HANDBOUND
AT THE
UNIVERSITY OF
TORONTO
HOME UNIVERSITY LIBRARY
OF MODERN KNOWLEDGE
No. 15
Editors:
THE
RT. HON. H. A. L. FISHER,
M.A., F.B.A.
PROF. GILBERT MURRAY, LiTT.D.,
LL.D., F.B.A.
PROF. SIR J.
THOMSON,
ARTHUR
M.A.
PROF.
WILLIAM
M.A.
T.
BREWSTER,
A
complete classified
list
of the volumes of
HOME UNIVERSITY LIBRARY
THE
already published
will be found at the back of this book.
INTRODUCTION
TO MATHEMATICS
BY
A. N.
WHITEHEAD
Sc.D., F.R.S.
AUTHOR OF
"UNIVERSAL
ALGEBRA**
NEW YORK
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
LONDON
THORNTON BUTTERWORTH
COPYRIGHT,
1911,
BT
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
Q
Pi
W5
u
t/.
THE UNIVERSITY
5. A.
PRESS, CAMBRIDGE, U.S.A.
CONTENTS
PAGE
CHAP.
I
II
III
THE ABSTRACT NATURE OF MATHEMATICS
VARIABLES
.
.
7
15
METHODS OF APPLICATION
25
IV DYNAMICS
V THE SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
VI GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBER
42
58
71
VII
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
VII
IMAGINARY NUMBERS (CONTINUED)
CO-ORDINATE GEOMETRY
112
CONIC SECTIONS
128
IX
X
XI
XII
FUNCTIONS
145
PERIODICITY IN NATURE
164
XIII
TRIGONOMETRY
XIV
SERIES
XV
173
:
THE DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
XVI GEOMETRY
XVII
87
101
.
217
236
245
QUANTITY
NOTE ON BOOKS
INDEX
194
.
251
.
353
AN INTRODUCTION TO
MATHEMATICS
CHAPTER
I
THE ABSTRACT NATURE OF MATHEMATICS
THE
study of mathematics is apt to com
The important
in disappointment.
applications of the science, the theoretical
interest of its ideas, and the logical rigour of
its methods, all generate the expectation of
a speedy introduction to processes of interest.
We are told that by its aid the stars are
weighed and the billions of molecules in a
drop of water are counted. Yet, like the
ghost of Hamlet s father, this great science
eludes the efforts of our mental weapons
Tis here,
tis
tis
to grasp it
there,
and what we do see does not suggest
gone"
the same excuse for illusiveness as sufficed
for the ghost, that it is too noble for our
show of violence," if
gross methods.
ever excusable, may surely be "offered"
to the trivial results which occupy the
mence
"
"A
7
8
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
pages
of
some
elementary
mathematical
treatises.
The reason
for this failure of the science to
reputation is that its funda
mental ideas are not explained to the student
disentangled from the technical procedure
which has been invented to facilitate their
live
up to
its
exact presentation in particular instances.
Accordingly, the unfortunate learner finds
himself struggling to acquire a knowledge of
a mass of details which are not illuminated
Without a
by any general conception.
doubt, technical facility is a first requisite
for valuable mental activity: we shall fail
to appreciate the rhythm of Milton, or the
passion of Shelley, so long as we find it nec
essary to spell the words and are not quite
certain of the forms of the individual letters.
In this sense there is no royal road to learn
But it is equally an error to confine
attention to technical processes, excluding
consideration of general ideas.
Here lies
the road to pedantry.
The object of the following chapters is not
to teach mathematics, but to enable students
from the very beginning of their course to
know what the science is about, and why it is
necessarily the foundation of exact thought
as applied to natural phenomena. All allu
sion in what follows to detailed deductions
in any part of the science will be inserted
ing.
NATURE OF MATHEMATICS
9
merely for the purpose of example, and care
will be taken to make the general argument
comprehensible, even if here and there some
technical process or symbol which the reader
does not understand is cited for the purpose
of illustration.
The first acquaintance which most people
have with mathematics is through arithmetic.
That two and two make four is usually taken
as the type of a simple mathematical pro
position which everyone will have heard of.
Arithmetic, therefore, will be a good subject
to consider in order to discover, if possible,
the most obvious characteristic of the science.
Now, thejjrst noticeable fact about arith
metic is that it applies to everything, to
tastes and to sounds, to apples and to angels,
to the ideas of the mind and to the bones of
the body. The nature of the things is per
fectly indifferent, of all things it is true that
two and two make four. Thus we write
down as the leading characteristic of mathe
matics that it deals with properties and
ideas which are applicable to things just be
cause they are things, and apart from any
particular feelings, or emotions, or sensa
tions, in any way connected with them.
This is what is meant by calling mathe
matics an abstract science.
The result which we have reached deserves
It is natural to think that an
attention.
10
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
abstract science cannot be of much import
ance in the affairs of human life, because it
has omitted from its consideration every
thing of real interest. It will be remembered
that Swift, in his description of Gulliver s
voyage to Laputa,
is
of
two minds on
this
He
describes the mathematicians of
that country as silly and useless dreamers,
whose attention has to be awakened by
point.
Also, the mathematical tailor
measures his height by a quadrant, and de
duces his other dimensions by a rule and
compasses, producing a suit of very illOn the other hand, the
fitting clothes.
mathematicians of Laputa, by their marvel
lous invention of the magnetic island floating
in the air, ruled the country and maintained
their ascendency over their subjects. Swift,
indeed, lived at a time peculiarly unsuited
for gibes at contemporary mathematicians.
Newton s Principia had just been written,
one of the great forces which have trans
formed the modern world. Swift might just
as well have laughed at an earthquake.
But a mere list of the achievements of
mathematics is an unsatisfactory way of
flappers.
an idea of its importance. It
worth while to spend a little thought in
getting at the root reason why mathematics,
because of its very abstractness, must always
remain one of the most important topics
arriving at
is
NATURE OF MATHEMATICS
11
Let us try to make clear
thought.
to ourselves why explanations of the order
events necessarily tend to become
of
for
mathematical.
Consider how all events are interconnected.
When we see the lightning, we listen for the
thunder; when we hear the wind, we look
for the waves on the sea; in the chill autumn,
the leaves fall. Everywhere order reigns, so
that when some circumstances have been
noted we can foresee that others will also be
The
progress of science consists in
these
mterconnecfions and in show
observing
ing with a patient ingenuity that the events
of this evershifting world are but examples of
a few general connections or relations called
laws. To see :what is general in what is parpresent.
ticular
and whaLJs permanent
in
what
is
transitory is the aim of scientific thought. In
the eye of science, the fall of an apple, the
of a planet round a sun, and the cling
ing of the atmosphere to the earth are all
seen as examples of the law of gravity. This
possibility of disentangling the most complex
evanescent circumstances into various exam
ples of permanent laws is the controlling idea
motion
of
modern thought.
Now
us think of the sort of laws which
in order completely to realize this
scientific ideal.
Our knowledge of the par
ticular facts of the world around us is gained
let
we want
12
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
from our sensations. We see, and hear, and
and smell, and feel hot and cold, and
and
rub, and ache, and tingle. These
push,
taste,
are just our own personal sensations: my
toothache cannot be your toothache, and my
sight cannot be your sight. Butwe ascribe
the origin of these sensations to relations" be
tween the things which form the external
Thus the dentist extracts not the
world.
toothache but the tooth. And not only so,
we also endeavour to imagine the world as
one connected set of things which underlies
all the perceptions of all people. There is not
one world of things for my sensations and an
other for yours, but one world in which we
both exist. It is the same tooth both for
dentist and patient.
Also we hear and we
touch the same world as we see.
It is easy, therefore, to understand that
we want to describe the connections between
these external things in
some way which
does not depend on any particular sensa
tions, nor even on all the sensations of any
particular person. The laws satisfied by the
course of events in the world of external
things are to be described, if possible, in a
neutral universal fashion, the same for blind
men as for deaf men, and the same for beings
with faculties beyond our ken as for normal
human
beings.
But when we have put
aside our immediate
NATURE OF MATHEMATICS
13
sensations, the most serviceable part from
its clearness, definiteness, and universality
of what is left is composed of our general
ideas of the abstract formal properties of
things; in fact, the abstract mathematical
ideas mentioned above. Thus it comes about
that, step by step, and not realizing the full
meaning of the process, mankind has been
led to search for a mathematical description
of the properties of the universe, because in
this way only can a general idea of the course
of events be formed, freed from reference to
particular persons or to particular types of
For example, it might be asked
sensation.
at dinner: "What was it which underlay my
sensation of sight, yours of touch, and his of
taste and smell?" the answer being "an
But in its final analysis, science
apple."
seeks to describe an apple in terms of the
and motions of molecules, a de
which ignores me and you and
him, and also ignores sight and touch and
taste and smell. Thus mathematical ideas,
because they are abstract, supply just what
is wanted for a scientific description of the
positions
scription
course of events.
This point has usually been misunderstood,
from being thought of in too narrow a way.
Pythagoras had a glimpse of it when he pro
claimed that number was the source of all
things. In modern times the belief that the
14
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
ultimate explanation of
all
things was to
be found in Newtonian mechanics was an
adumbration of the truth that all science as
it grows towards perfection becomes mathe
matical in
its ideas.
CHAPTER
II
VARIABLES
MATHEMATICS as a science commenced
when first someone, probably a Greek, proved
propositions about any things or about some
things, without specification of definite par
ticular things. These propositions were first
enunciated by the Greeks for geometry;
geometry was the great
Greek mathematical science. After the rise
of geometry centuries passed away before
and, accordingly,
made a really effective start, despite
faint anticipations by the later Greek
algebra
some
mathematicians
.
The
ideas of any and of some are intro
duced into algebra by the use of letters, in
stead of the definite numbers of arithmetic.
Thus, instead of saying that 2+3=3+2, in
algebra we generalize and say that, if x and y
stand for any two numbers, then x+y = y+x.
2, we
Again, in the place of saying that 3
generalize and say that if x be any number
there exists some number (or numbers) y
such that y
x. We may remark in passing
that this latter assumption for when put in
its strict ultimate form it is an assumption
>
>
15
16
is
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
of vital importance, both to philosophy
for by it the notion of
and to mathematics;
is introduced.
Perhaps it required
the introduction of the arabic numerals, by
which the use of letters as standing for defi
nite numbers has been completely discarded
in mathematics, in order to suggest to mathe
maticians the technical convenience of the
use of letters for the ideas of any number
infinity
and some number.
The Romans would have
stated the number of the year in which this
is written in the form
whereas
we write it 1910, thus leaving the letters for
the other usage. But this is merely a specu
After the rise of algebra the differ
lation.
ential calculus was invented by Newton and
Leibniz, and then a pause in the progress
of the philosophy of mathematical thought
occurred so far as these notions are con
cerned; and it was not till within the last
few years that it has been realized how fun
damental any and some are to the very
nature of mathematics, with the result of
opening out still further subjects for mathe
matical exploration.
Let us now make some simple algebraic
statements, with the object of understanding
exactly how these fundamental ideas occur.
MDCCCCX,
(1)
(2)
(3)
For any number x, x+%=%+x;
For some number x, x +2 =3;
3.
For some number x, x+%
>
VARIABLES
17
The first point to notice is the possibilities
contained in the meaning of some, as here
used. Since x -f-2 = 2 + x for any number x,
it is true for some number x.
Thus, as here
exclude
does
not
some
used,
any. Again, in
the second example, there is, in fact, only one
number x, such that x +2 = 3, namely, only
the number 1. Thus the some may be one
number only. But in the third example,
any number x which is greater than 1 gives
3.
Hence there are an infinite num
ber of numbers which answer to the some
number in this case. Thus some may be
anything between any and one only, includ
x +2
>
ing both these limiting cases.
It is natural to supersede the statements
(2) and (3) by the questions:
For what number x is x +2 =3;
For what numbers x is x +2
3.
x
=3
is
an
+2
Considering (2 ),
equation, and
(2
(3
it is
)
)
easy to see that
When we
>
its
solution
is
#=3
2
= 1.
have asked the question implied in
the statement of the equation #4-2=3, x is
called the unknown. The object of the solu
tion of the equation is the determination of
the unknown. Equations are of great im
portance in mathematics, and it seems as
though (2 ) exemplified a much more thor
ough-going and fundamental idea than the
original statement (2).
This, however, is a
mistake.
The
idea
of the undetercomplete
18
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
mined
"variable"
as occurring in the use of
is the really important
one in mathematics; that of the "unknown"
in an equation, which is to be solved as
"some"
or
"any"
quickly as possible, is only of subordinate
use, though of course it is very important.
One of the causes of the apparent triviality
of much of elementary algebra is the pre
occupation of the text-books with the solu
tion of equations. The same remark applies
to the solution of the inequality (3 ) as com
pared to the original statement (3).
But the majority of interesting formulae,
especially when the idea of some is present,
For ex
involve more than one variable.
the
consideration
of
the
pairs of num
ample,
bers x and y (fractional or integral) which
= 1 involves the idea of two cor
satisfy x +y
related variables, x and y. When two varia
bles are present the same two main types
For example, (1) for
of statement occur.
any pair of numbers, x and y, x+y=y-\-x,
and (2) for some pairs of numbers, x and y,
The second type of statement invites con
sideration of the aggregate of pairs of num
bers which are bound together by some fixed
relation in the case given, by the relation
x+y l. One use of formulae of the first
type, true for any pair of numbers, is that by
them formulae of the second type can be
VARIABLES
thrown into
lent forms.
=1
is
19
an indefinite number of equiva
For example, the relation x+y
equivalent to the relations
and so on. Thus a skilful mathematician
uses that equivalent form of the relation
under consideration which is most conve
nient for his immediate purpose.
It is not in general true that, when a pair
of terms satisfy some fixed relation, if one of
the terms is given the other is also definitely
For example, when x and y
determined.
2
=
4, y can be =*=2, thus,
satisfy y =x, if x
for any positive value of x there are alter
Also in the relation
native values for y.
1, when either x or y is given, an
x-\-y
indefinite number of values remain open for
>
the other.
Again there
is another important point to
be noticed. If we restrict ourselves to posi
tive numbers, integral or fractional, in con
sidering the relation x-\-y = l, then, if either
y be greater than 1, there is no positive
number which the other can assume so as
to satisfy the relation. Thus the "field" of
the relation for x is restricted to numbers less
than 1, and similarly for the "field" open
to y. Again, consider integral numbers only,
positive or negative, and take the relation
x or
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
20
2
pairs of such numbers.
integral value is given to y,
x can assume one corresponding integral
value.
So the "field" for y is unrestricted
among these positive or negative integers.
But the "field" for x is restricted in two
y =x,
satisfied
by
Then whatever
In the first place x must be positive,
in the second place, since y is to be in
tegral, x must be a perfect square. Accord
ingly, the "field" of x is restricted to the set
of integers I 2 , 2 2 , 3 2 , 4 2 , and so on, i.e., to 1,
4, 9, 16, and so on.
The study of the general properties of a
relation between pairs of numbers is much
facilitated by the use of a diagram constructed
ways.
and
as follows:
X
M
I
A
X
Fig. 1.
OX and OF at right angles;
any number x be represented by x units
Draw two lines
let
VARIABLES
scale) of length along
(in
any
ber
ybyy
units (in
21
OX, any num
any scale) of length along
be x units in
OF. Thus if OM, along
9
length, and ON, along OF, be y units in
OX
completing the parallelogram
a point P which corresponds
to the pair of numbers x and y. To each
point there corresponds one pair of numbers,
and to each pair of numbers there corre
sponds one point. The pair of numbers are
called the coordinates of the point.
Then
the points whose coordinates satisfy some
fixed relation can be indicated in a conve
nient way, by drawing a line, if they all lie
on a line, or by shading an area if they are
all points in the area.
If the relation can
be represented by an equation such as
x+y l, or y2 =x, then the points lie on a
line, which is straight in the former case and
curved in the latter. For example, consider
ing only positive numbers, the points whose
coordinates satisfy x +y = 1 lie on the straight
length,
by
OMPN we find
line
AB
Thus
where OA = 1 and OB = 1.
segment of the straight line AB
in Fig. 1,
this
gives a pictorial representation of the proper
ties of the relation under the restriction to
positive numbers.
Another example of a relation between two
variables is afforded by considering the varia
tions in the pressure and volume of a given
mass of some gaseous substance such as air
22
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
or coal-gas or steam
Let v be the
at a constant tempera
of cubic feet in
its volume and p its pressure in Ib. weight
per square inch. Then the law, known as
Boyle s law, expressing the relation between
p and v as both vary, is that the product
ture.
number
pv is constant, always supposing that the
temperature does not alter. Let us suppose,
for example, that the quantity of the gas
and its other circumstances are such that
we can put pv = \ (the exact number on the
right-hand side of the equation makes no
essential difference).
Then in Fig. 2 we take two lines, 0V and
OP, at right angles and draw OM along 0V
to represent v units of volume, and ON along
VARIABLES
23
OP to represent p units of pressure. Then
the point Q, which is found by completing the
parallelogram MONQ, represents the state of
the gas when its volume is v cubic feet and its
pressure is p Ib. weight per square inch. If
the circumstances of the portion of gas con
sidered are such that pv = I, then all these
points Q which correspond to any possible
state of this portion of gas must lie on the
curved line ABC, which includes all points
for which p and v are positive, and jw = l.
Thus this curved line gives a pictorial repre
sentation of the relation holding between the
volume and the pressure. When the pressure
is very big the corresponding point Q must
be near C, or even beyond C on the undrawn
part of the curve; then the volume will be
very small. When the volume is big Q will
be near to A, or beyond A; and then the
pressure will be small. Notice that an en
gineer or a physicist may want to know the
particular pressure corresponding to some
Then we have
definitely assigned volume.
the case of determining the unknown p when
v is a known number.
But this is only in
In considering generally
particular cases.
the properties of the gas and how it will be
have, he has to have in his mind the general
form of the whole curve
and its general
In
other
words
the
properties.
really funda
mental idea is that of the pair of variables
ABC
24
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
satisfying the relation pv = l. This example
how the idea of variables is funda
mental, both in the applications as well as in
the theory of mathematics.
illustrates
CHAPTER
III
METHODS OF APPLICATION
THE way in which the idea of variables
satisfying a relation occurs in the applica
tions of mathematics is worth thought, and
by devoting some time to it we shall clear
up our thoughts on the whole
subject.
Let us start with the simplest of examples:
Suppose that building costs Is. per cubic
1.
Then in all
foot and that 20s. make
the complex circumstances which attend the
building of a new house, amid all the various
sensations and emotions of the owner, the
architect, the builder, the workmen, and the
onlookers as the house has grown to comple
tion, this fixed correlation is by the law
assumed to hold between the cubic content
and the cost to the owner, namely that if x
be the number of cubic feet, and y the cost,
then %Qy=x. This correlation of x and y is
assumed to be true for the building of any
house by any owner. Also, the volume of
the house and the cost are not supposed to
have been perceived or apprehended by any
particular sensation or faculty, or by any
25
26
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
particular man. They are stated in an ab
stract general way, with complete indiffer
ence to the owner s state of mind when he
has to pay the bill.
Now think a bit further as to what all this
The
building of a house is a com
circumstances.
It is im
plicated
possible to begin to apply the law, or to test
it, unless amid the general course of events
it is possible to recognize a definite set of
occurrences as forming a particular instance
of the building of a house. In short, we must
means.
set
of
know a house when we
see
it,
and must
events which belong to its
Then
amidst these events, thus
building.
isolated in idea from the rest of nature, the
two elements of the cost and cubic content
must be determinable; and when they are
both determined, if the law be true, they
satisfy the general formula
recognize the
the law true? Anyone who has had
to do with building will know that we
have here put the cost rather high. It is
only for an expensive type of house that it
will work out at this price. This brings out
But
is
much
another point which must be made clear.
While we are making mathematical calcula
tions connected with the formula %Qy = x, it
is indifferent to us whether the law be true or
METHODS OF APPLICATION
27
In fact, the very meanings assigned
and y, as being a number of cubic feet
and a number of pounds sterling, are in
different. During the mathematical investi
false.
to x
gation we are, in fact, merely considering the
properties of this correlation between a pair
of variable numbers x and y.
Our results
will apply equally well, if we interpret y to
mean a number of fishermen and x the num
ber of fish caught, so that the assumed law
is that on the average each fisherman catches
The mathematical certainty of
fish.
the investigation only attaches to the results
considered as giving properties of the corre
lation %Qy=x between the variable pair of
twenty
numbers x and
y.
There
is
no mathematical
certainty whatever about the cost of the
actual building of any house. The law is not
quite true and the result it gives will not be
quite accurate. In fact, it may well be hope
lessly
wrong.
Now
all this no doubt seems very obvious.
in truth with more complicated instances
there is no more common error than to assume
But
that, because prolonged and accurate mathe
matical calculations have been made, the
application of the result to some fact of
nature is absolutely certain. The conclusion
of no argument can be more certain than the
assumptions from which it starts. All mathe
matical calculations about the course of
28
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
nature must start from some assumed law of
nature, such, for instance, as the assumed
law of the cost of building stated above.
Accordingly, however accurately we have
calculated that some event must occur, the
doubt always remains Is the law true? If
the law states a precise result, almost cer
tainly it is not precisely accurate; and thus
even at the best the result, precisely as calcu
But then we
lated, is not likely to occur.
have no faculty capable of observation with
ideal precision, so, after all, our inaccurate
laws may be good enough.
We will now turn to an actual case, that
This law
of Newton and the Law of Gravity.
states that any two bodies attract one an
other with a force proportional to the product
of their masses, and inversely proportional to
the square of the distance between them.
are the masses of the two
and
Thus if
bodies, reckoned in Ibs. say, and d miles is
the distance between them, the force on either
body, due to the attraction of the other and
m
M
H/f
directed towards
it, is
proportional to
-J2~
thus this force can be written as equal to
=
a2
,
where k
is
a definite number depending
on the absolute magnitude of this attraction
and also on the scale by which we choose to
measure forces. It is easy to see that, if we
METHODS OF APPLICATION
29
wish to reckon in terms of forces such as the
weight of a mass of 1 lb., the number which
k represents must be extremely small; for
and d are each put equal to
when m and
M
1,
~
a
becomes the gravitational attraction
of two equal masses of 1 lb. at the distance of
one mile, and this is quite inappreciable.
However, we have now got our formula for
the force of attraction.
F,
it is
F=
k-p-,
we
call this force
giving the correlation be
tween the variables F,
know
If
ra,
how
M, and
d.
We
all
was found out.
Newton, it states, was sitting in an orchard
and watched the fall of an apple, and then
the law of universal gravitation burst upon
It may be that the final formu
his mind.
lation of the law occurred to him in an
orchard, as well as elsewhere and he must
have been somewhere. But for our purposes
it is more instructive to dwell upon the vast
amount of preparatory thought, the product
of many minds and many centuries, which
was necessary before this exact law could be
formulated. In the first place, the mathe
matical habit of mind and the mathematical
procedure explained in the previous two
chapters had to be generated; otherwise
Newton could never have thought of a for
mula representing the force between any two
the story of
it
30
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
masses at any distance. Again, what are the
meanings of the terms employed, Force, Mass,
Distance? Take the easiest of these terms,
Distance. It seems very obvious to us to
conceive all material things as forming a
definite geometrical whole, such that the dis
tances of the various parts are measurable in
terms of some unit length, such as a mile or
a yard. This is almost the first aspect of a
material structure which occurs to us. It is
the gradual outcome of the study of geometry
and of the theory of measurement. Even
now, in certain cases, other modes of thought
are convenient. In a mountainous country
distances are often reckoned in hours. But
leaving distance, the other terms, Force and
Mass, are much more obscure. The exact
comprehension of the ideas which Newton
meant to convey by these words was of slow
growth, and, indeed, Newton himself was the
man who had thoroughly mastered the
first
true general principles of Dynamics.
Throughout the middle ages, under the in
fluence of Aristotle, the science was entirely
misconceived. Newton had the advantage of
after a series of great men, notably
Galileo, in Italy, who in the previous two
centuries had reconstructed the science and
had invented the right way of thinking about
He completed their work. Then, finally,
it.
having the ideas of force, mass, and distance
coming
METHODS OF APPLICATION
31
clear and distinct in his mind, and realizing
their importance and their relevance to the
fall of an apple and the motions of the planets,
he hit upon the law of gravitation and proved
it to be the formula always satisfied in these
various motions.
The vital point in the application of mathe
matical formulae is to have clear ideas and a
correct estimate of their relevance to the
phenomena under observation. No less than
ourselves, our remote ancestors were im
pressed with the importance of natural
phenomena and with the desirability of taking
energetic measures to regulate the sequence
of events. Under the influence of irrelevant
ideas they executed elaborate religious cere
monies to aid the birth of the new moon, and
performed sacrifices to save the sun during
the crisis of an eclipse. There is no reason to
believe that they were more stupid than we
are.
But at that epoch there had not been
opportunity for the slow accumulation of
clear and relevant ideas.
The
grow
sort of way in which physical sciences
into a form capable of treatment by
mathematical methods
is
illustrated
by the
history of the gradual growth of the science
of electromagnetism.
Thunderstorms are
events on a grand scale, arousing terror in
men and even animals. From the earliest
times they must have been objects of wild
m
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
and fantastic hypotheses, though it may be
doubted whether our modern scientific dis
coveries in connection with electricity are not
more astonishing than any of the magical
explanations of savages. The Greeks knew
that amber (Greek, electron) when rubbed
In
would attract light and dry bodies.
1600
the
A.D.,
first
scientific
Dr. Gilbert, of Colchester, published
work on the subject
method is followed.
in
which any
a
He made
list of substances possessing properties similar
to those of amber; he must also have the
credit of connecting, however vaguely, electric
and magnetic phenomena. At the end of the
seventeenth and throughout the eighteenth
Electrical
century knowledge advanced.
machines were made, sparks were obtained
from them; and the Leyden Jar was in
vented, by which these effects could be in
tensified.
Some organized knowledge was
but still no relevent mathe
obtained;
being
matical ideas had been found out. Franklin,
in the year 1752, sent a kite into the clouds
and proved that thunderstorms were elec
trical.
Meanwhile from the
earliest
epoch (2634
B. c.) the Chinese had utilized the characteristic
property of the compass needle, but do not
seem to have connected it with any theoretical
ideas. The really profound changes in human
life all have their ultimate origin in knowledge
METHODS OF APPLICATION
33
pursued for its own sake. The use of the com
pass was not introduced into Europe till the
end of the twelfth century A.D., more than
3000 years after its first use in China. The
importance which the science of electromagnetism has since assumed in every department
of human life is not due to the superior prac
tical bias of Europeans, but to the fact that
in the West electrical and magnetic phe
nomena were studied by men who were dom
inated by abstract theoretic interests.
The discovery of the electric current is due
to two Italians, Galvani in 1780, and Volta
in 1792. This great invention opened a new
phenomena for investigation. The
world had now three separate,
though allied, groups of occurrences on hand
series of
scientific
the effects of
"statical"
electricity
aris
ing from frictional electrical machines, the
magnetic phenomena, and the effects due
From the end of the
to electric currents.
eighteenth century onwards, these three lines
of investigation were quickly inter-connected
and the modern science of electromagnetism
was constructed, which now threatens to
transform
human
life.
Mathematical ideas now appear. During
the decade 1780 to 1789, Coulomb, a French
man, proved that magnetic poles attract or
repel each other, in proportion to the inverse
square of their distances, and also that the
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
34
same law holds
electric charges
laws
of
to
that
curiously analogous
gravitation.
In 1820, Oersted, a Dane, discovered that
electric currents exert a force on magnets,
and almost immediately afterwards the
mathematical law of the force was correctly
for
formulated by Ampere, a Frenchman, who
also proved that two electric currents exerted
forces on each other. "The experimental in
vestigation by which Ampere established the
law of the mechanical action between electric
currents is one of the most brilliant achieve
ments in science. The whole, theory and
experiment, seems as if it had leaped, fullgrown and full armed, from the brain of
It is perfect
the Newton of Electricity.
in form, and unassailable in accuracy, and it
is summed up in a formula from which all
the phenomena may be deduced, and which
must always remain the cardinal formula of
*
*
electro-dynamics."
The momentous laws of induction between
currents and between currents and magnets
were discovered by Michael Faraday in 183132.
Faraday was asked: "What is the use
He answered: "What is
discovery?"
the use of a child it grows to be a man."
Faraday s child has grown to be a man and
is now the basis of all the modern applications
of this
*
Electricity
and Magnetism, Clerk Maxwell. Vol.
II., ch.
iii.
METHODS OF APPLICATION
35
of electricity. Faraday also reorganized the
whole theoretical conception of the science.
His ideas, which had not been fully under
stood by the scientific world, were extended
and put into a directly mathematical form by
Clerk Maxwell in 1873. As a result of his
mathematical investigations, Maxwell recog
nized that, under certain conditions, electrical
vibrations ought to be propagated. He at
once suggested that the vibrations which
form light are electrical. This suggestion has
since been verified, so that now the whole
theory of light is nothing but a branch of the
Also Herz, a
great science of electricity.
German, in 1888, following on Maxwell s
ideas, succeeded in producing electric vibra
tions by direct electrical methods.
His
experiments are the basis of our wireless
telegraphy.
In more recent years even more funda
mental discoveries have been made, and the
science continues to grow in theoretic import
ance and in practical interest. This rapid
sketch of its progress illustrates how, by the
gradual introduction of the relevant theoretic
ideas, suggested by experiment and them
selves suggesting fresh experiments, a whole
mass
of isolated
and even
trivial
phenomena
are welded together into one coherent science,
in which the results of abstract mathematical
deductions, starting from a few simple as-
36
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
sumed
laws, supply the explanation to the
complex tangle of the course of events.
Finally, passing beyond the particular
sciences of electromagnetism and light, we
can generalize our point of view still further,
and direct our attention to the growth of
mathematical physics considered as one great
In the first
chapter of scientific thought.
in
what
the
barest
outlines
is the story
place,
of its growth?
It did not begin as one science, or as the
product of one band of men. The Chaldean
shepherds watched the skies, the agents of
Government in Mesopotamia and Egypt
measured the land, priests and philosophers
brooded on the general nature of all things.
The vast mass of the operations of nature
appeared due to mysterious unfathomable
forces. "The wind bloweth where it listeth"
expresses accurately the blank ignorance then
existing of any stable rules followed in detail
by the succession of phenomena. In broad out
line, then as now, a regularity of events was
patent. But no minute tracing of their inter
connection was possible, and there was no
knowledge how even to set about to construct
such a science.
Detached speculations, a few happy or un
happy shots at the nature of things, formed
the utmost which could be produced.
Meanwhile land-surveys had produced ge-
METHODS OF APPLICATION
37
ometry, and the observations of the heavens
disclosed the exact regularity of the solar
system. Some of the later Greeks, such as
Archimedes, had just views on the elementary
phenomena of hydrostatics and optics. In
deed, Archimedes, who combined a genius for
mathematics with a physical insight, must
rank with Newton, who lived nearly two
thousand years later, as one of the founders
of mathematical physics. He lived at Syra
cuse, the great
Greek
city of Sicily.
When
Romans
besieged the town (in 210 to
212 B.C.), he is said to have burned their ships
by concentrating on them, by means of
mirrors, the sun s rays. The story is highly
improbable, but is good evidence of the repu
tation which he had gained among his con
temporaries for his knowledge of optics. At
the end of this siege he was killed. According
to one account given to Plutarch, in his life of
Marcellus, he was found by a Roman soldier
absorbed in the study of a geometrical dia
gram which he had traced on the sandy floor
of his room. He did not immediately obey
the orders of his captor, and so was killed.
For the credit of the Roman generals it must
be said that the soldiers had orders to spare
him. The internal evidence for the other
famous story of him is very strong; for the
discovery attributed to him is one eminently
the
worthy
of his genius for
mathematical and
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
38
physical
research.
Luckily,
it
is
simple
enough to be explained here in detail. It is
one of the best easy examples of the method of
application of mathematical ideas to physics.
Hiero, King of Syracuse, had sent a quan
tity of gold to some goldsmith to form the
material of a crown. He suspected that the
craftsmen had abstracted some of the gold
and had supplied its place by alloying the
Hiero
remainder with some baser metal.
sent the crown to Archimedes and asked him
to test it. In these days an indefinite num
ber of chemical tests would be available.
But then Archimedes had to think out the
matter afresh. The solution flashed upon
him as he lay in his bath. He jumped
up and ran through the streets to the
(I have
palace, shouting Eureka ! Eureka !
found it, I have found it). This day, if we
knew which it was, ought to be celebrated as
the birthday of mathematical physics; the
science came of age when Newton sat in his
orchard. Archimedes had in truth made a
great discovery.
immersed
He saw
that a body
when
water is pressed upwards by the
surrounding water with a resultant force
equal to the weight of the water it displaces.
This law can be proved theoretically from the
mathematical principles of hydrostatics and
can also be verified experimentally. Hence,
Ib. be the weight of the crown, as weighed
if
W
in
METHODS OF APPLICATION
w
39
be the weight of the water
displaces when completely immersed,
w would be the extra upward force
necessary to sustain the crown as it hung in
and
in air,
which
W
Ib.
it
water.
Now, this upward force can easily be ascer
tained by weighing the body as it hangs in
water, as shown in the annexed figure. If
Weights
The
crown
Fig. 3.
the weights in the right-hand scale come to
then the apparent weight of the crown
in water is F Ib.; and we thus have
F Ib.,
and thus
and
w
W
(A)
where
and F are determined by the easy,
and fairly precise, operation of weighting.
40
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Hence, by equation (A),
W
w
is
W
w
is
known.
But
the ratio of the weight of the crown to
the weight of an equal volume of water.
This ratio is the same for any lump of metal of
the same material it is now called the specific
gravity of the material, and depends only on
the intrinsic nature of the substance and not
on its shape or quantity. Thus to test if the
:
crown were of gold, Archimedes had only to
take a lump of indisputably pure gold and
find its specific gravity by the same process.
If the two specific gravities agreed, the crown
was pure; if they disagreed, it was debased.
This argument has been given at length,
because not only is it the first precise example
of the application of mathematical ideas to
physics, but also because it is a perfect and
simple example of what must be the method
and spirit of the science for all time. The
discovery of the theory of specific gravity
marks a genius of the first rank.
The death of Archimedes by the hands of a
Roman soldier is symbolical of a world-change
of the first magnitude the theoretical Greeks,
with their love of abstract science, were super
seded in the leadership of the European world
by the practical Romans. Lord Beaconsfield, in one of his novels, has defined a practi
cal man as a man who practises the errors of
:
METHODS OF APPLICATION
41
The Romans were a great
but they were cursed with the sterility
which waits upon practicality. They did not
improve upon the knowledge of their fore
fathers, and all their advances were confined
to the minor technical details of engineering.
They were not dreamers enough to arrive at
new points of view, which could give a more
fundamental control over the forces of nature.
No Roman lost his life because he was ab
sorbed in the contemplation of a mathe
matical diagram.
his forefathers.
race,
CHAPTER
IV
DYNAMICS
THE world had to wait for eighteen hundred
till the Greek mathematical physicists
found successors. In the sixteenth and seven
years
teenth centuries of our era great Italians, in
particular Leonardo da Vinci, the artist
(born 1452, died 1519), and Galileo (born
1564, died 1642), rediscovered the secret,
known to Archimedes, of relating abstract
mathematical ideas with the experimental
investigation of natural phenomena. Mean
while the slow advance of mathematics and
the accumulation of accurate astronomical
knowledge had placed natural philosophers
in a much more advantageous position for
research. Also the very egoistic self-assertion
of that age, its greediness for personal ex
perience, led its thinkers to want to see for
themselves what happened; and the secret
of the relation of mathematical theory and
experiment in inductive reasoning was prac
It was an act eminently
tically discovered.
characteristic of the age that Galileo, a
42
DYNAMICS
43
philosopher, should have dropped the weights
from the leaning tower of Pisa. There are
always men of thought and men of action;
mathematical physics is the product of an
age which combined in the same men im
pulses to thought with impulses to action.
This matter of the dropping of weights
from the tower marks picturesquely an essen
tial step in knowledge, no less a step than
the first attainment of correct ideas on the
science of dynamics, the basal science of the
whole subject. The particular point in dis
pute was as to whether bodies of different
weights would fall from the same height in
the same time. According to a dictum of
Aristotle, universally followed up to that
epoch, the heavier weight would fall the
Galileo affirmed that they would
quicker.
fall in the same time, and proved his point
by dropping weights from the top of the
leaning tower. The apparent exceptions to
the rule all arise when, for some reason, such
as extreme lightness or great speed, the air
resistance is important. But neglecting the
air the law is exact.
Galileo s successful experiment was not the
result of a mere lucky guess. It arose from
his correct ideas in connection with inertia
and mass. The first law of motion, as follow
ing Newton we now enunciate it, is Every
body continues in its state of rest or of uni-
44
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
form motion
a straight line, except so far
compelled by impressed force to
change that state. This law is more than a
dry formula: it is also a psean of triumph
over defeated heretics. The point at issue
can be understood by deleting from the
law the phrase
of uniform motion in a
straight line." We there obtain what might
be taken as the Aristotelian opposition
formula: "Every body continues in its state
as
it
in
is
"or
of rest except so far as it is compelled by
impressed force to change that state."
In this last false formula it is asserted that,
apart from force, a body continues in a state
of rest; and accordingly that, if a body is
moving, a force is required to sustain the
motion; so that when the force ceases, the
motion ceases.
The true Newtonian law
takes diametrically the opposite point of
view. The state of a body unacted on by
force is that of uniform motion in a straight
line, and no external force or influence is to
be looked for as the cause, or, if you like to
put it so, as the invariable accompaniment
of this uniform rectilinear motion. Rest is
merely a particular case of such motion,
merely when the velocity is and remains zero.
Thus, when a body is moving, we do not seek
for any external influence except to explain
changes in the rate of the velocity or changes
in its direction.
So long as the body
is
moving
DYNAMICS
45
at the same rate and in the same direction
there is no need to invoke the aid of any
forces.
The
difference between the two points of
well seen by reference to the theory
of the motion of the planets. Copernicus, a
Pole, born at Thorn in West Prussia (born
view
is
1473, died 1543), showed
how much
simpler
Force (on False hypothesis)
Fig. 4.
was to conceive the planets, including the
earth, as revolving round the sun in orbits
which are nearly circular; and later, Kepler,
a German mathematician, in the year 1609
proved that, in fact, the orbits are practically
ellipses, that is, a special sort of oval curves
which we will consider later in more detail.
Immediately the question arose as to what
are the forces which preserve the planets in
this motion. According to the old false view,
it
46
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
held by Kepler, the actual velocity itself re
quired preservation by force. Thus he looked
for tangential forces, as in the accompanying
figure (4). But according to the Newtonian
law, apart from some force the planet would
move for ever with its existing velocity in a
straight line, and thus depart entirely from
the sun. Newton, therefore, had to search
for a force which would bend the motion
Planer
Fig. 5.
round into its elliptical orbit. This he showed
must be a force directed towards the sun, as in
In fact, the force is the
(5).
gravitational attraction of the sun acting
according to the law of the inverse square of
the distance, which has been stated above.
The science of mechanics rose among the
Greeks from a consideration of the theory of
the next figure
the mechanical advantage obtained by the
DYNAMICS
47
use of a lever, and also from a consideration of
various problems connected with the weights
of bodies. It was finally put on its true basis
at the end of the sixteenth and during the
seventeenth centuries, as the preceding ac
count shows, partly with the view of explain
ing the theory of falling bodies, but chiefly
in order to give a scientific theory of planetary
motions. But since those days dynamics has
taken upon itself a more ambitious task, and
now claims to be the ultimate science of which
the others are but branches.
The claim
amounts to this: namely, that the various
qualities of things perceptible to the senses
are merely our peculiar mode of appreciating
changes in position on the part of things
existing in space. For example, suppose we
look at Westminster Abbey.
It has been
standing there, grey and immovable, for cen
turies past. But, according to modern scien
tific theory, that greyness, which so heightens
our sense of the immobility of the building,
of itself nothing but our way of appreciating
the rapid motions of the ultimate molecules,
which form the outer surface of the building
and communicate vibrations to a substance
called the ether. Again we lay our hands on
its stones and note their cool, even tempera
ture, so symbolic of the quiet repose of the
But this feeling of temperature
building.
simply marks our sense of the transfer of
48
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
heat from the hand to the stone, or from the
stone to the hand; and, according to modern
science, heat is nothing but the agitation of
the molecules of a body. Finally, the organ
begins playing, and again sound is nothing
but the result of motions of the air striking
on the drum of the ear.
Thus the endeavour to give a dynamical
explanation of phenomena is the attempt to
explain them by statements of the general
form, that such and such a substance or body
was in this place and is now in that place.
Thus we arrive at the great basal idea of
modern science, that all our sensations are
the result of comparisons of the changed
configurations of things in space at various
times.
It follows, therefore, that the laws
of motion, that is, the laws of the changes
of configurations of things, are the ultimate
laws of physical science.
In the application of mathematics to the
investigation of natural philosophy, science
does systematically what ordinary thought
does casually. When we talk of a chair, we
usually mean something which we have been
seeing or feeling in some way; though most
of our language will presuppose that there
something which exists independently of
our sight or feeling. Now in mathematical
physics the opposite course is taken. The
chair is conceived without any reference to
is
DYNAMICST
49
anyone in particular, or to any special modes
The result is that the chair
of perception.
becomes in thought a set of molecules in
space, or a group of electrons, a portion of
the ether in motion, or however the current
But the point is
scientific ideas describe it.
that science reduces the chair to things
moving in space and influencing each other s
Then
elements or
of circum
stances, as thus conceived, are merely the
motions.
factors
the
various
which enter into a
set
things, like lengths of lines, sizes of angles,
areas, and volumes, by which the positions
of bodies in space can be settled. Of course,
in addition to these geometrical elements the
fact of motion and change necessitates the
introduction of the rates of changes of such
elements, that
to say, velocities, angular
and suchlike things.
Accordingly, mathematical physicc deals with
correlations between variable numbers which
are supposed to represent the correlations
is
velocities, accelerations,
which exist in nature between the measures
of these geometrical elements and of their
rates of change.
But always the mathe
matical laws deal with variables, and it is
only in the occasional testing of the laws by
reference to experiments, or in the use of
the laws for special predictions, that definite
numbers are substituted.
The
interesting point about the world as
50
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
thus conceived in this abstract way through
out the study of mathematical physics, where
only the positions and shapes of things are
considered together with their changes, is that
the events of such an abstract world are suffi
cient to "explain" our sensations. When we
hear a sound, the molecules of the air have
been agitated in a certain way: given the
agitation, or air-waves as they are called, all
normal people hear sound; and if there are
no air- waves, there is no sound. And, simi
larly, a physical cause or origin, or parallel
event (according as different people might
like to phrase it), underlies our other sensa
Our very thoughts appear to corre
spond to conformations and motions of the
brain; injure the brain and you injure the
thoughts. Meanwhile the events of this phys
tions.
universe succeed each other according to
the mathematical laws which ignore all special
sensations and thoughts and emotions.
Now, undoubtedly, this is the general
aspect of the relation of the world of mathe
matical physics to our emotions, sensations,
and thoughts; and a great deal of contro
versy has been occasioned by it and much ink
We need only make one remark.
spilled.
The whole situation has arisen, as we have
seen, from the endeavour to describe an ex
ternal world "explanatory" of our various
individual sensations and emotions, but a
ical
DYNAMICS
51
world, also not essentially dependent upon
any particular sensations or upon any par
Is such a world merely
but one huge fairy tale? But fairy tales are
ticular individual.
fantastic
and arbitrary:
if
in truth there
ought to submit itseli
to an exact description, which determines
accurately its various parts and their mutual
be such a world,
it
Now, to a large degree, this
world does submit itself to this
test and allow its events to be explored
and predicted by the apparatus of abstract
mathematical ideas. It certainly seems that
relations.
scientific
here
we have an
inductive verification of
assumption. It must be admitted
that no inductive proof is conclusive; but
if the whole idea of a world which has ex
istence independently of our particular per
ceptions of it be erroneous, it requires careful
explanation why the attempt to characterize
it, in terms of that mathematical remnant
of our ideas which would apply to it, should
issue in such a remarkable success.
It would take us too far afield to enter into
a detailed explanation of the other laws of
motion. The remainder of this chapter must
be devoted to the explanation of remarkable
ideas which are fundamental, both to mathe
matical physics and to pure mathematics:
these are the ideas of vector quantities and
the parallelogram law for vector addition.
our
initial
52
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
We
have seen that the essence of motion is
that a body was at A and is now at C. This
transference from A to C requires two dis
tinct elements to be settled before it is com
pletely determined, namely its magnitude
Now
(i.e. the length AC) and its direction.
is
which
like
this
transference,
anything,
completely given by the determination of a
magnitude and a direction is called a vector.
For example, a velocity requires for its defini
tion the assignment of a magnitude and of a
direction. It must be of so many miles per
hour in such and such a direction. The ex
istence and the independence of these two
elements in the determination of a velocity
are well illustrated by the action of the
captain of a ship, who communicates with
different subordinates respecting them: he
tells the chief engineer the number of knots
at which he is to steam, and the helmsman
DYNAMICS
53
the compass bearing of the course which he is
to keep. Again the rate of change of velocity,
that is velocity added per unit time, is also a
vector quantity: it is called the acceleration.
Similarly a force in the dynamical sense is
another vector quantity. Indeed, the vector
nature of forces follows at once according to
dynamical principles from that of velocities
and
but
this is a point which
It is sufficient here to
say that a force acts on a body with a certain
magnitude in a certain direction.
accelerations;
we need not go
into.
Now all vectors can be graphically repre
sented by straight lines. All that has to be
done is to arrange: (i) a scale according to
which units of length correspond to units of
magnitude of the vector for example, one
inch to a velocity of 10 miles per hour in the
case of velocities, and one inch to a force of
10 tons weight in the case of forces and (ii)
a direction of the line on the diagram corre
sponding to the direction of the vector. Then
a line drawn with the proper number of inches
of length in the proper direction represents the
required vector on the arbitrarily assigned
scale of magnitude. This diagrammatic rep
resentation of vectors is of the first import
ance. By its aid we can enunciate the famous
"parallelogram law" for the addition of
vectors of the same kind but in different
directions.
54
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
AC
in figure 6 as repre
Consider the vector
sentative of the changed position of a body
to C: we will call this the vector of
from
transportation. It will be noted that, if the
reduction of physical phenomena to mere
changes in positions, as explained above, is
correct, all other types of physical vectors are
really reducible in some way or other to this
Now the final transportation
single type.
to C is equally well effected by a
from
and a transporta
to
transportation from
tion from B to (7, or, completing the parallelo
to
gram ABCD, by a transportation from
and a transportation from
to C. These
transportations as thus successively applied
are said to be added together,
^is is simply
a definition of what we mean bjikhe addition
of transportations. Note further that, con
sidering parallel lines as being lines drawn in
the same direction, the transportations B to
C and to may be conceived as the same
transportation applied to bodies in the two
A
A
A
B
A
D
D
D
A
initial positions
B
and A.
With
this
con
we may
talk of the transportation
ception
as applied to a body in any position,
to
for example at B.
Thus we may say that
the transportation
to C can be conceived
as the sum of the two transportations
to
and
to
applied in any order. Here
we have the parallelogram law for the ad
dition of transportations: namely, if the
A
D
A
B
A
D
A
DYNAMICS
55
B
A
A
and
to D,
to
transportations are
then
the
and
parallelogram ABCD,
complete
the sum of the two is the diagonal AC.
All this at first sight may seem to be
very
But
artificial.
that nature
itself
it
must be observed
presents us with the idea.
For example, a steamer
is moving in the
direction
(cf. fig. 6) and a man walks
across its deck.
If the steamer were still,
in one minute he would arrive at B\ but
on
during that minute his starting point
the deck has moved to D, and his path on
to DC.
So
the deck has moved from
that, in fact, his transportation has been from
to C over the surface of the sea. It is,
however, presented to us analysed into the
sum of two transportations, namely, one from
to
relatively to the steamer, and one
from
to
which is the transportation of
AD
A
AB
A
A
B
A
D
the steamer.
By taking into account the element of time,
this diagram of the man s
namely one minute,
AC
transportation
represents his velocity.
if
represented so many feet of trans
portation, it now represents a transportation
of so many feet per minute, that is to say, it
Then
represents the velocity of the man.
AC
For
AD
AB
and
represent two velocities, namely,
his velocity relatively to the steamer, and the
velocity of the steamer, whose "sum" makes
up
his
complete velocity. It
is
evident that
56
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
diagrams and definitions concerning trans
portations are turned into diagrams and defi
nitions concerning velocities by conceiving
the diagrams as representing transportations
per unit time. Again, diagrams and defini
tions concerning velocities are turned into
Fig. 7.
diagrams and definitions concerning accelera
tions by conceiving the diagrams as repre
senting velocities added per unit time.
Thus by the addition of vector velocities
and of vector accelerations, we mean the
addition according to the parallelogram law.
Also, according to the laws of motion a
force is fully represented by the vector
acceleration it produces in a body of given
mass. Accordingly, forces will be said to be
added when their joint effect is to be reckoned
according to the parallelogram law.
DYNAMICS
Hence
for
the
57
fundamental vectors of
science, namely transportations, velocities,
and forces, the addition of any two of the same
kind is the production of a "resultant"
vector according to the rule of the parallelo
law.
far the simplest type of parallelogram
is a rectangle, and in pure mathematics it is
to the
the relation of the single vector
and AD, at right
two component vectors,
angles (cf. fig. 7), which is continually re
curring. Let x, y, and r units represent the
units
lengths of AB, AD, and AC, and let
of angle represent the magnitude of the angle
BAC. Then the relations between x, y, r,
and m, in all their many aspects are the con
tinually recurring topic of pure mathematics;
and the results are of the type required for
application to the fundamental vectors of
gram
By
AC
AB
m
mathematical physics. This diagram is the
chief bridge over which the results of pure
mathematics pass in order to obtain applica
tion to the facts of nature.
CHAPTER V
THE SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
WE
now
return to pure mathematics, and
closely the apparatus of ideas
out of which the science is built. Our first
concern is with the symbolism of the science,
and we start with the simplest and universally
known symbols, namely those of arithmetic.
Let us assume for the present that we have
sufficiently clear ideas about the integral
numbers, represented in the Arabic notation
consider
by
more
0,1,2,..., 9, 10, 11,...
100, 101,...
and
This notation was introduced into
Europe through the Arabs, but they appar
ently obtained it from Hindoo sources. The
first known work* in which it is systematic
ally explained is a work by an Indian mathe
matician, Bhaskara (born 1114 A.D.). But
the actual numerals can be traced back to the
seventh century of our era, and perhaps were
originally invented in Tibet. For our present
so on.
*
For the detailed
matics, I
historical facts relating to
pure mathe
am chiefly indebted to A Short History of Mathematics,
by W. W. R.
Ball.
SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
59
purposes, however, the history of the notation
The interesting point to notice
is a detail.
is
the admirable illustration which this
numeral system affords of the enormous im
portance of a good notation. By relieving
the brain of all unnecessary work, a good
notation sets it free to concentrate on more
advanced problems, and in effect increases
the mental power of the race. Before the
introduction of the Arabic notation, multipli
cation was difficult, and the division even of
integers called into play the highest mathe
matical faculties. Probably nothing in the
modern world would have more astonished a
Greek mathematician than to learn that,
under the influence of compulsory education,
the whole population of Western Europe,
from the highest to the lowest, could perform
the operation of division for the largest num
bers. This fact would have seemed to him a
sheer impossibility.
The consequential ex
tension of the notation to decimal fractions
was not accomplished till the seventeenth
Our modern power of easy reck
century.
oning with decimal fractions is the almost
miraculous result of the gradual discovery of
a perfect notation.
Mathematics is often considered a diffi
cult and mysterious science, because of the
numerous symbols which it employs. Of
is more incomprehensible than
course, nothing
60
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
a symbolism which we do not understand.
Also a symbolism, which we only partially
understand and are unaccustomed to use, is
difficult to follow.
In exactly the same way
the technical terms of any profession or trade
are incomprehensible to those who have never
been trained to use them. But this is not
because they are difficult in themselves. On
the contrary they have invariably been intro
duced to make things easy. So in mathe
matics, granted that we are giving any serious
attention to mathematical ideas, the sym
is invariably an immense simplifica
It is not only of practical use, but is
of great interest. For it represents an analy
sis of the ideas of the subject and an almost
bolism
tion.
pictorial representation of their relations to
each other. If any one doubts the utility of
symbols, let him write out in full, without any
symbol whatever, the whole meaning of the
following equations which represent some of
the fundamental laws of algebra:
x+y=y+x
(x+y)+z=x + (y+z)
xXy=yXx
(xXy)Xz=xx(yXz)
xx(y+x)=(xxy}+(xxz)
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
Here (1) and (2) are called the commutative
and associative laws for addition, (3) and (4)
SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
61
are the commutative and associative laws for
multiplication, and (5) is the distributive law
relating addition and multiplication, For ex
ample, without symbols, (1) becomes: If a
second number be added to any given number
the result is the same as if the first given
number had been added to the second number.
This example shows that, by the aid of sym
bolism, we can make transitions in reasoning
almost mechanically by the eye, which other
wise would call into play the higher faculties
of the brain.
It is a profoundly erroneous truism, repeated
by all copy-books and by eminent people when
they are making speeches, that we should
cultivate the habit of thinking of what we are
The precise opposite is the case.
doing.
Civilization advances by extending the num
ber of important operations which we can
perform without thinking about them. Opera
tions of thought are like cavalry charges in
a battle they are strictly limited in num
ber, they require fresh horses, and must only
be made at decisive moments.
One very important property for symbolism
to possess is that it should be concise, so as to
be visible at one glance of the eye and to be
we cannot place sym
rapidly written.
bols more concisely together than by placing
them in immediate juxtaposition. In a good
symbolism therefore, the juxtaposition of im-
Now
62
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
portant symbols should have an important
meaning. This is one of the merits of the
Arabic notation for numbers; by means of
ten symbols, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, and by
simple juxtaposition it symbolizes any number
whatever. Again in algebra, when we have
two variable numbers x and y, we have to
choice as to what shall be denoted by
Now the two most
their juxtaposition xy.
are
those of addition
on
hand
ideas
important
and multiplication. Mathematicians have
chosen to make their symbolism more concise
by defining xy to stand for xXy. Thus the
laws (3), (4), and (5) above are in general
make a
written,
xy=yx, (xy)z=x(yz) 9 x(y+z) =xy+xz,
thus securing a great gain in conciseness.
The same rule of symbolism is applied to the
juxtaposition of a definite number and a vari
able: we write Sx for 3 Xx, and 30z for 30 Xx.
It is evident that in substituting definite
numbers for the variables some care must be
taken to restore the X, so as not to conflict
with the Arabic notation. Thus when we
substitute 2 for x and 3 for y in xy, we must
write 2 X 3 for xy, and not 23 which means
20+3.
It is interesting to note how important for
the development of science a modest-looking
symbol may be. It may stand for the em
phatic presentation for an idea, often a very
SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
63
subtle idea, and by its existence make it easy
to exhibit the relation of this idea to all the
complex trains of ideas in which it occurs.
For example, take the most modest of all
symbols, namely, 0, which stands for the number zero. The Roman notation for numbers
had no symbol for zero, and probably most
mathematicians of the ancient world would
have been horribly puzzled by the idea of the
number zero. For, after all, it is a very
subtle idea, not at all obvious. A great deal
of discussion
on the meaning of the zero of
be found in philosophic works.
in real truth, more difficult or
will
quantity
Zero is not,
subtle in idea than the other cardinal numbers.
What do we mean by 1 or by 2, or by 3?
But we are familiar with the use of these ideas,
though we should most of us be puzzled to
give a clear analysis of the simpler ideas
which go to form them. The point about zero
is that we do not need to use it in the opera
tions of daily life. No one goes out to buy
zero fish. It is in a way the most civilized
of all the cardinals, and its use is only forced
on us by the needs of cultivated modes of
thought. Many important services are ren
dered by the symbol
0,
which stands
for the
number zero.
The symbol developed in connection with
the Arabic notation for numbers of which it
is
an
essential part.
For
in that notation the
64
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
value of a digit depends on the position in
which it occurs. Consider, for example, the
digit 5, as occurring in the numbers 25, 51,
3512, 5213. In the first number 5 stands for
five, in the second number 5 stands for fifty,
in the third number for five hundred, and in
the fourth number for five thousand. Now,
when we write the number fifty-one in the
symbolic form 51, the digit 1 pushes the digit
5 along to the second place (reckoning from
right to left) and thus gives it the value fifty.
But when we want to symbolize fifty by itself,
we can have no digit 1 to perform this service;
we want a digit in the units place to add
nothing to the total and yet to push the 5
along to the second place. This service is
performed by 0, the symbol for zero. It is
extremely probable that the men who intro
duced for this purpose had no definite con
ception in their minds of the number zero.
They simply wanted a mark to symbolize the
fact that nothing was contributed by the
digit s place in which it occurs. The idea of
zero probably took shape gradually from a
desire to assimilate the meaning of this mark
to that of the marks, 1,2,... 9, which do re
present cardinal numbers. This would not
represent the only case in which a subtle idea
has been introduced into mathematics by a
symbolism which in its origin was dictated by
practical convenience.
SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
65
was to make the
Thus the first use of
Arabic notation possible no slight service.
We can imagine that when it had been intro
duced for this purpose, practical men, of the
sort who dislike fanciful ideas, deprecated the
silly habit of identifying it with a number
But they were wrong, as such men
zero.
always are when they desert their proper
function of masticating food which others
have prepared. For the next service per
formed by the symbol
essentially depends
upon assigning to it the function of repre
senting the
number
zero.
This second symbolic use is at first sight
so absurdly simple that it is difficult to make
a beginner realize its importance. Let us
start with a simple example. In Chapter II
we mentioned the correlation between two
variable numbers x and y represented by the
equation x+y = l. This can be represented
in an indefinite number of ways; for example,
x = l y, y = Ix, %x+3y 1 =x+%y, and so
on. But the important way of stating it is
Similarly the important way of writing the
equation # = 1 is # 1=0, and of representing
the equation 3x-2 = 2x 2 is 2x*-3x+2 = 0.
The point is that all the symbols which repre
sent variables, e.g. x and y, and the symbols
66
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
representing some definite number other than
zero, such as 1 or 2 in the examples above,
are written on the left-hand side, so that the
whole left-hand side is equated to the number
The first man to do this is said to
zero.
have been Thomas Harriot, born at Oxford
in 1560 and died in 1621. But what is the
importance
cedure? It
of
this
simple
symbolic
pro
made
possible the growth of the
modern conception of algebraic form.
This is an idea to which we shall have con
tinually to recur; it is not going too far to
say that no part of modern mathematics can
be properly understood without constant re
currence to it. The conception of form is
so general that it is difficult to characterize
in abstract terms. At this stage we shall
do better merely to consider examples. Thus
the equations %x S = 0, x 1 = 0, 5x 6 = 0,
are all equations of the same form, namely,
it
equations involving one unknown x, which is
not multiplied by itself, so that x 2 #3 etc., do
not appear. Again 3x 2 - Zx + 1 = 0, x 2 = Sx +2
= 0, x2 4=0, are all equations of the same
form, namely, equations involving one un
known x in which xXx, that is z 2 appears.
These equations are called quadratic equa
tions.
Similarly cubic equations, in which
a3 appears, yield another form, and so on.
Among the three quadratic equations given
above there is a minor difference between the
,
,
,
SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
67
x2 4 = 0, and the preceding two
to the fact that x (as distinct
due
equations,
from x 2 ) does not appear in the last and
does in the other two. This distinction is
very unimportant in comparison with the
great fact that they are all three quadratic
last equation,
equations.
Then further there are the forms of equation
stating correlations between two variables;
for example,
2x+3y-8=Q, and
so on. These are examples of what is called
the linear form of equation. The reason for
this name of "linear" is that the graphic
method of representation, which is explained
at the end of Chapter II, always represents
x+y-l=0,
such equations by a straight line. Then there
are other forms for two variables for ex
ample, the quadratic form, the cubic form,
and so on. But the point which we here in
sist upon is that this study of form is facili
and, indeed, made possible, by the
standard method of writing equations with
on the right-hand side.
the symbol
There is yet another function performed by
in relation to the study of form. Whatever
tated,
number x may be, OX# = 0, and x+Q=x.
By means of these properties minor differ
ences of form can be assimilated. Thus the
difference mentioned above between the quad
ratic equations #2 =3a;+2 = 0, and x 2
4=0,
can be obliterated by writing the latter
68
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
2
=
equation in the form x + (0 X x) 4 0. For,
2
x
stated
the
laws
+ (QXx) 4 =
above,
by
2
4 = #* 4. Hence the equation x 2 4
a; +
= 0, is merely representative of a particular
class of quadratic equations and belongs to
the same general form as does x 2 3x+% =0.
For these three reasons the symbol 0, rep
resenting the number zero, is essential to
modern mathematics. It has rendered pos
sible types of investigation which would have
been impossible without it.
The symbolism of mathematics is in truth
the outcome of the general ideas which domi
nate the science. We have now two such
general ideas before us, that of the variable
and that of algebraic form. The junction of
these concepts has imposed on mathematics
another type of symbolism almost quaint in
We
its character, but none the less effective.
have seen that an equation involving two
variables, x and y, represents a particular cor
relation between the pair of variables. Thus
x+y \=Q represents one definite correla
5=0 represents another
tion, and 3x+%y
definite correlation between the variables x
and y\ and both correlations have the form
what we have called linear correlations.
But now, how can we represent any linear
of
correlation between the variable numbers x
and y? Here we want to symbolize any
linear correlation; just as x symbolizes any
SYMBOLISM OF MATHEMATICS
69
number. This is done by turning the numbers
which occur in the definite correlation 3x+%y
5=0 into letters. We obtain ax + by c = 0.
Here a, 6, c stand for variable numbers just
as do x and y: but there is a difference in the
use of the two sets of variables. We study
the general properties of the relationship be
tween x and y while a, 6, and c have un
changed values. We do not determine what
the values of a, 6, and c are; but whatever
they are, they remain fixed while we study
the relation between the variables x and y
for the whole group of possible values of x
and ?/. But when we have obtained the
properties of this correlation, we note that,
because a, 6, and c have not in fact been deter
mined, we have proved properties which must
belong to any such relation. Thus, by now
varying a, 6, and c, we arrive at the idea that
represents a variable linear
ax+by c =
correlation between x and y. In comparison
with x and y, the three variables a, 6, and c
are called constants. Variables used in this
way are sometimes also called parameters.
Now, mathematicians habitually save the
trouble of explaining which of their variables
are to be treated as "constants," and which
as variables, considered as correlated in their
equations, by using letters at the end of the
alphabet for the "variable" variables, and
letters at the beginning of the alphabet for
70
the
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
"constant"
or parameters.
naturally about the
variables,
The two systems meet
middle of the alphabet. Sometimes a word
or two of explanation is necessary; but as a
matter of fact custom and common sense are
usually sufficient, and surprisingly little con
fusion is caused by a procedure which seems
so lax.
The result of this continual elimination of
definite numbers by successive layers of para
meters is that the amount of arithmetic per
formed by mathematicians is extremely small.
Many mathematicians dislike all numerical
computation and are not particularly expert
at it. The territory of arithmetic ends where
the two ideas of "variables" and of "alge
braic form" commence their sway.
CHAPTER
VI
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
ONE great peculiarity of mathematics is the
set of allied ideas which have been invented
in connection with the integral numbers from
which we started. These ideas may be called
extensions or generalizations of number. In
the first place there is the idea of fractions.
The earliest treatise on arithmetic which we
possess was written by an Egyptian priest,
named Ahmes, between 1700
B.C.,
B.C. and 1100
probably a copy of a much older
It deals largely with the properties of
and
work.
it is
It appears, therefore, that this
concept was developed very early in the his
tory of mathematics. Indeed the subject is
a very obvious one. To divide a field into
three equal parts, and to take two of the
parts, must be a type of operation which had
often occurred.
Accordingly, we need not
be surprised that the men of remote civiliza
tions were familiar with the idea of twofractions.
71
72
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
thirds,
first
and with
Thus as the
number we place the
The Greeks thought of
allied notions.
generalization of
concept of fractions.
form of ratio, so
that a Greek would naturally say that a
line of two feet in length bears to a line of
three feet in length the ratio of 2 to 3.
Under the influence of our algebraic nota
tion we would more often say that one line
was two-thirds of the other in length, and
would think of two-thirds as a numerical
this subject rather in the
multiplier.
In connection with the theory of ratio, or
Greeks made a great discovery,
which has been the occasion of a large amount
of philosophical as well as mathematical
thought. They found out the existence of
"incommensurable" ratios.
They proved,
in fact, during the course of their geometrical
investigations that, starting with a line of any
fractions, the
length, other lines must exist whose lengths
do not bear to the original length the ratio
of any pair of integers
or, in other words,
that lengths exist which are not any exact
fraction of the original length.
For example, the diagonal of a square can
not be expressed as any fraction of the side of
the same square; in our modern notation the
length of the diagonal is V% times the length
of the side. But there is no fraction which
exactly represents V&.
We
can approximate
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
to
V2
as closely as
exactly reach
its
we
like,
but we never
49
For example,
value.
73
is
/vt/
just less than 2,
that
V%
lies
g
and -
is
greater than 2, so
73
between - and -
But the best
A
5
systematic way of approximating to A/2 in
obtaining a series of decimal fractions, each
bigger than the last, is by the ordinary
method of extracting the square root; thus
the series
14
is 1,
-,
1414
141
,
,
and so on.
Ratios of this sort are called by the Greeks
incommensurable. They have excited from
the time of the Greeks onwards a great deal
and the difficulties
connected with them have only recently been
of philosophic discussion,
cleared up.
We will put the incommensurable ratios
with the fractions, and consider the whole
set of integral numbers, fractional numbers,
and incommensurable numbers as forming
one class of numbers which we will call "real
We always think of the real
numbers."
numbers as arranged in order of magnitude,
starting from zero and going upwards, and
becoming
proceed.
indefinitely larger and larger as we
real numbers are conveniently
The
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
74
represented by points on a
line.
Let
OMANBPCQD
any
line
bounded at
OX be
X
and stretching away
Take any
indefinitely in the direction OX.
convenient point, A, on it, so that
OA repre
sents the unit length; and divide off lengths
AB, BC, CD, and so on, each equal to OA.
Then the point represents the number 0,
the number 1,
the number 2, and so on.
In fact the number represented by any point
is the measure of its distance from 0, in
terms of the unit length OA. The points
between
and
represent the proper frac
tions and the incommensurable numbers less
A
B
A
than
1
that of
~,
the middle point of
;
OA
represents -,
AB represents 3-, that of BC represents
and so
on.
In this way every point on
OX
represents some one real number, and
every real number is represented by some
one point on OX.
The series (or row) of points along OX,
and moving regularly in the
starting from
to X, represents the real
from
numbers as arranged in an ascending order
direction
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
75
of size, starting from zero and continually
increasing as we go on.
All this seems simple enough, but even at
this stage there are some interesting ideas to
be got at by dwelling on these obvious facts.
Consider the series of points which represent
the integral numbers only, namely, the points
0, A, B, C, D, etc. Here there is a first point
0, a definite next point, A, and each point,
such as A or B, has one definite immediate
predecessor and one definite immediate suc
cessor, with the exception of 0, which has no
predecessor; also the series goes on indefi
This sort of order is
nitely without end.
called the type of order of the integers; its
essence is the possession of next-door neigh
bours on either side with the exception of
No. 1 in the row. Again consider the integers
and fractions together, omitting the points
which correspond to the incommensurable
ratios.
The sort of serial order which we
now obtain is quite different. There is a first
term 0; but no term has any immediate pre
decessor or immediate successor.
This is
seen
to
be
the
for
between
case,
easily
any
two fractions we can always find another
fraction intermediate in value.
One very
of
is
this
to
add the
simple way
doing
fractions together and to halve the result.
For example, between f and f , the fraction
2 (f
I tnat is ||, lies; and between f and
+
)>
76
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
lies;
), that is ff
J| the fraction J(f +
and so on indefinitely. Because of this prop
erty the series is said to be "compact."
There is no end-point to the series, which in
creases indefinitely without limit as we go
along the line OX. It would seem at first
sight as though the type of series got in this
way from the fractions, always including the
integers, would be the same as that got from
all the real numbers, integers, fractions, and
incommensurables taken together, that is,
from all the points on the line OX. All that
we have hitherto said about the series of
,
fractions applies equally well to the series of
numbers. But there are important
differences which we now proceed to develop.
The absence of the incommensurables from
the series of fractions leaves an absence of
end points to certain classes. Thus, consider
all real
the incommensurable V%. In the series of
real numbers this stands between all the
numbers whose squares are less than 2, and
all the numbers whose squares are greater
than 2. But keeping to the series of fractions
alone and not thinking of the incommensur
ables, so that we cannot bring in V 9 there
no fraction which has the property of
dividing off the series into two parts in this
way, i. e. so that all the members on one side
is
have their squares less than 2, and on the
Hence in the
other side greater than 2.
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
77
a quasi-gap where
ought to come. This presence of quasigaps in the series of fractions may seem a
small matter; but any mathematician, who
happens to read this, knows that the possible
absence of limits or maxima to a class of
numbers, which yet does not spread over
the whole series of numbers, is no small evil.
series of fractions there is
V%
It is to avoid this difficulty that recourse is
had to the incommensurables, so as to ob
tain a complete series with no gaps.
There is another even more fundamental
difference between the two series.
We can
rearrange the fractions in a series like that of
the integers, that is, with a first term, and
such that each term has an immediate suc
cessor and (except the first term) an imme
We can show how this
diate predecessor.
can be done. Let every term in the series of
fractions and integers be written in the frac
tional form by writing y for 1, f for 2, and so
on for all the integers, excluding 0. Also for
the moment we will reckon fractions which
are equal in value but not reduced to their
lowest terms as distinct; so that, for example,
until further notice, f, f, f, T8^, etc., are all
reckoned as distinct. Now group the frac
tions into classes by adding together the
numerator and denominator of each term.
For the sake of brevity call this sum of the
numerator and denominator of a fraction
its
78
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
index. Thus 7 is the index of -J, and also of
Let the fractions in each class
f and of f
be all fractions which have some specified
index, which may therefore also be called
.
,
the class index. Now arrange these classes
in the order of magnitude of their indices.
The first class has the index 2, and its only
member is j; the second class has the index
the third
3, and its members are | and f
class has the index 4, and its members are J,
f f the fourth class has the index 5, and its
;
,
;
members
are \, f |- { ; and so on. It is easy
to see that the number of members (still in
cluding fractions not in their lowest terms)
belonging to any class is one less than its
index. Also the members of any one class
can be arranged in order by taking the first
member to be the fraction with numerator 1,
the second member to have the numerator 2,
and so on, up to (n
1) where n is the index.
Thus for the class of index n, the members
appear in the order.
,
,
~*
i
The members
of the first four classes have in fact been
mentioned in this order. Thus the whole set
of fractions have now been arranged in an
order like that of the integers. It runs thus:
1121 nn 31234
2
3
d 4 3 2
1
1
1
I""
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
w-2
I
and so
1
2
n-1
3
n-l n-2
n-3"
79
I
~T~ n
9
on.
Now we
can get rid of
fractions of the
repetitions of
striking
they appear after their
all
same value by simply
them out whenever
occurrence.
In the few initial terms
written down above, f which is enclosed above
in square brackets is the only fraction not in
its lowest terms.
It has occurred before as
Thus this must be struck out. But the
\.
series is still left with the same properties,
namely, (a) there is a first term, (6) each term
has next-door neighbours, (c) the series goes
on without end.
It can be proved that it is not possible to
arrange the whole series of real numbers in
this way. This curious fact was discovered
by Georg Cantor, a German mathematician
still living; it is of the utmost importance in
the philosophy of mathematical ideas.
are here in fact touching on the fringe of the
great problems of the meaning of continuity
first
We
and of infinity.
Another extension
of
number comes from
the introduction of the idea of what has been
variously named an operation or a step,
names which are respectively appropriate
from slightly different points of view. We
will start with a particular case.
Consider
80
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
the statement 2+3=5. We add 3 to 2 and
obtain 5. Think of the operation of adding
3:
=
let this
1.
be denoted by +3.
Think
Again
43
of the operation of subtracting
let this be denoted by -3. Thus instead
of considering the real numbers in themselves,
we consider the operations of adding or sub
tracting them: instead of A/2, we consider
3:
+ A/2
and
-A/2, namely the operations of
adding A/2 and of subtracting A/2. Then we
can add these operations, of course in a
different sense of addition to that in which we
add numbers. The sum of two operations is
the single operation which has the same effect
as the
two operations applied
successively.
In what order are the two operations to be
applied? The answer is that it is indifferent,
since for example
2+3+1=2+1+3;
so that the addition of the steps
+3 and +1
commutative.
Mathematicians have a habit, which is
puzzling to those engaged in tracing out
meanings, but is very convenient in practice,
of using the same symbol in different though
allied senses. The one essential requisite for
a symbol in their eyes is that, whatever its
possible varieties of meaning, the formal laws
In
for its use shall always be the same.
is
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
81
accordance with this habit the addition of
operations is denoted by + as well as the
addition of numbers.
Accordingly we can
write
where the middle -f- on the left-hand side
denotes the addition of the operations +3
and +1. But, furthermore, we need not be
so very pedantic in our symbolism, except in
the rare instances when we are directly tracing
meanings; thus we always drop the first +
of a line and the brackets, and never write
two + signs running. So the above equation
becomes
3+1=4,
which we interpret as simple numerical addi
more elaborate addition of
operations which is fully expressed in the
previous way of writing the equation, or
lastly as expressing the result of applying
the operation +1 to the number 3 and ob
taining the number 4.
Any interpretation
which is possible is always correct. But the
tion, or as the
only interpretation which is always possible,
under certain conditions, is that of operations.
The
other interpretations often give non
sensical results.
This leads us at once to a question, which
must have been
rising
insistently
in
the
m
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
reader s mind: What is the use of all this
elaboration? At this point our friend, the
practical
man,
will surely step in
and
insist
on
sweeping away all these silly cobwebs of the
brain. The answer is that what the mathe
matician is seeking is Generality. This is an
idea worthy to be placed beside the notions
of the Variable and of Form so far as concerns
its importance in governing mathematical
procedure. Any limitation whatsoever upon
the generality of theorems, or of proofs, or of
interpretation is abhorrent to the mathe
matical instinct. These three notions, of the
variable, of form, and of generality, compose
a sort of mathematical trinity which preside
over the whole subject.
They all really
spring from the same root, namely from the
abstract nature of the science.
Let us see how generality is gained by the
introduction of this idea of operations.
the equation # + 1=3; the solution is
Take
a;
=2.
Here we can interpret our symbols as mere
numbers, and the recourse to "operations"
is entirely unnecessary.
But, if # is a mere
number, the equation x+S = l is nonsense.
For x should be the number of things which
remain when you have taken 3 things away
from 1 thing; and no such procedure is
possible. At this point our idea of algebraic
form steps in, itself only generalization under
another aspect.
We
consider, therefore, the
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
general equation of the
This equation
is
83
as x 4- 1 = 3.
its solution is
same form
x+a = b, and
x = ba. Here our difficulties become acute;
for this form can only be used for the numeri
cal interpretation so long as b is greater than
a, and we cannot say without qualification
that a and b may be any constants. In other
words we have introduced a limitation on
the variability of the "constants" a and 6,
which we must drag like a chain throughout
all our reasoning.
Really prolonged mathe
matical investigations would be impossible
under such conditions.
Every equation
would at least be buried under a pile of limita
tions. But if we now interpret our symbols
as
"operations,"
all
limitation vanishes like
magic. The equation x + I =3 gives x= +2,
the equation #+3 = 1 gives x =
2, the equa
which is an opera
tion x +a = b gives x =
tion of addition or subtraction as the case
may be. We need never decide whether b a
represents the operation of addition or of
subtraction, for the rules of procedure with
the symbols are the same in either case.
It does not fall within the plan of this work
to write a detailed chapter of elementary
ba
algebra. Our object is merely to make plain
the fundamental ideas which guide the forma
tion of the science. Accordingly we do not
further explain the detailed rules by which
the "positive and negative numbers" are
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
84
We
have
multiplied and otherwise combined.
explained above that positive and negative
numbers are operations. They have also
been called "steps." Thus +3 is the step
3 is the
by which we go from 2 to 5, and
step backwards by which we go from 5 to 2.
Consider the line
divided in the way ex
plained in the earlier part of the chapter, so
that its points represent numbers. Then
OX
/
D C B A
-3 -2 -1
+1 +2 +3
A B C D E
the step from
to J5, or from A to C, or
the divisions are taken backwards along
to B , and so
) from C to A , or from
on. Similarly
2 is the step from
to J5 ,
or from B to
from C
, or from B to 0, or
to A.
We may consider the point which is reached
by a step from 0, as representative of that
is
(if
D
OX
D
A
represents +1, B represents
f
1, B represents
2, and
represents
so on. It will be noted that, whereas previ
ously with the mere "unsigned" real numbers
step.
+2,
Thus
A
the points on one side of
only, namely along
OX, were representative of numbers, now
with steps every point on the whole line
is representative
stretching on both sides of
of a step. This is a pictorial representation
of the superior generality introduced by the
positive and negative numbers, namely the
GENERALIZATIONS OF NUMBERS
85
operations or steps. These "signed" num
bers are also particular cases of what have
been called vectors (from the Latin veho, I
draw or carry). For we may think of a
to A, or from
particle as carried from
to B.
In suggesting a few pages ago that the
practical man would object to the subtlety
involved by the introduction of the positive
A
and negative numbers, we were libelling that
excellent individual. For in truth we are on
the scene of one of his greatest triumphs. If
the truth must be confessed, it was the practi
cal man himself who first employed the actual
Their origin is not very
symbols + and
certain, but it seems most probable that they
arose from the marks chalked on chests of
goods in German warehouses, to denote excess
or defect from some standard weight. The
earliest notice of them occurs in a book pub
.
They seem
mathematics
by a German mathematician, Stifel, in a book
lished at Leipzig, in A.D. 1489.
first to have been employed in
published at Nuremburg in 1544 A.D. But
then it is only recently that the Germans
have come to be looked on as emphatically
a practical nation. There is an old epigram
which assigns the empire of the sea to the
English, of the land to the French, and of the
clouds to the Germans. Surely it was from
the clouds that the Germans fetched
+
and
86
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
the ideas which these symbols have gener
;
ated are much too important for the wel
fare of humanity to have come from the sea
or from the land.
The possibilities of application of the posi
and negative numbers are very obvious.
one direction are represented by
a positive number, those in the opposite di
rection are represented by negative numbers.
tive
If lengths in
If a velocity in one direction is positive, that
in the opposite direction is negative.
If a
rotation round a dial in the opposite direction
to the hands of a clock (anti-clockwise) is
positive, that in the clockwise direction is
negative. If a balance at the bank is posi
If vitreous
tive, an overdraft is negative.
electrification is positive, resinous electrifica
tion is negative. Indeed, in this latter case,
the terms positive electrification and nega
tive electrification, considered as mere names,
have practically driven out the other terms.
An
endless series of examples could be given.
idea of positive and negative numbers
has been practically the most successful of
The
mathematical
subtleties.
CHAPTER
VII
IMAGINAKY NUMBERS
IF the mathematical ideas dealt with in the
last chapter have been a popular success,
those of the present chapter have excited
almost as much general attention. But their
success has been of a different character, it
has been what the French term a succes de
Not only the practical man, but
scandale.
also men of letters and philosophers have
expressed their bewilderment at the devo
tion of mathematicians to mysterious entities
name are confessed to be
which by their
very
imaginary. At this point it may be useful
to observe that a certain type of minor in
tellect is always worrying itself and others by
discussion as to the applicability of technical
terms.
Are the incommensurable numbers
properly called numbers? Are the positive
and negative numbers really numbers? Are
the imaginary numbers imaginary, and are
they numbers? are types of such futile
Now, it cannot be too clearly
understood that, in science, technical terms
questions.
are
names
arbitrarily assigned, like Christian
87
88
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
names
of the
to children.
There can be no question
names being
may be judicious
sometimes be so
remember, or so
important ideas.
right or wrong.
They
or injudicious; for they can
arranged as to be easy to
as to suggest relevant and
But the essential principle
involved was quite clearly enunciated in
Wonderland to Alice by Humpty Dumpty,
when he told her, a propos of his use of words,
pay them extra and make them mean
what I
So we will not bother as to
"I
like."
whether imaginary numbers are imaginary,
or as to whether they are numbers, but will
take the phrase as the arbitrary name of a
certain mathematical idea, which we will now
endeavour to make plain.
The origin of the conception is in every
way similar to that of the positive and nega
In exactly the same way it
tive numbers.
is due to the three great mathematical ideas
of the variable, of algebraic form, and of
generalization.
numbers arose
The positive and negative
from the consideration of
# + 1=3, x+3 = I, and the
equations like
general form x+a = b. Similarly the origin
of imaginarv numbers is due to equations like
# 2 + l=3, z 2 +3 = l, and x*+a = b. Exactly
the same process is gone through. The equa
tion a;2 + l =3 becomes x 2 ==%, and this has two
V%. The
solutions, either x = -\-V%, or x =
statement that there are these alternative
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
usually written x = =*= A/2. So far
plain sailing, as it was in the previous
solutions
all is
89
is
case. But now an analogous difficulty arises.
2 and
For the equation x2 +S = 1 gives x 2 =
there is no positive or negative number which,
when multiplied by itself, will give a negative
square. Hence, if our symbols are to mean
the ordinary positive or negative numbers,
there is no solution to x2 =
2, and the equa
is in fact nonsense.
Thus, finally taking
the general form x 2 +a = b, we find the pair
tion
=*=
of solutions x
V(b a), when, and only
when, b is not less than a. Accordingly we
cannot say unrestrictedly that the "con
stants"
a and b
may be any numbers,
that
is,
a and b are not, as they
ought to be, independent unrestricted "vari
and so again a host of limitations
ables";
and restrictions will accumulate round our
the
"constants"
as we proceed.
The same task as before therefore awaits
us: we must give a new interpretation to our
work
symbols, so that the solutions =t V(b a) for
the equation x z -}-a = b always have meaning.
In other words, we require an interpretation
of the symbols so that Va always has mean
Of
ing whether a be positive or negative.
course, the interpretation must be such that
all the ordinary formal laws for addition, sub
traction, multiplication, and division hold
good; and also it must not interfere with the
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
90
generality which we have attained by the use
of the positive and negative numbers.
In
fact, it must in a sense include them as
special cases.
c2 for
write
When
it,
a
is
so that c 2
negative
is
we may
Then
positive.
we can so interpret our symbols that
has a meaning, we have attained our
1) has come to be looked
object. Thus V(
on as the head and forefront of all the
Hence,
V(
if
1)
imaginary quantities.
This business of finding an interpretation
for V(
1) is a much tougher job than the
1.
In fact,
analogous one of interpreting
while the easier problem was solved almost
instinctively as soon as it arose, it at first
hardly occurred, even to the greatest mathe
maticians, that a problem existed which was
perhaps capable of solution. Equations like
x2
3, when they arose, were simply ruled
aside as nonsense.
it came to be gradually perceived
the
eighteenth century, and even
during
earlier, how very convenient it would be if
an interpretation could be assigned to these
nonsensical symbols. Formal reasoning with
these symbols was gone through, merely
assuming that they obeyed the ordinary
However,
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
91
algebraic laws of transformation; and it was
seen that a whole world of interesting results
could be attained, if only these symbols might
legitimately be used. Many mathematicians
were not then very clear as to the logic of
their procedure, and an idea gained ground
that, in
some mysterious way, symbols which
appropriate manip
mean nothing can by
ulation yield valid proofs of propositions.
Nothing can be more mistaken. A symbol
which has not been properly defined is not a
symbol at all. It is merely a blot of ink on
paper which has an easily recognized shape.
Nothing can be proved by a succession of
blots, except the existence of a bad pen or a
It was during this epoch
careless writer.
that the epithet "imaginary" came to be
applied to
V(
1).
What
these
mathema
ticians had really succeeded in proving were
a series of hypothetical propositions, of which
this is the
exist for
traction,
blank form:
If
interpretations
and
for the addition, sub
and division of
multiplication,
V(
1)
which make the ordinary algebraic
(e.g. x+y=y+x, etc.) to be satisfied,
then such and such results follow. It was
natural that the mathematicians should not
which ought
always appreciate the big
to have preceded the statements of their re
V(
1)
rules
"If,"
sults.
As may be expected the
interpretation,
92
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
when found, was a much more elaborate
affair
numbers and the
reader s attention must be asked for some
We have
careful preliminary explanation.
already come across the representation of a
point by two numbers. By the aid of the
than that
of the negative
Fig. 8.
positive and negative numbers we can now
represent the position of any point in a plane
by a pair of such numbers. Thus we take
and
the pair of straight lines
, at
right angles, as the "axes" from which we
start all our measurements.
Lengths mea
sured along
and
are positive, and
and
measured backwards along
are
negative.
Suppose that a pair of numbers,
written in order, e.g. (+3, -j-1), so that there
XOX
OX
YOY
OY
OX
OY
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
93
a first number (+3 in the above example),
and a second number ( + 1 in the above ex
ample), represents measurements from
along XOX for the first number, and along
YOY for the second number. Thus (cf.
fig. 9) in (+3, +1) a length of 3 units is to
be measured along XOX in the positive
towards X, and a
direction, that is from
length +1 measured along YOY in the posi
towards F.
tive direction, that is from
Similarly in (3, +1) the length of 3 units
towards
and of
is to be measured from
Also in ( 3,
1 unit from
towards Y
1)
the two lengths are to be measured along
OX and OY respectively, and in (+3, -1)
along OX and OY respectively. Let us for
the moment call such a pair of numbers an
"ordered
Then, from the two
couple."
numbers 1 and 3, eight ordered couples can
be generated, namely
is
X
,
.
+ 1, +3), (-1, +3), (-1, -3), ( + 1, -3),
(+3, +1), (-3, +1), (-3, -1), (+3, -1).
(
Each
of these eight
"ordered couples"
directs
XOX
and
a process of measurement along
YOY which is different from that directed
by any of the others.
The processes of measurement represented
by the last four ordered couples, mentioned
above, are given pictorially in the figure.
The lengths
and ON together correspond
OM
94
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
OM
to (+3, +1), the lengths
and ON to
and
gether correspond to (-3, +1),
and
together to (-3, -1), and
together to (+3, -1). But by com
pleting the various rectangles, it is easy to
see that the point P completely determines
and is determined by the ordered couple
ON
ON
OM
OM
(+3, +1), the point P by (-3, +1), the
point
by (-3, -1), and the point P
More generally in the pre
by (+3,
1).
"
P"
vious figure (8), the point P corresponds to
the ordered couple (x, y), where x and y in
the figure are both assumed to be positive, the
point P corresponds to (# y), where x in
the figure is assumed to be negative,
to
f
P
and
to
Thus
an
ordered
,
9
(x y )
(x, y ).
,
P"
"
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
95
couple (x, y), where x and y are any positive
or negative numbers, and the corresponding
point reciprocally determine each other. It
is convenient to introduce some names at this
In the ordered couple (x, y) the
juncture.
first number x is called the "abscissa" of the
corresponding point, and the second number
y is called the "ordinate" of the point, and
the two numbers together are called the
The idea of de
"coordinates" of the point.
a
the
of
point by its "co
position
termining
ordinates" was by no means new when the
was being formed.
imaginaries
theory of
It was due to Descartes, the great French
mathematician and philosopher, and appears
in his Discours published at Ley den in 1637
The idea of the ordered couple as a
A.D.
thing on its own account is of later growth
and is the outcome of the efforts to interpret
imaginaries in the most abstract way possible.
It may be noticed as a further illustration
of this idea of the ordered couple, that the
in fig. 9 is the couple (+3, 0), the
point
f
is the couple (0, +1), the point
point
the couple
the couple (3, 0), the point
the
the
0).
(0,
-1),
point
couple
(0,
Another way of representing the ordered
couple (x, y) is to think of it as representing
the dotted line OP (cf. fig. 8), rather than the
point P. Thus the ordered couple represents
a line drawn from an "origin," 0, of a certain
"
"
M
N
N
M
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
96
length and in a certain direction. The line
OP may be called the vector line from to
P, or the step from to P. We see, therefore,
that we have in this chapter only extended
the interpretation which we gave formerly of
the positive and negative numbers.
This
method of representation by vectors is very
useful when we consider the meaning to be
assigned to the operations of the addition and
multiplication of ordered couples.
We will now go on to this question, and
ask what meaning we shall find it convenient
to assign to the addition of the two ordered
f
couples (x, y) and (x , y ). The interpreta
tion must, (a) make the result of addition
to be another ordered couple, (6) make the
operation commutative so that (x, y)-\f
(x y )=(x y )+(x 9 y), (c) make the opera
tion associative so that
,
,
make the result of subtraction unique,
when we seek to determine the un
known ordered couple (x, y) so as to satisfy
(d)
so that
the equation
(x 9
y)+(a,
b)
= (c,
d),
is one and only one answer which we
can represent by
there
(a:,
y)=(c, d)-(a,
b).
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
97
All these requisites are satisfied by taking
(x, y)+(x , y ) to mean the ordered couple
(x+x 9 y+y ). Accordingly by definition we
put
Notice that here we have adopted the mathe
matical habit of using the same symbol + in
+
different senses. The
of the equation has the
on the left-hand side
new meaning of -fwhich we are just defining; while the two
4- s on the right-hand side have the meaning
of the addition of positive and negative num
bers (operations) which was defined in the
No
last chapter.
practical confusion arises
this double use.
from
As examples
of addition
we have
(+3, +l)+(+2, +6) =(+5, +7),
(+3, -!)+(-, -6)=( + l, -7),
(+3, +l)+(-3, -1)=(0, 0).
The meaning
for us.
We
(a?,
of subtraction
find that
y)
is
now
settle
- (u, v)=(x-u,y -v).
Thus
(+3, +2)-(+l, +l)=(+2, +1),
and
(+1, -2) -(+2, -4)=(-l, +2),
and
(-1, -2) -(+2, +3) =(-3, -5).
1
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
98
It
is
easy to see that
(x, y)
- (u,
v)
= (x, y)+(-u,
-v).
Also
(0,0).
Hence
(0, 0)
is
to be looked on as the zero
For example
ordered couple.
+ (0,
Cr,2/)
0)=(*,
y).
The pictorial representation of the addition
of ordered couples is surprisingly easy.
Y
Fig. 10.
Let
OP
OM=x
so that
(a?, y)
represent (xi, yj so that
i =yi.
OMi =Xi and
Complete the paral
and
lelogram OPRQ by the dotted lines
QR, then the diagonal OR is the ordered
and
represent
PM =y;
let
OQ
QM
couple (x+Xi, y+yi).
PR
For draw
PS
parallel
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
to
OX; then
and
MM
PRS
evidently the triangles
are in all respects equal.
=PS=x
l9
and
RS^QM,;
Hence
and there
fore
OM = OM +MM = x +xi,
RM =SM +RS =
Thus
OR
required.
OP
represents the ordered couple as
This figure can also be drawn
and OQ in other quadrants.
at once obvious that we have here
come back to the parallelogram law, which
was mentioned in Chapter VI, on the laws of
motion, as applying to velocities and forces.
It will be remembered that, if OP and OQ
represent two velocities, a particle is said to
be moving with a velocity equal to the two
with
It
is
velocities added together if it be moving with
the velocity OR. In other words OR is said
to be the resultant of the two velocities OP
and OQ. Again forces acting at a point of
a body can be represented by lines just as
can be; and the same parallelogram
law holds, namely, that the resultant of the
two forces OP and OQ is the force represented
by the diagonal OR. It follows that we can
look on an ordered couple as representing a
velocity or a force, and the rule which we
have just given for the addition of ordered
couples then represents the fundamental laws
of mechanics for the addition of forces and
velocities
100
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
One of the most fascinating
characteristics of mathematics is the sur
prising way in which the ideas and results of
different parts of the subject dovetail into
each other. During the discussions of this
velocities.
and the previous chapter we have been guided
merely by the most abstract of pure mathe
matical considerations; and yet at the end
of them we have been led back to the most
fundamental of all the laws of nature, laws
which have to be in the mind of every en
gineer as he designs an engine, and of every
naval architect as he calculates the stability
of a ship. It is no paradox to say that in our
most theoretical moods we may be nearest
to our most practical applications.
CHAPTER
VIII
IMAGINARY NUMBERS (Continued)
THE
of the multiplication of
guided by exactly the same
considerations as is that of their addition.
The interpretation of multiplication must be
such that
(a) the result is another ordered couple,
(ft) the operation is commutative, so that
definition
ordered couples
(x 9 y)
(7)
X (x
9
y
the operation
\(x 9
)
= (x y ) X (x
9
is
9
y),
associative, so that
y)x(x ,y )}x(u,v)
= 0,
(8)
is
2/)x{(z
,
y )x(u,
v)} 9
must make the result
[with an
of division unique
exception for the case of the zero
couple (0, 0)], so that when we seek to de
termine the unknown couple (x y) so as to
satisfy the equation
9
0, 2/)x(a, 6)=(c, d)
one and only one answer, which we
9
there
is
can represent by
(x, y)
= (c,
d)
+ (a,
6),
101
or
by
(x 9 y)
=
g^j-
102
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Furthermore the law involving both
(e)
addition and multiplication, called the dis
tributive law, must be satisfied, namely
= \(x,y)X(a,b)\+\(x,y)x(c,d)\.
All these conditions (a), (), (7), (8), (e)
can be satisfied by an interpretation which,
though it looks complicated at first, is capable
of a simple geometrical interpretation.
By
(x, y)
definition
X
This
symbol
(*
is
,
2/0
we put
- {(** - 2/2/0,
f
(xy
+ x y]
\
(A)
the definition of the meaning of the
it is written between two
X when
ordered couples. It follows evidently from
this definition that the result of multiplica
is another ordered couple, and that the
value of the right-hand side of equation (A)
is not altered by simultaneously interchang
Hence condi
ing x with x and y with y
tion
f
,
.
tions (a) and (/3) are evidently satisfied.
proof of the satisfaction of (7), (S),
The
(e)
is
equally easy when we have given the geo
metrical interpretation, which we will pro
ceed to do in a moment. But before doing
be interesting to pause and see
whether we have attained the object for
which all this elaboration was initiated.
We came across equations of the form
z2 =
3, to which no solutions could be
this it will
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
103
assigned in terms of positive and negative
numbers. We then found that all our
difficulties would vanish if we could interpret
the equation x 2 =
1, i.e., if we could so de
real
that
xV(-l) = -1.
the
three special or
Now let us consider
dered couples * (0,0), (1,0), and (0,1).
We have already proved that
fine
V(-l)
VpT)
(*,)+ (0,0)
=(*,?).
Furthermore we now have
(*,y)x(0,0)-(0,0).
Hence both for addition and for multiplica
tion the couple (0,0) plays the part of zero in
elementary arithmetic and algebra; com
pare the above equations with x-{-Q=x and
9
Again consider (1, 0): this plays the part
of 1 in elementary arithmetic and algebra.
In these elementary sciences the special char
acteristic of 1 is that xXl = x, for all values
of x.
by our law of multiplication
Now
(*, y)
X(l, 0) ={(*-0), (y+0)} =(*, y).
Thus
(1, 0) is
*
the unit couple.
For the future we follow the custom of omitting the
wherever possible, thus f 1,0) stands for (+1,0) and
4- sign
(0,1) for
(O.+
l).
104
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Finally consider (0,1):
for us the
symbol V(
this will interpret
The symbol must
1).
therefore possess the characteristic property
that
V(~l)X V/(-l)=
law of
multiplication
(0,1)
X (0,1) ={(0-1),
But
(1,0) is
Now by the
ordered couples
-1.
for
(0+0)} =(-1, 0).
the unit couple, and (-1, 0)
the negative unit couple; so that (0,1) has
the desired property. There are, however,
two roots of
1 to be provided for, namely
is
=*=V(
1).
Consider
membering that
(0,
2
(
1)
1);
= 1, we
here again re
find, (0,
-1)
X(0, -1)=(-1,0).
Thus (0,
1) is the other square root of
V( 1). Accordingly the ordered couples
(0,1)
and
1)
(0,
are the interpretations of
terms of ordered couples. But
=*=V(
which corresponds to which? Does (0,1)
correspond to + V( 1) and (0,
1) to
1) in
-A/(-l),or
(0,1) to
-V(-l), and
(0,
-1)
1)? The answer is that it is per
fectly indifferent which symbolism we adopt.
The ordered couples can be divided into
to -f A/(
three types,
(i)
the
"complex
imaginary"
type (x,y\ in which neither x nor y is zero;
(ii) the
type (s,0); (iii) the "pure
Let us consider the
imaginary" type (0,y).
relations of these types to each other. First
"real"
multiply together the
"complex imaginary"
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
couple (x,y) and the
"real"
105
couple (a,0)
we
find
(a,0)
X (x,y) = (ax,
ay).
Thus the
effect is merely to multiply each
of the couple (x,y) by the positive or
negative real number a.
term
Secondly, multiply together the "complex
couple (x,y) and the "pure
imaginary" couple (0,6), we find
imaginary"
Here the effect is more complicated, and is
best comprehended in the geometrical inter
pretation to which we proceed after noting
three yet more special cases.
Thirdly, we multiply the
couple
(a,0) with the imaginary (0,6) and obtain
"real"
(a,0)X(0,6)=(0, a6).
Fourthly, we multiply the two
couples (a,0) and (a , 0) and obtain
(a,0)x(a ,0)=(aa
Fifthly,
couples"
(0,6)
We now
tation,
,0).
we multiply the two
(0,6)
and
(0, 6)
"real"
"imaginary
and obtain
x (0,6 ) =( -66
,
0).
turn to the geometrical interpre
beginning first with some special
106
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Take the couples (1,3) and (2,0) and
consider the equation
cases.
(2,0)
X (1,3) =(2,6)
(fig. 11) the vector OP
represents (1, 3), and the vector
repre
sents (0,2), and the vector OQ represents
Thus the product (2,0) X (1,3) is
(2,6).
found geometrically by taking the length of
the vector OQ to be the product of the
lengths of the vectors OP and ON, and (in
this case) by producing OP to Q to be of
the required length.
Again, consider the
In the diagram
product
X (1,3), we have
(0, 2) X (1,3) =(-6,
ON
(0,2)
2)
The vector ON, corresponds to
the vector OR to (-6,2). *Thus
and
which
(0, 2)
OR
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
107
represents the new product is at right angles
to OQ and of the same length. Notice that
we have the same law regulating the length
of OQ as in the previous case, namely, that
its length is the product of the lengths of
the two vectors which are multiplied to
gether; but now that we have ONi along the
"ordinate"
axis OF, instead of
along
the "abscissa" axis OX, the direction of OP
ON
has been turned through a right-angle.
Hitherto in these examples of multiplication
we have looked on the vector OP as modified
by the vectors ON and ONi. We shall get
a clue to the general law for the direction by
inverting the way of thought, and by think
ing of the vectors ON and ONi as modified by
the vector OP. The law for the length re
mains unaffected; the resultant length is the
length of the product of the two vectors.
The new direction for the enlarged ON (i.e.
OQ) is found by rotating it in the (anti-clock
wise) direction of rotation from OX towards
OF through an angle equal to the angle POX:
it is an accident of this particular case that
this rotation makes OQ lie along the line OP.
Again consider the product of ONi and OP;
the new direction for the enlarged ONi (i.e.
OR) is found by rotating ON in the anti
clockwise direction of rotation through an
angle equal to the angle POX, namely, the
angle NiOR is equal to the angle POX.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
108
The general rule for the geometrical repre
sentation of multiplication can now be
enunciated thus:
Fig. 12.
of the two vectors OP and
a vector OR, whose length is the pro
duct of the lengths of OP and OQ and whose
direction OR is such that the angle
is
to
the
sum
of
the
and
equal
angles
QOX.
Hence we can conceive the vector OP as
making the vector OQ rotate through an
angle
(i.e. the angle ROQ=the angle
POX), or the vector OQ as making the vector
OP rotate through the angle QOX (i.e. the
angle ROP = the angle QOX).
We do not prove this general law, as we
The product
OQ
is
ROX
POX
POX
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
109
should thereby be led into more technical
processes of mathematics than falls within the
design of this book. But now we can im
mediately see that the associative law [num
bered (7) above] for multiplication is satisfied.
Consider first the length of the resultant
vector; this is got by the ordinary process
of multiplication for real numbers; and thus
the associative law holds for it.
Again, the direction of the resultant vector
is got by the mere addition of angles, and the
associative law holds for this process also.
We
So much for multiplication.
have now
rapidly indicated, by considering addition and
multiplication, how an algebra or "calculus"
of vectors in one plane can be constructed,
which is such that any two vectors in the
plane can be added, or subtracted, and can
be multiplied, or divided one by the other.
have not considered the technical de
tails of all these processes because it would
lead us too far into mathematical details;
but we have shown the general mode of protedure. When we are interpreting our alge
braic symbols in this way, we are said to be
employing "imaginary quantities" or "com
These terms are mere
plex quantities."
details, and we have far too much to think
about to stop to enquire whether they are or
are not very happily chosen.
The net result of our investigations is that
We
110
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
like
any equations
x +3 = 2 or (#+3) 2 =
2
can now always be interpreted into terms of
In
vectors, and solutions found for them.
seeking for such interpretations it is well to
note that 3 becomes (3,0) and
2 becomes
(2,0), and x becomes the "unknown"
couple
(u, v):
so the
respectively (w,
v)
two equations become
and {(u,v)
+ (3,0) = (2,0),
We
have now completely solved the initial
which caught our eye as soon as
we considered even the elements of algebra.
The science as it emerges from the solution is
much more complex in ideas than that with
which we started. We have, in fact, created
a new and entirely different science, which
will serve all the purposes for which the old
science was invented and many more in addi
difficulties
tion.
But, before
we can
congratulate our
this result to our labours, we must
allay a suspicion which ought by this time to
have arisen in the mind of the student. The
selves
on
question which the reader ought to be asking
himself is: Where is all this invention of new
interpretations going to end? It is true that
we have succeeded in interpreting algebra so
as always to be able to solve a quadratic
2
%x +4=0; but there are
equation like x
an endless number of other equations, for
3
&r+4=0, a^+a: 3 +2=0, and so
example, x
on without limit. Have we got to make a
IMAGINARY NUMBERS
new
science whenever a
111
new equation ap
pears?
Now,
if
this
were the case, the whole of our
preceding investigations, though to some
minds they might be amusing, would in truth
be of very trifling importance. But the great
fact, which has made modern analysis possible,
is that, by the aid of this calculus of vectors,
every formula which arises can receive its
proper interpretation; and the "unknown"
quantity in every equation can be shown to
indicate some vector. Thus the science is now
itself as far as its fundamental
ideas are concerned. It was receiving its final
form about the same time as when the steam
complete in
engine was being perfected, and will remain
a great and powerful weapon for the achieve
ment of the victory of thought over things
when curious specimens of that machine
repose in museums in company with the
helmets and breastplates of a slightly earlier
epoch.
CHAPTER IX
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
THE methods and
ideas of coordinate geo
metry have already been employed in the
previous chapters. It is now time for us to
consider them more closely for their own
sake; and in doing so we shall strengthen our
hold on other ideas to which we have attained.
In the present and succeeding chapters we
will go back to the idea of the positive and
negative real numbers and will ignore the
imaginaries which were introduced in the last
two chapters.
We have been perpetually using the idea
that, by taking two axes, XOX and YOY
in a plane, any point P in that plane can be
determined in position by a pair of positive
or negative numbers x and y, where (cf.
fig. 13) x is the length OM and y is the length
,
PM
This conception, simple as it looks, is
the main idea of the great subject of co
Its discovery marks a
ordinate geometry.
momentous epoch in the history of mathe
It is due (as has been
matical thought.
.
112
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
113
already said) to the philosopher Descartes,
and occurred to him as an important mathe*matical method one morning as he lay in bed,
Philosophers,
when they have possessed a
thorough knowledge of mathematics, have
been among those who have enriched the
P
y
Y
Fig. 13.
science with some of its best ideas. On the
other hand it must be said that, with hardly
an exception, all the remarks on mathematics
made by those philosophers who have pos
sessed but a slight or hasty and late-acquired
knowledge of it are entirely worthless, being
either trivial or wrong. The fact is a curious
one; since the ultimate ideas of mathematics
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
114
i
all, to be very simple, almost
childishly so, and to lie well within the
province of philosophical thought. Probably
their very simplicity is the cause of error; we
are not used to think about such simple
seem, after
abstract things, and a long training is neces
sary to secure even a partial immunity from
error as soon as we diverge from the beaten
track of thought.
The discovery of coordinate geometry, and
also that of projective geometry about the
same time, illustrate another fact which is
being continually verified in the history of
knowledge, namely, that some of the greatest
discoveries are to be made among the most
well-known topics.
By the time that the
seventeenth century had arrived, geometry
had already been studied for over two thou
sand years, even if we date its rise with the
Greeks. Euclid, taught in the University of
Alexandria, being born about 330 B.C.; and he
only systematized and extended the work of a
long series of predecessors, some of them men
of genius. After him generation after genera
tion of mathematicians laboured at the im
Nor did the
provement of the subject.
from
that
fatal
to progress,
suffer
bar
subject
namely, that its study was confined to a
narrow group of men of similar origin and
outlook quite the contrary was the case;
by the seventeenth century it had passed
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
115
through the minds of Egyptians and Greeks,
Arabs and of Germans. And yet, after all
this labour devoted to it through so many
ages by such diverse minds its most important
secrets were yet to be discovered.
No one
can have studied even the elements of ele
mentary geometry without feeling the lack
of some guiding method. Every proposition
has to be proved by a fresh display of in
genuity; and a science for which this is true
of
lacks the great requisite of scientific thought,
namely, method. Now the especial point of
coordinate geometry is that for the first
time it introduced method.
The remote
deductions of a mathematical science are not
of primary theoretical importance.
The
science has not been perfected, until it consists
in essence of the exhibition of great allied
methods by which information, on any desired
topic which falls within its scope, can easily
be obtained. The growth of a science is not
primarily in bulk, but in ideas; and the more
the ideas grow, the fewer are the deductions
which it is worth while to write down. Un
fortunately, mathematics is always encum
bered by the repetition in text-books of
numberless subsidiary propositions, whose im
portance has been lost by their absorption
into the role of particular cases of more
general truths and, as we have already in
sisted, generality is the soul of mathematics.
116
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Again, coordinate geometry illustrates
another feature of mathematics which has
already been pointed out, namely, that mathe
matical sciences as they develop dovetail into
each other, and share the same ideas in com
mon. It is not too much to say that the
various branches of mathematics undergo a
perpetual process of generalization, and that
become generalized, they coalesce.
Here again the reason springs from the very
as they
nature of the science, its generality, that is
to say, from the fact that the science deals
with the general truths which apply to all
things in virtue of their very existence as
things. In this connection the interest of co
ordinate geometry lies in the fact that it
relates together geometry, which started as
the science of space, and algebra, which has
its origin in the science of number.
Let us now recall the main ideas of the two
sciences, and then see how they are related
by Descartes method of coordinates. Take
will not trouble
algebra in the first place.
ourselves about the imaginaries and will
think merely of the real numbers with posi
tive or negative signs. The fundamental idea
is that of any number, the variable number,
We
which is denoted by a letter and not by any
definite numeral.
then proceed to the
consideration of correlations between vari
ables. For example, if x and y are two vari-
We
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
117
we may conceive them as correlated by
x+y = \, or by x +?/ = !, or in
of
an
one
indefinite
number of other ways.
any
ables,
the equations
This at once leads to the application of the
idea of algebraic form.
We think,
in fact, of
some
interesting type, thus
rising from the initial conception of vari
able numbers to the secondary conception of
variable correlations of numbers. Thus we
into the
generalize the correlation #+2/ =
correlation ax
by = c. Here a and b and c,
being letters, stand for any numbers and are
in fact themselves variables.
But they are
the variables which determine the variable
any
correlation of
l>
+
correlation;
and the
correlation,
when
deter
mined, correlates the variable numbers x and
Variables, like a, 6, and c above, which
y.
are used to determine the correlation, are
called "constants," or parameters. The use
of the term "constant" in this connection
for what is really a variable may seem at first
sight to be odd; but it is really very natural.
For the mathematical investigation is con
cerned with the relation between the variables
x and y, after a, &, c are supposed to have
been determined. So in a sense, relatively to
x and y, the "constants" a, b, and c are con
stants
.
Thus ax+by = c stands for the general
example of a certain algebraic form, that is,
for a variable correlation belonging to a cer
tain class.
118
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
2
2
2
Again we generalize # +2/ = l into ax -}-
by2
= c,
C9
or
further into ax 2 +%hxy -\-by 2
2
2
further, into ax -\-hxy-\- by -}-%gx
still
or, still
+%fy=c.
Here again we are
led to variable correla
tions which are indicated by their various
algebraic forms.
Now let us turn to geometry. The
of the science at once recalls to our
name
minds
the thought of figures and diagrams exhibiting
and rectangles and squares and
circles, all in special relations to each other.
The study of the simple properties of these
figures is the subject matter of elementary
geometry, as it is rightly presented to the
beginner. Yet a moment s thought will show
that this is not the true conception of the
subject. It may be right for a child to com
triangles
mence
on shapes,
and squares, which he has cut
out with scissors. What, however, is a tri
angle? It is a figure marked out and bounded
by three bits of three straight lines.
Now the boundary of spaces by bits of
lines is a very complicated idea, and not at
all one which gives any hope of exhibiting
his geometrical reasoning
like triangles
the simple general conceptions which should
form the bones of the subject. We want
something more simple and more general. It
is this obsession with the wrong initial ideas
very natural and good ideas for the creation
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
119
of first thoughts on the subject
which was
the cause of the comparative sterility of the
study of the science during so many centuries.
Coordinate geometry, and Descartes
its in
ventor, must have the credit of disclosing the
true simple objects for geometrical thought.
In the place of a bit of a straight line, let
us think of the whole of a straight line
throughout its unending length in both direc
tions.
This is the sort of general idea from
which to start our geometrical investigations.
The Greeks never seem to have found any
use for this conception which is now funda
mental in all modern geometrical thought.
Euclid always contemplates a straight line as
drawn between two definite points, and is
very careful to mention when it is to be pro
duced beyond this segment. He never thinks
of the line as an entity given once for all as a
whole. This careful definition and limitation,
so as to exclude an infinity not immedi
ately apparent to the senses, was very char
acteristic of the Greeks in all their many
activities.
It
is
enshrined in the difference
between Greek architecture and Gothic archi
tecture, and between the Greek religion and
the modern religion. The spire on a Gothic
cathedral and the importance of the un
bounded straight line in modern geometry
are both emblematic of the transformation of
the modern world.
120
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
The
is
straight line, considered as a whole,
accordingly
the
modern geometry
root
idea
from which
But then
and we arrive
starts.
other
at the
sorts of lines occur to us,
of
the
curve
which
at
complete
conception
every point of it exhibits some uniform char
acteristic, just as the straight line exhibits
at all points the characteristic of straightness. For example, there is the circle which
at all points exhibits the characteristic of
being at a given distance from its centre, and
again there is the ellipse, which is an oval
curve, such that the sum of the two distances
of any point on it from two fixed points, called
its foci, is constant for all points on the curve.
It is evident that a circle is merely a particu
lar case of an ellipse when the two foci are
superposed in the same point; for then the
sum of the two distances is merely twice
the radius of the circle. The ancients knew
the properties of the ellipse and the circle and,
of course, considered them as wholes.
For
example, Euclid never starts with mere seg
ments (i.e., bits) of circles, which are then pro
longed. He always considers the whole circle
It is unfortunate that the
as described.
circle is not the true fundamental line in
geometry, so that his defective consideration
of the straight line might have been of less
consequence.
This general idea of a curve which at any
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
121
point of it exhibits some uniform property is
expressed in geometry by the term "locus."
locus is the curve (or surface, if we do not
confine ourselves to a plane) formed by points,
A
of which possess some given property.
every property in relation to each other
which points can have, there corresponds
some locus, which consists of all the points
In investigating
possessing the property.
the properties of a locus considered as a
whole, we consider any point or points on
the locus. Thus in geometry we again meet
with the fundamental idea of the variable.
Furthermore, in classifying loci under such
headings as straight lines, circles, ellipses,
etc., we again find the idea of form.
Accordingly, as in algebra we are con
cerned with variable numbers, correlations
between variable numbers, and the classifica
tion of correlations into types by the idea of
algebraic form; so in geometry we are con
cerned with variable points, variable points
satisfying some condition so as to form a
locus, and the classification of loci into types
by the idea of conditions of the same form.
Now, the essence of coordinate geometry
is the identification of the algebraic corre
lation with the geometrical locus. The point
on a plane is represented in algebra by its
two coordinates, x and y, and the condition
satisfied by any point on the locus is repreall
To
122
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
sented
the
corresponding correlation
Finally to correlations
y.
expressible in some general algebraic form,
such as ax+by = c there correspond loci of
some general type, whose geometrical con
ditions are all of the same form.
We have
thus arrived at a position where we can
effect a complete interchange in ideas and
Each
results between the two sciences.
science throws light on the other, and itself
by
between x and
9
It is im
gains immeasurably in power.
possible not to feel stirred at the thought
of the emotions of men at certain historic
moments of adventure and discovery
Columbus when he first saw the Western
shore, Pizarro when he stared at the Pacific
Ocean, Franklin when the electric spark
came from the string of his kite, Galileo
when he first turned his telescope to the
heavens. Such moments are also granted to
students in the abstract regions of thought,
and high among them must be placed the
morning when Descartes lay in bed and in
vented the method of coordinate geometry.
When one has once grasped the idea of
coordinate geometry, the immediate ques
tion which starts to the mind is, Wliat sort of
loci correspond to the well-known algebraic
forms? For example, the simplest among
the general types of algebraic forms is ax
by
= c. The
+
sort of locus
which corresponds
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
to this
is
a straight
line,
123
and conversely to
every straight line there corresponds an equa
It is fortunate that the
tion of this form.
simplest among the geometrical loci should
correspond to the simplest among the al
gebraic forms. Indeed, it is this general
correspondence of geometrical and algebraic
simplicity which gives to the whole subject
It springs from the fact that the
its power.
connection between geometry and algebra is
not casual and artificial, but deep-seated and
The equation which corresponds
essential.
to a locus is called the equation of (or
the locus. Some examples of equations of
straight lines will illustrate the subject.
"to")
Fig
14
124
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Consider y # = 0; here the a, b and c, of
the general form have been replaced by 1,
1,
and respectively. This line passes through
the "origin," 0, in the diagram and bisects
the angle XOY. It is the line L OL of the
diagram. The fact that it passes through the
origin, 0, is easily seen by observing that the
equation is satisfied by putting x = Q and
y = simultaneously, but and are the co
ordinates of 0. In fact it is easy to generalize
and to see by the same method that the
equation of any line through the origin is of
the form ax+by = Q. The locus of equation
= also passes through the origin and
y-\-x
bisects the angle
OY: it is the line
i
of the diagram.
Consider y x 1 the corresponding locus
does not pass through the origin. We there
fore seek where it cuts the axes. It must cut
the axis of x at some point of coordinates
x and 0. But putting y = in the equation,
we get x = 1 ; so the coordinates of this
1 and 0. Similarly the point
point (A) are
and
(B) where the line cuts the axis OY are
1.
The locus is the line
in the figure and
is parallel to LOL
Similarly y+x = l is the
equation of line AJ3 of the figure; and the
9
X
L&L
:
AB
.
is parallel to LiOL i.
It is easy to prove
the general theorem that two lines represented
by equations of the forms ax+by = Q and
locus
ax+by = c
are parallel.
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
125
which we next come
important to deserve a
chapter to themselves. But before going on
to them we will dwell a little longer on the
The group
upon are
main
of loci
sufficiently
ideas of the subject.
The position of any point P is determined
by arbitrarily choosing an origin, 0, two
axes, OX and OF, at right-angles, and then
by noting its coordinates x and y i.e. OM
and PM. Also, as we have seen in the last
9
chapter,
P
can be determined by the
"vec
OP, where the idea
of the vector in
cludes a determinate direction as well as a
tor"
From an abstract
determinate length.
mathematical point of view the idea of an
arbitrary origin may appear artificial and
clumsy, and similarly for the arbitrarily
drawn
axes,
OX
and OF.
But
in relation to
the application of mathematics to the events
of the Universe we are here symbolizing with
direct simplicity the most fundamental fact
respecting the outlook on the world afforded
We each of us refer
to us by our senses.
our sensible perceptions of things to an origin
which we call "here": our location in a
particular part of
space round which we
is the essential fact
group the whole Universe
of our bodily existence.
We
can imagine
beings who observe all phenomena in all space
with an equal eye, unbiassed in favour of any
With us it is otherwise, a cat at our
part.
126
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
feet claims more attention than an earth
quake at Cape Horn, or than the destruction
of a world in the Milky Way. It is true that
in making a common stock of our knowledge
with our fellowmen, we have to waive some
thing of the strict egoism of our own in
We substitute "nearly
dividual "here."
for "here"; thus we measure miles
here"
from the town hall of the nearest town, or
from the capital of the country. In measuring
the earth, men of science will put the origin
astronomers even
at the earth s centre;
rise to the extreme altruism of putting their
origin inside the sun. But, far as this last
origin may be, and even if we go further to
some convenient point amid the nearer fixed
stars, yet, compared to the immeasurable
infinities of space, it remains true that our
first procedure in exploring the Universe is
to fix upon an origin "nearly here."
Again the relation of the coordinates
and
(i.e. x and y) to the vector OP is an
instance of the famous parallelogram law, as
can easily be seen (cf. diagram) by completing
the parallelogram OMPN. The idea of the
"vector"
OP, that is, of a directed magni
tude, is the root-idea of physical science.
Any moving body has a certain magnitude
of velocity in a certain direction, that is to
say, its velocity is a directed magnitude, a
MP
vector.
OM
Again a force has a certain magni-
COORDINATE GEOMETRY
tude and has a definite direction.
when
127
Thus,
analytical geometry the ideas of
the "origin," of "coordinates," and of
are introduced, we are studying
"vectors"
the abstract conceptions which correspond
to the fundamental facts of the physical
world.
in
CHAPTER X
CONIC SECTIONS
WHEN the Greek geometers had exhausted,
as they thought, the more obvious and inter
esting properties of figures made up of
straight lines and circles, they turned to
the study of other curves; and, with their
almost infallible instinct for hitting upon
things worth thinking about, they chiefly
devoted themselves to conic sections, that
is, to the curves in which planes would cut
The man
the surfaces of circular cones.
who must have the credit of inventing the
study is Menaechmus (born 375 B.C. and
died 325 B.C.); he was a pupil of Plato and
one of the tutors of Alexander the Great.
Alexander, by the by, is a conspicuous ex
ample of the advantages of good tuition,
for another of his tutors was the philosopher
We may suspect that Alexander
Aristotle.
found Menaechmus rather a dull teacher,
for it is related that he asked for the proofs
128
CONIC SECTIONS
129
to be made shorter. It was to this request
that Menaechmus replied: "In the country
there are private and even royal roads, but
in geometry there is only one road for
This reply no doubt was true enough in
the sense in which it would have been imme
But if
diately understood by Alexander.
Menaechmus thought that his proofs could
not be shortened, he was grievously mis
taken; and most modern mathematicians
would be horribly bored, if they were com
pelled to study the Greek proofs of the prop
erties of conic sections.
Nothing illustrates
better the gain in power which is obtained
by the introduction of relevant ideas into a
science than to observe the progressive
shortening of proofs which accompanies the
all."
There is a cer
of richness in idea.
tain type of mathematician who is always
rather impatient at delaying over the ideas
of a subject: he is anxious at once to get on
to the proofs of "important" problems. The
history of the science is entirely against him.
There are royal roads in science; but those
who first tread them are men of genius and
growth
not kings.
The way in which conic sections first pre
sented themselves to mathematicians was as
follows: think of a cone (cf. fig. 15), whose
vertex (or point) is V, standing on a circular
base STU. For example, a conical shade to
130
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
an electric light is often an example of such
a surface. Now let the "generating" lines
which pass through V and lie on the surface
be all produced backwards; the result is a
double cone, and PQR is another circular
V
cross section on the opposite side of
to the
cross section STU.
The axis of the cone
f
passes through all the centres of these
circles and is perpendicular to their planes,
which are parallel to each other. In the
diagram the parts of the curves which are
supposed to lie behind the plane of the paper
CVC
are dotted lines, and the parts on the plane
or in front of it are continuous lines. Now
suppose this double cone is cut by a plane
not perpendicular to the axis CVC or at
least not necessarily perpendicular to it.
Then three cases can arise:
(1) The plane may cut the cone in a
closed oval curve, such as
E which
lies entirely on one of the two half -cones.
In this case the plane will not meet the other
half -cone at all.
Such a curve is called an
is
it
an
oval
A particular
curve.
ellipse;
case of such a section of the cone is when
the plane is perpendicular to the axis CVC ,
then the section, such as
or PQR, is a
circle.
Hence a circle is a particular case of
the ellipse.
(2) The plane may be parallel to one of
the "generating" lines of the cone, as for
9
AEA
STU
CONIC SECTIONS
131
example the plane of the curve DiAiDi in
the diagram is parallel to the generating line
VS; the curve is still confined to one of the
half-cones, but it is now not a closed oval
curve, it goes on endlessly as long as the
generating lines of the half-cone are pro
duced away from the vertex. Such a conic
section
(3)
is
called a parabola.
The plane may
cut both the half-
cones, so that the complete curve consists of
two detached portions, or "branches" as
they are called; this case is illustrated by
two branches G 2A 2 G 2 and LiAJLJ
which together make up the curve. Neither
branch is closed, each of them spreading out
the
endlessly as the
away from the
is
two half -cones are prolonged
vertex. Such a conic section
called a hyperbola.
There are accordingly three types of conic
sections, namely, ellipses, parabolas, and
hyperbolas. It is easy to see that, in a sense,
parabolas are limiting cases lying between
ellipses and hyperbolas.
They form a more
special sort and have to satisfy a more par
ticular condition.
These three names are
apparently due to Apollonius of Perga (born
about 260 B.C., and died about 200 B.C.),
who wrote a systematic treatise on conic
sections which remained the standard work
till the sixteenth century.
It must at once be apparent how awkward
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
132,
and
the investigation of the proper
these curves must have been to the
Greek geometers. The curves are plane
curves, and yet their investigation involves
difficult
ties of
the drawing in perspective of a solid figure.
in the diagram given above we have
practically drawn no subsidiary lines and yet
the figure is sufficiently complicated. The
Thus
CONIC SECTIONS
133
curves are plane curves, and it seems obvious
that we should be able to define them without
B
going beyond the plane into a solid figure.
At the same time, just as in the "solid"
M
Fig. 17.
definition there is one uniform method of
definition
namely, the section of a cone by
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
134
which yields three cases, so in any
definition there also should be one
uniform method of procedure which falls into
Their shapes when drawn on
three cases.
their planes are those of the curved lines in
a plane
"plane"
the three figures 16, 17, and 18. The points
and A in the figures are called the ver-
A
Fig. 18.
and the line AA the major axis. It
be noted that a parabola (cf. fig. 17) has
*
that
only one vertex. Apollonius proved
tices
will
the ratio of
PM to AM.M
(i.e.
..
\
-
A
AM.MA
4
remains constant both for the
hyperbola
*
(figs.
Cf. Ball, loc.
Pappus.
ellipse and the
16 and 18), and that the ratio
cit.t
for this account of Apollonius
and
CONIC SECTIONS
of
of
PM
on
2
to
17;
fig.
AM
is
constant for the parabola
and he bases most
this fact.
We
135
of his
work
are evidently advancing
towards the desired uniform definition which
does not go out of the plane; but have not
yet quite attained to uniformity.
In the diagrams 16 and 18, two points, S
and S will be seen marked, and in diagram 17
one points, S. These are the foci of the curves,
and are points of the greatest importance.
Apollonius knew that for an ellipse the sum
of SP and S P (i.e. SP+S P) is constant, as
P moves on the curve and is equal to AA 1
Similarly for a hyperbola the difference S
,
.
P
SP is constant, and equal to AA when P is
SP
on one branch, and the difference, SP
is constant and equal to AA when P is on
y
But no corresponding
the other branch.
point seemed to exist for the parabola.
Finally 500 years later the last great Greek
geometer, Pappus of Alexandria, discovered
the final secret which completed this line of
thought. In the diagrams 16 and 18 will be
and in diagram
and
seen two lines,
17 the single line, XN. These are the direc
trices of the curves, two each for the ellipse
and the hyperbola, and one for the parabola.
Each directrix corresponds to its nearer focus.
The characteristic property of a focus, S, and
XN
its
XN
corresponding directrix,
of the three types of curve,
,
XN,
is
for
any one
that the ratio
136
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
t. e.
SP to PN ft.
is
constant, where
PN is
the perpendicular on the directrix from P,
and P is any point on the curve. Here we
have finally found the desired property of the
curves which does not require us to leave
the plane, and is stated uniformly for all
three curves.
than
1,
For ellipses, the
for parabolas it
equal to
SP
-=
is less
1,
and
for
greater than 1.
Pappus had finished his investiga
hyperbolas
When
is
ratio
it is
he must have felt that, apart from
minor extensions, the subject was practically
exhausted; and if he could have foreseen the
history of science for more than a thousand
years, it would have confirmed his belief.
Yet in truth the really fruitful ideas in con
nection with this branch of mathematics had
not yet been even touched on, and no one
had guessed their supremely important ap
No more impressive
plications in nature.
warning can be given to those who would
confine knowledge and research to what is
apparently useful, than the reflection that
conic -sections were studied for eighteen hun
dred years merely as an abstract science,
without a thought of any utility other than
to satisfy the craving for knowledge on the
part of mathematicians, and that then at the
end of this long period of abstract study, they
tions,
CONIC SECTIONS
137
were found to be the necessary key with
which to attain the knowledge of one of the
most important laws of nature.
Meanwhile the entirely distinct study of
astronomy had been going forward. The
great Greek astronomer Ptolemy (died 168
A.D.) published his standard treatise on the
subject in the University of Alexandria, ex
plaining the apparent motions among the
fixed stars of the sun and planets by the con
ception of the earth at rest and the sun and
the planets circling round it.
During the
next thirteen hundred years the number and
the accuracy of the astronomical observa
tions increased, with the result that the de
scription of the motions of the planets on
Ptolemy s hypothesis had to be made more
and more complicated. Copernicus (born
1473 A.D. and died 1543 A.D.) pointed out
that the motions of these heavenly bodies
could be explained in a simpler manner if the
sun were supposed to rest, and the earth and
planets were conceived as moving round it.
However, he still thought of these motions as
essentially circular, though modified by a set
of small corrections arbitrarily superimposed
on the primary circular motions. So the
matter stood when Kepler was born at Stutt
gart in Germany in 1571 A.D. There were
two sciences, that of the geometry of conic
sections and that of astronomy, both of which
138
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
had been studied from a remote antiquity
without a suspicion of any connection be
tween the two. Kepler was an astronomer,
but he was also an able geometer, and on the
subject of conic sections had arrived at ideas
advance of his time. He is only one of
examples of the falsity of the idea that
success in scientific research demands an ex
clusive absorption in one narrow line of study.
Novel ideas are more apt to spring from
an unusual assortment of knowledge not
necessarily from vast knowledge, but from a
thorough conception of the methods and ideas
of distinct lines of thought.
It will be re
membered that Charles Darwin was helped
to arrive at his conception of the law of
evolution
by reading Malthus famous Essay
on Population, a work dealing with a dif
ferent subject at least, as it was then
in
many
thought.
Kepler enunciated three laws of planetary
motion, the first two in 1609, and the third
ten years later. They are as follows:
(1) The orbits of the planets are ellipses,
the sun being in the focus.
(2) As a planet moves in its orbit, the
radius vector from the sun to the planet
sweeps out equal areas in equal times.
(3) The squares of the periodic times of the
several planets are proportional to the cubes
of their major axes.
CONIC SECTIONS
139
These laws proved to be only a stage to
wards a more fundamental development of
ideas.
Newton (born 1642 A.D. and died
1727 A.D.) conceived the idea of universal
gravitation, namely, that any two pieces of
matter attract each other with a force pro
portional to the product of their masses and
inversely proportional to the square of their
This sweeping
distance from each other.
general law, coupled with the three laws of
motion which he put into their final general
shape, proved adequate to explain all astro
nomical phenomena, including Kepler s laws,
and has formed the basis of modern physics.
Among other things he proved that comets
might move in very elongated ellipses, or in
parobolas, or in hyperbolas, which are nearly
parabolas. The comets which return such
as Halley s comet must, of course, move in
ellipses. But the essential step in the proof of
the law of gravitation, and even in the sug
gestion of its initial conception, was the veri
fication of Kepler s laws connecting the
motions of the planets with the theory of
conic sections.
From the seventeenth century onwards the
abstract theory of the curves has shared in
the double renaissance of geometry due to
the introduction of coordinate geometry and
In protective geo
cluster round
ideas
the
fundamental
metry
of projective geometry.
140
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
the consideration of sets (or pencils, as they
are called) of lines passing through a common
Now
point (the vertex of the "pencil").
(cf. fig. 19) if A, B, C, D, be any four fixed
points on a conic section and P be a variable
point on the curve, the pencil of lines PA,
Fig. 19.
PB, PC, and PD, has a
known as the constancy of
special property,
cross ratio. It
will suffice here to say that cross ratio is a
fundamental idea in projective geometry.
For projective geometry this is really the
definition of the curves, or some analogous
property which is really equivalent to it. It
its
CONIC SECTIONS
141
will be seen how far in the course of ages of
study we have drifted away from the old
original idea of the sections of a circular cone.
We know now that the Greeks had got hold
of a minor property of comparatively slight
importance; though by some divine good
fortune the curves themselves deserved all
the attention which was paid to them. This
unimportance of the "section" idea is now
marked in ordinary mathematical phrase
ology by dropping the word from their
As often as not, they are now
names.
named merely "conies" instead of "conic
sections."
we come back
to the point at
coordinate geometry in the last
chapter. We had asked what was the type
of loci corresponding to the general algebraic
form ax-{-by=c 9 and had found that it was
the class of straight lines in the plane.
had seen that every straight line possesses an
equation of this form, and that every equation
of this form corresponds to a straight line.
We now wish to go on to the next general
type of algebraic forms. This is evidently
to be obtained by introducing terms involv
2
2
Thus the new general
ing x and xy and y
form must be written
Finally,
which we
left
We
.
ax 2 +2hxy +by 2 +2gx +2fy +c =
What
does this represent?
The answer
is
142
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
that it always represents a conic section, and,
furthermore, that the equation of every conic
section can always be put into this shape.
The discrimination of the particular sorts of
conies as given by this form of equation is
very easy. It entirely depends upon the con
2
sideration of
where a, 6, and h, are
,
the "constants" as written above. If ab
h 2 is a positive number, the curve is an
abh
ellipse;
if
bola:
and
curve
is
abh
if
ab
2
= Q,
h2
is
the curve is a para
a negative number, the
a hyperbola.
For example, put a = 6 = 1,
c=
= 0.
We
h=g=f = Q,
then get the equation # 2 +2/ 2 4
It is easy to prove that this is the equa
tion of a circle, whose centre is at the origin,
2
and radius is 2 units of length. Now
becomes 1 Xl O 2 that is, 1, and is therefore
Hence the circle is a particular
positive.
case of an ellipse, as it ought to be. Genera
lizing, the equation of any circle can be
2
2
put into the form a(x +y ) +2gx+2fy+c=Q.
2
Hence
becomes a2 0, that is, a 2
which is necessarily positive. Accordingly
all circles satisfy the condition for ellipses.
The general form of the equation of a para
bola is
4.
abh
,
abh
,
2
(dx+ey) -Hfy
so that the terms of the second degree, as
CONIC SECTIONS
143
they are called, can be written as a perfect
square. For squaring out, we get
so that by comparison a d2 9 h=de, b=e2 9
2 =
d 2e 2 (de) 2 = 0. Hence
and therefore
the necessary condition is automatically satis
The equation %xy 4=0, where a = b
fied.
abh
= 0=j* = 0, h = l, c=
bola.
I2,
4, represents a hyper
For the condition abk 2 becomes
that is,
1, which is negative.
Some exceptional cases are included in the
general form of the equation which may not
be immediately recognized as conic sections.
By properly choosing the constants the equa
tion can be made to represent two straight
lines.
may
Now
fairly
two
intersecting straight lines
be said to come under the Greek
idea of a conic section. For, by referring to
the picture of the double cone above, it will
be seen that some planes through the vertex,
V, will cut the cone in a pair of straight lines
intersecting at V. The case of two parallel
straight lines can be included by considering
a circular cylinder as a particular case of a
Then a plane, which cuts it and is
cone.
parallel to its axis, will cut it in two parallel
straight lines. Anyhow, whether or no the
ancient Greek would have allowed these
special cases to be called conic sections, they
144
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
are certainly included among the curves re
presented by the general algebraic form of
the second degree. This fact is worth noting;
for
it is
characteristic of
modern mathematics
general forms all sorts of
particular cases which would formerly have
received special treatment. This is due to
to include
its
among
pursuit of generality.
CHAPTER XI
FUNCTIONS
THE mathematical use of the term function
has been adopted also in common life. For
example, "His temper is a function of his
the term exactly in this
digestion," uses
mathematical sense. It means that a rule
can be assigned which will tell you what his
temper will be when you know how his
Thus the idea of a
digestion is working.
"function" is
simple enough, we only have
to see how it is applied in mathematics to
variable numbers. Let us think first of some
concrete examples If a train has been travel
ling at the rate of twenty miles per hour, the
distance (s miles) gone after any number of
hours, say t, is given by s=%QXt 9 and s is
called a function of t. Also 20 X t is the func
tion of t with which s is identical. If John
is one year older than Thomas, then, when
Thomas is at any age of x years, John s age
l; and y is a
(y years) is given by y=x
function of x, namely, is the function # + 1.
In these examples t and x are called the
:
+
145
146
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
"arguments"
of the functions in
which they
appear. Thus t is the argument of the func
tion 20 Xt, and x is the argument of the func
tion x + 1. If s=20X/, and y=x + l, then s
and y are called the "values" of the functions
20 Xt and x+l respectively.
Coming now to the general case, we can
define a function in mathematics as a corre
lation between two variable numbers, called
respectively the argument and the value of
the function, such that whatever value be
assigned to the "argument of the function"
the value of the "value of the function" is
The
definitely (i.e. uniquely) determined.
converse is not necessarily true, namely, that
when the value of the function is determined
the argument is also uniquely determined.
Other functions of the argument x are y = x 2 ,
y=%x2 +3x + l, y=x,y=logx, y=sin
x.
The
group will be
who
understand
those
readily recognizable by
a little algebra and trigonometry. It is not
worth while to delay now for their explana
tion as they are merely quoted for the sake
last
two functions
of example.
Up to this point,
of
this
though we have defined
what we mean by a function in general, we
have only mentioned a series of special func
But mathematics, true to its general
tions.
methods of procedure, symbolizes the general
idea of any function. It does this by writing
FUNCTIONS
147
9 etc., for any function of
F(x),f(x) 9 g(x),
where the argument x is placed in a bracket
and some letter like F,f, g,
etc., is prefixed
to the bracket to stand for the function.
This notation has its defects. Thus it ob
viously clashes with the convention that the
single letters are to represent variable num
bers; since here F, /, g, $, etc., prefixed to a
bracket stand for variable functions.
It
would be easy to give examples in which we
can only trust to common sense and the
context to see what is meant.
One way of
evading the confusion is by using Greek
letters (e.g.
as above) for functions; an
other way is to keep to / and F (the initial
letter of function) for the functional letter,
and, if other variable functions have to be
symbolized, to take an adjacent letter like g.
With these explanations and cautions, we
write y f(x) to denote that y is the value of
some undetermined function of the argument
<t>(x)
x,
<,
<f>
,
where f(x) may stand for anything such
2
&r-f-l, sin x, log x, or merely for
+1, x
x itself. The essential point is that when x
is given, then y is thereby definitely deter
mined. It is important to be quite clear as
to the generality of this idea. Thus in y
x;
as
we may determine, if we choose, f(x) to
mean that when x is an integer, f(x) is zero,
and when x has any other value, f(x) is 1.
f(x),
Accordingly, putting y =f(x), with this choice
148
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
or 1 accord
for the meaning of /, y is either
ing as the value of x is integral or otherwise.
Thus /(I) = 0, /(2) = 0, /( J) = 1, /( V$) = 1, and
This choice for the meaning of f(x)
gives a perfectly good function of the argu
ment x according to the general definition of
a function.
function, which after all is only a sort
of correlation between two variables, is rep
resented like other correlations by a graph,
that is in effect by the methods of coordinate
geometry. For example, fig. 2 in Chapter II
so on.
A
is
the graph of the function - where v
is
the
argument and p the value of the function.
In this case the graph is only drawn for posi
tive values of v, which are the only values
possessing any meaning for the physical ap
plication considered in that chapter. Again
in fig. 14 of Chapter IX the whole length of
the line AB, unlimited in both directions, is
the graph of the function x + I, where x is the
argument and y is the value of the function;
and in the same figure the unlimited line
AiB is the graph of the function 1 x, and
the line LOU is the graph of the function x,
x being the argument and y the value of the
function.
These functions, which are expressed by
simple algebraic formulae, are adapted for
But for some
representation by graphs.
FUNCTIONS
149
functions this representation would be very
misleading without a detailed explanation, or
might even be impossible. Thus, consider
the function mentioned above, which has the
value 1 for all values of its argument x, except
those which are integral, e.g. except for x = 0,
x = l, x = %, etc., when it has the value 0.
Its appearance on a graph would be that of
the straight line
drawn parallel to the
ABA
B Cf C2 C3 C4
12345
Fig. 20.
axis
XOX
length.
at a distance from
But the points d,
it
(7 2 ,
ol 1 unit of
C C
3,
4,
etc.,
corresponding to the values 1, 2, 3, 4, etc., of
the argument x, are to be omitted, and in
stead of them the points BI, B 2)
s
B^ etc.,
on the axis OX, are to be taken. It is easy
to find functions for which the graphical
representation is not only inconvenient but
Functions which do not lend
impossible.
themselves to graphs are important in the
B
,
150
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
higher mathematics, but we need not concern
ourselves further about them here.
The most important division between func
tions is that between continuous and discon
tinuous functions.
function is continuous
A
when
its
value
only
alters
gradually
gradual alterations of the argument,
for
and
is
when it can alter its value by
sudden jumps. Thus the two functions x + 1
discontinuous
and
Ix,
whose graphs are depicted as
Chapter IX, are con
straight lines in fig. 14 of
tinuous functions, and so
is
the function -,
v
depicted in Chapter II, if we only think of
But the function de
positive values of v.
picted in fig. 20 of this chapter is discontinu
ous since at the values x = 1, x = 2, etc., of its
argument, its value gives sudden jumps.
Let us think of some examples of functions
presented to us in nature, so as to get into
our heads the real bearing of continuity and
discontinuity. Consider a train in its journey
along a railway line, say from Euston Station,
the terminus in London of the London and
North- Western Railway. Along the line in
order lie the stations of Bletchley and Rugby.
Let t be the number of hours which the train
has been on its journey from Euston, and s be
the number of miles passed over. Then s is
a function of t, i.e. is the variable value cor
responding to the variable argument t. If
FUNCTIONS
151
we know the circumstances of the train s
run, we know s as soon as any special value
of t is given. Now, miracles apart, we may
confidently assume that s is a continuous
function of t. It is impossible to allow for
the contingency that we can trace the train
continuously from Euston to Bletchley, and
that then, without any intervening time, how
ever short, it should appear at Rugby. The
idea is too fantastic to enter into our calcula
tion: it contemplates possibilities not to be
found outside the Arabian Nights; and even
in those tales sheer discontinuity of motion
hardly enters into the imagination, they do
not dare to tax our credulity with anything
more than very unusual speed. But unusual
speed is no contradiction to the great law of
continuity of motion which appears to hold in
nature. Thus light moves at the rate of about
190,000 miles per second and comes to us
from the sun in seven or eight minutes; but,
in spite of this speed, its distance travelled is
always a continuous function of the time.
It is not quite so obvious to us that the
velocity of a body is invariably a continuous
function of the time. Consider the train at
any time
t,
it is
velocity, say
zero
is
definite
per hour, where v is
at rest in a station and
when the train is
when the train
Now
is backing.
cannot
v
that
allow
change its
readily
negative
we
moving with some
v miles
152
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
value suddenly for a big, heavy train. The
train certainly cannot be running at forty
miles per hour from 11.45 A.M. up to noon,
and then suddenly, without any lapse of time,
commence running at 50 miles per hour.
at once admit that the change of velocity
We
will be a gradual process.
But how about
sudden blows of adequate magnitude? Sup
pose two trains collide; or, to take smaller
objects, suppose a man kicks a football. It
certainly appears to our sense as though the
football began suddenly to move. Thus, in
the case of velocity our senses do not revolt
at the idea of its being a discontinuous func
tion of the time, as they did at the idea of the
train being instantaneously transported from
Bletchley to Rugby. As a matter of fact,
if the laws of motion, with their
conception
of mass, are true, there is no such thing as
discontinuous velocity in nature. Anything
that appears to our senses as discontinuous
change of velocity must, according to them,
be considered to be a case of gradual change
which is too quick to be perceptible to us.
It would be rash, however, to rush into the
generalization that no discontinuous func
tions are presented to us in nature.
man
who, trusting that the mean height of the
A
land above sea-level between London and
Paris was a continuous function of the dis
tance from London, walked at night on
FUNCTIONS
153
s Cliff by Dover in contempla
Milky Way, would be dead before
he had had time to rearrange his ideas as
Shakespeare
tion of the
to the necessity
conclusions.
It
is
of
caution
in
scientific
very easy to find a discontinuous
if we confine ourselves to the
function, even
X
Y
Fig. 21.
simplest of the algebraic formulae.
ample, take the function of y
=
-,
For ex
which we
have already considered in the form
where
v
was confined to positive
p=
values.
-,
But
154
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
now let x have any value, positive or negative.
The graph of the function is exhibited in fig.
Suppose x to change continuously from
a large negative value through a numerically
decreasing set of negative values up to 0, and
thence through the series of increasing posi
tive values. Accordingly, if a moving point,
starts at the
M, represents x on
extreme left of the axis
and succes
etc.
2
sively moves through MI,
The corresponding points on the function are
It is easy to see that
PI, P2, PS, P4, etc.
there is a point of discontinuity at x = 0, i.e.
at the origin 0. For the value of the function
on the negative (left) side of the origin be
comes endlessly great, but negative, and the
function reappears on the positive (right)
side as endlessly great but positive. Hence,
there is a
however small we take M%,
s
finite jump between the values of the func
tion at 1/2 and
3
Indeed, this case has
the peculiarity that the smaller we take
2
so long as they enclose the origin, the
3
bigger is the jump in value of the function
between them. This graph brings out, what
is also apparent in fig. 20 of this chapter, that
for many functions the discontinuities only
occur at isolated points, so that by restrict
ing the values of the argument we obtain
a continuous function for these remaining
values. Thus it is evident from fig. 21 that
21.
XOX M
XOX
,
M
,
M^ M^
M
M
M
,
.
,
M
FUNCTIONS
in
y=
-,
x
if
we keep
and exclude the
155
to positive values only
origin,
we obtain a continuous
function. Similarly the same function, if we
keep to negative values only, excluding the
origin, is continuous.
Again the function
which is graphed in fig. 20 is continuous be
tween B and Ci, and between Ci and C 2 and
between Cz and Cs, and so on, always in each
case excluding the end points. It is, how
,
ever, easy to find functions such that their
discontinuities occur at all points.
For
example, consider a function /(#), such that
when x is any fractional number /(#)=!,
and when x is any incommensurable number
/(#)=2. This function is discontinuous at
all
points.
Finally, we will look a little more closely
at the definition of continuity given above.
have said that a function is continuous
when its value only alters gradually for
gradual alterations of the argument, and is
We
when it can alter its value by
sudden jumps. This is exactly the sort of
definition which satisfied our mathematical
forefathers and no longer satisfies modern
mathematicians. It is worth while to spend
some time over it; for when we understand
the modern objections to it, we shall have
gone a long way towards the understanding
of the spirit of modern mathematics.
The
discontinuous
156
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
whole difference between the older and the
newer mathematics lies in the fact that vague
half -metaphorical terms like
"gradually"
are
no longer tolerated in its exact statements.
Modern mathematics will only admit state
ments and definitions and arguments which
exclusively employ the few simple ideas about
number and magnitude and variables on
which the science is founded. Of two num
bers one can be greater or less than the
other; and one can be such and such a multi
ple of the other; but there is no relation of
between two numbers, and
"graduality"
hence the term is inadmissible. Now this
may seem at first sight to be great pedantry.
To this charge there are two answers. In
the first place, during the first half of the
nineteenth century it was found by some
great mathematicians, especially Abel in
Sweden, and Weierstrass in Germany, that
large parts of mathematics as enunciated in
the old happy-go-lucky manner were simply
wrong.
Macaulay in his essay on Bacon
contrasts the certainty of mathematics with
the uncertainty of philosophy; and by way
of a rhetorical example he says, "There has
been no reaction against Taylor s theorem."
He could not have chosen a worse example.
For, without having made an examination of
English text-books on mathematics contem
porary with the publication of this essay, the
FUNCTIONS
157
assumption is a fairly safe one that Taylor s
theorem was enunciated and proved wrongly
in every one of them.
Accordingly, the
anxious precision of modern mathematics is
necessary for accuracy. In the second place
it is necessary for research.
It makes for
clearness of thought, and thence for boldness
of thought and for fertility in trying new
combinations of ideas.
When the initial
statements are vague and slipshod, at every
subsequent stage of thought, common sense
has to step in to limit applications and to
in creative thought
explain meanings.
common sense is a bad master. Its sole
criterion for judgment is that the new ideas
shall look like the old ones. In other words
it can only act by suppressing originality.
Now
In working our way towards the precise
definition of continuity (as applied to func
tions) let us consider more closely the state
ment that there is no relation of "graduality
between numbers. It may be asked, Cannot
"
one number be only slightly greater than
another number, or in other words, cannot
the difference between the two numbers be
small? The whole point is that in the ab
stract, apart from some arbitrarily assumed
application, there is no such thing as a great
A million miles is a
or a small number.
small number of miles for an astronomer
investigating the fixed stars, but a million
158
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
is a large yearly income.
Again, onequarter is a large fraction of one s income to
give away in charity, but is a small fraction
of it to retain for private use. Examples can
be accumulated indefinitely to show that
great or small in any absolute sense have
no abstract application to numbers. We can
say of two numbers that one is greater or
smaller than another, but not without speci
fication of particular circumstances that any
one number is great or small. Our task
therefore is to define continuity without any
mention of a "small" or "gradual" change
in value of the function.
In order to do this we will give names to
pounds
some ideas, which will also be useful when
we come to consider limits and the differen
tial calculus.
An "interval" of values of the argument
x of a function f(x) is all the values lying
between some two values of the argument.
For example, the interval between x = 1 and
x = 2 consists of all the values which x can
take lying between 1 and 2, i.e. it consists of
all the real numbers between 1 and 2.
But
the bounding numbers of an interval need
not be integers. An interval of values of the
argument contains a number a, when a is a
member of the interval. For example, the
interval between 1 and 2 contains f f J, and
,
so on.
,
FUNCTIONS
159
A set of numbers approximates to a num
ber a within a standard k, when the numerical
difference between a and every number of the
set is less than k.
Here k is the "standard
of approximation."
Thus the set of num
bers 3, 4, 6, 8, approximates to the number
5 within the standard 4. In this case the
standard 4 is not the smallest which could
have been chosen, the set also approximates
to 5 within any of the standards 3-1 or 3*01
or 3 001. Again, the numbers, 3*1, 3*141,
3-1415, 3-14159 approximate to 3-13102
within the standard -032, and also within the
smaller standard -03103.
These two ideas
of
an interval and
of
ap
proximation to a number within a standard
are easy enough; their only difficulty is that
they look rather trivial. But when combined
with the next idea, that of the "neighbour
hood" of a number, they form the founda
tion of modern mathematical reasoning.
What do we mean by saying that something
is true for a function f(x) in the neighbour
hood of the value a of argument x ? It is
this fundamental notion which we have now
got to make precise.
The values of a function f(x) are said to
possess a characteristic in the "neighbour
when some interval can be found,
hood of
which (i) contains the number a not as an
end-point, and (ii) is such that every value
a"
160
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
of the function for arguments, other than a,
lying within that interval posessses the char
acteristic. The value /(a) of the function for
the argument a may or may not possess the
characteristic.
point
Nothing
is
decided on this
by statements about the neighbourhood
of a.
For example, suppose we take the par
x2
Now in the neighbour
hood of 2, the values of x 2 are less than 5.
For we can find an interval, e.g. from 1 to
2*1, which (i) contains 2 not as an end-point,
and (ii) is such that, for values of x lying
within it, x 2 is less than 5.
Now, combining the preceding ideas we
know what is meant by saying that in the
ticular function
.
neighbourhood of a the function f(x) approxi
mates to c within the standard k. It means
that some interval can be found which (i) in
cludes a not as an end-point, and (ii) is such
that all values of f(x), where x lies in the inter ^
val and is not a, differ from c by less than k.
For example, in the neighbourhood of 2, the
function ^/x approximates to 1 41425 within
the standard -0001. This is true because the
square root of 1-99996164 is 1-4142 and the
square root of 2-00024449 is 1-4143; hence
for values of x lying in the interval
1-99996164 to 2-00024449, which contains 2
not as an end-point, the values of the function
+Jx all lie between 1*4142 and 1-4143, and
FUNCTIONS
161
they therefore all differ from 1 -41425 by less
than 0001. In this case we can, if we like,
standard of approximation,
fix a smaller
namely -000051 or -0000501. Again, to take
another example, in the neighbourhood of 2
the function x 2 approximates to 4 within the
standard -5. For (l-9) 2 = 3-61 and (2-l) 2 =
4-41, and thus the required interval 1-9 to
2-1, containing 2 not as an end-point, has
been found. This example brings out the
fact that statements about a function f(x) in
the neighbourhood of a number a are distinct
from statements about the value of f(x) when
x = a. The production of an interval, through
out which the statement is true, is required.
Thus the mere fact that 2 2 =4 does not by
itself justify us in saying that in the neigh
bourhood of 2 the function x 2 is equal to 4.
This statement would be untrue, because no
interval can be produced with the required
2
property. Also, the fact that 2 =4 does not
by itself justify us in saying that in the
2
neighbourhood of 2 the function x approxi
mates to 4 within the standard *5; although
as a matter of fact, the statement has just
been proved to be true.
If we understand the preceding ideas, we
understand the foundations of modern
mathematics. We shall recur to analogous
ideas in the chapter on Series, and again
in the chapter on the Differential Calculus.
162
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Meanwhile, we are now prepared to define
A
function f(x)
at a value a of its argu
ment, when in the neighbourhood of a
its values approximate to /(a) (i.e. to its
value at a) within every standard of ap
"continuous
is
functions."
"continuous"
proximation.
This means that, whatever standard k be
chosen, in the neighbourhood of a f(x) ap
proximates to /(a) within the standard k.
For example, x 2 is continuous at the value 2
of its argument, x 9 because however k be
chosen we can always find an interval, which
(i) contains 2 not as an end-point, and (ii) is
such that the values of x 2 for arguments lying
within it approximate to 4 (i.e. 2 2 ) within
the standard k. Thus, suppose we choose
the standard -1; now (l-999) 2 = 3 -996001,
and (2-01) 2 =4-0401, and both these numbers
differ from 4 by less than *1. Hence, within
the interval 1-999 to 2-01 the values of x 2
approximate to 4 within the standard !.
Similarly an interval can be produced for any
other standard which we like to try.
Take the example of the railway train. Its
velocity is continuous as it passes the signal
box, if whatever velocity you like to assign
(say one-millionth of a mile per hour) an in
terval of time can be found extending before
and after the instant of passing, such that at
all instants within it the train s velocity
FUNCTIONS
163
differs from that with which the train passed
the box by less than one-millionth of a mile
per hour; and the same is true whatever
other velocity be mentioned in the place of
one-millionth of a mile per hour.
CHAPTER
XII
PERIODICITY IN NATURE
THE
whole
life
of
Nature
is
dominated by
the existence of periodic events, that is, by
the existence of successive events so analogous
to each other that, without any straining of
language, they may be termed recurrences of
the same event. The rotation of the earth
produces the successive days. It is true that
each day is different from the preceding days,
however abstractly we define the meaning of
a day, so as to exclude casual phenomena.
But with a sufficiently abstract definition of
a day, the distinction in properties between
two days becomes
faint
and remote from
practical interest; and each day may then
be conceived as a recurrence of the phenome
non of one rotation of the earth. Again the
path of the earth round the sun leads to the
yearly recurrence of the seasons, and imposes
another periodicity on all the operations of
Another less fundamental perio
nature.
dicity is provided by the phases of the moon.
In modern civilized life, with its artificial light,
these phases are of slight importance, but in
164
PERIODICITY IN NATURE
165
ancient times, in climates where the days are
burning and the skies clear, human life was
apparently largely influenced by the existence
of moonlight. Accordingly our divisions into
weeks and months, with their religious associ
ations, have spread over the European races
from Syria and Mesopotamia, though inde
pendent observances following the moon s
phases are found amongst most nations. It
is, however, through the tides, and not through
its phases of light and darkness, that the
moon s periodicity has chiefly influenced the
history of the earth.
Our bodily life is essentially periodic.
It is dominated by the beatings of the
heart, and the recurrence of breathing.
The
presupposition of periodicity
is
indeed
fundamental to our very conception of life.
We cannot imagine a course of nature in
which, as events progressed, we should be
unable to say: "This has happened before."
The whole conception of experience as a guide
Men would
to conduct would be absent.
always find themselves in new situations
possessing no substratum of identity with
anything in past history. The very means of
measuring time as a quantity would be ab
Events might still be recognized as
sent.
occurring in a series, so that some were earlier
and others later. But we now go beyond this
bare recognition. We can not only say that
166
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
three events, A, B C, occurred in this order,
came before B, and B before C;
so that
but also we can say that the length of time
between the occurrences of
and B was
twice as long as that between B and C. Now,
9
A
A
quantity of time is essentially dependent on
observing the number of natural recurrences
which have intervened. We may say that
the length of time between A and B was
so many days, or so many months, or so
many years, according to the type of recur
rence to which we wish to appeal. Indeed,
at the beginning of civilization, these three
modes of measuring time were really distinct.
It has been one of the first tasks of science
among
civilized or semi-civilized nations, to
into one coherent measure. The
extent of this task must be grasped. It
is necessary to determine, not merely what
number of days (e.g. 365-25. .) go to some
one year, but also previously to determine
that the same number of days do go to the
successive years. We can imagine a world in
which periodicities exist, but such that no two
are coherent. In some years there might be
200 days and in others 350. The determina
tion of the broad general consistency of the
more important periodicities was the first step
This consistency arises
in natural science.
from no abstract intuitive law of thought;
it is merely an observed fact of nature
fuse
them
full
.
PERIODICITY IN NATURE
167
guaranteed by experience. Indeed, so far is
from being a necessary law, that it is not
even exactly true. There are divergencies in
every case. For some instances these diver
gencies are easily observed and are therefore
immediately apparent. In other cases it re
it
the most refined
astronomical accuracy to
quires
observations
and
make them appar
Broadly speaking, all recurrences de
pending on living beings, such as the beatings
of the heart, are subject in comparison with
ent.
other recurrences to rapid variations. The
great stable obvious recurrences stable in
the sense of mutually agreeing with great
accuracy are those depending on the motion
of the earth as a whole, and on similar motions
of the heavenly bodies.
We therefore assume that these astronomi
cal recurrences mark out equal intervals of
But how are we to deal with their
time.
discrepancies which the refined observations
of astronomy detect? Apparently we are
reduced to the arbitrary assumption that one
or other of these sets of phenomena marks out
equal times e.g. that either all days are of
equal length, or that all years are of equal
This is not so: some assumptions
must be made, but the assumption which
length.
underlies the whole procedure of the astrono
mers in determining the measure of time is
that the laws of motion are exactly verified.
168
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Before explaining how this is done, it is in
teresting to observe that this relegation of the
determination of the measure of time to the
astronomers arises (as has been said) from
the stable consistency of the recurrences with
which they deal. If such a superior con
sistency had been noted among the recur
rences characterisitc of the human body, we
should naturally have looked to the doctors
of medicine for the regulation of our clocks.
In considering how the laws of motion
come into the matter, note that two incon
sistent modes of measuring time will yield
different variations of velocity to the same
body. For example, suppose we define an
hour as one twenty-fourth of a day, and take
the case of a train running uniformly for two
hours at the rate of twenty miles per hour.
Now take a grossly inconsistent measure of
time, and suppose that it makes the first hour
to be twice as long as the second hour. Then,
according to this other measure of duration,
the time of the train s run is divided into
two parts, during each of which it has tra
versed the same distance, namely, twenty
miles; but the duration of the first part is
twice as long as that of the second part.
Hence the velocity of the train has not been
uniform, and on the average the velocity
during the second period is twice that during
the first period.
Thus the question as to
PERIODICITY IN NATURE
169
whether the train has been running uniformly
or not entirely depends on the standard of
time which we adopt.
Now, for all ordinary purposes of life on the
earth, the various astronomical recurrences
may be looked on as absolutely consistent;
and, furthermore assuming their consistency,
and thereby assuming the velocities and
changes of velocities possessed by bodies, we
find that the laws of motion, which have
been considered above, are almost exactly
But only almost exactly when we
verified.
come
some
of the astronomical phenomena.
however, that by assuming slightly
different velocities for the rotations and
motions of the planets and stars, the laws
would be exactly verified. This assumption
is then made; and we have, in fact thereby,
adopted a measure of time, which is indeed
defined by reference to the astronomical
phenomena, but not so as to be consistent
with the uniformity of any one of them. But
the broad fact remains that the uniform flow
of time on which so much is based, is itself
dependent on the observation of periodic
We
to
find,
events.
Even phenomena, which on the surface
seem casual and exceptional, or, on the other
hand, maintain themselves with a uniform
persistency, may be due to the remote influ
ence of periodicity. Take, for example, the
170
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
principle of
when two
resonance.
Resonance
arises
connected circumstances
have the same periodicities. It is a dynami
cal law that the small vibrations of all bodies
when left to themselves take place in definite
times characteristic of the body. Thus a
pendulum with a small swing always vibrates
in
some
sets of
definite time,
characteristic of its
shape and distribution of weight and length.
A more complicated body may have many
ways of vibrating; but each of its modes of
vibration will have its own peculiar "period."
Those periods of vibration of a body are
called its
periods. Thus a pendulum
has but one period of vibration, while a sus
pension bridge will have many. We get a
musical instrument, like a violin string, when
"free"
the periods of vibration are all simple submultiples of the longest; i.e. if t seconds be
the longest period, the others are \t, \t, and so
on, where any of these smaller periods may be
absent. Now, suppose we excite the vibra
tions of a body by a cause which is itself peri
odic; then, if the period of the cause is very
nearly that of one of the periods of the body,
that mode of vibration of the body is very
violently excited; even although the magni
tude of the exciting cause is small. This
phenomenon
is
called
"resonance."
The
general reason is easy to understand. Any
one wanting to upset a rocking stone will
PERIODICITY IN NATURE
171
tune" with the oscillations of the
as always to secure a favourable
so
stone,
moment for a push. If the pushes are out
of tune, some increase the oscillations, but
others check them. But when they are in
tune, after a time all the pushes are favour
push
"in
The word "resonance comes from con
siderations of sound: but the phenomenon
extends far beyond the region of sound. The
"
able.
laws of absorption and emission of light de
it, the "tuning" of receivers for wire
less telegraphy, the comparative importance
of the influences of planets on each other s
motion, the danger to a suspension bridge as
troops march over it in step, and the excessive
vibration of some ships under the rhythmical
beat of their machinery at certain speeds.
This coincidence of periodicities may produce
steady phenomena when there is a constant as
sociation of the two periodic events, or it may
produce violent and sudden outbursts when
the association is fortuitous and temporary.
Again, the characteristic and constant
pend on
periods of vibration mentioned above are
the underlying causes of what appear to
us as steady excitements of our senses.
work for hours in a steady light, or we listen
to a steady unvarying sound. But, if modern
science be correct, this steadiness has no
counterpart in nature. The steady light is
due to the impact on the eye of a countless
We
172
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
number of periodic waves in a vibrating ether,
and the steady sound to similar waves in a
vibrating air. It is not our purpose here to
explain the theory of light or the theory of
sound* We have said enough to make it
evident that one of the first steps necessary
to make mathematics a fit instrument for the
investigation of Nature is that it should be
able to express the essential periodicity of
If we have grasped this, we can
things.
understand the importance of the mathe
matical conceptions which we have next to
consider, namely, periodic functions.
CHAPTER
XIII
TRIGONOMETRY
TRIGONOMETRY did not take its rise from
the general consideration of the periodicity of
nature. In this respect its history is analo
gous to that of conic sections, which also had
their origin in very particular ideas. Indeed,
a comparison of the histories of the two
sciences yields some very instructive analogies
and contrasts. Trigonometry, like conic sec
had its origin among the Greeks. Its
inventor was Hipparchus (born about 160
B.C.), a Greek astronomer, who made his
observations at Rhodes.
His services to
tions,
astronomy were very great, and it left his
hands a truly scientific subject with important
results established, and the right method of
progress indicated.
Perhaps the invention
of trigonometry was not the least of these
services to the main science of his study. The
next man who extended trigonometry was
Ptolemy, the great Alexandrian astronomer,
whom we have already mentioned. We now
173
174
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
see at once the great contrast between conic
sections and trigonometry.
The origin of
trigonometry was practical; it was invented
because it was necessary for astronomical re
search.
The
origin
of
conic sections
was
purely theoretical. The only reason for its
initial study was the abstract interest of the
ideas involved.
Characteristically enough
conic sections were invented about 150 years
earlier than trigonometry, during the very
best period of Greek thought. But the im
portance of trigonometry, both to the theory
and the application
of mathematics, is only
one of innumerable instances of the fruitful
ideas which the general science has gained
from its practical applications.
We will try and make clear to ourselves
what trigonometry is, and why it should be
generated by the scientific studyjof astronomy.
In the first place: What are the measure
ments which can be made by an astronomer?
They are measurements of time and measure
ments of angles. The astronomer may adjust
a telescope (for it is easier to discuss the
familiar instrument of modern astronomers)
it can only turn about a fixed axis
pointing east and west; the result is that
the telescope can only point to the south, with
a greater or less elevation of direction, or, if
turned round beyond the zenith, point to the
north. This is the transit instrument, the
so that
TRIGONOMETRY
175
great instrument for the exact measurement
of the times at which stars are due south or
due north. But indirectly this instrument
measures angles. For when the time elapsed
between the transits of two stars has been
noted, by the assumption of the uniform
rotation of the earth, we obtain the angle
through which the earth has turned in that
period of time. Again, by other instruments,
the angle between two stars can be directly
measured. For if
is the eye of the astrono-
E
Fig. 22.
mer, and EA and EB are the directions in
which the stars are seen, it is easy to devise
instruments which shall measure the angle
AEB. Hence, when the astronomer is form
ing a survey of the heavens, he is, in fact,
measuring angles so as to fix the relative
directions of the stars and planets at any in
stant.
Again, in the analogous problem of
176
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
land-surveying, angles are the chief subject
of measurements. The direct measurements
of length are only rarely possible with any
accuracy; rivers, houses, forests, mountains,
and general irregularities of ground all get in
the way. The survey of a whole country will
depend only on one or two direct measure
ments of length, made with the greatest
elaboration in selected places like Salisbury
Plain.
The main work of a survey is the
measurement of angles. For example, A, 9
and C will be conspicuous points in the dis-
B
Fig. 23.
surveyed, say the tops of church towers.
visible each from the others.
Then it is a very simple matter at A to
measure the angle BAC, and at B to measure
the angle ABC, and at C to measure the angle
BCA. Theoretically, it is only necessary to
measure two of these angles; for, by a wellknown proposition in geometry, the sum of
the three angles of a triangle amounts to two
trict
These points are
TRIGONOMETRY
177
right-angles, so that when two of the angles
are known, the third can be deduced. It is
better, however, in practice to measure all
three, and then any small errors of observa
tion can be checked. In the process of map-
making a country
is
completely covered with
triangles in this way. This process is called
triangulation, and is the fundamental process
in a survey.
Now, when all the angles of a triangle are
known, the shape of the triangle is known
that is, the shape as distinguished from the
We
here come upon the great principle
size.
The idea is very
of geometrical similarity.
familiar to us in its practical applications.
are all familiar with the idea of a plan
drawn to scale. Thus if the scale of a plan
be an inch to a yard, a length of three inches
in the plan means a length of three yards in
the original. Also the shapes depicted in the
plan are the shapes in the original, so that a
right-angle in the original appears as a rightangle in the plan. Similarly in a map, which
We
only a plan of a country, the proportions
of the lengths in the map are the proportions
of the distances between the places indicated,
and the directions in the map are the direc
tions in the country. For example, if in the
map one place is north-north-west of the
other, so it is in reality; that is to say, in a
is
map
the angles are the same as in reality.
178
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
Geometrical similarity
Two
may
be defined thus:
figures are similar (i) if to any point
in one figure a point in the other figure
corresponds, so that to every line there is a
corresponding line, and to every angle a
corresponding angle, and (ii) if the lengths
of corresponding lines are in a fixed propor
tion, and the magnitudes of corresponding
angles are the same. The fixed proportion
of the lengths of corresponding lines in a map
(or plan) and in the original is called the scale
of the map.
The scale should always be
indicated on the margin of every map and
plan. It has already been pointed out that
two
triangles whose angles are respectively
equal are similar. Thus, if the two triangles
B
C
Fig. 24.
ABC
and DEF have the angles at A and D
equal, and those at B and E and those at C
and F, then DE is to AB in the same propor9
TRIGONOMETRY
tion as
But
EF
is
to
EC, and
as
FD
179
is
to
CA.
not true of other figures that simi
larity is guaranteed by the mere equality of
angles. Take, for example, the familiar cases
of a rectangle and a square. Let ABCD be
a square, and ABEF be a rectangle. Then
But
all the corresponding angles are equal.
it is
C
B
Fig. 25.
AB
of the square is equal to
of the rectangle, the side BC of
the side
the square is about half the size of the side
Hence it is not true
of the rectangle.
that the square ABCD is similar to the rect
angle ABEF. This peculiar property of the
triangle, which is not shared by other recti
linear figures, makes it the fundamental
figure in the theory of similarity. Hence in
surveys, triangulation is the fundamental
process; the hence also arises the word "tri-
whereas the side
AB
BE
180
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
gonometry," derived from the two Greek
words trigonon, a triangle, and metria, meas
urement. The fundamental question from
which trigonometry arose is this Given the
magnitudes of the angles of a triangle, what can
be stated as to the relative magnitudes of the
sides. Note that we say "relative magnitudes
:
since by the theory of similarity
the
proportions of the sides which
only
In order to answer this ques
are known.
tion, certain functions of the magnitudes of
an angle, considered as the argument, are in
In their origin these functions
troduced.
were got at by considering a right-angled tri
angle, and the magnitude of the angle was
defined by the length of the arc of a circle.
In modern elementary books, the funda
mental position of the arc of the circle as de
fining the magnitude of the angle has been
pushed somewhat to the background, not to
the advantage either of theory or clearness
of explanation.
It must first be noticed
that, in relation to similarity, the circle holds
the same fundamental position among curvi
linear figures, as does the triangle among
rectilinear figures. Any two circles are simi
of the
sides,"
it is
they only differ in scale. The
the
circumferences of two circles,
of
lengths
and AiPiAi in the fig. 26 are
such as
in proportion to the lengths of their radii.
lar figures;
APA
Furthermore,
if
the two circles have the same
TRIGONOMETRY
181
centre 0, as do the two circles in fig. 26, then
and AiPi intercepted by the
the arcs
arms of any angle A OP, are also in propor
tion to their radii. Hence the ratio of the
AP
Fig. 26.
length of the arc
radius OP, that
is
is
AP
-^?
to the length of the
radius
7T^
OP
is
a number which
quite independent of the length
the same as the fraction
r
\^-.
radms
OPi
.
OP, and
is
This f rac-
tion of "arc divided by radius" is the proper
theoretical way to measure the magnitude of
182
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
an angle;
for it is dependent on no arbitrary
unit of length, and on no arbitrary way of
dividing up any arbitrarily assumed angle,
Thus the
such as a right-angle.
fraction
represents the magnitude of the angle
AP
A OP.
Now draw PM perpendicularly to OA. Then
PM
the Greek mathematicians called the line
the sine of the arc AP, and the line
the
cosine of the arc AP. They were well aware
that the importance of the relations of these
various lines to each other was dependent on
the theory of similarity which we have just
expounded. But they did not make their
definitions express the properties which arise
from this theory. Also they had not in their
heads the modern general ideas respecting
functions as correlating pairs of variable num
bers, nor in fact were they aware of any
OM
modern conception
and algebraic
was
natural to
analysis.
Accordingly,
them to think merely of the relations between
certain lines in a diagram. For us the case
of algebra
it
different: we
powerful ideas.
wish to embody our more
is
Hence, in modern mathematics, instead
of
considering
the fraction
the
AP
-,
arc
which
same for all lengths of
considering the lines
AP, we
is
a number the
OP; and,
PM
consider
and
instead of
we con-
OM
,
TRIGONOMETRY
183
,OM
-
j
*u fractions
t
4.sider
the
and
,
,
,
.
which again
are numbers not dependent on the length of
OP, i.e. not dependent on the scale of our
diagrams.
Then we
to be the sine of the
number
-
number
define the
number
PA
-,
PM
and the
to be the cosine of the
number
These fractional forms are clumsy to
print;
so let us put
u
for the fraction
AP
which represents the magnitude of the angle
AOP, and put
for the fraction
v for
-y^
.
the fraction
Then u
9
v,
pi/
,
w
9
are
and
w
num
we are talking of any angle
are
variable numbers.
But a
they
correlation exists between their magnitudes,
so that when u (i.e. the angle AOP) is given
the magnitudes of v and w are definitely deter
mined. Hence v and w are functions of the
have called v the sine of
argument u.
wish to adapt
u, and w the cosine of u.
the general functional notation y=f(x) to
these special cases: so in modern mathe-
bers, and, since
AOP,
We
We
for
"/"
when we want
184
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
to indicate the special function of "sine,"
for
when we want to indicate
and
the special function of "cosine." Thus, with
"cos"
"/"
the above meanings for u,
v
= sin
u,
and
w,
v,
w = cos u
we
get
9
where the brackets surrounding the x in f(x)
are omitted for the special functions. The
meaning of these functions sin and cos as
correlating the pairs of numbers u and v, and
u and w is, that the functional relations are to
26) an angle
divided by OP"
is equal to u, and that then v is the number
given by "PM divided by OP" and w is the
number given by "OM divided by OP."
It is evident that without some further defi
nitions we shall get into difficulties when the
number u is taken too large. For then the arc
may be greater than one-quarter of the
circumference of the circle, and the point
and A and not
(cf. fig. 26) may fall between
and A. Also P may be below
between
the line AOA and not above it, as in fig. 26.
In order to get over this difficulty we have
recourse to the ideas and conventions of co
ordinate geometry in making our complete
Let one
definitions of the sine and cosine.
arm OA of the angle be the axis OX, and
produce the axis backwards to obtain its
Draw the other axis
.
negative part
be found by constructing
AOP, whose measure
AP
"
(cf. fig.
AP
M
OX
TRIGONOMETRY
YOY
185
P
f
perpendicular to it. Let any point
at a distance r from
have coordinates x
and y. These coordinates are both positive
in the first "quadrant" of the plan, e.g. the
coordinates x and y of
in fig. 27. In the
P
other quadrants, either one or both of the
1
coordinates are negative, for example, x and
y for
for
P
f
P
P"
P",
# and
f
and x and y for
and # and $ for
,
2/
,
in
and x and #
27, where
fig.
are both negative numbers. The
is the arc
divided
positive angle
AP
POA
77
by
r, its
sine
is
- and
T*
its
cosine
is
-; the posi-
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
186
tive angle
P OA is the arc ABP
its sine is
77^
sine
is
-
f
angle
by
P"
r, its
r,
1*
- and cosine -
the arc
is
P"OA
divided by
/
7/
and
OA
sine
its
;
divided by r, its
T^
cosine is - ; the positive
P"
the arc
is
is
ABA
the positive angle
- and
its
r
ABA B
cosine
P"
divided
is -.
r
But even now we have not gone far enough.
For suppose we choose u to be a number
greater than the ratio of the whole circum
ference of the circle to its radius. Owing to
the similarity of all circles this ratio is the
same for all circles. It is always denoted in
mathematics by the symbol ^TT, where TT
is the Greek form of the letter p and its
name in the Greek alphabet is
It can
be proved that TT is an incommensurable
number, and that therefore its value cannot
be expressed by any fraction, or by any
"pi."
terminating or recurring decimal. Its value
to a few decimal places is 3 14 159; for many
purposes a sufficiently accurate approximate
22
value is - Mathematicians can easily cal
culate
just as
TT
to
of accuracy required,
can be so calculated. Its value
actually given to 707 places of
Such elaboration of calculation is
V%
has been
decimals.
any degree
TRIGONOMETRY
187
merely a curiosity, and of no practical or
theoretical
interest.
The
accurate
deter
one of the two parts of
the famous problem of squaring the circle.
The other part of the problem is, by the
theoretical methods of pure geometry to
mination of
TT
is
describe a straight line equal in length to the
circumference.
Both parts of the problem
are now known to be impossible; and the
insoluble problem has now lost all special
practical or theoretical interest, having be
come absorbed
in wider ideas.
After this digression on the value of TT, we
now return to the question of the general
definition of the magnitude of an angle, so as
to be able to produce an angle corresponding
to any value u. Suppose a moving point, Q,
to start from A on
(cf. fig. 27), and to
rotate in the positive direction (anti-clock
wise, in the figure considered) round the cir
cumference of the circle for any number of
times, finally resting at any point, e.g. at
or
or P or
Then the total length
of the curvilinear circular path traversed,
divided by the radius of the circle, r, is the
OX
P
P"
P"
.
generalized definition of a positive angle of
any size. Let x 9 y be the coordinates of the
point in which the point Q rests, i.e. in one of
the four alternative positions mentioned in
fig. 27; x and y (as here used) will either x
and 2/, or x and y, or x and y 9 or x and
y".
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
188
Then
the sign of this generalized angle
is
T
/M
and
its
cosine
With
is
these definitions
r
the functional relations v = sin u and w = cos
u, are at last defined for all positive real values
of u. For negative values of u we simply take
rotation of Q in the opposite (clockwise)
direction; but it is not worth our while to
elaborate further on this point, now that the
general method of procedure has been
explained.
These functions of sine and cosine, as thus
defined, enable us to deal with the problems
concerning the triangle from which Trigono
metry took its rise. But we are now in a
position to relate Trigonometry to the wider
idea of Periodicity of which the importance
was explained in the last chapter. It is easy
to see that the functions sin u and cos u are
For consider the
periodic functions of u.
position, P (in fig. 27), of a moving point, Q,
which has started from A and revolved round
the circle. This position, P, marks the angles
arc
arc
arc
,
AP
and 6
TT
AP
--
-j
,
and so on
r
Now,
all
these angles have the
7/
cosine, namely, - and
AP
.
indefinitely.
same
sine
and
3*
Hence
it is
easy to
TRIGONOMETRY
189
u be chosen to have any value, the
arguments u and %TT+U, and 47r+w, and
6-Tr-fw, and STT+U and so on indefinitely,
have all the same values for the correspond
ing sines and cosines. In other words,
see that,
if
sn u =sn ?rw =sn ?rw =sn
= etc.
cos u = cos (2?r + u) = cos (4-Tr +u) =
= etc.
;
This fact is expressed by saying that sin u
and cos u are periodic functions with their
period equal to
%TT.
The graph of the function y = sin x (notice
that we now abandon v and u for the more
familiar y
and
x) is
shown
in
fig.
28.
We
take on the axis of x any arbitrary length at
pleasure to represent the number TT, and on
the axis of y any arbitrary length at pleasure
The numerical
to represent the number 1.
values of the sine and cosine can never ex
The recurrence of the figure
ceed unity.
This
after periods of &TT will be noticed.
of
the
periodic
graph represents
simplest style
function, out of which all others are con
The cosine gives nothing funda
structed.
different
from the sine. For it is
mentally
easy to prove that cos x
it
=
sin
(
x+
^
;
hence
J
can be seen that the graph of cos x is simply
28 modified by drawing the axis of OF
fig.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
190
through the point on
of
drawing
it
OX
marked
,
instead
in its actual position
on the
figure.
It
is
easy to construct a sine function in
/A\tt2X/r\
\3ft
I
\/
6
_r\V
4jtf
\y
Fig. 28.
which the period has any assigned value
For we have only to write
a.
and then
gm
L_^
i
a
=Sm
Thus the period
J
of this
a
new
^TT
L
= Sm
function
is
a
now
a.
Let us now give a general definition of what
TRIGONOMETRY
191
we mean by a
periodic function. The func
tion f(x) is periodic, with the period a, if (i)
for any value of x we have f(x) =f(x+a), and
(ii) there is no number b smaller than a such
that for any value of x, f(x) =f(x+b).
The second clause is put into the definition
because when
we have
sin
it is
,
a
not only
periodic in the period a, but also in the periods
2a and 3a, and so on; this arises since
.
sin
-=
%7r(x+3a)
i
a
.
sin
-\ a
f%7TX
\
,
,
\-Qir
(
}
-
= sin %7TX
.
.
a
)
So it is the smallest period which we want to
get hold of and call the period of the function.
The greater part of the abstract theory of
periodic functions and the whole of the appli
cations of the theory to Physical Science are
dominated by an important theorem called
Fourier s Theorem; namely that, if f(x) be a
periodic function with the period a and if f(x)
also satisfies certain conditions, which prac
tically are always presupposed in functions
suggested by natural phenomena, then f(x)
can be written as the sum of a set of terms
in the form
CQ
+d sin (
~
.
+c 3 sin
+ei\ +c 2
-a
/6-Tnr
,
(
[-03
\
sin f -
\
+
,
1
J
etc.
-
+e z
J
192
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
this formula c , Ci, Cz, c 3 , etc., and also
2, e s , etc., are constants, chosen so as to
suit the particular function. Again we have
In
0i,
to ask, How many terms have to be chosen?
here a new difficulty arises: for we can
prove that, though in some particular cases
And
a definite number will do, yet in general all
we can do is to approximate as closely as
we like to the value of the function by tak
more and more terms. This process of
gradual approximation brings us to the con
sideration of the theory of infinite series, an
essential part of mathematical theory which
we will consider in the next chapter.
The above method of expressing a periodic
function as a sum of sines is called the "har
monic analysis" of the function. For ex
ample, at any point on the sea coast the tides
Thus at a point
rise and fall periodically.
near the Straits of Dover there will be two
daily tides due to the rotation of the earth.
The daily rise and fall of the tides are com
plicated by the fact that there are two tidal
waves, one coming up the English Channel,
and the other which has swept round the
North of Scotland, and has then come south
ward down the North Sea. Again some high
ing
tides are higher than others: this is due to
the fact that the Sun has also a tide-generat
ing influence as well as the Moon. In this
way monthly and other periods are intro-
TRIGONOMETRY
193
We
leave out of account the excep
tional influence of winds which cannot be
The general problem of the har
foreseen.
monic analysis of the tides is to find sets of
terms like those in the expression on page
191 above, such that each set will give with
approximate accuracy the contribution of
the tide-generating influences of one "period"
to the height of the tide at any instant. The
argument x will therefore be the time reckoned
duced.
from any convenient commencement.
Again, the motion of vibration of a violin
string is submitted to a similar harmonic
analysis, and so are the vibrations of the
ether and the air, corresponding respectively
to waves of light and waves of sound. We
are here in the presence of one of the funda
mental processes of mathematical physics
namely, nothing less than its general method
of dealing with the great natural fact of
Periodicity.
CHAPTER XIV
SERIES
No part of Mathematics suffers more from
the triviality of its initial presentation to
beginners than the great subject of series.
Two
minor examples of series, namely arith
metic and geometric series, are considered;
these examples are important because they
are the simplest examples of an important
general theory.
But the
general ideas are
never disclosed; and thus the examples,
which exemplify nothing, are reduced to
silly trivialities.
The
general mathematical idea of a series
that of a set of things ranged in order, that
This meaning is accurately
is, in sequence.
represented in the common use of the term.
Consider, for example, the series of English
Prime Ministers during the nineteenth cen
tury, arranged in the order of their first tenure
of that office within the century. The series
commences with William Pitt, and ends with
is
Lord Rosebery, who, appropriately enough,
the biographer of the first member. We
is
194
SERIES
195
might have considered other serial orders for
the arrangement of these men; for example,
according to their height or their weight.
These other suggested orders strike us as
trivial in connection with Prime Ministers,
and would not naturally occur to the mind;
but abstractedly they are just as good orders
as any other. When one order among terms
is very much more important or more obvious
than other orders, it is often spoken of as the
order of those terms. Thus the order of the
integers would always be taken to mean their
order as arranged in order of magnitude. But
of course there is an indefinite number of
other ways of arranging them. When the
number of things considered is finite, the
number of ways of arranging them in order
is called the number of their permutations.
The number of permutations of a set of n
things,
where n
is
some
finite integer, is
rcX(rc-l)X(ra-2)X(ra-3)X...X4X3X2Xl
that is to say, it is the product of the first n
this product is so important in
mathematics that a special symbolism is
used for it, and it is always written
Thus, 2!=2X1=2, and 3!=3X2Xl=6, and
41=4X3X2X1=24, and 5!=5X4X3X2Xl
integers;
"ft!"
= 120. As n increases, the value of n\ in
creases very quickly; thus 100! is a hundred
times as large as 99!
196
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
It is easy to verify in the case of small
values of n that nl is the number of ways
of arranging n things in order.
Thus con
sider two things a and b; these are capable
of the two orders ab and 6a, and 2! =2.
Again, take three things a, 6, and c; these
are capable of the six orders, abc, acb, bac,
bca, cab, cba, and 3! = 6.
Similarly for the
twenty-four orders in which four things a, b,
c,
and
d,
can be arranged.
When we come to the
infinite sets of things
like the sets of all the integers, or all the
fractions, or all the real numbers for instance
we come at once upon the complications of
the theory of order-types. This subject was
touched upon in Chapter VI in considering
the possible orders of the integers, and of the
The
fractions, and of the real numbers.
whole question of order-types forms a com
paratively new branch of mathematics of
great importance. We shall not consider it
any further. All the infinite series which we
consider now are of the same order-type as
the integers arranged in ascending order of
magnitude, namely, with a first term, and
such that each term has a couple of nextdoor neighbours, one on either side, with the
exception of the first term which has, of
course, only one next-door neighbour. Thus,
if m be any integer (not
zero), there will be
always an mth term. A series with a finite
SERIES
197
of terms (say n terms) has the same
characteristics as far as next-door neighbours
are concerned as an infinite series; it only
differs from infinite series in having a last
term, namely, the nth.
The important thing to do with a series of
numbers using for the future "series" in
number
the restricted
mentioned
is
sense which has just been
to add its successive terms
together.
are respec
if ui, u 2 u 3 ,
Un
.
the
nth,
1st, 2nd, 3rd, 4th,
tively
terms of a series of numbers, we form succes
sively the series Ui, Ui+u 2 , Ui+u 2 +u 3 , Ui
W2+w 3 -hW4, and so on; thus the sum of the
Thus
,
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
.
+
1st
n terms may be written.
the series has only a finite number of
terms, we come at last in this way to the
sum of the whole series of terms. But, if
the series has an infinite number of terms,
this process of successively forming the sums
of the terms never terminates; and in this
sense there is no such thing as the sum of an
If
infinite series.
But why is it important successively to add
the terms of a series in this way? The answer
is that we are here symbolizing the funda
mental mental process of approximation.
This is a process which has significance iar
198
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
of mathematics.
Our
limited intellects cannot deal with compli
cated material all at once, and our method of
arrangement is that of approximation. The
beyond the regions
statesman in framing his speech puts the
dominating issues first and lets the details
naturally into their subordinate places.
of course, the converse artistic
is,
method of preparing the imagination by the
presentation of subordinate or special details,
and then gradually rising to a crisis. In
either way the process is one of gradual
fall
There
summation of effects; and this is exactly
what is done by the successive summation
of the terms of a series.
Our ordinary
method of stating numbers is such a process
of gradual summation, at least, in the case
of large numbers.
Thus 568,213 presents
itself to the mind as
500,000+60,000 +8,000 +200 + 10 +3
In the case of decimal fractions this
Thus 3-14159
more avowedly.
3 +lV +TOT +T0W +TO
Also, 3
0~0~0
is
so
is
+TToVoiT
and 3 + TV, and 3 + TV + T fo and 3 + TV
and S+yV+Tw+T^W+Ttflors
,
+T^+TFO~O>
are successive approximations to the complete
result 3-14159.
from right to
If
we read 568,213 backwards
left,
starting with the 3 units,
SERIES
199
we read it in the artistic way, gradually pre
paring the mind for the crisis of 500,000.
The ordinary process of numerical multi
plication proceeds by means of the summa
Consider the computation
tion of a series.
658
2736
1710
2052
225036
Hence the three
lines to be added form a
which the first term is the upper
This series follows the artistic method
line.
of presenting the most important term last,
not from any feeling for art, but because of
the convenience gained by keeping a firm
hold on the units place, thus enabling us to
omit some O s, formally necessary.
But when we approximate by gradually
adding the successive terms of an infinite
The
series, what are we approximating to?
in
no
is
that
series
has
the
difficulty
the straightforward sense of the word, because
the operation of adding together its terms
can never be completed. The answer is that
we are approximating to the limit of the
summation of the series, and we must now
series of
"sum"
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
200
proceed to explain what the
series
"limit"
of
a
is.
The summation of a series approximates to
a limit when the sum of any number of its
terms, provided the number be large enough,
is as nearly equal to the limit as you care to
approach. But this description of the mean
ing of approximating to a limit evidently will
not stand the vigorous scrutiny of modern
mathematics.
What is meant by large
by nearly equal, and by care to
All
these vague phrases must be
approach?
explained in terms of the simple abstract
ideas which alone are admitted into pure
enough, and
mathematics.
Let the successive terms of the
MI,
u2
,
Us, u*,
.
.
nth term of the
sum
of the 1st
.,
un
,
series.
series
u
so that
etc.,
Also
let sn
be
the
be the
is
n terms, whatever n may
be.
So that
,
Then the terms
form
sn
81, s 2 s s
and the formation of this series
the process of summation of the original
a new
is
and
,
,
.
.
.
,
.
.
.
series,
Then the
"approximation" of the
original series to a "limit"
means the "approximation of the terms of
this new series to a limit."
And we have
series.
summation of the
SERIES
now
to explain
201
what we mean by the approxi
mation to a limit of the terms of a series.
Now, remembering the definition (given in
Chapter XII) of a standard of approxima
the idea of a limit means this: /
the limit of the terms of the series s\ 9
tion,
is
$2*
,...#,...,
if, corresponding to each
taken as a standard of
approximation, a term sn of the series can
be found so that all succeeding terms (i.e.
sn+i, sn+z, etc.)
approximate to I within
that standard of approximation. If another
smaller standard k 1 be chosen, the term
sn may be too early in the series, and a
later term sm with the above property will
then be found.
If this property holds, it is evident that as
you go along to series s l9 s z **,... ,4* ...
from left to right, after a time you come to
terms all of which are nearer to / than any
number which you may like to assign. In
other words you approximate to I as closely
The close connection of this
as you like.
definition of the limit of a series with the
definition of a continuous function given in
Chapter XI will be immediately perceived.
real
mumber
k,
.
,
Then coming back to the original series u\ 9
Uz 9 u s
, Un,
, the limit of the terms of
sn9
the series s i9 s 2 s S9
., is called
the "sum to infinity" of the original series.
But it is evident that this use of the word
,
.
.
.
.
,
.
.
.
.
.
9
.
.
202
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
is very aritficial, and we must not
assume the analogous properties to those of
"sum"
the ordinary sum of a finite number of terms
without some special investigation.
Let us look at an example of a "sum to
Consider the recurring decimal
infinity."
1111.
This decimal is merely a way of
symbolizing the "sum to infinity" of the
.
series
ing
.
.
-001, -0001, etc.
-1, -01,
series
The correspond
is
Si = -l,
etc.
The limit
found by summation
= -n, s 3 =-lll, * 4 = -llll,
of the terms of this series is ^; this
see by simple division, for
s2
i = -1
Hence,
+ -fa = -11 +
if
is
^7
<nh)
is
easy to
= -HI + 9 oV o =
etc.
given (the k of the definition),
and all succeeding terms differ from ^ by
3
less than T y if loVo is given (another choice
for the k of the definition), -111 and all suc
ceeding terms differ from ^ by less than I ^Vo5
and so on, whatever choice for k be made.
1
;
It is evident that nothing that has been
said gives the slightest idea as to how the
of a series is to be
"sum to
infinity"
have merely stated the condi
found.
tions which such a number is to satisfy. In
deed, a general method for finding in all
cases the sum to infinity of a series is intrinsic
ally out of the question, for the simple reason
that such a "sum," as here defined, does not
always exist. Series which possess a sum to
We
SERIES
203
infinity are called convergent, and those which
infinity are called
do not possess a sum to
divergent.
An
obvious example of a divergent series
i.e. the series of in
., n
1, 2, 3,
For
order
of
in
their
magnitude.
tegers
whatever number I you try to take as its
sum to infinity, and whatever standard of
approximation k you choose, by taking
enough terms of the series you can always
is
make
.
their
.
.
sum
.
differ
.
from
/
by more than
Again, another example of a divergent
series is 1, 1, 1, etc., i.e. the series of
which each term is equal to 1. Then the
sum of n terms is n, and this sum grows
without limit as n increases. Again, another
example of a divergent series is 1, -1, 1, -1,
1, -1, etc., i.e. the series in which the terms
are alternately 1 and -1. The sum of an
odd number of terms is 1, and of an even
number of terms is 0. Hence the terms of
the series Si, s 2 s s ... sn) ... do not ap
proximate to a limit, although they do not
increase without limit.
It is tempting to suppose that the condi
tion for Wi, u 2 ... Wn, ... to have a sum
to infinity is that u n should decrease inde
k.
,
,
,
n increases. Mathematics would
be a much easier science than it is, if this
were the case. Unfortunately the supposition
is not true.
finitely as
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
204
For example the
series
111
1
4
n
2
3
divergent. It is easy to see that this is
the case; for consider the sum of n terms
A
term.
These n
beginning at the (tt-f-l)
is
111
are
n
of
Hence
,
,
them and
their
i.e.
is
2ra
1
-
terms are
-
2n
sum
is
is
sum
.
.
the least
.
2
.,
:
there
among them.
greater than
greater than
altering the
,
,
n times
Now, without
to infinity,
if
it
exist,
we
can add together neighbouring terms, and
obtain the series
is, by what has been said above, a series
whose terms after the 2nd are greater than
that
those of the series,
1, }, J, i, etc.,
where
all
the terms after the
first
But
this series is divergent.
original series is divergent.
This question of divergency
careful
we must be
in arguing
are equal.
Hence the
shows how
from the pro-
SERIES
205
perties of the sum of a finite number of terms
to that of the sum of an infinite series. For
the most elementary property of a finite
number of terms is that of course they
possess a sum: but even this fundamental
not necessarily possessed by an
This caution merely states
that we must not be misled by the suggestion
of the technical term "sum of an infinite
It is usual to indicate the sum of
series."
the infinite series
property
is
infinite series.
Ui,
u z u s ...
,
,
... by
Un,
We
now pass on to a generalization of the
idea of a series, which mathematics, true to
its method, makes by use of the variable.
we have only contemplated series
which each definite term was a definite
number. But equally well we can generalize,
and make each term to be some mathematical
Hitherto,
in
expression containing a variable x.
we may consider the series 1, x, x2 , x3 9
xn,
, and the series
.
.
Thus
.
.
.
,
.
9
?!
L
?L
2
3
n
In order to symbolize the general idea of
any such function, conceive of a function of
x, fn (x) say, which involves in its formation
a variable integer n, then, by giving n the
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
206
values
we
in succession,
1, 2, 3, etc.,
get the
series
MX), MX), MX),
.
.
.,/(*),
.
.
.
Such a series may be convergent for some
values of x and divergent for others. It is,
in fact, rather rare to find a series involving a
variable x which is convergent for all values
at least in any particular instance it is
to assume that this is the case.
unsafe
very
For example, let us examine the simplest of
all
instances, namely, the "geometrical"
of x,
series
1,
The sum
sn
Now
Now
line
X X
9
of
9
X
)
n terms
.
is
.,27,
.
.
.
.
given by
= I+x+x*+x*+.
.
.
+x\
multiply both sides by x and we get
subtract the last line from the upper
and we get
Sn (l
and hence
-x)=Sn -XSn =l- X n+1
(if
n
x be not equal to
l-x
9
1)
l-xx
Now if x be numerically
than 1, for suffin
x
is always less
ciently large values of n,
A ~~ X
less
--
SERIES
207
than Jc, however k be chosen. Thus, if x be
than 1, the series 1, x, x 2 , ... x n , ... is
less
convergent, and
--
-
J.
ment
JL
~
is
X
is its limit.
This state-
symbolized by
X
But
x
numerically greater than 1, or
numerically equal to 1, the series is divergent.
In other words, if x lie between
1 and +1,
the series is convergent; but if x be equal
1 or to -f 1, or if x lie outside the interval
to
1 to +1, then the series is divergent. Thus
the series is convergent at all "points"
within the interval
1 to
exclusive of
the end-points.
At this stage of our enquiry another ques
tion arises. Suppose that the series
if
is
+1>
/l(*)
+/!(*)+/(*)+
-
-
+/(*)+
is convergent for all values of x lying within
the interval a to 6, i.e. f(x) is convergent for
any value of x which is greater than a and
than b. Also, suppose we want to be
sure that in approximating to the limit we
add together enough terms to come within
less
some standard of approximation k. Can we
always state some number of terms, say n,
such that, if we take n or more terms to
form the sum, then whatever value x has
208
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
within the interval we have satisfied the
desired standard of approximation?
Sometimes we can and sometimes we can
not do this for each value of k. When we
can, the series is called uniformly convergent
throughout the interval, and when we cannot
do so, the series is called non-uniformly con
vergent throughout the interval. It makes
a great difference to the properties of a series
whether it is or is not uniformly convergent
through an interval. Let us illustrate the
matter by the simplest example and the
simplest numbers.
Consider the geometric series
convergent throughout the interval
==!.
excluding the end values x
But it is not uniformly convergent through
out this interval. For if sn (x) be the sum of
n terms, we have proved that the difference
1
x n+1
between sn (x) and the limit is l
l
x
x
Now suppose n be any given number of terms,
say 20, and let k be any assigned standard
of approximation, say -001. Then, by taking
x near enough to +1 or near enough to
1,
21
x
we can make the numerical value of to
l
x
be greater than -001. Thus 20 terms will
It
is
1 to -f-1,
-
SERIES
209
not do over the whole interval, though it is
more than enough over some parts of it.
The same reasoning can be applied what
ever other number we take instead of 20,
and whatever standard of approximation in
stead of -001.
Hence the geometric series
1 + x + x2 + Xs -fis non-uni+ xn +
-
formly convergent over
1 to +1.
convergence
whole interval of
if we take any
smaller interval lying at both ends within the
1 to +1, the geometric series is
interval
For ex
uniformly convergent within it.
ample, take the interval to + TV- Then any
its
But
x n+l
value for n which makes
less
than k
at these limits
for all values of
x between these
-
x 1+1
it
X numerically
for x also serves
A ~~
so happens that
-
l
limits, since
diminishes in numeri-
x
cal value as x diminishes in numerical value.
For example, take k =-001; then, putting
we find:
#=
V>
for
for
n-1,--L
X
1
5-
=
^ = -0111
T
n-8,
Thus
three terms will do for the whole in-
210
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
terval, though, of course, for
some parts
the interval it is more than
Notice that, because 1 + x
is
of
necessary.
+
x 2 -f- ...
n
...
is
x
+ +
convergent (though not uni
1 to +1,
formly) throughout the interval
for each value of x in the interval some num
ber of terms n can be found which will satisfy
a desired standard of approximation; but,
as we take x nearer and nearer to either end
value +1 or
1, larger and larger values of
n have to be employed.
It is curious that this important distinction
between uniform and non-uniform conver
gence was not discovered till 1847 by Stokes
afterwards, Sir George Stokes and later, in
dependently in 1850 by Seidel, a German
mathematician.
The critical points, where non-uniform con
vergence comes in, are not necessarily at the
limits of the interval throughout which con
vergence holds. This is a speciality belonging
to the geometric series.
In the case of the geometric series \-\-x
a simple algebraic
x
+ 2 + ... + x n +
.
expression
^JL ~~
X
.
.
,
can be given for
its limit in
interval of convergence. But this is not
always the case. Often we can prove a series
to be convergent within a certain interval,
though we know nothing more about its
limit except that it is the limit of the seriesits
SERIES
But this is a very good way of defining a func
as the limit of an infinite conver
and is, in fact, the way in which
most functions are, or ought to be, defined.
Thus, the most important series in ele
tion;
viz.
gent
series,
mentary analysis
is
where n\ has the meaning defined earlier in
This series can be proved to
be convergent for all values of x, and to be
uniformly convergent within any interval
which we like to take. Hence it has all the
comfortable mathematical properties which
a series should have. It is called the ex
ponential series. Denote its sum to infinity
by expo;. Thus, by definition,
this chapter.
expo; is called the exponential function.
It is fairly easy to prove, with a little
knowledge of elementary mathematics, that
(expz)
X (expy) = exp(x+y)
In other words that
(expz)
X (expy) =
(x+y)
n!
.
.
.
(A)
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
is an example of what
an addition-theorem. When any
function [say /(#)] has been defined, the first
thing we do is to try to express f(x+y) in
terms of known functions of x only, and
known functions of y only. If we can do so,
the result is called an addition-theorem.
This property (A)
is
called
Addition-theorems play a great part in
mathematical analysis. Thus the additiontheorem for the sine is given by
sin (x-\-y)
and
=sin x cos ^+cos x sin
for the cosine
cos (x-\-y)
y,
by
=cos x cos y
sin
x
sin y.
As a matter
fining sin
of fact the best ways of de
x and cos x are not by the elaborate
geometrical methods of the previous chapter,
but as the limits respectively of the series
z3
x7
ar>
""
^""
andl
"
*
1
~2! + 4!~6! +etC
so that
,
,
*
----
*
we put
Xs X5 X 7
sm x =x - ^+ - +
,
i
-
6
2
X
-
,
*>
tf
/:
X*
etc.
.
.
.,
SERIES
213
These definitions are equivalent to the geo
metrical definitions, and both series can be
proved to be convergent for all values of x,
and uniformly convergent throughout any
These series for sine and cosine
have a general likeness to the exponential
interval.
series given above.
They
are, indeed, inti
mately connected with it by means of the
theory of imaginary numbers explained in
Chapters VII and VIII.
X
Z
Fig. 29.
The graph of the exponential function is
given in fig. 29. It cuts the axis OF at the
point 2/ = l, as evidently it ought to do, since
when cc = every term of the series except
the first is zero. The importance of the ex
ponential function is that it represents any
changing physical quantity whose rate of
increase at any instant is a uniform per
centage of its value at that instant. For
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
example, the above graph represents the size
at any time of a population with a uniform
birth-rate, where the x corresponds to the
time reckoned from any convenient day, and
the y represents the population to the proper
The scale must be such that OA re
scale.
presents the population at the date which is
taken as the origin. But we have here come
upon the idea of "rates of increase" which
is the topic for the next chapter,
An important function nearly allied to the
exponential function is found by putting
x2 for x as the argument in the exponential
2
We thus get exp.
function.
The
).
graph
2/
= exp.
(x
(x
2
) is
given in
fig.
30.
Fig. 30.
The
hat,
is
curve, which
is
something like a cocked
normal error. Its
called the curve of
SERIES
215
corresponding function is vitally important
to the theory of statistics, and tells us in
many cases the sort of deviations from the
average results which we are to expect.
Another important function is found by
combining the exponential function with the
sine, in this
way:
y = exp( -
ex)
X sin
Fig. 31.
Its graph is given in fig. 31. The points
A, B, 0, C D, E F, are placed at equal in
tervals %p and an unending series of them
should be drawn forwards and backwards.
9
9
9
This function represents the dying away of
vibrations under the influence of friction or of
"damping" forces.
Apart from the friction,
the vibrations would be periodic, with a
period p; but the influence of the friction
216
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
makes the extent
of each vibration smaller
than that of the preceding by a constant per
centage of that extent. This combination
of the idea of "periodicity" (which requires
the sine or cosine for its symbolism) and of
"constant percentage" (which requires the
exponential function for its symbolism) is the
reason for the form of this function, namely,
its form as a product of a sine-function into
an exponential function.
CHAPTER XV
THE DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
THE
invention of the differential calculus
crisis in the history of mathematics.
The progress of science is divided between
periods characterized by a slow accumulation
of ideas and periods, when, owing to the new
material for thought thus patiently collected,
some genius by the invention of a new method
or a new point of view, suddenly transforms
the whole subject on to a higher level. These
contrasted periods in the progress of the
history of thought are compared by Shelley
to the formation of an avalanche.
marks a
The sun-awakened avalanche! whose mass,
Thrice sifted by the storm, had gathered there
Flake after flake,
in heaven-defying minds
As thought by thought is piled, till some great truth
Is loosened, and the nations echo round,
The comparison
The final burst of
bear some pressing.
sunshine which awakens
the avalanche is not necessarily beyond com
parison in magnitude with the other powers
of nature which have presided over its slow
will
217
218
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
The same is true in science. The
genius who has the good fortune to produce
the final idea which transforms a whole
region of thought, does not necessarily excel
all his predecessors who have worked at the
preliminary formation of ideas. In consider
ing the history of science, it is both silly and
ungrateful to confine our admiration with a
gaping wonder to those men who have made
the final advances towards a new epoch.
In the particular instance before us, the
subject had a long history before it as
sumed its final form at the hands of its
two inventors. There are some traces of its
methods even among the Greek mathe
maticians, and finally, just before the actual
production of the subject, Fermat (born 1601
A.D., and died 1665 A.D.), a distinguished
French mathematician, had so improved on
previous ideas that the subject was all but
created by him.
Fermat, also, may lay
claim to be the joint inventor of coordinate
formation.
geometry in company with his contemporary
and countryman, Descartes. It was, in fact,
Descartes from whom the world of science
received the new ideas, but Fermat had cer
tainly arrived at them independently.
We need not, however, stint our admira
tion either for
Newton
or for Leibniz.
New
ton was a mathematician and a student of
physical science, Leibniz was a mathema-
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
219
and a philosopher, and each of them
own department of thought was one of
the greatest men of genius that the world
The joint invention was the
has known.
tician
in his
occasion of an unfortunate and not very
creditable dispute.
Newton was using the
methods of Fluxions, as he called the sub
ject, in 1666,
and employed
it
in the
com
position of his Principia, although in the work
as printed any special algebraic notation is
avoided. But he did not print a direct state
ment of his method till 1693. Leibniz pub
He was
lished his first statement in 1684.
accused by Newton s friends of having got
it
from a MS. by Newton, which he had been
privately. Leibniz also accused New
ton of having plagiarized from him. There
is now not very much doubt but that both
should have the credit of being independent
The subject had arrived at a
discoverers.
shown
stage in which it was ripe for discovery, and
there is nothing surprising in the fact that
two such able men should have indepen
dently hit upon
it.
These joint discoveries are quite common
Discoveries are not in general
before they have been led up to by
the previous trend of thought, and by that
time many minds are in hot pursuit of the
important idea. If we merely keep to dis
coveries in which Englishmen are concerned,
in science.
made
220
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
the simultaneous enunciation of the law of
natural selection by Darwin and Wallace,
and the simultaneous discovery of Neptune
by Adams and the French astronomer,
Leverrier, at once occur to the mind. The
disputes, as to whom the credit ought to be
given, are often influenced by an unworthy
The really inspiring
spirit of nationalism.
reflection suggested by the history of mathe
matics is the unity of thought and interest
among men
of so
many
epochs, so many
Indians, Egyp
Greeks, Arabs, Italians,
nations, and so many
tians,
Assyrians,
races.
Frenchmen, Germans, Englishmen, and Rus
sians, have all made essential contributions
to the progress of the science. Assuredly the
jealous exaltation of the contribution of one
particular nation is not to show the larger
spirit.
The importance
of the differential calculus
of the subject,
which is the systematic consideration of the
rates of increase of functions. This idea is
immediately presented to us by the study of
nature; velocity is the rate of increase of the
arises
from the very nature
distance travelled, and acceleration is the
rate of increase of velocity. Thus the funda
mental idea of change, which is at the basis of
our whole perception of phenomena, imme
diately suggests the enquiry as to the rate of
The familiar terms of "quickly"
change.
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
221
and
"slowly" gain their meaning from a tacit
reference to rates of change. Thus the differ
ential calculus is concerned with the very
key of the position from which mathematics
can be successfully applied to the explana
tion of the course of nature.
This idea of the rate of change was certainly
in Newton s mind, and was embodied in the
T
N
M
jf
Fig. 32.
language in which he explained the subject.
It may be doubted, however, whether this
point of view, derived from natural pheno
mena, was ever much in the minds of the
preceding mathematicians who prepared the
subject for its birth. They were concerned
with the more abstract problems of drawing
tangents to curves, of finding the lengths of
curves, and of finding the areas enclosed by
curves. The last two problems, of the recti-
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
and the quadrature of
named, belong to the In
tegral Calculus, which is however involved in
the same general subject as the Differential
fication of curves
curves as they are
Calculus.
The introduction of coordinate geometry
makes the two points of view coalesce. For
be any curved line and let
(cf. fig. 32) let
be the tangent at the point
on it. Let
the axes of coordinates be
and
and
let y=f(x) be the equation to the curve,
= x, and
so that
y. Now let Q be any
on
the
with coordinates
curve,
moving point
AQP
PT
P
OX
OY
PM
OM
Xi,yi; then?/i=/(i).
And let Q be the point
on the tangent with the same abscissa
Xi\
suppose that the coordinates of Q are Xi and
moves along the
Now suppose that
y
axis OX from left to right with a uniform
velocity; then it is easy to see that the ordinate y of the point Q on the tangent TP
also increases uniformly as Q moves along
the tangent in a corresponding way. In fact
N
.
f
it is easy to see that the ratio of the rate of
to the rate of increase of
increase of Q
to TN, which is the same
is in the ratio of Q
But the
at all points of the straight line.
rate of increase of QN, which is the rate of
increase of f(xi), varies from point to point of
the curve so long as it is not straight. As Q
passes through the point P, the rate of in
crease of f(xi) (where Xi coincides with x for
N
N
ON
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
223
is the same as the rate of in
on the tangent at P. Hence, if
the moment)
crease of y
we have a general method of determining
the rate of increase of a function f(x) of a
variable x, we can determine the slope of the
tangent at any point (x, y), on a curve, and
thence can draw it. Thus the problems of
drawing tangents to a curve, and of deter
mining the rates of increase of a function
are really identical.
It will be noticed that, as in the cases of
Conic Sections and Trigonometry, the more
artificial of the two points of view is the one
in which the subject took its rise. The really
fundamental aspect of the science only rose
into prominence comparatively late in the
day. It is a well-founded historical generali
zation, that the last thing to be discovered
in any science is what the science is really
about.
Men go on groping for centuries,
guided merely by a dim instinct and a
puzzled curiosity, till at last "some great
truth is loosened."
Let us take some special cases in order to
familiarize ourselves with the sort of ideas
which we want to make precise. A train is in
motion how shall we determine its velocity
at some instant, let us say, at noon? We can
take an interval of five minutes which includes
noon, and measure how far the train has gone
in that period. Suppose we find it to be five
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
we may then conclude
that the train
of 60 miles per hour.
But five miles is a long distance, and we
cannot be sure that just at noon the train
was moving at this pace. At noon it may
miles,
was running at the rate
have been running 70 miles per hour, and
afterwards the break may have been put on.
It will be safer to work with a smaller interval,
say one minute, which includes noon, and to
measure the space traversed during that
But for some purposes greater
period.
accuracy may be required, and one minute
may be too long. In practice, the necessary
inaccuracy of our measurements makes it
useless to take too small a period for measure
ment. But in theory the smaller the period
the better, and we are tempted to say that
for ideal accuracy an infinitely small period
The older mathematicians, in
is required.
particular Leibniz, were not only tempted,
but yielded to the temptation, and did say
Even now it is a useful fashion of speech,
it.
provided that we know how to interpret it
It is
into the language of common sense.
curious that, in his exposition of the founda
tions of the calculus, Newton, the natural
scientist,
is
much more
philosophical than
and on the other
hand, Leibniz provided the admirable nota
tion which has been so essential for the pro
gress of the subject.
Leibniz, the philosopher,
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
Now take another example within the region
of pure mathematics. Let us proceed to find
the rate of increase of the function x2 for
have not
any value x of its argument.
defined what we mean by rate of
really
yet
will try and grasp its meaning
increase.
in relation to this particular case. When x
increases to x+h, the function x 2 increases to
2
(x+h) ; so that the total increase has been
2
x 2 , due to an increase h in the argu
(x+h)
ment. Hence throughout the interval x to
(x +h) the average increase of the function per
We
We
unit increase of the argument
is
^
x
nI
But
and therefore
2
(x+h) -x*
~h~
Thus
2hx+h?_^
ljt
~T~
%x-\-h is the average increase of the
function x 2 per unit increase in the argument,
the average being taken over by the interval
x to x+ h. But %x+h depends on h, the size
of the interval. We shall evidently get what
we want, namely the rate of increase at the
value x of the argument, by diminishing h
more and more. Hence in the limit when h
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
has decreased
indefinitely,
we say that %x
is
the
rate of increase of x 2 at the value x of the
argument.
Here again we are apparently driven up
against the idea of infinitely small quantities
in the use of the words "in the limit when h
has decreased indefinitely." Leibniz held that,
mysterious as it may sound, there were actu
ally existing such things as infinitely small
quantities, and of course infinitely small num
bers corresponding to them. Newton s lan
guage and ideas were more on the modern
lines; but he did not succeed in explaining
the matter with such explicitness as to be
evidently doing more than explain Leibniz s
ideas in rather indirect language. The real
explanation of the subject was first given by
Weierstrass and the Berlin School of mathe
maticians about the middle of the nineteenth
But between Leibniz and Weier
century.
strass a copious literature, both mathematical
and philosophical, had grown up round these
mysterious infinitely small quantities which
mathematics had discovered and philosophy
Some philosophers,
proceeded to explain.
Bishop Berkeley, for instance, correctly denied
the validity of the whole idea, though for
reasons other than those indicated here. But
the curious fact remained that, despite all
criticisms of the foundations of the subject,
there could be no doubt but that the mathe-
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
227
matical procedure was substantially right.
In fact, the subject was right, though the ex
planations were wrong. It is this possibility
of being right, albeit with entirely wrong ex
planations as to what is being done, that so
often makes external criticism that is so far
as it is meant to stop the pursuit of a method
singularly barren and futile in the progress
of science. The instinct of trained observers,
and their sense of curiosity, due to the fact
that they are obviously getting at something,
are far safer guides.
Anyhow the general
effect of the success of the Differential Cal
culus was to generate a large amount of bad
philosophy, centring round the idea of the in
finitely small.
The
relics
of this verbiage
may still be found in the explanations of
many elementary mathematical text-books on
the Differential Calculus. It is a safe rule to
apply that, when a mathematical or philoso
phical author writes with a misty profundity,
he is talking nonsense.
Newton would have phrased the question
by saying that, as h approaches zero, in the
%x+h becomes %x. It is our task so to
explain this statement as to show that it does
not in reality covertly assume the existence
of Leibniz s infinitely small quantities.
In
reading over the Newtonian method of state
ment, it is tempting to seek simplicity by
limit
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
saying that %x-\-h is &r, when h is zero. But
this will not do; for it thereby abolishes the
interval from x to x+h, over which the aver
age increase was calculated. The problem is,
how to keep an interval of length h over which
to calculate the average increase, and at the
same time to treat h as if it were zero. New
ton did this by the conception of a limit, and
we now proceed to give Weierstrass s expla
nation of its real meaning.
In the first place notice that, in discussing
%x+h, we have been considering x as fixed in
value and h as varying. In other words x
has been treated as a "constant" variable,
or parameter, as explained in Chapter IX;
and we have really been considering %x-\-h as
a function of the argument h. Hence we can
generalize the question on hand, and ask
what we mean by saying that the function
f(h) tends to the limit I, say, as its argument
h tends to the value zero. But again we shall
see that the special value zero for the argument
does not belong to the essence of the subject;
and again we generalize still further, and ask
what we mean by saying that the f unction f(h)
as h tends to the value a.
to the Weierstrassian ex
planation the whole idea of h tending to the
value a, though it gives a sort of metaphorical
picture of what we are driving at, is really off
the point entirely. Indeed it is fairly obvious
tends to the limit
Now, according
I
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
229
that, as long as we retain anything like
as a fundamental idea, we are
tending to
really in the clutches of the infinitely small;
for we imply the notion of h being infinitely
"h
a,"
near to
This
a.
is
just
what we want
to get
rid of.
Accordingly, we shall yet again restate our
phrase to be explained, and ask what we
mean by saying that the limit of the function
(fh) at a is I.
The limit of f(h) at a is a property of the
neighbourhood of a, where "neighbourhood"
is used in the sense defined in Chapter XI
during the discussion of the continuity of
The value
functions.
of the function f(h) at
but the limit is distinct in idea
from the value, and may be different from
it, and may exist when the value has not
been defined. We shall also use the term
a
is
/(a);
of approximation" in the sense
is defined in Chapter XI.
In
fact, in the definition of "continuity" given
towards the end of that chapter we have
practically defined a limit. The definition of
"standard
in
which
a limit
is
it
:
A
function f(x) has the limit I at a value
a of its argument x, when in the neighbour
hood of a its values approximate to / within
every standard of approximation.
Compare this definition with that already
given for continuity, namely:
230
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
A
function f(x) is continuous at a value a
of its argument, when in the neighbourhood
of a its values approximate to its value at a
within every standard of approximation.
It is at once evident that a function is con
tinuous at a when (i) it possesses a limit at a,
and (ii) that limit is equal to its value at a.
Thus the illustrations of continuity which
have been given at the end of Chapter XI are
illustrations of the idea of a limit, namely,
they were all directed to proving that /(a)
was the limit of f(x) at a for the functions
considered and the value of a considered. It
is really more instructive to consider the
limit at a point where a function is not con
tinuous. For example, consider the function
of which the graph is given in fig. 20 of Chap
ter XI. This function f(x) is defined to have
the value 1 for all values of the argument
except the integers 1, 2, 3, etc., and for these
integral values it has the value 0. Now let
us think of its limit when x = 3. We notice
that in the definition of the limit the value
of the function at a (in this case, a = 3) is ex
cluded.
But, excluding /(3), the values of
f(x), when x lies within any interval which
(i) contains 3 not as an end-point, and (ii)
does not extend so far as 2 and 4, are all
equal to 1; and hence these values approxi
mate to 1 within every standard of approxi
mation. Hence 1 is the limit of f(x) at the
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
value 3 of the argument
x,
231
but by definition
.
This is an instance of a function which
possesses both a value and a limit at the
value 3 of the argument, but the value is not
equal to the limit. At the end of Chapter
XI the function x 2 was considered at the
value 2 of the argument. Its value at % is 2 2 ,
i.e. 4, and it was proved that its limit is also
Thus here we have a function with a
value and a limit which are equal.
Finally we come to the case which is essen
tially important for our purposes, namely, to
a function which possesses a limit, but no
defined value at a certain value of its argu
ment.
We need not go far to look for
4.
such a function,
Now
in
%x
-
-
will serve
our purpose.
any mathematical book, we might
find the equation,
hesitation or
2x
x
=
comment.
culty in this; for
when x
2,
written without
But
is
there
zero,
is
=
x
a
diffi
-; and
u
- has no defined meaning.
Thus the value
%x
at # =
x
has no defined
of the function
232
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
But
meaning.
for every other value of x 9
the value of the function
limit of
at x
Qx
- -
= 0.
at x
=
is 2,
2x
x
is 2.
and
it
Similarly the limit of
a whatever a
may
has no value
x2
at x = a
x
But the value
is 0.
takes the form -,
meaning.
We now
rr
2
of
x
at x
=
which has no defined
Thus the function
but no value at
is
be, so that the limit of
2
Xat x =
x
Thus the
x2
has a limit
x
0.
come back
which we started
to the problem from
this discussion
on the nature
How
of a limit.
are we going to define the
rate of increase of the function x 9 at any
value x of its argument. Our answer is that
this rate of increase is the limit of the func-
at the value zero for
its
argument h. (Note that x is here a "con
Let us see how this answer works
stant."
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
235
in the light of our definition of a limit.
We
have
Now
h(2x+h)
h
h
h
in finding the limit of
-
7
-
n
- at
the
of the argument h, the value (if any)
value
is excluded.
But for
of the function at h =
all values of h, except /i = 0, we can divide
through by
h.
Thus the
limit of
at
is the same as that of %x+h at h = Q.
Now, whatever standard of approximation k
we choose to take, by considering the interval
from
%k to +|fc we see that, for values of h
which fall within it, %x+h differs from %x by
less than %k, that is by less than k. This is true
A=
any standard k. Hence in the neighbour
hood of the value for h,%x+h approximates
to %x within every standard of approxima
tion, and therefore %x is the limit of %x+h
at /& = 0. Hence by what has been said above
for
c is
the limit of
h
at the value
It follows, therefore, that %x is what
called the rate of increase of x2 at
Thus this
the value x of the argument.
method conducts us to the same rate of in-
for h.
we have
234
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
crease for x 2 as did the Leibnizian
way
of
making h grow "infinitely small."
The more abstract terms "differential co
or "derived function," are gener
used for what we have hitherto called the
"rate
of increase" of a function.
The
definition
is
as
follows:
the
differ
general
efficient,"
ally
ential coefficient of the function f(x)
limit,
of the
if it
exist, of
the f unction
is
^x +h
argument h at the value
the
"^
]
h
of its argu
ment
How
have we, by
this definition and the
a limit, really managed
definition
of
subsidiary
to avoid the notion of "infinitely small num
which so worried our mathematical
For them the difficulty arose
because on the one hand they had to use an
interval x to x+h over which to calculate
the average increase, and, on the other hand,
they finally wanted to put h = 0. The result
was they seemed to be landed into the notion
of an existent interval of zero size.
Now
how do we avoid this difficulty? In this
bers"
forefathers?
we use the notion that corresponding
to any standard of approximation, some in
terval with such and such properties can
be found. The difference is that we have
grasped the importance of the notion of "the
way
variable,"
and they had not done
so.
Thus,
DIFFERENTIAL CALCULUS
235
at the end of our exposition of the essential
notions of mathematical analysis, we are led
back to the ideas with which in Chapter II
we commenced our enquiry that in mathe
matics the fundamentally important ideas
are those of "some things" and "any
things."
CHAPTER XVI
GEOMETRY
GEOMETRY, like the rest of mathematics, is
abstract. In it the properties of the shapes
and relative positions of things are studied.
But we do not need to consider who is observ
ing the things, or whether he becomes ac
quainted with them by sight or touch or
In short, we ignore all particular
hearing.
sensations.
Furthermore, particular things
such as the Houses of Parliament, or the
terrestrial globe are ignored.
Every pro
position refers to any things with such and
such geometrical properties.
Of course it
helps our imagination to look at particular
examples of spheres and cones and triangles
But the propositions do not
merely apply to the actual figures printed in
the book, but to any such figures.
Thus geometry, like algebra, is dominated
and squares.
ideas of "any" and "some" things.
Also, in the same way it studies the inter
relations of sets of things. For example, con
by the
sider
any two
triangles
ABC and DEF.
236
GEOMETRY
What
relations
must
exist
237
between some of
the parts of these triangles, in order that the
triangles may be in all respects equal? This
is one of the first investigations undertaken
in all elementary geometries. It is a study
a
c
F
Fig. 33.
of a certain set of possible correlations be
triangles. The answer is that
the triangles are in all respects equal, if:
Either, (a) Two sides of the one and the in
cluded angle are respectively equal to two
sides of the other and the included angle:
Or, (6) Two angles of the one and the side
tween the two
joining them are respectively equal to two
angles of the other and the side joining them:
Or, (c) Three sides of the one are respec
tively equal to three sides of the other.
This answer at once suggests a further en
quiry. What is the nature of the correlation
between the triangles, when the three angles
of the one are respectively equal to the three
This further inves
angles of the other?
tigation leads us on to the whole theory
238
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
(cf. Chapter XIII), which is
another type of correlation.
Again, to take another example, consider
the internal structure of the triangle ABC.
Its sides and angles are inter-related
the
greater angle is opposite to the greater side,
and the base angles of an isosceles triangle
of similarity
are equal.
If we proceed to trigonometry
this correlation receives a more exact deter
mination in the familiar shape
sin
a?
= b 2 -f c2
A
sin
QbccosA,
B
sin
with
C
two
similar
formulae.
Also there
is
the
still
simpler correlation
between the angles of the
triangle, namely,
equal to two right angles;
and between the three sides, namely, that the
sum of the lengths of any two is greater than
the length of the third.
Thus the true method to study geometry is
to think of interesting simple figures, such as
the triangle, the parallelogram, and the circle,
and to investigate the correlations between
their various parts. The geometer has in his
mind not a detached proposition, but a figure
with its various parts mutually inter-depend
ent. Just as in algebra, he generalizes the
triangle into the polygon, and the side into
that their
sum
is
GEOMETRY
the conic section.
239
Or, pursuing a converse
route, he classifies triangles according as they
are equilateral, isosceles, or scalene, and
polygons according to their number of sides,
and conic sections according as they are
hyperbolas, ellipses, or parabolas.
The preceding examples illustrate how the
fundamental ideas of geometry are exactly
the same as those of algebra; except that
algebra deals with numbers and geometry
with lines, angles, areas, and other geo
metrical entities. This fundamental identity
is one of the reasons why so many geo
metrical truths can be put into an algebraic
dress. Thus if A, B, and C are the numbers
of degrees respectively in the angles of the
triangle ABC, the correlation between the
angles is represented by the equation
=
180
and if a, 6, c are the number of feet respec
tively in the three sides, the correlation be
tween the sides is represented by a b -f c,
Also the trigonometrical
6
c -f- a, c<a+b.
formulae quoted above are other examples of
the same fact. Thus the notion of the vari
able and the correlation of variables is just as
essential in geometry as it is in algebra.
<
<
parallelism between geometry and
be pushed still further, owing to
can
algebra
the fact that lengths, areas, volumes, and
But the
240
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
angles are all measurable; so that, for exam
the size of any length can be determined
by the number (not necessarily integral) of
times which it contains some arbitrarily
ple,
known
and
similarly for areas, volumes,
trigonometrical formulae,
given above, are examples of this fact. But it
receives its crowning application in analytical
and
unit,
angles.
The
This great subject is often mis
as Analytical Conic Sections, thereby
fixing attention on merely one of its sub
It is as though the great science
divisions.
of Anthropology were named the Study of
Noses, owing to the fact that noses are a
prominent part of the human body.
Though the mathematical procedures in
geometry and algebra are in essence identical
and intertwined in their, development, there
is
necessarily a fundamental distinction
between the properties of space and the
properties of number in fact all the essential
difference between space and number. The
and the numerosity
"spaciness" of space
of number are essentially different things, and
geometry.
named
"
"
directly apprehended. None of the
applications of algebra to geometry or of
geometry to algebra go any step on the road
to obliterate this vital distinction.
One very marked difference between space
and number is that the former seems to be so
much less abstract and fundamental than the
must be
GEOMETRY
241
The number of the archangels can be
counted just because they are things. When
we once know that their names are Raphael,
Gabriel, and Michael, and that these distinct
latter.
names represent
distinct beings,
we know
without further question that there are three
All the subtleties in the world
of them.
about the nature of angelic existences can
not alter this fact, granting the premisses.
But we are still quite in the dark as to
their relation to space.
Do they exist in
at
all?
it
is
space
Perhaps
equally nonsense
to say that they are here, or there, or any
where, or everywhere. Their existence may
simply have no relation to localities in space.
Accordingly, while numbers must apply to
all things, space need not do so.
The
perception of the locality of things
would appear to accompany, or be involved
in many, or all, of our sensations. It is in
dependent of any particular sensation in the
sense that it accompanies many sensations.
But
it is
a special peculiarity of the things
which we apprehend by our sensations. The
direct apprehension of what we mean by the
positions of things in respect to each other
is a thing sui generis, just as are the appre
hensions of sounds, colours, tastes, and smells.
At first sight therefore it would appear that
mathematics, in so far as it includes geometry
in its scope, is not abstract in the sense in
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
which abstractness is ascribed to it in
Chapter I.
This, however, is a mistake; the truth
being that the "spaciness" of space does not
enter into our geometrical reasoning at all.
It enters into the geometrical intuitions of
mathematicians in ways personal and pecu
But what enter into
liar to each individual.
the reasoning are merely certain properties of
things in space, or of things forming space,
which properties are completely abstract in
the sense in which abstract was defined in
Chapter I; these properties do not involve
any peculiar space-apprehension or spaceintuition or space-sensation.
They are on
exactly the same basis as the mathematical
properties of number. Thus the space-intui
tion which is so essential an aid to the study
of geometry is logically irrelevant: it does
not enter into the premisses when they are
properly stated, nor into any step of the rea
soning. It has the practical importance of an
example, which is essential for the stimulation
of our thoughts. Examples are equally neces
sary to stimulate our thoughts on number.
When we think of "two" and "three" we
see strokes in a row, or balls in a heap, or
some other physical aggregation of particular
The peculiarity of geometry is the
things.
and
overwhelming importance of the
fixity
one particular example which occurs to our
GEOMETRY
minds.
243
The
abstract logical form of the
fully stated is,
any
of things have such and such
propositions
collections
when
"If
abstract properties, they also have such and
such other abstract properties." But what
appears before the mind s eye is a collection
of points, lines, surfaces, and volumes in the
this example inevitably appears, and
the sole example which lends to the propo
sition its interest. However, for all its over
space:
is
whelming importance,
Geometry, viewed
it is
but an example.
as a mathematical
science, is a division of the more general
It may be called the
science of order.
science of dimensional order; the qualifica
tion "dimensional" has been introduced
because the limitations, which reduce it to
only a part of the general science of order,
are such as to produce the regular relations
of straight lines to planes, and of planes to
the whole of space.
It is easy to understand the practical im
portance of space in the formation of the
scientific conception of an external physical
world. On the one hand our space-percep
tions are intertwined in our various sensa
nor
tions and connect them together.
mally judge that we touch an object in the
same place as we see it; and even in ab
normal cases we touch it in the same space
We
as
we
see
it,
and
this
is
the real fundamental
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
244
which
ties together our various sensa
Accordingly, the space perceptions
are in a sense the common part of our sensa
tions.
Again it happens that the abstract
fact
tions.
properties of space form a large part of what
ever is of spatial interest.
It is not too
much to say that to every property of space
there corresponds an abstract mathematical
statement.
To
take the most unfavourable
instance, a curve may have a special beauty
of shape: but to this shape there will cor
respond some abstract mathematical prop
erties which go with this shape and no
others.
Thus to sum up: (1) the properties of
space which are investigated in geometry,
like those of number, are properties belong
ing to things as things, and without special
reference to any particular mode of appre
hension; (2) Space-perception accompanies
our sensations, perhaps all of them, certainly
many; but it does not seem to be a necessary
quality of things that they should all exist
in one space or in any space.
CHAPTER XVII
QUANTITY
IN the previous chapter we pointed out
that lengths are measurable in terms of some
unit length, areas in term of a unit area, and
volumes in terms of a unit volume.
When we have a set of things such as
lengths which are measurable in terms of any
one of them, we say that they are quantities
of the same kind. Thus lengths are quantities
of the same kind, so are areas, and so are
volumes. But an area is not a quantity of
the same kind as a length, nor is it of the
same kind as a volume. Let us think a little
more on what
is
meant by being measurable,
taking lengths as an example.
Lengths are measured by the foot-rule. By
transporting the foot-rule from place to place
we judge of the equality of lengths. Again,
three adjacent lengths, each of one foot, form
one whole length of three feet. Thus to meas
ure lengths we have to determine the equality
of lengths and the addition of lengths. When
some test has been applied, such as the trans
porting of a foot-rule, we say that the lengths
are equal;
and when some process has been
245
246
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
applied, so as to secure lengths being con
tiguous and not overlapping, we say that the
lengths have been added to form one whole
length. But we cannot arbitrarily take any
test as the test of equality and any process
as the process of addition.
The results of
operations of addition and of judgments of
equality must be in accordance with certain
preconceived conditions. For example, the
addition of two greater lengths must yield
a length greater than that yielded by the
addition of two smaller lengths. These pre
conceived conditions when accurately formu
lated may be called axioms of quantity. The
only question as to their truth or falsehood
which can arise is whether, when the axioms
are satisfied, we necessarily get what ordinary
people call quantities. If we do not, then
the name "axioms of quantity" is ill-judged
that is all.
These axioms of quantity are entirely ab
stract, just as are the mathematical proper
ties of space.
They are the same for all
quantities, and they presuppose no special
of perception.
The ideas associated
with the notion of quantity are the means by
which a continuum like a line, an area, or a
volume can be split up into definite parts.
Then these parts are counted; so that num
bers can be used to determine the exact prop
erties of a continuous whole.
mode
QUANTITY
247
Our perception of the flow of time and of
the succession of events is a chief example
of the application of these ideas of quantity.
We measure time (as has been said in con
sidering periodicity) by the repetition of
similar events the burning of successive
inches of a uniform candle, the rotation of
the earth relatively to the fixed stars, the
rotation of the hands of a clock are all ex
amples of such repetitions. Events of these
types take the place of the foot-rule in rela
tion to lengths. It is not necessary to assume
that events of any one of these types are
exactly equal in duration at each recurrence.
What is necessary is that a rule should be
known which will enable us to express the
relative durations of, say, two examples of
some type. For example, we may if we like
suppose that the rate of the earth s rotation
is decreasing, so that each day is longer than
the preceding by some minute fraction of a
second. Such a rule enables us to compare
the length of any day with that of any other
day. But what is essential is that one series
of repetitions, such as successive days, should
be taken as the standard series; and, if the
various events of that series are not taken as
of equal duration, that a rule should be
stated which regulates the duration to be
assigned to each day in terms of the dura
tion of any other day.
248
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
What
then are the requisites which such
ought to have? In the first place it
should lead to the assignment of nearly equal
durations to events which common sense
a
rule
judges to possess equal durations.
which
lengths,
made days
of
and which made
A
rule
different
the speeds of ap
violently
parently similar operations vary utterly out
of proportion to the apparent minuteness of
their differences, would never do. Hence the
first requisite is general agreement with com
mon sense. But this is not sufficient abso
lutely to determine the rule, for common
sense is a rough observer and very easily
satisfied.
The next requisite is that minute
adjustments of the rule should be so made as
to allow of the simplest possible statements
of the laws of nature. For example, astron
omers tell us that the earth s rotation is slow
ing down, so that each day gains in length by
some inconceivably minute fraction of a
second. Their only reason for their assertion
(as stated more fully in the discussion of
periodicity) is that without it they would
have to abandon the Newtonian laws of
motion. In order to keep the laws of motion
simple, they alter the measure of time. This
is a perfectly legitimate procedure so long as
it is thoroughly understood.
What has been said above about the ab
stract nature of the mathematical properties
QUANTITY
249
space applies with appropriate verbal
changes to the mathematical properties of
time. A sense of the flux of time accompa
nies all our sensations and perceptions, and
practically all that interests us in regard to
time can be paralleled by the abstract mathe
matical properties which we ascribe to it.
Conversely what has been said about the two
requisites for the rule by which we determine
the length of the day, also applies to the rule
for determining the length of a yard measure
namely, the yard measure appears to retain
the same length as it moves about. Accord
ingly, any rule must bring out that, apart
from minute changes, it does remain of in
variable lengths. Again, the second requisite
is this, a definite rule for minute changes
shall be stated which allows of the simplest
For ex
expression of the laws of nature.
re
second
the
with
in
accordance
ample,
to
are
measures
the
supposed
yard
quisite
expand and contract with changes of tem
perature according to the substances which
they are made of.
Apart from the facts that our sensations are
accompanied with perceptions of locality and
of duration, and that lines, areas, volumes,
and durations, are each in their way quanti
ties, the theory of numbers would be of very
subordinate use in the exploration of the laws
As it is, physical science
of the Universe.
of
250
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS
reposes on the main ideas of number, quan
The mathematical
tity, space, and time.
sciences associated with them do not form
the whole of mathematics, but they are the
substratum of mathematical physics as at
present existing.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
NOTE ON THE STUDY OF MATHEMATICS
THE
difficulty that beginners find in the
study of this
due to the large amount of technical detail which
has been allowed to accumulate in the elementary text
books, obscuring the important ideas.
The first subjects of study, apart from a knowledge of
arithmetic which is presupposed, must be elementary
geometry and elementary algebra. The courses in both
subjects should be short, giving only the necessary ideas;
the algebra should be studied graphically, so that in prac
tice the ideas of elementary coordinate geometry are also
being assimilated. The next pair of subjects should be
elementary trigonometry and the coordinate geometry of
the straight line and circle. The latter subject is a short
one; for it really merges into the algebra. The student
is then prepared to enter upon conic sections, a very short
course of geometrical conic sections and a longer one of
science
is
analytical conies.
But
in
all
these courses great care
should be taken not to overload the mind with more
detail than is necessary for the exemplification of the
fundamental
The
ideas.
differential calculus
and afterwards the integral
same system.
A good teacher will already have illustrated them by the
consideration of special cases in the course on algebra
and coordinate geometry. Some short book on three
dimensional geometry must also be read.
calculus
now remain
to be attacked on the
This elementary course of mathematics
is sufficient for
It is also the necessary
of professional career.
preliminary for any one wishing to study the subject for its
intrinsic interest.
He is now prepared to commence on a
more extended course. He must not, however, hope to be
some types
251
BIBLIOGRAPHY
252
able to master it as a whole. The science has grown tosuch vast proportions that probably no living mathe
matician can claim to have achieved this.
Passing to the serious treatises on the subject to be read
after this preliminary course, the following may be men
tioned: Cremona s Pure Geometry (English Translation,
Clarendon Press, Oxford), Hobson s Treatise on Trigono
metry, Chrystal s Treatise on Algebra (2 volumes), Salmon s
Conic Sections, Lamb s Differential Calculus, and some
book on Differential Equations. The student will probably
not desire to direct equal attention to all these subjects, but
will study one or more of them, according as his interest
He will then be prepared to select more ad
dictates.
vanced works for himself, and to plunge into the higher
he
on the theory
of Fractions or the Complex Variable; if he prefers to
specialize in Geometry, he must now proceed to the
standard treatises on the Analytical Geometry,! of three
parts of the subject.
should
If his interest lies in analysis,
now master an elementary
treatise
dimensions. But at this stage of his career hi learning
he will not require the advice of this note.
I have deliberately refrained from mentioning any
elementary works. They are very numerous, and of
various merits, but none of such outstanding superiority
as to require special mention by name to the exclusion of
all
the others.
INDEX
Abel, 156
Abscissa, 95
Cantor, Georg, 79
180 etseqq.
Circular Cylinder, 143
Clerk Maxwell, 34, 35
Columbus, 122
Circle, 120, 130,
Abstract Nature of Geo
metry, 242 et seqq.
Abstractness (defined), 9, 13
Adams, 220
Addition Theorem, 212
Ahmes, 71
Alexander the Great, 128,
129
Algebra, Fundamental Laws
of, 60
Ampere, 34
Analytical Conic Sections,
240
Apollonius of Perga, 131,
134
Approximation, 197 et seqq.
Arabic Notation, 58 et seqq.
Archimedes, 37 et seqq.
Argument of a Function,
146
Aristotle, 30, 43, 128
Astronomy, 137, 173, 174
Axes, 125
Axioms of Quantity, 246
et seqq.
Compact Series, 76
Complex Quantities, 109
Conic Sections, 128 et seqq.
Constants, 69, 117
Continuous Functions, 150
et seqq.; 162 (defined)
Convergent, 203 et seqq.
Coordinate Gemeotry, 112
et seqq.
Coordinates, 95
Copernicus, 45, 137
Cosine, 182
et seqq.
Coulomb, 33
Cross Ratio, 140
Darwin, 138, 220
Derived Function, 234
Descartes,
122, 218
Differential
95,
113,
Calculus,
116,
217
et seqq.
Differential Coefficient,
Directrix, 135
Bacon, 156
W. W. R., 58
Beaconsfield, Lord, 40
Berkeley, Bishop, 226
Discontinuous
150 et seqq.
Distance, 30
Divergent, 203
Ball,
Bhaskara, 58
253
234
Functions,
ei seqq.
INDEX
254
Dynamical
Explanation,
47 et seqq.
Dynamics, 30, 43 et seqq.
13, 14,
Electric Current, 33
Electricity, 32 et seqq.
31
Electromagnetism,
et
45,
Imaginary Quantities, 109
Incommensurable Ratios,
211
Infinitely Small Quantities,
72
Exponential
Series,
seqq
Form, Algebraic, 66
226
et seqq.
Kepler, 45, 46, 137, 138
Kepler
et seqq. t
117
Fourier s Theorem, 191
82,
Fractions, 71 et seqq.
Franklin, 32, 122
Function, 145 et seqq.
42
et seqq.,
122
Galvani, 33
Generality in Mathematics,
82
Geometrical
et seqq.
Integral Calculus, 222
Interval, 158 et seqq.
Faraday, 34
Fermat, 218
Fluxions, 219
Focus, 120, 135
Force, 30
Galileo, 30,
et
et
130
120,
Euclid, 114
et
Imaginary Numbers, 87
seqq.
seqq.
Ellipse,
Herz, 35
Hiero, 38
Hipparchus, 173
Hyperbola, 131 et seqq.
s
Laws, 138
Laputa, 10
Laws of Motion, 167 et seqq.
248
Leibniz, 16, 218 et seqq.
Leonardo da Vinci, 42
Leverrier, 220
Light, 35
Limit of a Function, 227
et seqq.
Limit
of
a
Series,
199
et seqq.
206
Series,
et seqq.
Geometry, 36, 236 et
Gilbert, Dr., 32
Graphs, 148 et seqq.
Limits, 77
Locus, 121
et seqq.,
141
seqq.
Gravitation, 29, 139
Halley, 139
Harmonic Analysis, 192
Harriot, Thomas, 66
Macaulay, 156
Malthus, 138
Marcellus, 37
Mass, 30
Mechanics, 46
Menaechmus, 128, 129
Motion, First Law, of 43
INDEX
Neighbourhood, 159 et seqq.
Newton, 10, 16, 30, 34, 37,
38, 43, 46, 139, 218 et seqq.
Non-Uniform Convergence,
208
Relations between
ables, 18 et seqq.
Resonance, 170, 171
Rosebery, Lord, 194
Vari
et seqq.
Normal
Error,
Curve
of,
214
Oersted, 34
Order, 194 et seqq.
Order, Type of, 75
Parabola, 131 et seqq.
Parallelogram Law, 51
seqq., 99, 126
Parameters, 69, 117
Pencils, 140
Period, 170, 189 et seqq.
et
et
seqq.,
William, 194
Pizarro, 122
Plutarch, 37
Positive and Negative
Num
et seqq.
Projective Geometry, 139
Ptolemy, 137, 173
Pythagoras, 13
from),
et
seqq.,
237
159
229
Steps, 79 et
Stifel, 85
tion,
et seqq.,
seqq.,
et seqq.
seqq.,
201
et
96
Stokes, Sir George, 210
Sum to Infinity, 201
Surveys, 176
Swift, 10
et
et seqq.
Tangents, 221, 222
Theorem,
156,
Taylor s
157
Time, 166 et seqq., 247
et seqq.
et seqq.
of,
et seqq.
Triangle, 176 et seqq., 237
Triangulation, 177
Trigonometry, 173
et seqq.
Uniform Convergence, 208
et seqq.
Real Numbers, 73
Rectangle, 57
177
Transportation, Vector
Rate of Increase of Func
tions, 220 et seqq.
Ratio, 72
(quotation
et
217
54
Quantity, 245
194
seqq.,
Sine, 182 et seqq.
Specific Gravity, 41
Squaring the Circle, 187
Standard of Approxima
Pappus, 135, 136
bers, 83
et
Similarity,
et seqq.
Origin, 95, 125
164
Map, 178
210
74
Shelley
et seqq.,
Ordered Couples, 93
Ordinate, 95
Periodicity,
188, 216
Scale of a
Seidel,
Series,
196
Pitt,
255
et seqq.
et seqq.
Unknown, The,
17,
23
256
INDEX
Value of a Function, 146
Variable, The, 18, 24, 49,
82, 234, 239
Variable Function, 147
Vectors, 51 et seqq., 85, 96
Vertex, 134
Volta, 33
Wallace, 220
Weierstrass, 156, 226, 228
Zero, 63
et seqq.,
103
THE
HOME UNIVERSITY
MODERN
LIBRARY OF
KNOWLEDGE
EDITED BY
PROFESSOR SIR J. ARTHUR THOMSON
PROFESSOR GILBERT MURRAY
THE
RT.
HON.
PROFESSOR W.
/
H. A.
T.
L.
FISHER
BREWSTER
titles listed in the Home University Library
1pHE
* are not
written for
are
reprints: they
well-known
especially
by recognized authorities in
their respective fields.
Some of the most distin
guished names in America and England will be
found among the authors of the following books.
The series embraces virtually every prominent edu
this
series
cational and cultural subject and is kept thor
oughly up to date by additions and revisions.
ORDER BY NUMBER
$1.25
HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY
ONE PARK AVENUE
-
NEW YORK
EACH
THE
HOME UNIVERSITY
LIBRARY OF
MODERN
KNOWLEDGE
AMERICAN HISTORY
[Order
Number]
WAR
25.
THE
39.
RECONSTRUCTION AND UNION
CIVIL
(1854-1865). By Frederick L.
Paxson, Professor of American History, University of
Wisconsin.
By
Paul Leland Haworth.
States in our
47.
own
A
(1865-1912).
History of the United
times.
THE COLONIAL PERIOD
Charles
McLean Andrews,
By
(1607-1766).
Professor of American His
tory, Yale.
67.
FROM JEFFERSON TO LINCOLN
(1815-1860).
Professor of History, Brown
author makes the history of this period
By William MacDonald,
University.
The
circulate about constitutional ideas
82.
and slavery sentiment.
THE WARS BETWEEN ENGLAND AND AMER
ICA (1763-1815). By Theodore C. Smith, Professor
of American History, Williams College.
history of the
period, with especial emphasis on The Revolution and The
War of 1812.
A
3.
GENERAL HISTORY AND GEOGRAPHY
THE FRENCH REVOLUTION. By Hilaire Belloc,
4.
A SHORT HISTORY OF WAR AND PEACE.
7.
MODERN GEOGRAPHY.
M.A.
By
G. H. Perris, author of
"Russia
By
in Revolution," etc.
Dr. Marion
I.
New-
Shows the relation of physical
bigin, F.R.G.S., D.Sc.
features to living things and to some of the chief institu
tions of civilization.
8.
POLAR EXPLORATION. By
leader of the "Scotia" expedition.
of the expedition.
13.
18.
Dr. W. S. Bruce,
Emphasizes the results
MEDIEVAL
EUROPE. By H. W. C. Davis, Late
Regius Professor of Modern History, Oxford University,
author of "Charlemagne," etc.
THE OPENING UP OF AFRICA.
By
Sir
H. H.
Johnston, G.C.M.G.
19.
THE CIVILIZATION OF CHINA.
By H.
A.
Giles, LL.D., Professor of Chinese, Cambridge.
20.
HISTORY OF OUR TIME
By
(1885-1911).
C. P.
Gooch, D.Litt., F.B.A.
22.
THE PAPACY AND MODERN TIMES. By
William Barry, D.D., author of
The story of the rise and
Monarchy," etc.
Rt. Rev.
"The
fall
The
Papal
of the
Temporal Power.
26.
THE DAWN OF HISTORY.
By J. L. Myres,
Wykeham Professor of Ancient History, Oxford.
ROME. By W. Warde Fowler, author of "Social Life
F.S.A.,
30.
at
33.
Rome,"
etc.
THE HISTORY OF ENGLAND.
lard,
F.B.A.,
D.Litt.,
Professor of
By
A. F. Pol
English
History,
University of London.
34.
36.
CANADA. By A. G. Bradley.
PEOPLES AND PROBLEMS OF INDIA. By
T.
W.
Holderness, G.C.B.
Sir
best small treatise
dealing with the range of subjects fairly indicated by the
title."
The Dial.
51.
MASTER MARINERS. By
"The
John R. Spears, author
History of Our Navy," etc. A history of seacraft adventure from the earliest times.
of
"The
57.
NAPOLEON. By The
Rt.
72.
76.
GERMANY OF TO-DAY. By Charles Tower.
THE OCEAN. A GENERAL ACCOUNT OF THE
SCIENCE OF THE SEA. By Sir John Murray,
K.C.B.,
Naturalist
joint author of
78.
"The
H. M. S. "Challenger," 1872-1876,
Depths of the Ocean," etc.
LATIN AMERICA. By
fessor of History, Columbia.
artistic
86.
William R. Shepherd, Pro
With maps. The historical,
and commercial development of the Central South
American
84.
Hon. H. A. L. Fisher,
Author of "The Re
of New College, Oxford.
publican Tradition in Europe."
Warden
republics.
THE GROWTH OF EUROPE.
By Granville A. J.
Cole, Professor of Geology, Royal College of Science,
A study of the geology and physical geography
Ireland.
in connection with the political geography.
EXPLORATION OF THE ALPS.
By Arnold
Limn, M.A.
92.
94.
THE ANCIENT
EAST. By D. G. Hogarth, M.A.,
F.B.A., F.S.A. Connects with Prof. Myres s "Dawn of
(No. 26) at about 1000 B.C. and reviews the
History"
history of Assyria, Babylon, Cilicia, Persia and Macedonia.
THE NAVY AND SEA POWER.
nay, author of
By David Han-
History of the Royal Navy," etc.
brief history of the navies, sea power, and ship growth
of all nations, including the rise and decline of America on
the sea, and explaining the present British supremacy.
"Short
A
95.
BELGIUM. By
R. C. K. Ensor, sometime Scholar of
The geographical, linguistic,
College.
artistic and literary associations.
Balliol
100.
historical,
POLAND. By
J. Alison Phillips, Lecky Professor of
The history of
History, University of Dublin.
Poland with special emphasis upon the Polish question of
the present day.
Modern
102.
SERBIA. By L. F. Waring, with preface by J. M.
Jovanovitch, Serbian Minister to Great Britain. The
main outlines of Serbian history, with special emphasis on
the immediate causes of the war and the questions in the
after-the-war settlement.
104.
OUR
FORERUNNERS. By M. C. Burkitt, M.A.,
F.S.A. A comprehensive study of the beginnings of man
kind and the culture of the prehistoric era.
IDS-
COMMERCIAL GEOGRAPHY. By
Newbigin, F.R.G.S., D.Sc.
Dr. Marion I.
Fundamental conceptions of
commodities, transport and market.
108.
WALES. By W. Watkin
S.,
etc.
no.
Davies, M.A., F.R. Hist.
Barrister-at-Law, author of
EGYPT.
By
Sir
E.
"How
Wallis
A.
to
Read
History,"
Budge, Litt.D.,
F.S.A.
114.
THE BYZANTINE EMPIRE.
Baynes, M.A.
By Norman H.
The
period from the recognition of Chris
tianity by the state to the date when the Latin sovereigns
supplanted the Byzantines.
120.
ENGLAND UNDER THE TUDORS AND THE
STUARTS. By Keith Feiling,
Transition from 1485 to 1688.
121.
The
period of
HISTORY OF ENGLAND (1688-1815). By E. M.
WRONG, M.A. A continuation and development of Mr.
Felling s
127.
M.A.
"England
Under
the
Tudors and the
THE CIVILIZATION OF JAPAN.
Stuarts."
By
J.
Ingram
Bryan, M.A., M.Litt., Ph.L., Extension Lecturer for the
University of Cambridge in Japanese History and Civili
A brief sketch of the origins and developments of
zation.
Japanese civilization.
128.
HISTORY OF ENGLAND
(1815-1918). By Dr. J.
Gives a vivid impression of the chief
ways in which English life was transformed in the cen
tury between Waterloo and the Armistice and of the
forces which caused the transformation.
R.
129.
137.
M.
Butler.
THE BRITISH EMPIRE.
By Basil Williams,
Professor of History at Edinburgh University. Sketches
the growth of the British Empire from the times of the
early adventurers to the present day.
POLITICAL CONSEQUENCES OF THE GREAT
WAR. By Ramsay Muir, formerly Professor of Mod
ern History in the University of Manchester.
141.
2.
FASCISM.
By Major J. S. Barnes, F.R.G.S., late
Secretary-General of the International Center of Fascist
Studies, Lausanne.
LITERATURE AND ART
SHAKESPEARE. By John Masefield,
D.Litt. "One
of the very few indispensable adjuncts to a Shakespearian
Library."
Boston Transcript.
27.
MODERN ENGLISH LITERATURE.
From Wyatt and Surrey
Mair.
"One
of the best of this great
to
series."
By G. H.
Synge and Yeats.
Chicago Evening
Post.
31.
LANDMARKS
IN
FRENCH LITERATURE. By
Lytton Strachey, Scholar of Trinity
"It
to imagine
is difficult
how
College, Cambridge.
a better account of French
Literature could be given in 250
London Times.
pages."
ARCHITECTURE. By
Prof. W. R. Lethaby. An
38.
introduction to the history and theory of the art of
building.
40.
THE ENGLISH LANGUAGE. By L.
concise history of
45.
its
P. Smith.
A
origin and development.
MEDIEVAL ENGLISH LITERATURE. By W. P.
Ker, Professor of English Literature, University College,
London. "One of the soundest scholars. His style is ef
The Athenaeum.
fective, simple, yet never dry."
48.
GREAT WRITERS OF AMERICA.
Trent and John Erskine, Columbia
58.
P.
THE NEWSPAPER.
By G. Binney Dibblee. The
account from the inside of newspaper organiza
first full
tion as
59.
By W.
University.
DR.
it
exists today.
JOHNSON AND HIS CIRCLE.
By John
Bailey. Johnson s life, character, works and friendships
are surveyed
and there is a notable vindication of the
;
"Genius
61.
of
Boswell."
THE VICTORIAN AGE
IN LITERATURE.
By
G. K. Chesterton.
62.
PAINTERS AND PAINTING. By
Wedmore.
64.
With
Sir Frederick
16 half-tone illustrations.
THE LITERATURE OF GERMANY.
By
Profes
sor J. G. Robertson, M.A., B.Sc.
66.
WRITING ENGLISH PROSE.
By William T.
BrewBter, Professor of English, Columbia University.
"Should be put into the hands of every man who is be
ginning to write and of every teacher of English who has
brains enough to understand sense." New York Sun.
70.
ANCIENT ART AND RITUAL. By
rison, LL.D., D.Litt.
books of 1913." New
73.
"One
Jane E. Har
of the 100 most important
York Times Review.
EURIPIDES AND HIS AGE. By
Regius Professor of Greek, Oxford.
Gilbert Murray,
75-
SHELLEY, GODWIN AND THEIR CIRCLE. By
The
H. N. Brailsford.
tion
81.
influence of the
French Revolu
on England.
CHAUCER AND HIS TIMES.
By Grace
E.
Oxford; Late
Lecturer Lady Margaret Hall,
Hadow,
Reader, Bryn Mawr.
83.
WILLIAM MORRIS: HIS WORK AND INFLU
ENCE.
A. Glutton Brock, author of "Shelley:
the Poet." William Morris believed that
By
The Man and
the artist should toil for love of his work rather than the
gain of his employer, and so he turned from making
works of art to remaking society."
87.
THE RENAISSANCE.
"Catherine
de
Medici,"
By Edith Sichel, author of
and Women of the French
"Men
Renaissance."
89.
ELIZABETHAN LITERATURE.
Hon.
M. Robertson, M.P.,
J.
"Montaigne
Rt.
and
"Modern Humanists."
Shakespeare,"
93.
By The
author of
AN OUTLINE OF RUSSIAN LITERATURE. By
The Hon. Maurice Baring,
etc.
People,"
"The
Russian
Tolstoi, Tourgeniefr, Dostoieffsky,
Pushkin
author of
(the father of Russian Literature), Saltykov (the satir
Leskov, and many other authors.
ist),
97.
101.
MILTON. By John Bailey.
DANTE. By Jefferson B. Fletcher,
An
interpretation of
versity.
his writings.
106.
Dante and
Columbia Uni
from
his teaching
PATRIOTISM IN LITERATURE.
By
John
Drinkwater.
109.
MUSIC.
By
Sir
W. H. Hadow,
F.R.C.M., Vice-Chancellor of
117.
DRAMA. By
D.Mus., F.R.S.L.,
Sheffield University.
Ashley Dukes.
The nature and varie
make up the theatre,
of drama and the factors that
from dramatist to audience.
ties
132.
THE LITERATURE OF JAPAN.
By
J.
Ingram
Bryan, M.A., M.Litt., Ph.D., Extension Lecturer for the
University of Cambridge in Japanese History and Civili
zation.
134.
AN ANTHOLOGY OF ENGLISH POETRY:
135.
AN ANTHOLOGY OF ENGLISH POETRY:
Wyatt
to Dryden.
den to Blake.
By Kathleen
Campbell.
By Kathleen Campbell.
Dry-
9,
NATURAL SCIENCE
THE EVOLUTION OF PLANTS. By
Dr. D. H.
Scott, LL.D., F.R.S., President of the Linnean Society
of London. The story of the development of flowering
plants, from the earliest zoological times, unlocked from
technical language.
12.
THE ANIMAL WORLD. By
Prof. F.
W. Gamble,
F.R.S.
14.
15.
EVOLUTION. By Prof. Sir J. Arthur Thomson
and Prof. Patrick Geddes. Explains to the layman
what the title means to the scientific world.
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICS. By Pro
fessor A. N. Whitehead, D.Sc., F.R.S., author of
versal
17.
"Uni
Algebra."
CRIME AND INSANITY. By
F.R.C.P., F.R.C.S., author of
Dr. C. A. Mercier,
and Criminals,"
"Crime
etc.
21.
AN INTRODUCTION TO SCIENCE. By
Prof.
Sir J. Arthur Thomson, LL.D., Science Editor of the
Home University Library. For those unacquainted with
the scientific volumes in the series this should prove an
excellent introduction.
23.
ASTRONOMY.
By A. R. Hinks, Chief Assistant at
the Cambridge Observatory. "Decidedly original in sub
stance, and the most readable and informative little book
on modern astronomy we have seen for a long time."
Nature.
24.
37.
41.
PSYCHICAL RESEARCH.
By Sir W. F. Barrett,
F.R.S., formerly President of the Society for Psychical
Research.
ANTHROPOLOGY.
By R. R. Marett, D.Sc.,
F.R.A.I., Reader in Social Anthropology, Oxford. Seeks
to plot out and sum up the general series of changes,
bodily and mental, undergone by man in the course of his
So enthusiastic, so clear and witty, and
tory. "Excellent.
so well adapted to the general reader." American Library
Association Booklist.
PSYCHOLOGY, THE STUDY OF BEHAVIOUR.
Professor William McDougall, F.R.S., Reader in
Mental Philosophy, Oxford University. A well-digested
By
summary of
literary
42.
the essentials of the science put in excellent
form by a leading authority.
THE PRINCIPLES OF PHYSIOLOGY.
By Prof.
A compact statement by the
G. McKendrick.
Emeritus Professor at Glasgow, for uninstructed readers.
J.
43.
MATTER AND
ENERGY. By F. Soddy, F.R.S.,
Professor of Inorganic and Physical Chemistry in the
Can hardly be sur
University of Oxford. "Brilliant
Sure to attract attention." New York Sun.
passed.
53.
ELECTRICITY. By Gisbert Kapp, Late Professor
of Electrical Engineering, University of Birmingham.
54.
THE MAKING OF THE EARTH.
By
J.
W.
Gregory, F.R.S., Professor of Geology, Glasgow Uni
versity. 38 maps and figures. Describes the origin of the
earth, the formation and changes of its surface and struc
ture,
and
56.
geological history, the first appearance of
influence upon the globe.
its
its
life,
MAN: A HISTORY OF THE HUMAN BODY.
Sir A. Keith, F.R.S., Hunterian Professor, Royal
College of Surgeons of England. Shows how the human
body developed.
By
63.
THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF LIFE. By Pro
fessor Benjamin Moore.
68.
DISEASE AND ITS CAUSES. By W. T. Council
man, M.D., LL.D., Professor of Pathology, Harvard
University.
71.
74.
85.
PLANT
LIFE. By Sir J. B. Farmer, D.Sc., F.R.S.,
Professor of Botany in the Imperial College of Science,
London. This very fully illustrated volume contains an
account of the salient features of plant form and function.
NERVES. By David Fraser Harris, M.D., Professor
of Physiology, Dalhousie University, Halifax. Explains
in nontechnical language the place and powers of the
nervous system.
SEX. By
Geddes,
90.
Profs. Sir J.
joint authors of
CHEMISTRY.
in.
"The
Evolution of
Sex."
By Raphael
Meldola, F.R.S., Late
Finsbury Technical College.
Revised by Alexander Findlay, D.Sc., F.I.C., Profes
Pre
sor of Chemistry in the University of Aberdeen.
sents the way in which the science has developed and the
stage it has reached.
Professor
107.
Arthur Thomson and Patrick
of
Chemistry,
AN INTRODUCTION TO THE STUDY OF
HEREDITY. By E. W. MacBride, D.Sc., Professor
of Zoology in the Imperial College of Science and Tech
nology, London.
BIOLOGY. By
Patrick Geddes.
Profs. Sir J. Arthur
Thomson and
BACTERIOLOGY.
ii2.
By
Prof. Car! H. Browning,
F.R.S.
MICROSCOPY. By
115.
Robert M.
Neill, Aberdeen
Uni
Microscopic technique subordinated to results of
investigation and their value to man.
versity.
EUGENICS.
116.
By
Professor A. M. Carr-Saunders.
Biological problems, together with the facts and theories
of heredity.
AND
GAS
GASES. By R. M. Caven, D.Sc., F.I.C.,
Professor of Inorganic and Analytical Chemistry in the
The chemical and
Royal Technical College, Glasgow.
physical nature of gases, both in their scientific and his
119.
torical aspects.
BIRDS, AN INTRODUCTION TO ORNITHOL
OGY. By A. L. Thompson, O.B.E., D.Sc. A general
122.
account of the characteristics, mainly of habit and be
havior of birds.
SUNSHINE AND HEALTH. By
124.
Macfie, M.B.C.M.,
LL.D. Light and
Ronald Campbell
its
relation to
man
treated scientifically.
INSECTS.
125.
By Frank
Balfour-Browne, F.R.S.E.,
Professor of Entomology in the
Science and Technology, London.
Imperial
College
of
TREES.
By Dr. MacGregor Skene, D.Sc., F.L.S.
Senior Lecturer on Botany, Bristol University. A concise
study of the classification, history, structure, architecture,
growth, enemies, care and protection of trees. Forestry
and economics are also discussed.
126.
138.
THE LIFE OF THE
CELL.
By David
Lands-
B.Sc., Ph.D., Lecturer in Biochem
istry, McGill University.
borough Thomson,
142.
35.
VOLCANOES. By G. W. Tyrrell, A.R., C.Sc.,
Ph.D., F.G.S., F.R.S.E., Lecturer in Geology in the
University of Glasgow.
PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION
THE PROBLEMS OF PHILOSOPHY.
By The
Hon. Bertrand Russell, F.R.S., Lecturer and Late Fel
low, Trinity College, Cambridge.
44.
BUDDHISM.
By Mrs. Rhys
Davids, Lecturer on
Indian Philosophy, Manchester.
46.
ENGLISH SECTS: A HISTORY OF NONCON
FORMITY. By The Rev. W. B. Selbie, Principal of
Mansfield College, Oxford.
50.
52.
55.
THE MAKING OF THE NEW TESTAMENT.
By B. W. Bacon, D.D., LL.D., Professor of New Tes
tament Criticism, Yale. An authoritative summary of the
results of modern critical research with regard to the
origins of the New Testament.
ETHICS. By Professor G. E. Moore, D.Litt., Lec
turer in Moral Science, Cambridge.
Discusses what is
right and what is wrong, and the whys and wherefores.
MISSIONS:
MENT. By
THEIR RISE AND DEVELOP
Mrs. Mandell Creighton, author of
The author
sions have done more to civilize
human agency.
tory of
60.
65.
England."
"His
seeks to prove that mis
the world than any other
COMPARATIVE
RELIGION. By Prof. J. Estlin
Carpenter, LL.D. "One of the few authorities on this
subject compares all the religions to see what they have to
offer on the great themes of religion."
Christian Work
and Evangelist.
THE LITERATURE OF THE OLD TESTA
MENT.
By George F. Moore, Professor of the His
tory of Religion, Harvard University.
popular work
of the highest order. Will be profitable to anybody who
cares enough about Bible study to read a serious book on
the subject." American Journal of Theology.
"A
69.
A HISTORY OF FREEDOM OF THOUGHT. By
John B. Bury, M.A., LL.D., Late Regius Professor of
Modern History in Cambridge University. Summarizes
the history of the long struggle between authority and
reason and of the emergence of the principle that coercion
of opinion is a mistake.
88.
RELIGIOUS DEVELOPMENT BETWEEN OLD
AND NEW TESTAMENTS. By The Ven. R. H.
Charles, D.D., F.B.A., Canon of Westminster. Shows
religious and ethical thought between 180 B.C. and
100 A.D. grew naturally into that of the New Testament.
how
96.
A HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. By
Clement
130.
C. J.
Professor
Webb, F.B.A.
JESUS OF NAZARETH. By The
Rt. Rev. Charles
Gore, D.D., formerly Bishop of Oxford.
SOCIAL SCIENCE
i.
PARLIAMENT.
TION,
ITS HISTORY,
AND PRACTICE. By
CONSTITU
Sir Courtenay P.
Ilbert, G.C.B., K.C.S.I., late Clerk of the House of
Commons.
THE STOCK EXCHANGE.
By F. W. Hirst, for
merly Editor of the London Economist. Reveals to the
nonfinancial mind the facts about investment, speculation,
and the other terms which the title suggests.
6. IRISH NATIONALITY.
By Mrs. J. R. Green,
D.Litt. A brilliant account of the genius and mission of
the Irish people. "An entrancing work, and I would ad
vise everyone with a drop of Irish blood in his veins or a
vein of Irish sympathy in his heart to read
New
York Times Review. (Revised Edition, 1929.)
SOCIALIST
10.
By The Rt.
5.
it."
THE
Hon.
11.
MOVEMENT.
J.
Ramsay Macdonald, M.P.
THE SCIENCE OF WEALTH. By
of Poverty/
A
J.
A. Hobson,
study of the struc
ture and working of the modern business world.
16. LIBERALISM.
By Prof. L. T. Hobhouse, LL.D.,
author of "Democracy and Reaction."
masterly phil
osophical and historical review of the subject.
author of
"Problems
A
23.
THE EVOLUTION OF INDUSTRY.
MacGregor, Drummond Professor
D. H.
Economy,
By
in Political
University of Oxford. An outline of the recent changes
that have given us the present conditions of the working
classes and the principles involved.
29.
ELEMENTS OF ENGLISH LAW. By W.
M.
Geldart, B.C.L., Vinerian Professor of English Law,
Oxford. Revised by Sir William Holdsworth, K.C.,
D.C.L., LL.D., Vinerian Professor of English Law, Uni
versity of Oxford. A simple statement of the basic prin
ciples of the English legal system on which that of the
United States is based.
32.
49.
THE SCHOOL: AN INTRODUCTION TO THE
STUDY OF
EDUCATION. By J. J. Findlay, M.A.,
formerly Professor of Education, Manchester. Presents
the history, the psychological basis, and the theory of the
school with a rare power of summary and suggestion.
ELEMENTS OF POLITICAL ECONOMY. By
Sir S. J.
Chapman,
late
Professor of Political
Economy
and Dean of Faculty of Commerce and Administration,
University of Manchester.
77.
CO-PARTNERSHIP AND PROFIT-SHARING.
By Aneurin
Chairman, Executive Com
Explains
the various types of co-partnership and profit-sharing, and
the
details
of
in
now
force
in
gives
arrangements
many of
Williams,
late
mittee, International Co-operative Alliance, etc.
the great industries.
79.
UNEMPLOYMENT. By
A. C. Pigou, M.A., Pro
fessor of Political Economy at Cambridge. The meaning,
measurement, distribution and effects of unemployment,
its relation to wages, trade fluctuations and disputes, and
some proposals of remedy or
80.
COMMON SENSE
relief.
IN LAW.
By Prof. Sir Paul
Vinogradoff, D.C.L., LL.D. Social and Legal RulesLegal Rights and Duties Facts and Acts in Law Legis
lationCustomJudicial Precedents Equity The Law
of Nature.
91.
THE NEGRO. By W. E.
of
"Souls
man
98.
of Black
in Africa,
Folks,"
Burghardt DuBois, author
etc.
A
history of the black
America and elsewhere.
POLITICAL THOUGHT: FROM
HERBERT
SPENCER TO THE PRESENT DAY. By
Pro
fessor Ernest Barker, D.Litt., LL.D.
99.
POLITICAL THOUGHT: THE UTILITARIANS,
FROM BENTHAM TO
J. S.
William L. Davidson, LL.D.
103.
MILL. By
Professor
ENGLISH POLITICAL THOUGHT. From
Locke
to Bentham. By Harold J. Laski, Professor of Politi
cal Science in the London School of Economics.
113.
118.
ADVERTISING. By Sir Charles Higharn.
BANKING. By Dr. Walter Leaf, late President,
In
Bankers; President, International Chamber
Commerce. The elaborate machinery of the financing
stitute of
o:
o:
industry.
123.
COMMUNISM. By
Harold J. Laski, Professor o
Political Science at the University of London. The autho:
tries to state the communist "theses" in such a way tha
even its advocates will recognize that an opponent cai
summarize them
131.
fairly.
INDUSTRIAL PSYCHOLOGY.
Edited by Dr
Na
Charles
S. Myers, G.B.E., F.R.S., Director of the
tional Institute of Industrial Psychology in England. Th
only comprehensive study of the human factor in industry
133.
THE
GROWTH
THOUGHT. By
OF
INTERNATIONAI
F. Melian Stawell.
139-
LIQUOR CONTROL.
An
140.
By George E. G. Catlin.
impartial and comprehensive study of the subject.
RACES OF AFRICA. By
F.R.S.
C. G. Seligman, F.R.C.P.
QA
W53
1911
Whitehead, Alfred North
An introduction to
mathematics.
PLEASE
CARDS OR
DO NOT REMOVE
SLIPS
UNIVERSITY
FROM
THIS
OF TORONTO
POCKET
LIBRARY