religions
Article
New Technologies—Old Anthropologies?
Levi Checketts
Graduate Theological Union, 2918 Regent St #D, Berkeley, CA 94705, USA;
[email protected]
Academic Editor: Noreen Herzfeld
Received: 1 March 2017; Accepted: 29 March 2017; Published: 31 March 2017
Abstract: Eighty years ago, Nicholas Berdyaev cautioned that new technological problems needed
to be addressed with a new philosophical anthropology. Today, the transhumanist goal of mind
uploading is perceived by many theologians and philosophers to be dangerous due to its violation
of the human person. I contrast transhumanist “patternist” views of the person with Brent Waters’s
Augustinian view of the technological pilgrim, Celia Deane-Drummond’s evolutionary Thomistic view
of humanity, and Francis Fukuyama’s insistence on the inviolability of “Factor X”. These latter three
thinkers all disagree with the patternist position, but their views are also discordant with each other.
This disagreement constitutes a challenge for people of faith confronting transhumanism—which
view is to be taken right? I contend that Science, Technology and Society (STS) studies can enrich our
understanding of the debates by highlighting the transmutation of philosophical view into scientific
theory and the intermingled nature of our forms of knowledge. Furthermore, I contend that STS helps
Christians understand the evolution of their own anthropologies and suggests some prospects for
future theological anthropology.
Keywords: consciousness uploading; Science, Technology and Society studies (STS); theological
anthropology; philosophical anthropology; transhumanism
The debate between transhumanists and their opponents, argues Gregory Stock, is “about
philosophy and religion. It is about what it means to be human, about our vision of the human
future” ([1], p. 303). A brief survey of a few of the articles and books written on the topic suggests he
is right. Transhumanists contend that human beings should use the tools of science and technology to
enhance themselves beyond what is biologically natural [2]. Their intellectual opponents, sometimes
called “bioconservatives”, argue that doing so violates human dignity [3], endangers human rights [4],
or elevates humanity above their rightful station [5]. Transhumanists in turn retort that the principle of
dignity need not exclude the posthuman (i.e. what “humans” are once they are no longer biologically
Homo sapiens) [6], that rights can be better ensured by enhanced persons [7] and that humanity has
no reason to be bounded [2]. As one surveys the literature, it is clear that these agonists are trying
to engage with each other, but one gets the feeling they are still speaking past each other. Surely
whatever Leon Kass meant by human dignity in relation to finitude excludes Nick Bostrom’s more
“expanded” concept. C. A. J. Coady’s concern about hubris imposes limits unacceptable to Max More’s
unbounded vision of humanity. The question of enhancement, one must conclude, reduces to simple
understandings of what it means to be a person.
I take up but one example of the highly-contested transhumanist goals in this paper, namely the
proposal of mind uploading. This is a technological project favored by such technological luminaries
as Ray Kurzweil, Hans Moravec, the late Marvin Minsky and Peter Thiel. Currently, Dmitri Itskov
is one of a few persons actively pursuing this goal with his 2045 Initiative, a movement to bring
together various scientific and technological achievements, including robotics, neuroscience and
artificial intelligence, into the singular task of removing persons’ consciousnesses from their biological
bodies and transferring them to superior computer substrates [8]. Literature supporting this project is
Religions 2017, 8, 52; doi:10.3390/rel8040052
www.mdpi.com/journal/religions
Religions 2017, 8, 52
2 of 9
diverse, including Moravec’s Mind Children, Kurzweil’s, The Age of Spiritual Machines, Steve Fuller’s
Humanity 2.0, and essays by computer programmers, AI researchers and entrepreneurs. The aim of
such a project is to liberate humanity from its biological limitations, especially mental and physical
weaknesses and the inevitability of death. The uploaded mind would be free from the slowness of
neurons, boundaries of memory capacity and biological vulnerabilities to the passage of time.
Accomplishing this task, according to pro-uploaders, requires progress in three technological
and scientific areas. First, computer hardware must be up to the task. Running a computer mind
requires huge amounts of data storage and powerful and fast processors. However, we are already
approaching the low-end estimates of some of the older predictions for uploading in our standards
for home computing technology ([9], p. 60). This means the necessary hardware for the task will be
available soon and will be inexpensive. Second, computer software must be sophisticated enough
to do all that the brain does reliably. According to some software experts, we are far from reaching
this goal because software programming suffers from an “inverse Moore’s Law” whereby progress
slows over time rather than accelerates [10]. However, the intricacies and complexity of the necessary
programming seems just to be a matter of time, not of ability. Finally, we must have an improved
understanding of the brain and how it functions. “What” the mind is and “how” it works is important
information for moving it successfully into a new home. Neuroscience and “brain mapping” is being
pursued to this end, but understanding the brain remains the most elusive project so far. To get around
this last obstacle, some have proposed “whole brain emulating” whereby a sufficient “map” of the
brain created by deep tissue scanning is simply recreated within a computer environment and allowed
to function as it would in a physical medium [11]. Although several real obstacles remain, many
proponents of this project expect to accomplish all of these ends, and thus feasibly uploading itself, as
early as 2045 (hence the 2045 Initiative).
Aside from very real concerns about environmental impact, distribution of technology and
existential threats, most opponents of uploading are concerned that doing so crosses important moral
boundaries regarding the status of the human person. Some, like Nicholas Agar, believe it to be
ontologically impossible and thus “a novel way to commit suicide” ([12], p. 27). Others fear it is
possible but will result in a disembodied monstrosity [13]. Others still worry about the harm that can
be done from being removed from one’s material origins [14]. Nonetheless, those in favor of uploading
hold a “patternist” theory of mind, which holds that human identity is reducible to a brain pattern ([9],
pp. 116–22). The successful copy of this brain pattern into another “substrate” constitutes having one’s
identity transferred to another substrate. A mind is therefore analogous to a poem; written on bark,
vellum, stone or paper, the text contains the same meaning and (theoretically) significance.
I contend that in these discussions, we see the need for careful anthropological consideration. This
is not a novel thought for technological ethics; eighty years ago, Nicholas Berdyaev began considering
the challenges we face in our “technological” world and the threat they pose to humanity. His
conclusion was that the answer to the technological challenge lies “in the Christian view of [humanity]
as such, for we can no longer be satisfied by the patristic, scholastic, or humanistic anthropologies . . .
Philosophical anthropology becomes a central problem: [human] and machine, [human] and organism,
[human] and cosmos, are what is has to deal with” ([15], p. 213).
In this essay, I examine briefly three anthropological views contending against transhumanism that
are reminiscent of Berdyaev’s concern (NB: not all of these authors write specifically against patternism,
but their anthropological views clearly allow no room for mind uploading as a morally worthwhile
technological pursuit). I take up the writings of Brent Waters, who holds an Augustinian view of
humanity, Celia Deane-Drummond, who adopts a Thomistic anthropology, and Francis Fukuyama,
who uses a mostly humanist perspective. I show that within the context of the transhumanist debate,
the discordance of these views leaves the reader with no clear answers. Thus, I advocate for outside
perspectives informed by work done in Science, Technology and Society (STS) studies. Too many of
our backwards-looking anthropological frameworks lead only to struggle and contention about the
Religions 2017, 8, 52
3 of 9
moral challenge of transhumanism. The work done in STS however, reframes the anthropological
debate by contextualizing its evolution, thereby providing a new solution to intractable disputes.
1. A Sampling of Anthropologies
I contend that Berdyaev’s call has not truly been answered today. This is not to say that
nobody has taken up the anthropological question, but rather that many views are beholden to
older anthropological traditions. For example, Jacques Ellul wrote a great deal about humanity’s
relationship to technology, but his thought remains fairly Augustinian. He suggests, for instance, that
Adam did not have to work in the perfect Garden of Eden, so work and technology arise only as a
result of sin [16]. W. Norris Clarke, SJ, on the other hand, writes about technology from a Thomistic
perspective and suggests it is a genuinely human expression of God’s gifts of rationality to human
beings [17]. Finally, one must note that the transhumanists themselves consider their own intellectual
heritage to be the early humanist movement [2]. One notes, for example, that patternism is a somewhat
Cartesian substance dualist view of the human person, who should be free from the suffering and pain
attendant to biological bodies. For the rest of this section, I examine three major figure’s anthropological
views relating specifically to the question of transhumanism and why it is dangerous. Each author
corresponds loosely to one of Berdyaev’s anthropological models, and each critiques transhumanism
from this perspective.
Brent Waters has written extensively on new technologies, and especially the implications of
transhumanism and its misplaced conceptions. Waters writes more in line with the philosophy
of Hannah Arendt, but as a Protestant theologian, his writing is unmistakably (and undeniably)
Augustinian in tone. Waters begins by arguing that the “technoculture” we live in leaves us homeless
and estranged ([18], p. 122). This homelessness affects everyone, but Waters argues that we Christians
are called to respond to this differently from non-Christians. Non-Christians find themselves as
“nomads”, wandering the world with no sense of meaning or purpose, while Christians are “pilgrims”,
recognizing that our journey has a direction and that the trip itself is sacred. The pilgrim Christians
of Waters’s framework are residents of the earthly city, though they are citizens of the heavenly
city ([18], p. 149). Christians, in this framework, recognize that their will is set right by grace toward
the Parousia, while non-Christians variously try to navigate as nomads through private revelation,
universal reason, casuistic readjustment or moral subjectivism ([18], pp. 148–52). Thus, Christians, as
citizens of the heavenly city, are called to a different moral orientation from non-Christians who have
no such awareness, despite the fact that our situation as homeless in the technological world is the
same. The heavenly orientation of Christians makes our journey here one of pilgrimage, while the lack
of such vision among non-Christians results in aimless nomadism. This heavenly orientation, Waters
contends, allows the Christian to not fear death the way the transhumanist does; for while death is the
enemy of both transhumanists and Christians, the transcendent focus on Christ’s resurrection changes
the meaning of death for the Christian pilgrim [19].
Celia Deane-Drummond writes much on Thomistic and Aristotelian implications of new scientific
advances and technological developments. Deane-Drummond’s approach is interesting in that she
combines both a strong natural scientific perspective and a strong Thomistic perspective into one.
She concedes, for example, an evolutionary understanding of humanity: we are a species in continuum
with other living species and not necessarily morphologically distinct from extinct hominids [20,21].
She likewise takes seriously the promises offered by transhumanist technologies, including human
gene editing. Nonetheless, she holds this in tension with a strong theological view. She champions, for
example, the centrality of virtue for moral decision-making, especially Aquinas’s four cardinal moral
virtues and the three theological virtues [22,23]. She argues virtue is a necessary moral orientation for us
to have because of the centrality of grace for Christian anthropology. Our transformation through grace
is a transformation of both our moral orientation and our being, and so a perspective that admits for
moral growth is necessary. Furthermore, she contends that humans are not distinct from other animals
by virtue of our rationality alone, but more significantly, through God’s transformative grace our
Religions 2017, 8, 52
4 of 9
animal nature is uplifted to one imprinted by the divine [20]. Thus, human beings are simultaneously
natural, rational animals and imago Dei transformed through God’s grace [20,21]. Therefore, accounts of
the person which either denigrate the natural and animal elements of being human or which ignore the
divine spark within us fail to do justice to theological accounts of personhood. Technological projects
that seek to “take leave of the animal” by evacuating soul from body or control our future and thus
obviate grace are immoral [21,22].
Francis Fukuyama is a secular philosopher who sat as a member of George W. Bush’s President’s
Council on Bioethics. He is strongly influenced by both Nietzsche and Aristotle, but his anthropological
orientation centers around the concept of human dignity separate from any theological underpinnings.
Fukuyama defines human dignity as “Factor X” which is “some essential human quality underneath
[all contingent characteristics] that is worthy of a certain minimal level of respect” ([24], p. 149). Lest
we attribute this to some central aspect of our being human, such as rationality, Fukuyama assures
us that Factor X “cannot be reduced to the possession of moral choice, or reason, or language, or
sociability, or sentience, or emotions, or consciousness, or any other quality that has been put forth as a
ground for human dignity. It is all of these qualities coming together in a human whole that make
up Factor X” ([24], p. 171). He does not provide greater explanation to this; he simply contends that
the Gestalt of Factor X is worthy of moral respect. Fukuyama goes on to suggest this entails a need to
preserve what is biologically natural and to ensure the “genetic endowment” of all of humanity for
future generations ([24], p. 171). In terms of transhumanism, this means any morphological change
that directly violates Factor X or affects our genetic endowment would be a violation of human dignity.
Thus, uploading, which renders the genetic endowment obsolete and would likely alter or distort
elements of being human like emotion and sociability, would violate human dignity in a profound
way. The uploaded mind is a natural transgression and thus a trespass against human dignity.
The above should not be taken to be any sort of exhaustive look at the various anthropologies
offered to reflect on transhumanism, nor is this a thorough examination of even these three thinkers’
positions. My intention here is simply to note that there are, in fact, various philosophical and
theological positions raised against transhumanism, coming from diverse viewpoints and contending
in favor of certain traditional understandings of the person. This selection could have been substituted
for others, including non-Augustinian patristic thinkers like Todd T. W. Daly or other humanists
like Michael Sandel. However, I believe the selection above provides a diverse-enough sampling to
understand what people are saying about transhumanism and why there is resistance to it. In all three
above cases, the patternists’ anthropology is seen as dangerous because it violates key components of
what it means to be human.
2. Hearing amid the Noise
If one browses through such volumes as Mercer and Trothen’s Religion and Transhumanism: The
Unknown Future of Human Enhancement, Mercer and Maher’s Transhumanism and the Body: The World
Religions Speak or Hansell and Grassie’s H±: Transhumanism and Its Critics, she may believe that there
are many more arguments against uploading than there are in favor of it. Indeed, the positions
outlined above suggest this is the case: uploading is primarily supported by a very particular humanist
perspective based on the thought of figures like Bacon and informed by an uncertain amount of
Cartesian dualism. However, many authors, from various traditions, contend that the pro-uploaders
are wrong, and, worse still, that their project is dangerous. One might dream this agreement would
solve the problem once and for all, but transhumanism remains still popular. Moreover, a further moral
challenge arises due to the diversity represented in anti-uploading views; while transhumanism itself
may be widely opposed, the reasons why authors oppose it are diverse and sometimes incompatible.
We may see a preliminary problem in this challenge by noting that while Waters, Deane-Drummond
and Fukuyama agree that uploading is morally irresponsible, they come to this consideration from
rather different standpoints. Waters, a Protestant theologian, follows Augustine and Arendt (who
also follows Augustine to a certain extent) in his thought. Deane-Drummond, a Catholic theologian,
Religions 2017, 8, 52
5 of 9
follows Aquinas and Aristotle in her thought. Fukuyama, a secular philosopher, nominally follows
Aristotle and Nietzsche, though his thinking looks unlike either of theirs and is more informed by a
rich Enlightenment humanism. These three thinkers do depart from their point of origin—it would be
hard to really apply Augustine, Aquinas or Nietzsche to the problem of uploading—but they also do
take their cues from these sources. More importantly, while Augustine, Aquinas and Nietzsche can
all be broadly categorized under the rubric of the Western philosophical canon, they occupied very
different social locations, with very different interests and had very different understandings of the
world. Augustine’s Roman Christian concerns are different from Aquinas’s scholastic concerns, and
neither are strictly relevant to Nietzsche’s Wilhelmian Germany. These differences are not irrelevant,
so we should be careful in relativizing all philosophical perspectives that share some modicum of
agreement too quickly.
Secondly, and more to the point, our three authors’ views are not all the way consonant.
Augustinian “earthly city” language does not flatter Aquinas’s natural law position favoring the
“natural”, nor does it favor Fukuyama’s deference to secular philosophers. Similarly, Fukuyama’s view
of the unassailability of the “genetic endowment” of humanity seems at odds with Waters’s favored
perspective of our alienation on this earth, and more so to Deane-Drummond’s recognition that human
uniqueness goes beyond genetics. Thus, a challenge in reading these arguments is deciding which has
the most merit. A clever uploader could “cherry pick” elements from each anthropology to support
his own: the dualism characteristic of Augustine’s view, the transformative aspect of the Thomistic
vision, and the secularism of Fukuyama all resonate with patternism, though they do not resonate
across the boundaries of our three authors. Indeed, the discordance of these thinkers functions to the
advantage of patternists and it becomes easy (and perhaps prudent) for transhumanists to dismiss the
other positions as merely differences of opinion.
The conclusion we are left with after surveying and analyzing these positions is that from an
outside position, the disagreements boil down to differences in philosophy. Those who uphold a
patristic or patristic inspired worldview are not likely to share the same values or understandings
as those who uphold a scholastic or neo-scholastic worldview nor those who favor a humanistic
worldview. In other words, if Deane-Drummond’s account of the human is right, then Fukuyama’s,
Waters’s, and the transhumanists’ cannot be. But transhumanists have no vested interest in accepting
either theological or non-theological philosophies that contradict their own. It is in their best interest
to allow the challenge of their opponents to reduce to qualms about philosophy. Thus, the obstacle
remaining is to somehow overcome these intractable philosophical anthropological differences.
3. STS: A Way Out?
At the risk of pursuing a seeming non-sequitur, I wish to suggest that a solution to this problem
may arrive from Science, Technology and Society (STS) studies. STS combines approaches from the
social sciences of anthropology, sociology and history. The work done in STS over the past eighty years
has yielded new insights into the way that scientific knowledge is produced (Sociology of Scientific
Knowledge), the historical development of scientific theories and technologies (History of Science
and History of Technology), the way that technologies are created in social circumstances (Social
Construction of Technology) and even multi-disciplinary approaches that appreciate the interconnected
networky nature of scientific work and technological progress (Actor-Network Theory or ANT). While
philosophers and theologians of technology going back to Heidegger and Ellul have been engaged in
debates about the development of technologies, the best models to oppose certain developments, the
dangers present and the way out, STS folk have been happy to examine primarily how things came to
be the way they are.
Among STS insights that are helpful here, the ANT work of Bruno Latour is perhaps the most
pertinent. In his landmark We Have Never Been Modern, Latour suggests that the “modern constitution”
consists of two important tenets. First, “it is not [human beings] who make Nature; Nature has always
existed and has always already been there; we are only discovering its secrets”. Second, “human
Religions 2017, 8, 52
6 of 9
beings, and only human beings, are the ones who construct society and freely determine their own
destiny” ([25], p. 30). In other words, we traditionally believe that the world of human commerce
and interaction (including politics, sociology, and, dare I say, philosophy and theology) is necessarily
separate from the world of “science” (the things of nature); the elements pertaining to the former are
contingent and made by human minds for human beings while elements pertaining to the latter are
intrinsic to the world and only involve us in the “discovery” of their secrets. Latour argues that the
modern constitution is not true: the propositions for the human world and those for the natural world
are not held separate but are all “mixed” together and so that all forms of knowledge are “hybrid”
knowledge ([25], p. 41). We thus never fully achieved the “modern” separation of these two spheres:
our science of Nature is tainted by our human biases and our society is affected by natural relations.
Humans and non-humans interplay in entangled networks that ground our mode of being in the
world. In other words, just as the clever anthropologist notes the cosmological unity of “pre-modern”
peoples’ views of nature and society, Latour argues that our society is likewise cosmologically unified
and has never truly been modern ([25], p. 46).
This insight helps us understand the epistemological heritage of the uploaders. As Hubert Dreyfus
notes in What Computers Still Can’t Do, the assumption that computers emulate human thought is itself
based on ancient Greek perspectives of human cognition as calculation ([26], p. 67). The image of a
calculating machine influences Alan Turing, whose work in computing and hypothesis of a “Turing
Machine” become the basis for artificial intelligence work ([26], p. 74). The possibility of a Turing
machine in turn underlies much of the theory informing the uploaders. This Plato-Turing lineage
finds its expression in patternist philosophy in the following manner: the mind operates on a set of
instructions like a computer, and so a sufficient calculating machine (perhaps one running numerous
parallel processes and operating with formidable processing power) will accomplish what the human
brain accomplishes and therefore be able to run the same program as a brain ([9], ch. 1). Assuming
Dreyfus is correct, this means that the viability of uploading relies, not on a thoroughly “modern”
natural science worldview, but rather on Socratic theories of epistemology, the same epistemology that
contends all knowledge is intrinsic and simply in need of being brought forth by the right stimulus
rather than learned. The patternists, however scientific they may seem, are not “postmodern” or even
“modern”; they are, in fact, pre-modern.
STS reveals, therefore, three crucial dangers about the uploading project that are otherwise
obscured by arguments from various philosophical anthropologies. The first problem is that the
patternist philosophy of the transhumanists is just that—a philosophy and not a science. Thomas
Kuhn notes that science is singular among all disciplines of knowledge in that it does not allow
for competing schools to emerge ([27], p. 162). The scientific paradigm that admits of oxygen as a
chemical element utterly replaces the paradigm that understands dephlogisticated air. Newtonian
theory replaces Aristotelian physics and becomes hegemonic—one cannot be a scientist and now hold
that fire is attracted to the sun. This is not the case, however, with philosophy or theology (barring,
notes Kuhn, dogmatic theology). The diversity of thought detailed above is proof of this. The rigor
and policing that keeps science from admitting “junk science” (when done properly) is not relevant
to systems like philosophy where plural views are held within the same discipline. This is why the
modern constitution is held—science is practiced with much greater scrutiny and authoritarianism
than any other field, and so is held to be unbiased and unaffected. Any given philosophical view,
therefore, should not be treated as though it were a scientific principle.
The second danger is that modern theories are constantly in flux. Braden Allenby warns that
our constructions of technological versions of humanity will be based on our current mental models,
models which are subject to destabilization with new discoveries [28]. Each of the authors mentioned
above represents a different perspective of what it means to be human, and each importantly represents
an evolution of earlier ideas as well. Waters is not fully Augustinian; he is also informed by twentieth
and twenty-first century science and philosophy. Deane-Drummond is not fully Thomistic; she
synthesizes the Angelic Doctor with evolutionary theory. Scientific models evolve and, hopefully, are
Religions 2017, 8, 52
7 of 9
perfected over time. The scientific perspectives of patternism are yet untested, and a failure on this
front will be fatal (“suicidal”). Human lives should not be staked on unstable scientific claims. This
principle holds true across moral traditions and one does not need to hold a strong “precautionary”
view to support it.
The final danger, a sort of synthesis of the first two, is that contingent philosophical views are
being taken to have the same certainty as scientific ones. Transhumanists, in taking their philosophical
view to be scientific, risk great danger because patternist philosophy is not subject to the same
rigor or trials of strength as scientific theories ([29], pp. 74–79). One cannot prove theories about
human consciousness or identity in a laboratory, just as one cannot prove moral propositions, literary
theories or the existence of God. These are positions held as a matter of worldview, not as scientific
principles. To treat them as scientific theories, as the uploaders do, is dangerous first and foremost
because the “patternist” theory is not subject to proof or disproof the way that the vacuum of Robert
Boyle’s air pump was subject to proof [30]. Consciousness and identity are held as philosophical
propositions—there is no “proof” of a human soul or any given person’s persistent mind. These are
rather universally held philosophical and theological positions. Indeed, the belief in a self that persists
over time chafes against scientific findings that all somatic cells are replaced every seven years, leading
to a veritable “Ship of Theseus” paradox for human identity ([31], p. 260). To treat philosophical
tenets as scientific views, therefore, is a category mistake, and misunderstands both the nature of the
philosophical claims of human identity and what pertains to the domain of science.
4. Conclusions: Complicating Anthropologies
The discussion above may lead one to conclude that there is no solution to the problem at hand.
The uploaders will do as they please, and the anti-uploaders will do as they please, and neither
side will convince the other. Perhaps, for example, a sufficient program can be uploaded that passes
the “Kurzweil Turing Test”, convincingly responding to any given stimulus the way that a given
person (e.g., Ray Kurzweil) would ([31], p. 257). Pro-uploaders will accept this as sufficient scientific
evidence to validate their claims. Anti-uploaders, however, will see reason to dispute this—perhaps
the immaterial soul was lost, or perhaps the program is merely a clever mimic (or perhaps demonic
impersonation) of the uploaded person. Arguments grounded in older philosophical systems, whether
in favor of or against uploading crash against the same obstacle, namely the non-scientific nature of
claims of consciousness and identity.
STS illustrates not only the problem of this category mistake, but also suggests a solution. Our
world is not yet modern, so Latour claims, though he offers us a way to accept this. Human beings
are hybrid creatures—”quasi-subjects” creating “quasi-objects” ([25], p. 137). ANT theorists note
that we live and operate in long “networks” of being, constituted by both human and non-human
actors affecting and influencing each other. This offers two conclusions for the present discussion.
The first is that our philosophical and theological arguments must take seriously the intermingling of
fields. Theology has, in fact, influenced science, just as science fiction has influenced technological
progress. There is no clean divide, and the uploader who believes his work is “pure science” is
mistaken. Uploaders must be ready to see that their “patternist” philosophy is not more scientific than
Thomistic theories about the self or Augustinian accounts of fallen nature. Anthropological accounts
are and always have been informed by a series of discussions about the person that cross between
“hard” scientific and “soft” philosophical and theological domains. Deane-Drummond’s evolutionary
Thomism is a wonderful example of this cross-disciplinary approach. The patternists’ view is likewise
a constructed philosophical vision, articulated through discussions about the nature of cognition
reaching back as far as Socrates, and given further strength in twentieth-century computer science. All
positions have genealogies, and none is “purified” from the messiness of disciplinary intermingling.
The second, more significant conclusion, is that human nature, whatever it is, is not
“finished.” Our accounts of humanity are continually evolving. One thinks of the anthropological
“revolutions” associated with Copernicus, Darwin and Freud: heliocentricity, evolutionary theory and
Religions 2017, 8, 52
8 of 9
psychoanalysis have yielded ineradicable changes to our conception of what we are. We are, of course,
not done yet either. The past several decades have seen the success of the Human Genome Project,
discussions of nuclear cloning, and the discovery of CRISPR/Cas9 gene editing. Philosophical and
theological accounts of humanity may be struggling harder to keep up with these changes than are
popular understandings (or, worse yet, “scientistic” understandings like that of the uploaders), but
this only underscores the need for caution. There may never be a “finalized” concept of the human
person—new discoveries about the mind, about evolution, about genetics and epigenetic factors or
even sociological data may yield unending knowledge. This instability, however, suggests the need
for caution. A technological project that risks ending human lives deliberately should not be pursued
based on highly contestable and overly confident scientifically-masked philosophies of what it means
to be a person.
A final word must be said for theological accounts of being human. While it is reckless, and
perhaps impossible, to try to utterly abandon ancient theological visions of the human being (e.g., those
of Augustine, Aquinas, Luther and others), we should be cautious about holding too strictly to them
as well. Augustine’s theology was informed by his neo-Platonic understanding of the world, just as
Aquinas’s was shaped by his Aristotelian science. As new sciences and technologies emerge, we must
be willing to rethink our anthropological models. A step in this direction is the recognition with ANT
theorists that part of being human is being part of these entangled webs of relations. The twenty-first
century Western Christian cannot be understood wholly apart from the Internet, smartphones, global
positional satellites and worsening climate change. Developments in and toward transhumanist
visions of the future may be misguided, but the Christian must also be ready to understand herself in
new terms if a consciousness is “successfully” uploaded. The strength of Christian faith has been in its
adaptation throughout the centuries to new sciences and philosophies. We may face another such task
of adaptation in the “posthuman” future.
Conflicts of Interest: The author declares no conflict of interest.
References
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
Stock, Gregory. “The Battle for the Future.” In The Transhumanist Reader Classical and Contemporary Essays
on the Science, Technology and Philosophy of the Human Future. Edited by Max More and Natasha Vita-More.
Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013, pp. 302–16.
More, Max. “The Philosophy of Transhumanism.” In The Transhumanist Reader Classical and Contemporary
Essays on the Science, Technology and Philosophy of the Human Future. Edited by Max More and
Natasha Vita-More. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013, pp. 3–17.
Kass, Leon. “Death with Dignity and the Sanctity of Life.” In Life, Liberty and the Defense of Dignity: The
Challenge for Bioethics. San Francisco: Encounter Books, 2002, pp. 231–56.
Kamm, Frances. “What Is and Is Not Wrong with Enhancement?” In Human Enhancement. Edited by
Julian Savulescu and Nick Bostrom. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009, pp. 91–130.
Coady, C. A. J. “Playing God.” In Human Enhancement. Edited by Julian Savulescu and Nick Bostrom. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2009, pp. 155–80.
Bostrom, Nick. “In Favor of Posthuman Dignity.” In H±: Transhumanism and Its Critics. Edited by
Gregory Hansell and William Grassie. Philadelphia: Metanexus Institute, 2011, pp. 55–66.
Savulescu, Julian. “The Human Prejudice and the Moral Status of Enhanced Beings: What Do We Owe the
Gods?” In Human Enhancement. Edited by Julian Savulescu and Nick Bostrom. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2009, pp. 211–50.
“2045 Strategic Social Initiative.” Available online: http://2045.com/ (accessed on 28 January 2017).
Moravec, Hans. Mind Children: The Future of Robot and Human Intelligence. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1988.
Lanier, Jaron. “One Half of a Manifesto.” Available online: https://www.edge.org/documents/archive/
edge74.html (accessed on 2 February 2017).
Religions 2017, 8, 52
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
29.
30.
31.
9 of 9
Koene, Randal. “Uploading to Substrate-Independent Minds.” In The Transhumanist Reader Classical and
Contemporary Essays on the Science, Technology and Philosophy of the Human Future. Edited by Max More and
Natasha Vita-More. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, 2013, pp. 146–56.
Agar, Nicholas. “Ray Kurzweil and Uploading: Just Say No! ” Journal of Evolution & Technology 22 (2011):
23–36.
Hayles, N. Katherine. “Wrestling with Transhumanism.” In H±: Transhumanism and Its Critics. Edited by
Gregory Hansell and William Grassie. Philadelphia: Metanexus Institute, 2011, pp. 176–88.
Thweatt-Bates, J. Cyborg Selves: A Theological Anthropology of the Posthuman. Farnham: Ashgate, 2012.
Berdyaev, Nicholas. “Man and Machine.” In Philosophy and Technology: Readings in the Philosophical Problems
of Technology. Edited by Carl Mitcham and Robert Mackey. New York: The Free Press, 1972, pp. 203–13.
Ellul, Jacques. “Technique and the Opening Chapters of Genesis.” In Theology and Technology: Essays in
Christian Analysis and Exegesis. Edited by Carl Mitcham and Jim Grote. Lanham: University Press of America,
1984, pp. 123–38.
Clarke, W. Norris. “Technology and Man: A Christian View.” In Philosophy and Technology: Readings in the
Philosophical Problems of Technology. Edited by Carl Mitcham and Robert Mackey. New York: The Free Press,
1972, pp. 247–58.
Waters, Brent. Christian Moral Theology in the Emerging Technoculture: From Posthuman Back to Human.
Farnham: Ashgate, 2014.
Waters, Brent. “Flesh Made Data: The Posthuman Project in Light of the Incarnation.” In Religion and
Transhumanism: The Unknown Future of Human Enhancement. Edited by Calvin Mercer and Tracy J. Trothen.
Santa Barbara: Praeger, 2015, pp. 291–302.
Deane-Drummond, Celia. “God’s Image and Likeness in Humans and Other Animals: Performative
Soul-Making and Graced Nature.” Zygon 47 (2012): 934–48. [CrossRef]
Deane-Drummond, Celia. “Taking Leave of the Animal? The Theological and Ethical Implications of
the Transhuman Projects.” In Transhumanism and Transcendence: Christian Hope in an Age of Technological
Enhancement. Edited by Ronald Cole-Turner. Washington: Georgetown University Press, 2011, pp. 115–30.
Deane-Drummond, Celia. “How Might a Virtue Ethic Frame Debates in Human Genetics?” In Brave New
World? Theology, Ethics and the Human Genome. Edited by Celia Deane-Drummond. London: T & T Clark,
2003, pp. 225–52.
Deane-Drummond, Celia. “Future Perfect? God, the Transhuman Future and the Quest for Immortality.”
In Future Perfect? God, Medicine and Human Identity. Edited by Celia Deane-Drummond and Peter M. Scott.
London: T & T Clark, 2006, pp. 168–82.
Fukuyama, Francis. Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution. New York: Farrar,
Strauss and Giroux, 2002.
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern. Translated by Catherine Porter. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1993.
Dreyfus, Hubert L. What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1994.
Kuhn, T. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 50th Anniversary ed. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 2012.
Allenby, Braden. “Technology and Transhumanism: Unpredictability, Radical Contingency and
Accelerating Change.” In Building Better Humans? Refocusing the Debate on Transhumanism. Edited by
Hava Tirosh-Samuelson and Kenneth L. Mossman. Frankfurt: Peter Lang Gmbh, 2012, pp. 441–63.
Latour, Bruno. Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1987.
Shapin, Steven, and Simon Schaffer. Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985.
Kurzweil, Ray. The Singularity Is Near: When Humans Transcend Biology. New York: Viking, 2005.
© 2017 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access
article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution
(CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).