Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
…
5 pages
1 file
To accompany premiere recording of the ?Josquin mass on Quem dicunt homines. Brief review & summary of the literature for popular audience. [CD title "The Spirit like a Dove"] Available on Spotify, YouTube (https://www.youtube.com/playlist?list=OLAK5uy_k94-9Uq_PYN9qZQ5QvagabVBqkAlq05e4) etc
Philosophical Readings IV.1 is out! It includes: 1. Patricia Springborg, Calvin and Hobbes: A Reply to Curley, Martinich and Wright – 2. A.P. Martinich, On Thomas Hobbes’s English Calvinism: Necessity, Omnipotence, and Goodness – 3. Mauro Farnesi Camellone, Hobbes e i martiri del Leviatano. Sui limiti della coscienza– 4. Antonio Vernacotola, Profili di gnoseologia e teologia politica nel modulo epistemologico della ‘scienza civile’ di Hobbes – 5. Understanding Hobbes. Interview with Quentin Skinner by Marco Sgarbi – 6. Patricia Springborg, Reply to Martinich on Hobbes’s English Calvinism. Reviews of M. del Rosario Acosta López: La tragedia como conjuro: el problema de lo sublime en Friedrich Schiller (Bogotá: Universidad Nacional de Colombia, 2008) (L. Bodas Fernández); Lieve Van Hoof, Plutarch’s Practical Ethics. The Social Dynamics of Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010) (A. Corti); Cordula Burtscher e Markus Hien (cur.), Schiller im philosophischen Kontext (Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 2011) (L.A. Macor); Davide Tarizzo, La vita, un’invenzione recente (Roma-Bari: Laterza, 2010) (G. Velasco Arias).
Aim and Method: It appears as if a deified humanity with infinite appetite for consumption and experience, endless expectations of what the union of science and technology can accomplish, and neither recognizing nor setting limits on its freedom, is close to the terminus of an historical progress which is also the destruction of the conditions of human life on earth. The natural and engineering sciences which have enabled this seem capable now only of measuring our steps toward this extinction, or proposing solutions of extreme and incalculable danger. The philosophical, theological, social, and humanistic disciplines which were or are implicated in creating both this self-confident divine Anthropos and its cynical nihilist despair have been made, or have made themselves, powerless to move it. However, as the Encyclical “Laudatio si” indicates, this global world order was largely a creation of the Christian West and spread or imposed from and by it. It behooves us then to investigate how it came about and what its essential elements are. The history this class covers will not bring all the essentials into view but some cruxes will appear. Exposing these is its aim. My method in this seminar will differ from what I usually do: I shall not work with members on discerning the logic and argument of a single text. In fact, we shall read no text completely. Instead we shall look at portions of several texts from Plato, Aristotle, Philo of Alexandria, Plotinus, Augustine, Boethius, Eriugena, and Aquinas as embedded in my interpretations of them (and the interpretations of a few others) in order to discern the character of an historical development. The following contain most of my argument and most of the texts we shall examine: 1. “Placing the human: Reason as Participation in Divine Intellect for Boethius and Aquinas,” Res philosophica 93, no. 4 (October 2018): 583–615. 2. “’Complectitur Omnem’: Divine and Human Happiness in Aristotle and in Aquinas’ Summa theologiae,” Kronos VII (2018): 187–205. The following brings these two together and shows the importance of Aquinas’ use of the idea of participation to establish the human in relation to the divine. 3. Dwight Crowell, “Thomas Aquinas’ Attribution of Participation to Aristotle,” Dionysius 37 (2019): 134–64. This volume of Dionysius is posted on the Brightspace. *** 4. “Augustine’s Trinitarian Cosmos,” Dionysius 35 (2017): 61–98, exposes the interconnection of the human and divine. Usefully read with “Between and Beyond Augustine and Descartes: More than a Source of the Self,” Augustinian Studies 32:1 (2001): 65–88, especially, pp. 7-12 of the posted text and with “Re-evaluating E.R. Dodds’ Platonism,” Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 103 (2007): 499–541, especially 521-23 on the shift to the human in Late Antiquity. 5. “Ratio, Preces, Intuitus: Prayer’s Mediation in Boethius’ Consolation,” Praying and Contemplating: Religious and Philosophical Interactions in Late Antiquity, Studies and Texts in Antiquity and Christianity (Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2018), 71–96, examines how the characteristic form of human knowing and willing is restored after its absorption into the Divine. 6. “John Scottus Eriugena,” Cambridge History of Late Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy, 2010. Eriugena’s is the most profound humanism ever developed philosophically and theologically, see especially, pp. 10-13 of the posted text. Usefully read with “Augustine, Denys, Eriugena and the Western turn to the World,” Hermathena 165 (Winter, 1998): 9–70, especially 39-45 of the posted text, and “Jean Trouillard: Authentic Neoplatonism in a French Seminary.” 7. God in Himself, Aquinas’ Doctrine of God as Expounded in the Summa Theologiae, Oxford Theological Monographs / Oxford Scholarly Classics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987 / 2000), Introduction, is a brief assertion and contextualization of Aquinas’ humanism. 8. “God’s Indwelling: Aquinas’ Platonist Systematization of Aristotelian Participation,” for Participation in the Divine, edited Douglas Hedley and Evan King, Notre Dame University Press, in press. Aquinas unites the human to the divine through the notion of participation. Understanding how participation functions in Aquinas is crucial. Usefully read when you are reading Dwight Crowell, “Thomas Aquinas’ Attribution of Participation to Aristotle.” 9. “The Conversion of God in Aquinas’ Summa theologiae: Being’s Trinitarian and Incarnational Self Disclosure,” Dionysius 35 (2017): 132–170, demonstrates how the human moves the Summa theologiae and explicates the Divine. Everything necessary for the class will be posted on its Brightspace site, but participants will find it useful to have a copy of the collected dialogues of Plato, Aristotle’s De Anima, Metaphysics, and Nicomachean Ethics, the Enneads of Plotinus, the Confessions of Augustine, the Consolation of Philosophy of Boethius, portions of the Periphyseon of Eriugena, and the Summa theologiae of Aquinas.
2024
What is the relationship between the concept of person and the concept of intentionality? Is the phenomenological notion of essence somehow related to that of medieval philosophies? What kind of entity is the person understood in her irreducible singularity? These are some of the questions that the chapters in this book seek to address and develop by focusing on the thought of Aquinas, Scotus and Edith Stein. Indeed, the editors of the book are led by the conviction that a fruitful dialogue between medieval philosophy and 20th century phenomenology may prove useful in addressing questions and problems that are still relevant in contemporary debates. The book is divided into three sections, devoted respectively to medieval philosophy, phenomenology and some of the possible systematic and historical intersections between them. Contributors are Sarah Borden Sharkey, Antonio Calcagno, Therese Cory, Daniele De Santis, Andrew LaZella, Dominik Perler, Giorgio Pini, Francesco Valerio Tommasi, Anna Tropia, and Ingrid Vendrell Ferran.
History of Psychiatry, 2005
This article stresses the main lines of Thomas Aquinas’s philosophy on the nature of the body-soul union. Following Aristotle, Aquinas sees the soul as a ‘principle of life’ which is intimately bound to a body. Together they form a non-contingent composition. In addition, the distinctive feature of the human soul is rationality, which implies that a human needs a mind to be what it is. However, this is not to say, as Descartes proposes, that the reason that I am a human is that I am fully self-conscious. On the contrary, I will show that self-consciousness is not necessarily a key to defining a human being. To that aim, and based on Aquinas’s views, I draw a distinction between what I will call ‘egos’ and ‘selves’.
One of St. Thomas Aquinas's most ingenious, yet underappreciated, philosophical innovations is his synthesis of Plato's dualism and Aristotle's hylomorphism in his theory of the human person. Aquinas's view of the person expresses itself in a number of aspects of his thought. In this paper, I explore how his understanding of the passions is a reflection of his account of the unity of the human person. Just as Aquinas's view of the person reconciles elements of dualism and hylomorphism, his explanation of the passions steers a middle course between intellectualist and physicalist accounts of the human emotions and resists the reductionism characteristic of these dominant kinds of theories. Because Aquinas depicts the passions as engaging the whole person, I conclude the paper with a brief sketch of the significance of the passions for his moral theory.
Dissertation (Radboud University Nijmegen) , 2018
Lumen Veritatis, 2014
1998
L'objectif du present article est de retrouver les tendances essentielles de la philosophie de Thomas d'Aquin et de Martin Heidegger, et particulierement leur maitrise de la metaphysique. Tous deux sont d'authentiques philosophes a cause de leur constante preoccupation de la question de l'etre; Thomas d'Aquin avec sa conception de 'esse' et le 'Ipsum Esse Subsistens', la realite absolue et la causalite primordiale universelle de 'actus essendi'; et Martin Heidegger, avec sa penetration dans le 'Sein', la tâche de l'etre humain etant de repondre par la reflexion a ce qui lui est dit.
The Oxford Handbook of the Reception of Aquinas, ed. Levering and Plested, 2021
This chapter proposes that Aquinas's philosophy of the human person is fundamentally motivated by his vision of the distinctive unity of the human way of life, illustrated by (a) his account of the human soul as the " horizon " of the bodily and spiritual worlds, and (b) his definition of the human being as 'rational animal'. Commitment to this vision is essential for any attempt to revive Aquinas's anthropology today. In this chapter, I also problematize the standard way of labeling Aquinas's anthropology as "Aristotelian," and make a case for rejecting such labels, not only in evaluating his own work, but also in evaluating receptions of Aquinas's own thought.
Semiotica, 2004
The Role of Thomas Aquinas in the Development of Semiotic Consciousness", Semiotica 152-1/4 (2004), 75-139., is presented here in SSA Style (i.e., with footnotes instead of endnotes and with the references historically layered), but with the pagination of the published version indicated in bold square brackets to enable the reader to make reference to the published text.
newsletter di L. Porpora, 2023
Journal of Translational Genetics and Genomics, 2024
Routledge eBooks, 2024
Musriadi, S.Sos., M.Si, 2020
Gosudarstvennyj apparat upravlenija v imperii Romanovych, 2021
Malaria Journal, 2008
South African Journal of Animal Science, 2019
Agrokémia és Talajtan, 2019
International journal of engineering research and technology, 2017
Medicina Clínica, 2004
Statistical Journal of the IAOS
Jurnal Matematika "MANTIK", 2020
The Journal of Maternal-Fetal & Neonatal Medicine, 2018
Proceedings of the 1st International Conference on Sustainable Management and Innovation, ICoSMI 2020, 14-16 September 2020, Bogor, West Java, Indonesia, 2021