"Historians take note: motivation = emotion", Diogenes 51 Issue 3 (2003) 19-25
by Ramsay MacMullen
[Abstract: in the journal's French-language edition also, pp. 23-31, and Spanish, Arabic, and
Chinese, this short piece addresses not only specialist readers. It is concerned with historical
method, as outlined in the author's Feelings in History, Ancient and Modern of the same year, to
be offered on a large scale in 2014, in Why Do We Do What We Do? Motivation in History and
the Social Sciences. A few small additions in square brackets, 2017, clarify the original]
[page 19] Whether we act as we do at the urging of our thinking mind or of our feelings is
something we don't ordinarily see in simple terms. The two alternatives are better thought of as
opposing poles on a scale. Action at different moments will be better explained, but not
completely explained, by the one or by the other. Overall, or in a given week, it wouldn't be easy
to say which had most controlled our behavior. That is how the layman thinks, anyway.
Not so, the learned. Over the course of the last century, they generally ignored the one:
the pole of feelings. When the historian Marc Bloch in the early 1940s spoke out in protest, it
sounded as if his life had been lived till then, unwillingly, in a second Age of Reason; as if the
whole field of human action which is history had been pervaded by the assumption which he
denied, and which he saw most aggressively and authoritatively expressed in that one part called
economic history. Nor was there any great change to be seen after his death, in the second half of
the century. "To read certain history books," he wrote, "one might suppose humanity to be made
up solely of logicians' intentions, books for which the motives of action have nothing at all
obscure about them." In just this belief lay their grand illusion "which is, again, to repeat while
exaggerating the mistake so often held up for correction, of that ancient economic theory. Its
homo economicus was not an empty shadow only for the reason of imagining him to be solely
focused on his interests; worse still, the illusion consisted in believing he could form even so
clear a conception of these interests."1
Economic history, offering its magic to other sorts of history as an exemplar, indeed had
at its center that mythical being and the conjoined assumption "that homo economicus makes his
decisions on the basis of considerations of self-interest" -- this, "the model beloved of 'pure'
economists", as Daniel Kahneman put it. 2 The model was all rationality, all calculation. Calling
it in question earned him a Nobel prize, while other prizes, if less glorious, fell to Robert Shiller
for offering a similar challenge from a different point of view, not that of a psychologist but
formidably mathematical (Market Volatility [1996] and Irrational Exuberance [2000]).
[page 20] So, in that second Age of Reason, the first cracks began to appear in the 1980s and
1990s: reminders that we are not, at least in our economic behavior (which is indeed so much of
our lives) purely rational. We are rather prey to fads and fashions, to the idiocies of the herd
instinct. We think in crowds.
True; but the fact has nothing very surprising about it for the layman; nor does it discover
our irrationality so much as our merely imperfect reasoning. We can be shown to be foolishly
mistaken but not totally capricious. We respond to the impressions we form from each other at
1
2
Marc Bloch's posthumous Apologie pour l'histoire, ou, Métier d'historien (Paris 1949) 101.
Kahneman, quoted in The Jerusalem Report of 10 February, 2003.
the urging of social impulses and consequential excesses of spirit. Which is not to say, altogether
without thought. It is enough to recall the California Gold Rush to see how the herd instinct once
operated upon homo economicus in a fashion or fad reasonably rational; that is to say, there
really was gold out there, and many won it, and the report of their winnings produced an
exuberance which had some sense to it, however giddy it was as well.
But received truths of market-theory loom so enormous over the field, what seems a
brave advance to the insiders, well worthy of a prize, may be judged very differently by others
on the outside. As Kahneman put it on the occasion cited, "You need to have studied economics
for many years before you'd be surprised by my research."
And it is easy to understand, too, the resistance offered by received truth and its
defenders. The challengers, in taking account of fads and fashions at least as explanatory
postulates, want to introduce causal factors which are not subject to quantifiable analysis. Such
factors are seen as anathema, the enemies of good method. How can anyone think or argue at all
scientifically or conclusively without numbers? As Dr. Johnson said long ago [in Boswell's Life,
April 18, 1783], "That is the good of counting. It brings everything to a certainty which before
floated in the mind indefinitely".
Cannot numbers be somehow applied to the examination of fads and fashions? At least
their external manifestations, in visible acts, can be measured and turned into figures. Just this,
indeed, Marc Bloch and his school of historical interpretation did attempt. In their monographs
and their trade-mark journal, the Annales, they undertook to examine all varieties of human
behavior in numerical terms. Their fondness for graphs and percentages provoked some gentle
ridicule;3 but they persisted in it then and now. They deal with things like sexual morality or
piety through reckoning up all births out of wedlock or memorial masses funded in people's
wills; and so forth, for similar topics generally left to the social sciences. The findings inevitably
remain very much on the surface of things.
A deeper, truer understanding resisted by the economic Establishment might have been
sought in psychology. Its own received truths, like those in most areas of modern research, have
been laid out in encyclopedias, updated from time to time. In one such (1998), consider the essay
devoted to decision-making, in which there is no allowance at all, in all 45,000 words, for
caprice or feelings of any sort; rather, a firm adherence to the "utility principle", that is, pure
rationality, in explaining economic affairs. But this essay is followed in the same gigantic
volume by another titled "Emotions", by quite a different authority. He leads off with the defiant
statement, "This is the first time", among the many editions thus far, that a chapter on emotions
appears in the Handbook of Social Psychology"; and he goes on, "emotions are of prime
importance". So, signs of another crack in the present Age of Reason.
[page 21] In the area of history itself, observers may notice a marked rise of interest in emotions
considered diachronically and as objects of study, through "emotionology" (the word proposed in
the mid-1980s). From works of a generation ago or more, on accidie and melancholy, the focus
had moved on to marriage and love with a much admired book by Lawrence Stone (1977); to the
[J. H.] Jack Hexter ["Fernand Braudel and the monde Braudellien …,"] in the Journal of
Modern History 44 (1972) [486-93].
3
once-general enjoyment of sensibility and horror, tears and shudders, in literature and in
common behavior; more recently, to shame, anger, or disgust. The shaping or controlling of
feelings of various sorts, or of all sorts, at different times by different societies, has been recently
studied, too. The Chronicle of Higher Education (February 21, 2003) surveyed the whole area
through an eccentric but indicative selection of studies. Many more could be added from beyond
the Anglophone academy. 4
A revolution? The strictly cognitive, logical approach to strictly cognitive and logical
human beings (whether or not the layman is inclined to call these beings, human) has indeed
been challenged. In all three disciplines, economists, psychologists, and historians have done so,
and have with more or less triumph called attention to the novelty of their work in the last decade
or so. There was indeed, as there still remains, much to be done.
Progress has been made through breaching the boundaries of disciplines, though with
certain inherent difficulties. Psychologists don't naturally think like historians; are not likely to
have the slightest interest in anything that happened yesterday, necessarily beyond the control of
replication. Their laboratory experiments can show that people (the inevitable students in a
survey course) may write down accounts of a moment filled with strong emotions, and designate
which emotions; and on a scale of one to twenty they may rate the strength of these; and other
people may read the account and by empathy identify and feel those feelings and rate their
strength in turn; and the two outcomes may then be compared, and will match quite closely.
Surely this has something to say about what historians commonly do. But no-one from the
laboratory has run to tell them; nor do historians reach out for such help. I return to the point in a
moment.
As to economists thinking as historians -- that is, trying to understand market trends,
which are of course events of the sort that historians have traditionally concerned themselves
with -- they demonstrate thus far no curiosity about those irrational fads and fashions and
caprices in the past which they are beginning to take seriously in the present. They do go so far
as to see that these arise out of moods or conditions of readiness for action of one sort or another,
venturesome or the reverse; and this perception and its defense they owe to psychology; but they
have not extended their examination to the origin, operation, or force of moods (and to force,
also, I return in a moment).
All sorts of well-controlled experiments in laboratory conditions have relevance to both
economics and history. An instance from our new millennium is the report by George
Loewenstein, to which Robert Shiller has drawn attention. Loewenstein extends the description
and analysis of the irrational in decision-making.5 In deliberating about a choice, we wonder how
it would feel? Affect is there, in the midst of our thinking; it helps to explain market behavior.
But the finding arises out of earlier work of other researchers of a much broader application,
showing cognition and emotion to be generally intertwined in our minds, not opposing poles of
the [page 22] whole range of mental activity. Psychologists and neurologists have observed how
a given perception is received and responded to, to avoid or to attack or whatever else we may
do; is marked at the instant with the corresponding sign or tag which is affective -- of disgust,
4
5
Works of the 1990s by Michael Bernsen, Werner Röcke, Frédéric Chavaud ….
Psychological Bulletin 127 (2001).
fear, happiness, concupiscence, curiosity, or nurturing along with the familiar bodily sensations
attending each -- and is so stored in memory; so that the whole cluster of experience which we
perceive as an emotion and a plan of action together is instantly retrievable under that sign, and
similar clusters with it. The way our memory works allows for the speed of response that may be
necessary. True, a great deal of problem-solving mental activity at the level of detail may on in
our heads with no emotion that we are conscious of; but what drives it all and leads to action is
of a different, richly colored quality -- that is, richly emotional. Consensus on these matters is
reflected in, for example, the study referred to above at n. 3.
And from these teachings historians even more than economists may well profit. A sort
of license or authority is given to those studying some individual, in biography, to consider
affective factors in operation; and in contrast it would be easy to instance this or that
unsatisfactory "life" in which the person described is followed only from one calculation to
another; never feels but only reasons; "never comes to life", as the reader will say.
As to the study of groups of people, whole societies, even nations, this is of course
another matter. Marc Bloch remarks on the emotionalism of the medieval world where "attacks
of despair or rage, wild outbursts, and sudden changes of heart present historians with a real
challenge, inclined as they are by instinct to reconstruct the past along lines of rationality;
ponderable elements in history though such phenomena always are, certainly, yet on the course
of political events in feudal Europe they had an effect which should not be passed over in
silence, out of some false sense of shame". 6
The passage draws attention to what others among his fellow-historians will still confess
to today, "shame" as Block puts it, meaning the expectation of disapproval, scorn, rejection at the
hands of their peers, for the crime of taking emotions seriously; shame that must be felt in any
mode of interpretation less than scientific, which it to say, less than quantifying. The overthrow
of the Age of Reason is not yet!
Nor can it go far unless emotionology, the study of fashions in feelings and social
constructs of one sort or another, takes account of consequences in behavior that may be called
political. Political change is after all what the layman thinks of as history, and Bloch was quite
right to indicate the centrality of that aspect of the past -- for all his devotion, and the devotion of
his school, to mentalities. Without force of feeling there is no action; without action, no change;
without change, in at least the traditional and the layman's sense of the term, there is no history.
Of force, different emotions by their nature have more or less; and the less tail off into
moods or more or less passive states of mind such as depression or contentment, lacking force
entirely. Differences can be imagined as lying along a bipolar scale, the extent of which can be
calibrated like familiar Richter scale for earthquakes, arbitrarily but not indefensibly. So
psychology here too has a teaching of importance for historians.
We may say, ruminating happily on the start of the day and its croissant and [page 23]
strong coffee, that we "love" breakfast; and a minute later, as the conversation shifts, that we
"love" our country. The latter but not the former love might lead us to do something. It
6
La société féodale; la formation des liens de dépendance, 1939 [1949], p. 118.
motivates. Marc Bloch in his last work did at points insist on the operation of broadly shared
impulses of "the heart", of "devotion" to "la patrie", of the ability "to thrill" to the national past
and its grandest chapters, above all those of the monarchy and the Republic. In that sense "there
are", he wrote, "two kinds of Frenchmen who will never understand France's history: those who
will not thrill at the recall of the rites of Rheims, and those who read without emotion an account
of the Festival of Federation". 7
He himself was not of these two kinds. So in the First World War he was wounded and
decorated, and chose to continue in the post-war reserves, and to come forward for service in the
next war, being then well into his 50s; and after his country's strange defeat, he chose again to
enlist in a war beneath the war, in which he met his death. The flow of decision-making which
led to action at these various junctures was all obedient to his heart. In and by him, so far as that
little thing, that thing called an individual, can make history, history was made by emotions that
had force.
Once this is said, the question to be put to historians is obvious: how can force be
measured and action in consequence explained?
The answer has been given, above: there are experiments to show the ability of one
person to divine the feelings of another from written accounts, or better still, from face-to-face
encounters. We can achieve, even across a gulf of time or customs, "psychological closeness, a
sort of transcultural identification with our subjects". The words are those of Clifford Geertz
invoking the operation of empathy, that stronger cousin of sympathy. 8 Empathy works. And we
need to make use of it; for without it -- without it, there can be no understanding of others, no
insight. The fact is long familiar in philosophy, therefore in German, as Geertz continues: "What
happens to Verstehen when Einfühlen disappears?"
In the first Age of Reason [over much of the last century], according to one set of
arguments, truth in Einfühlung was denied; in the second Age [exemplified in Homo
economicus], denied by another set. The learned teacher [Geertz], the academician, was sure -but no more than the layman was sure -- that the academician is an ass. For, in the ordinary
conduct of our quite ordinary lives, we are all conscious of reading each other by this power of
ours, constantly. Only recently has psychology come to the aid of common sense, with findings
of empathy in the behavior of the tiniest infants, blending into the same behavior in small
children of an age to speak and explain what is going on in their minds; and so to confirm in turn
the self-reporting by adults on which psychologists build so much of their science. To deny
ourselves the use of this power of understanding, if we are historians, would be asinine.
That it is in fact used by historians, not obedient to the present Age of Reason, can be
shown in a million good history books, of which Thucydides wrote one. None better, perhaps.
And here follows a passage from that author (7.69.2) where he conveys the feel of a moment of
great historical significance: the impending defeat of the Athenians in Sicily under their
commander Nicias:
7
Marc Bloch, L'étrange défaite. Témoignage écrit en 1940, [Paris] 1957, p. 210.
C. Geertz, "'From the native's point of view." On the nature of anthropological understanding,"
Bulletin of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 28 [Issue 1, Oct.] 1974, [p.] 28
8
[page 24] Nicias, driven almost out of his mind by the situation, and seeing
the real dangers and their imminence and how short a time before the setting
out, suffered the torments usual in major engagements. Everything to be done
by his forces was, he thought, still not ready; everything to be said had still
not been said enough. Once again he called on each trireme captain singly,
addressing them by their fathers' name, their given name and tribe, that they
should live up to whatever good fame each had won, and not bring to naught
ancestral virtues so marked in their forebears. He reminded them of their
fatherland, the freest ever, and of the unconstrained choices it afforded in
one's daily life; he added all those things that men in such situations as those
present will say, oblivious of what might be trite and usual, in similar terms,
for every cause: appeals to wives, children, and ancestral gods, which men
will shout out, in the consternation they feel, thinking them of some use.9
How did the author know the commander was "driven almost out of his mind"? Is
Thucydides' conjecture real history? The layman has no difficulty with an answer to that
question: any intelligent contemporary with the needed powers of empathy (which many
in fact would have) would feel no hesitation in declaring a knowledge of Nicias, an
Einfühlung even for the inner man, just as Thucydides did not hesitate to do. Nor should
we hesitate today. No problem! Let it be even in the language of philosophy, kein
Problem! Only the second Age of Reason stands in our way; and it is on the way out.
With it may disappear, in time at least, the more learned disposition to admire
Thucydides only for his complete, his pervasive and imagined, rationality, which
historians must imitate.
In a larger demonstration, it would be easy to show how willingly intuitive this
particular writer was. His ancient readers recognized this power or proclivity in him, as
did some readers of the last generation, against the consensus of the Age of Reason which
could see only the rationalist. Gradually the dawn breaks.
And it is not only in moments of high drama that Thucydides acknowledges the
play of emotions in the past. He is consistent in distinguishing between those that impel
men to step outside of themselves, outside the rut of their daily lives, to do those things
that deserve the historian's interest: things that account for change. Naturally, in a book
about a war involving hundreds of states and several distinct phases, such changes were
generally (but not solely) from peace to war. Anger and its variants, outrage and
indignation and the desire for revenge, are the urges to which he assigns the origins of
actions that count, at dozens of junctures; and ancient historians in general did so, too.10
Which is not to deny that subsequent action which obeys and effectuates major choices
may be calculating: in modern market-analytical terms, people count the costs (and
notice, "count", quantify).
9
Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War.
In the first chapter of my Feelings in History, Ancient and Modern (Fr. edn, Ramsay
MacMullen, Les sentiments dans l'histoire ancienne et moderne), 2003, I supply the findings for
this and for the rest of my essay here.
10
Acknowledgement of the role of feelings in making history, without ignoring
calculation, was common sense among those ancient writers. So, sometimes, for le grand
public and out of sight of the learned, history has been and always will be written. But
our own age would do well to free it from academic insistence on reason.
Ramsay MacMullen
Dunham Professor of History, emeritus, Yale University