Academia.eduAcademia.edu

Art Now Exists in the Condition of Philosophy

AI-generated Abstract

This paper explores the intricate relationship between art and philosophy, particularly focusing on the implications of aesthetic judgment as discussed by philosophers such as Stanley Cavell and Immanuel Kant. It examines the non-objective nature of aesthetic evaluations and their demand for universal assent, questioning whether the absence of consensus undermines their rationality. Additionally, the paper reflects on the personal and subjective experiences of aesthetic sensation, emphasizing its incommunicability and the introspective process required for meaningful judgments.

This art icle was downloaded by: [ David Rodowick] On: 15 April 2012, At : 11: 57 Publisher: Rout ledge I nform a Lt d Regist ered in England and Wales Regist ered Num ber: 1072954 Regist ered office: Mort im er House, 37- 41 Mort im er St reet , London W1T 3JH, UK Contemporary French and Francophone Studies Publicat ion det ails, including inst ruct ions f or aut hors and subscript ion inf ormat ion: ht t p: / / www. t andf online. com/ loi/ gsit 20 Questionnaire D. N. Rodowick Available online: 03 Apr 2012 To cite this article: D. N. Rodowick (2012): Quest ionnaire, Cont emporary French and Francophone St udies, 16: 2, 245-247 To link to this article: ht t p: / / dx. doi. org/ 10. 1080/ 17409292. 2012. 668818 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTI CLE Full t erm s and condit ions of use: ht t p: / / www.t andfonline.com / page/ t erm sand- condit ions This art icle m ay be used for research, t eaching, and privat e st udy purposes. Any subst ant ial or syst em at ic reproduct ion, redist ribut ion, reselling, loan, sublicensing, syst em at ic supply, or dist ribut ion in any form t o anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warrant y express or im plied or m ake any represent at ion t hat t he cont ent s will be com plet e or accurat e or up t o dat e. The accuracy of any inst ruct ions, form ulae, and drug doses should be independent ly verified wit h prim ary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, act ions, claim s, proceedings, dem and, or cost s or dam ages what soever or howsoever caused arising direct ly or indirect ly in connect ion wit h or arising out of t he use of t his m at erial. Contemporary French and Francophone Studies Vol. 16, No. 2, March 2012, 245–247 QUESTIONNAIRE Downloaded by [David Rodowick] at 11:57 15 April 2012 D. N. Rodowick Art now exists in the condition of philosophy In considering Lacoue-Labarthe’s provocative statement, I am reminded immediately of an even earlier assertion by Stanley Cavell: ‘‘Art now exists in the condition of philosophy’’ (1979, 14). Cavell is the one contemporary American philosopher who has systematically explored the tightly woven skein linking philosophy to art, literature, or cinema in ways similar to LacoueLabarthe, Jean-Luc Nancy, or Jacques Rancière. Moreover, the ethical turn in philosophy and literature or art in France is anticipated by many decades by Cavell’s work, especially as represented in Must We Mean What We Say? and The Claim of Reason. In the early period of his published work, one of Cavell’s main concerns is to restore the claim of reason to aesthetic and ethical judgments, and also to assert the force of literature, art, and cinema as philosophical texts. One of Cavell’s most original strategies is to revisit Kant’s examination of the paradoxical quality of aesthetic conversation in The Critique of Judgment (also a touchstone for many French philosophers): that it requires a disinterested and subjective assessment, as if a conversation of self with self, that is both perceptual and affective (Derrida calls this autoaffection), which in turn desires or claims universal assent from all others within range of its hearing. The question can be put another way: Does the absence of universal agreement in aesthetic judgments demonstrate their lack of rationality, or alternatively, do they convey another picture of rationality? One of Kant’s first steps in the Critique of Judgment is to observe that because aesthetic judgments are grounded entirely in the subjective, they can be neither objective, logical, nor theoretical. The non-theoretical character of aesthetic judgments has a precise sense here: such judgments are singular and thus ISSN 1740-9292 (print)/ISSN 1740-9306 (online)/12/020245–3 ß 2012 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17409292.2012.668818 Downloaded by [David Rodowick] at 11:57 15 April 2012 246 CONTEMPORARY FRENCH AND FRANCOPHONE STUDIES not generalizable, and in addition are unmediated by concepts. Aesthetic judgments also have the peculiar character of asking for universal assent, even if we know that it cannot and will not be granted, at least universally. Does this mean that aesthetic judgments are irrational since we cannot hope for universal consensus and thus risk isolation and ridicule in making them? And what to make of Kant’s assertion that aesthetic judgments are without concept, which is a scandal from the point of view of many currents of contemporary philosophy? At the same time, Cavell takes Kant at his philosophical word but without wishing to dissolve the paradox. For this paradox may be expressive of another power of great value—the nature of aesthetic judgments is to be open to interpretation, that is, arguable, discussable, or provoking discussion, as if to say that the capacity for disagreement is also the capacity for conversation and sociability. And there is another paradox to confront in our ordinary practices of expressing aesthetic judgments. One of Wittgenstein’s most important and difficult lessons is that at some point reasons are exhaustible. (Recall §217 of the Philosophical Investigations where Wittgenstein states: ‘‘If I have exhausted the justifications I have reached the bedrock, and my spade is turned. Then I am inclined to say: ‘This is simply what I do.’’’) Or to put it another way, there will be moments when speech loses it force; hence Wittgenstein’s frequent appeals to look and to see, which might be an appeal to the other to find their own Idea and own concept or context, since mine seems to be at some point incommunicable. ‘‘It matters that others know what I see,’’ Cavell writes in ‘‘Music Discomposed,’’ in a way it does not matter they know my tastes. It matters, there is a burden, because I can tell what I know, there is a suggestion (and to myself as well) that I do not know. But I do—what I see is that (pointing to the object). But for that to communicate, you have to see it too. Describing one’s experience of art is itself a form of art; the burden of describing it is like the burden of producing it. Art is often praised because it brings men together. But it also separates them. (2002, 193) Literature, and indeed all forms of art, has a power of ethical questioning commensurate with philosophy’s own—it confronts us as an Other who demands that we investigate and perhaps change our mode of existence. Respecting the autonomy of a work of art—its separate and perhaps unknowable and uncertain existence before you—means allowing yourself to be questioned, interrogated, or investigated by it, to be open to it in ways that allow an interpretation in which you yourself, reader, are subject to criticism and change. In any case, one of the great powers of aesthetic sensation is that it is incommunicable. Or rather, every effort to convey such sensations to others rebounds to the subject himself who, in face of the doubts and uncertainties of QUESTIONNAIRE his interlocutors, including the work itself, must reflexively discover the depth of her conviction and the clarity of her criteria for judgment. Works Cited Downloaded by [David Rodowick] at 11:57 15 April 2012 Cavell, Stanley. ‘‘Music Discomposed.’’ Must We Mean What We Say? Cambridge: Cambridge U P, 2002. —. The World Viewed: Reflections on the Ontology of Film. Cambridge, MA: Harvard U P, 1979. D. N. Rodowick is at Harvard University. His research interests include aesthetics and the philosophy of art, the history of film theory, philosophical approaches to contemporary art and culture, and the impact of new technologies on contemporary society. He is the author of numerous essays as well as five books: The Virtual Life of Film (2007); Reading the Figural, or, Philosophy after the New Media (2001); Gilles Deleuze’s Time Machine (1997); The Difficulty of Difference: Psychoanalysis, Sexual Difference, and Film Theory (1991); and The Crisis of Political Modernism: Criticism and Ideology in Contemporary Film Theory (1989 and 1994). His edited collection, Afterimages of Gilles Deleuze’s Film Philosophy, was published by in 2009, and his essay, ‘‘An Elegy for Theory,’’ received the Katherine Singer Kovacs Essay Award from the Society for Cinema and Media Studies in 2009. 247