Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Locke's justification for private property

Locke’s theory of property as found in the Second Treatise of Government was regarded as the cornerstone of classical liberalism (Gough, 1950). His attempt to ground the right to property in natural law was seen to be an important device for asserting the rights of individuals against the state and for limiting the moral authority of the state in a crucial area of human endeavor (Vaughn, 1980). This essay is broadly divided into two parts: the former explaining the justification of private property and the latter evaluating the same. While explaining, we will stick to the time and situation of Locke back in the seventeenth century and while evaluating we shall apply the same in present time and different critiques. While doing this, we shall touch upon Locke’s theory of property, the definitions of property and labour, restrictions and criticisms on the theory, role of government and the evaluation.

Political Thinkers Essay Question: Explain and evaluate Locke’s justification for private property. Locke’s theory of property as found in the Second Treatise of Government was regarded as the cornerstone of classical liberalism (Gough, 1950). His attempt to ground the right to property in natural law was seen to be an important device for asserting the rights of individuals against the state and for limiting the moral authority of the state in a crucial area of human endeavor (Vaughn, 1980). This essay is broadly divided into two parts: the former explaining the justification of private property and the latter evaluating the same. While explaining, we will stick to the time and situation of Locke back in the seventeenth century and while evaluating we shall apply the same in present time and different critiques. While doing this, we shall touch upon Locke’s theory of property, the definitions of property and labour, restrictions and criticisms on the theory, role of government and the evaluation. As Aaron asserts (1955: 276), Locke had accepted the traditional communism of medieval thought―in the diluted form in which it was handed on to the seventeenth century. In the state of nature, according to Locke, men were born free and equal (Connolly, 2004). ‘Although it is a state of liberty, it is not a state of license,’ (Locke, 1689, 2.6) because it is ruled over by the law of nature which everyone is obliged to obey. Locke places the right to possessions on the same level as the right to life, health, and liberty (Heywood, 1997: 26). God had given all things ‘to mankind in common’ (Locke, 1689, 2.26) and man was to use them for his own convenience. Yet to use, one must possess, and possess absolutely and not communally. It was no longer held that men actually possess all things in common in a positive way. Locke makes this argument strongly (1689: 2.34), ‘God gave the world to men in common, but since he gave it for their benefit and the greatest conveniences of life they were capable to draw from it, it cannot be supposed he meant it should always remain common and uncultivated.’ Land which is common is uncultivated. A piece of land taken and cultivated is the private property of the individual who has cultivated it (Dunn, 1982). ‘In this way, although starting with communism of a sort, Locke can none the less justify property’ (Aaron, 1955: 277). He is content to show that the possession of private property is fundamental in human life and belongs to man in the state of nature. Locke begins his argument by identifying the one form of property against which no other man could possibly have a claim in a world of political equals, the property each man that each man possesses himself, his own person, absolutely (O’Connor, 1952: 209). Locke built on this concept of self-ownership when he used it to explain how one derives a right to possess objects outside of one’s self, his labour theory of property (Hartogh, 1990). Locke used the term Labour to characterize the act by which men create property. Labour, for Locke (1689: 2.46), includes picking up acorns from the ground, gathering apples from wild trees, tracking deer in the forest, and catching fish in the ocean, labour ranges from simple acts of appropriation to production involving planning and effort. Thus it is labour which creates property and gives value to most of the things. ‘It is labour indeed that puts the difference of value on everything… Of the products of the earth useful to the life of man nine-tenths are the effects of labour.’ (Locke, 1689, 2.40). Locke argued that private property was moral as unassisted nature really provides very little that is useful to mankind. Locke here suggested a ‘labour theory of value’ as the center of a systematic defence of property. He argues that, if one considers the value of the products of the earth, nine tenths will be found to be attributed to labour and only the remaining fraction to nature itself (Laslett, 1988). A man’s labour and the work of his hands are necessarily his own and so also should be their products. Locke’s definition of property does not only include tangible goods but also encompasses human rights such as the ‘right to life and liberty’ (Macpherson, 1962: 198). He sometimes uses ‘property’ in a wide sense so as to include life and indeed other goods as well as material possessions (Moulds, 1964). The right to property broadly includes (Locke, 1689, 2.32) both ‘the fruits of the earth and the earth itself’. The earth and all inferior creatures were held in common by all men; each man had as ‘property’ only his own person, the labour of his body, and the work of his hands (Morris, 1931: 59). But in addition he also possesses anything ‘with which he has mixed his labour’. As Locke puts (1689, 2.27), ‘Whatsoever, then, he removes out of the state that nature hath provided and left it in, he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his own, and thereby makes it his property.’ Locke derives the right to private property from the right of self-preservation (Mabbot, 1973: 147). When a man by his own effort has changed a thing from the state in which nature made it, that thing from being common becomes the property of him that mixed his labour with. Locke makes this argument strongly (1689, 2.30), ‘Though the water running in the fountain is every one’s, yet who can doubt but that in the pitcher is his only who drew it out.’. Locke includes that the individual appropriating property for himself does not lessen but rather increases ‘the common stock of mankind’, hence supporting such a system of collective social benefit. To say that anything is a man’s property is to say that he can do what he likes with it including making gifts of it, and, it should follow, bequeathing it to whomever he likes at his own death (Mabbot, 1972: 147). ‘Labour being unquestionable property of the labourer, no man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to, at least where there is enough and as good left in common for others’ (Locke, 1689, 2.27). The implication is that one’s right to property is only clear and exclusive so long as it doesn’t jeopardize anyone else’s ability to create equivalent kinds of property from himself. The right of property is a right assigned by Nature; it requires no government to establish it, nor can any government take it away (Morris, 1931: 59). But reason assigns a natural limit to the application of this principle, and Locke includes three restrictions to his theory. Macpherson argues (1962: 203), as the argument progresses, each of these restrictions is transcended. The first restriction Locke imposes is when he says a man may appropriate as much as he can use, (1689, 2.31), ‘One may only possess as much as any one can make use of, to any advantage of life, before it spoils it.’. As much as anyone can make use of to advantage of life or comfort before it spoils, so much he may by his labour fix his property in. Beyond this he may not go; nothing was made by God for man to spoil or destroy (Morris, 1931: 60). It ceases to be meaningful with the intervention of money because value can be stored in a medium that does not decay (Macpherson, 1962). The Second restriction according to Locke states, one may only take from the common stock when ‘there is enough and as good left in common for others.’ (1689, 2.33). Laslett comments (1988), but the surplus limitation can be evaded by the use of money. If surplus products which would spoil if hoarded are exchanged for money, which cannot spoil if hoarded, then there need be no limit to the process of acquisition. It according to Macpherson (1962) is transcended because the creation of private property so increases productivity that even those who no longer have the opportunity to acquire land will have more opportunity to acquire what is necessary for life. The third restriction, Macpherson (1962) argues, was not one Locke actually held at all. Though Locke appears to suggest that one can only have property in what one has personally labored on when he makes labor the source of property rights, Locke clearly recognized that even in the state of nature, ‘the turfs my servants has cut’ (1689, 2.28) can become my property. Locke, according to Macpherson (1962), thus clearly recognized that labour can be alienated. He portrays Locke as a defender of unrestricted capitalist accumulation. James Tully (1980) attacked Macpherson’s interpretation by pointing out that Locke (Locke, 1689, 1.42) in his other writings includes a duty of charity towards those who have no other means of subsistence. Nozick (1991) criticized the labour theory with his famous example of mixing tomato juice one rightfully owns with the sea, when we mix what we own with what we do not, why should we think we gain property instead of losing it? Nozick takes Locke to be a libertarian, with the government having no right to take property to use for the common good without the consent of the property owner. Overcoming the spoilage limitation, will have consequences in form of property disputes and increasing concern for personal safety, men will find it greatly to their advantage to come together to form a contract to enter into civil society and establish a government (Tuckness, 2005). Thus, Locke’s justification of property eventually necessitates the formation of a social contract or government (1689, 2.38). Locke, here describes that men form governments to protect their property which according to him includes life, liberty and estate (Laslett, 1988). By agreeing to give up his right to be judges in his own case, each man gains the benefits of increased order and security. Hence the ownership of private property is one of the major causes of the existence of the state (Waldron, 1990). The government is expected to rule in the public good, and not for its own good; should the government fail to meet its obligations the citizens have the right to change the government (Locke, 1689, 2.38). Locke’s idea of government can be interpreted as supporting limited governance, where the government is set up to simply ensure a state of minimal order to allow men to pursue their private accumulation of property untroubled by such social problems as basic inequality and injustice (Tully, 1980: 150). Locke was led to oversimplify the problem (Morris, 1931: 60). He thought that the distribution of property and wealth was easily and perfectly controlled by nature herself, and that in this sphere the exercise of human ingenuity and organization was not required. In this he was the true forerunner of the laissez-faire economists and politicians. It is clear that Locke did not consider the possibility of a state of affairs like the present in which there is little or no product of nature which is not, under the sanction of the established order, the property of some one, so that a man may easily die of starvation before he can reach any unappropriated material which he can by labour make his own (Davis, 2014). As Morris comments (1931: 60), Locke’s principle has played the part of a fruitful seed from which have grown many different solutions of the problem, none of these solutions can be reasonably attributed to Locke himself. His theory of the origin of the right to property ‘has all but completely established the fundamental principle which lies at the bottom of the science of Wealth’ (Fraser, 1959: 102). As Morris comments (1931: 59), although three-quarters of a century elapsed before the importance of his doctrine came to be fully recognized, its influence can readily be traced in the classical economists, and since the writings of Karl Marx it has assumed first-rate importance as the main principle lying at the root of Socialistic theory. Bibliography Aaron, R. (1955), John Locke. Oxford University Press. London. Connolly, P. (2008), ‘The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: John Locke.’ Available at: http://www.iep.utm.edu/locke/ Davis, M. (2014), ‘Locke’s Political Society’, Journal of Moral Philosophy II, pp. 209-231. Dunn, J. (1982) The Political Thought of John Locke, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 97, 101, 103. Fraser, A.C. (1959), John Locke: An essay concerning Human Understanding, New York: Dover Publications. Gough, J.W. (1950), Locke’s Political Philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Hartogh, G.A. (1990), ‘Tully’s Locke’, Political Theory, vol. 18, no. 4, pp. 656-672. Heywood, A. (2013), Politics, Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Laslett, P. (1988), Locke: Two Treatises of Government, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Locke, John, (1689), The Two Treatises of Government. Mabbott, J.D. (1973), John Locke, London: Macmillan Press. Macpherson, C.B. (1962), The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Morris, C.R. (1931), Locke Berkeley Hume, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Moulds, H. (1964), ‘Private Property in John Locke’s State of Nature’, The American Journal of Economics and Sociology, vol. 23, no. 2, pp. 179-188. Nozick, R. (1991), Locke on Property: Property, Justice and the Minimal State, Oxford: Blackwell Publishers. O’Connor, D.J. (1952), John Locke, London: Dover Publications. Tuckness, A. (2005), ‘Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Locke’s Political Philosophy.’ Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke-political/ - Pro Tully, J. (1980), A Discourse on Property: John Locke and his adversaries, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Vaughn, K. (1980), ‘Locke on Property: A Bibliographical Essay’, Literate of Liberty: A Review of Contemporary Liberal Thought, vol. III, no. 1. Waldron, J. (1990), The Right to Private Property, Oxford: Clarendon Press.