struggles with the non-finality of ownership when new labor is added to a property. By addressing these concerns, the paper argues that Locke’s labor theory of property is limited in scope and insufficient for addressing modern complexities of property rights, suggesting the need for a more comprehensive approach.
The United States Constitution. From the Studies of the American Political System, 2018
The Article examines the private property theory of a 17th century English philosopher John Locke (1632-1704) and its rich impact on the American Founding Fathers, as well as its particular influence on the foundational documents of the new American Republic: The Declaration of Independence, state constitutions, and the federal United States Constitution. Ab initio, the Article is centered on interpretation of chapter V of the Lockean Second Treatise of Government entitled “Of Property” and the notion of the God-granted right to property in the state of nature. Further, the Article investigates Locke’s assumption of the emergence of government as a necessary guarantor of private property rights and the role of positive state law in regards to their effective preservation, and then presents the natural limits on the vast scope of property set forth by Locke in his writings. Finally, the Author – by employing historical and linguistic mode of analysis – explores the magnitude of influence of Locke’s property theory, of which legacy is still clearly apparent in fully-binding documents such as the Declaration of Independence and constitutional acts of the United States, as well as throughout many sources of knowledge about the intellectual and political milieu of revolutionary and post-revolutionary America.
It is traditional to ascribe to Locke the view that every person who acquires natural property rights by labouring on resources is obligated to leave sufficient resources for everyone else. But during the last several decades, a number of authors have contributed to a compelling textual case against this reading. Nevertheless, Locke clearly indicates that there is something wrong with distributions in which some suffer while others thrive. But if he does not endorse the traditional proviso, what exactly is the problem? In this paper, I offer a solution to this puzzle. I argue that according to Locke, once people use their natural rights to acquire large properties, many individuals are unable to enjoy the material and moral wellbeing, or “preservation,” that is the end of natural law. For even if such large properties pose no problem for material preservation, they foster arbitrary power that offends against moral preservation.
This paper considers the theological and philosophical basis for private property (and the ethics of why and how it should exist and be used) in Scripture, Greek philosophy, medieval theology, and the thought of John Locke. Locke is specifically argued to be more of a Neo-medieval thinker than the modern figure he is usually portrayed as.
The University of Chicago Law School Roundtable, 2002
Among Locke's most famous ideas is the origin of private property through one's labor. Thousands of undergrads still read this section of The Second Treatise of Government every year. Catholic Social Teaching is openly hostile to communism, and is also critical of liberalism. So, Locke is generally not a popular figure within Catholic Social Teaching. It strikes me as curious, then, that Locke's idea of the origin of private property is seemingly appropriated into Catholic Social Teaching by Pope John Paul II in Laborem Exercens, where John Paul appears to repeat Locke's argument. In this paper I compare these two accounts of the origins of private property in detail to see how similar they actually are. I argue that the main difference lies in what each figure sees the purpose of private property to be.
Centre for Studies in Social Sciences, Calcutta, 2022
Afrika tanulmányok, 2024
REVISTA DO SELL, 2019
Proceedings of the Sixth International Conference Computational Linguistics in Bulgaria (CLIB 2024), 2024
EcoProduction, 2014
The British Journal of Social Work
Journal of Food Science and Engineering, 2012
Molecular Genetics and Metabolism, 2020
Transplantation Proceedings, 2005
Molecular Immunology, 2006
Journal of the American Heart Association, 2020
Journal of Inorganic and Organometallic Polymers and Materials, 2010
2020 XXXIIIrd General Assembly and Scientific Symposium of the International Union of Radio Science, 2020
Nuclear Instruments and Methods in Physics Research Section A: Accelerators, Spectrometers, Detectors and Associated Equipment, 2014