Beyond World Images: Belief as Embodied Action in the World
Michael Strand, Omar Lizardo
Abstract
In this paper we outline the analytic limitations of action theories and interpretive schemes
that conceive of beliefs as explicit mental representations linked to a desire-opportunity
folk psychology. Drawing on pragmatism and practice theory, we recast the notion of
belief as a species of habit, with pre-reflexive anticipation the primary mechanism
accounting for both the formation of beliefs and their causal influence on action. We
demonstrate the utility of this approach in three ways: first, by linking it with recent
research on the cognitive and motor development of infants; second, by drawing out a
typology of belief states that accounts for a range different experiential traits; and third, by
applying the new model to reinterpret two belief-based phenomena of broad sociological
interest: “irrational” decision-making and religious conversion.
1 Introduction
The theory of action has undergone in recent years what might be called a Weberian
revitalization. Intrasubjectivity, “interior states” and first-person meanings have again
become the focus of sociological accounts of action (Hedstrom 2005; Vaisey 2008; Reed
2011). The claim that action can be explained simply by “reference to the social context in
which they occur” (Campbell 1996: 40) has been augmented by approaches that are
attentive to actor motivations, reasons, desires, attitudes, and beliefs. With this move
toward actor subjectivity, causality and the theory of action have been joined together
again (Martin 2011). Here, actor-level traits are treated as analytically distinguishable from
observable events and conditions. This gives subjectivity a decisive force in shaping lines of
action. In this way, this recent spate of claims mirrors Weber’s original emphasis on the
interpretive recovery of the subjective meaning of action as the recommended means for
generating causal claims in sociology (Turner 1983).
An important part of this renewal of subjectivity in the theory of action has centered
around actor beliefs. This is not surprising given how closely intertwined the notion of
belief has traditionally been for both Parsonian action theory (Parsons and Shils 1951:
168-69) and the post-behaviorist philosophy of action (Bernstein 1971; Rosenberg 1995).
The notion of belief refers, in this formulation, to an actor’s “world-images” as
representations about the world. Beliefs consist of ideas, often interrelated in systems, that
link the actor to the world through the medium of symbolic meaning (Borhek and Curtis
1975: 5). Beliefs provide a critical ingredient to causal accounts of action by maintaining
the “autonomy” of the actor’s interior states in the face of external or impersonal
processes (Davidson 1980). The social-scientific notion of belief often serves as the
intrasubjective mechanism linking cultural scripts, frames, codes and ideologies with their
inferred effects on observable lines of action. Belief is therefore frequently targeted as a
central explanatory resource for producing “intentional” explanations of action (Hedstrom
2005). Together, these are characteristic features of what we will refer to as the
representationalist model of belief, and the Weberian revitalization of the theory of action
overwhelmingly relies on it.
In this paper, we argue that the representationalist model of belief is fundamentally limited
and should be at least partially replaced. The model is appealing because it seems to give
the social scientist interpretive access (via language) to the often mysterious interior
wellsprings of action (Henderson 1993). However, this appearance is misleading as the
effectiveness of the model largely involves the common sense intuitability generated by its
dual presence as both a folk “category of practice” and a scientific “category of analysis”
(Brubaker and Cooper 2000; Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992: 235ff; Jepperson and Meyer
2011). Thus, we analyze the predominant model of belief in sociology as a version of “folk
psychology” and argue that, in spite of its face validity, it makes problematic assumptions
about the “interior” causes of action (Rosenberg 1995). We contend that in order to
maintain an approach to the theory of action that has both causal and intrasubjective
adequacy “at the level of meaning” (Weber 1978: 12) it is necessary, drawing from
pragmatism and practice theory, to redefine belief as a species of habit.
1.1. Representationalism in Contemporary Accounts of Belief
While implicitly or explicitly animating action-explanations of all theoretical stripes, the
representationalist model is most explicitly articulated in contemporary versions of
“sociological” rational actor theory (RAT). Allegiance to representationalism (sometimes
referred to as “cognitivism”) separates the “soft” sociological variation of RAT from its
stronger counterpart in marginalist (non-behavioral) economics (Goldthorpe 1998;
Hedstrom 2005). As Boudon (1997) has argued, the orthodox model falters precisely
because it is of “little use as far as the explanation of beliefs is concerned” (75, our italics;
see also Morgan 2005: 213). The basic insight of sociological RAT is that action is guided
by potentially fallible beliefs about existing opportunities rather than by “objective”
knowledge of the world (Hedstrom and Swedberg 1996: 128; Elster 1984: 72). Outlining
the mechanisms that generate fallibility in the belief-formation process thus becomes a
central concern in this explanatory tradition (Rydgren 2008).
It is important to underscore that the analytic problem of belief is not the localized
affliction of rational choice sociologists. Instead, the representationalist model of belief
evident in “Desire-Belief-Opportunity” (DBO) theory is found in nearly all interpretivist
approaches to action that can trace their roots to Weber and the neo-Kantians. This
includes most contemporary attempts to provide explanations of action for which
“culture” and “interpretation” feature prominently (e.g. Reed 2011). Thus, cultural
theorists like Geertz (1973) and Archer (1995) propose that beliefs link to one another
via chains of logical implication to form autonomous “belief systems” (Rydgren 2009: 88;
Borhek and Curtis 1975). The explicit theory behind these sometimes informal proposals
is the Weberian idea that beliefs drive action by providing the input into a decision-making
mechanism that matches goals to the conditions of their fulfillment (Turner 1983). Action
is thus the pragmatic end of a “deductive chain” that starts with the high-level, antecedent
premises provided by a cultural system, model, frame, code or ideology (see Swidler 2001:
187-88; Borhek and Curtis 1975).
While cultural systems provide one route to recover intrasubjectivity, interpretivists
(alongside DBO theorists) draw this together with an additional set of substantive
assumptions in order to theorize the causal efficacy of belief. Weber recognized that
sociology could not dispense with a focus on subjective meaning nor with causal
explanations. His concern with intrasubjectivity (as a “subjective meaning-complex”) in
opposition to the application of a natural-scientific rationality in sociology still grounds
concerns with meaning in the discipline (Campbell 1996).
Importantly, Weber’s argument on these points converges with similar arguments in the
philosophy of action (Turner 1983). Tracing the “irreducibility of the mental” was the
post-behaviorist form taken by mind-body dualism, with philosophers seeking to explain
how action could not be redescribed in a purely natural-scientific register of impersonal,
material causation (Bernstein 1971). Among the most influential statements came from
Donald Davidson and his argument that irreducibility, in this sense, consists of holistic
belief/desire complexes (“reasons”) that causally interact with the observable world of
physical events as “mental events”(1980: 217, 225).
While sharing almost nothing else in common, DBO and cultural-interpretive accounts
both draw from Davidson’s argument in support of their shared claim that “reasons” are
analytically distinguishable as an intrasubjective causal factor shaping courses of action
(Hedstrom 2005: 38-39; Reed 2011: 135f).1 For DBO theorists this involves beliefs that
provide substantive variation in action otherwise geared toward the fulfillment of interests
or desires (Rydgren 2009: 72-73). For interpretivists, culturally shaped world-images
1
Critical realists also draw from Davidson’s argument. Here, beliefs constitute a crucial part of what
Bhaskar calls the “principle of psychic ubiquity” according to which “states of the mind” serve as the
irreducible foundation of agency (see Bhaskar 1998: 96-97).
provide the analytically separable “forming” causes that mold motivations (as “interior
states”) and mechanisms that serve as “efficient” causes of social action (Reed 2011: 166).
Thus, following Weber and Davidson, DBO theorists and interpretivists reference
“intentionalist” properties like beliefs in order to provide their accounts of action with
causal adequacy at an intrasubjective or “interior” level. The only relevant difference, in
this last respect, is that interpretivists refuse to judge the propriety of beliefs according to
an exogenous normative standard (e.g. “rationality”).
1.2 Enter Folk Psychology
The philosophical foundations of this argument have taken an important turn in recent
decades, however, with the rise of the debate on the status of “folk psychology” in the
Philosophy
of
Mind
(FP;
see
Rosenberg
1995).
Here
the
argument
about
action-explanation becomes much more reflexive: the identification of actor-level “familiar
mental states” (beliefs, desires, hopes, feelings) invokes a common sense (or “folk”)
accounting scheme that naturally credits mental states as the causes of action
(Godfrey-Smith 2005; Churchland 1981). Rather than dispute the “dualistic” presence of
mental events, FP treats them as part of a generalized action-accounting template that
makes all actions seem reasonable by recasting them (post-hoc) as the deductive
consequence of belief/desire complexes understood as mental representations.2
For our purposes, it is important that Davidson’s “reasons as causes” argument is here
recast as a version of FP. Thus, sociological accounts that draw from it in order to lend
intrasubjective adequacy to causal explanations of action become, in a basic sense, versions
of FP. This folk “category of practice” lends validity to these arguments by introjecting
scientific “categories of analysis” with common sense schemas “that go without saying”
(Brubaker and Cooper 2000; Rosenberg 1995). Since FP is seemingly the most intuitive
accounting scheme available to lay actors and sociologists alike, its routine use to invoke
“interior states” drives home the appeal of DBO and interpretivist arguments as giving a
window of access onto the often mysterious interior causes of action. Yet FP’s intuitive
2
The sequence linking belief and action, mediated by goals/desires, is so common in scholarly and folk
accounts of action that it is referred to as the law of folk psychology: “x desires that p; x believes that if
q then p; x has the opportunity to bring it about that q; therefore x brings it about that q” (see
Churchland 1981: 71; Bernstein 1971: 277ff; Rosenberg 1995: 37). Plug any desire/belief combination
into p and q and you can retrieve a “common sense” meaning of action (Fodor 1987: xii). For parallel
examples of the FP “law” in sociology, see Reed (2011: 161) and Hedstrom (2005: 120ff).
appeal also glosses the fact that it is fundamentally inconsistent with what is known about
underlying cognitive, emotional, and neural mechanisms, committing sociological accounts
of action to a problematic heritage of mind/body dualism (Clark and Millican 1999).
FP relies on an understanding of beliefs as holistic, well-structured “propositional
attitudes.” These are “semantically interpretable mental states that play a causal role in the
production of other propositional attitudes and ultimately in the production of behavior”
(Ramsey, Stich and Garon 2006: 1030, our italics).3 As an argument about cognition, this
involves the rule-based manipulation of symbols derived from an interlinked conceptual
system (Fodor 1987). However, the “language of thought” hypothesis underlying this
claim has been challenged on the grounds that the cognitive or “interior” dimension of
action only in rare instances consists of something that resembles this kind of “internal
mental representation” (Lave 1994; Strauss and Quinn 1997; Shapiro 2011).
1.3 Outline of the Argument
The key implication, then, is that FP, as a highly intuitive set of explanatory categories,
may work well as a folk accounting scheme but it is less than adequate as an analytic
resource for sociology. This problem has not gone unrecognized. Hedstrom (2005: 41),
for instance, contends that sociologists simply accept FP even if it is problematic because
no other vocabulary is available that provides the same kind interpretive access to the
subjective meanings of action (see also Turner 1983: 517). In this article, we claim that,
on the contrary, there is an alternative vocabulary available that retains the concept of
belief as an intrasubjective resource for the theory of action, yet dispenses with the
problematic FP commitment to beliefs as mental representations that are deductively
created according to the logic of propositional attitudes.
We claim that the sociological version of FP and its representationalist model of belief
must rely on a similar “logical logic” by relying on the “power of the logic of ideas” to
produce causal inferences about action (Swidler 2001: 187-88). This follows relatively
straightforwardly from Weber’s own contention that tracing the “logic” of believed-in
3
Note that the concept of “propositional attitudes” is indistinguishable from the classical notion of
“ideas” found in post-classical action theory (Parsons 1938). Both are content-bearing states to which
the actor stands in a certain relationship (e.g. acceptance/non-acceptance).
ideas provides access to the “psychological” or motivational domain of action (Weber
1949: 88-89).4
Yet there are two problems encountered by explanations of action rooted in this
accounting scheme. First, it makes the causal effect of belief on action exclusively a matter
of deductive logic. As Weber himself understood, however, this mechanism applies only in
unique contexts or to socially rare groups of actors (“virtuosos”; see Lizardo and Strand
2010). This leaves unexplored the intrasubjective presence of belief in the vast majority of
actions. Second, it cannot coherently link the beliefs or interior states imputed by the
analyst using FP’s deductive logic to make an action “interpretable” (particularly if it
appears “irrational”) with the non-decisional belief-formation process that results in the
acquisition of those beliefs (see Elster 1983: 57).5 In this regard, FP in sociology involves
“sliding from the model of reality to the reality of the model” (Bourdieu 1990: 39). A
descriptive resource (deductive logic of “reasons” from belief/desire complexes) here
becomes a rule that directly governs its object (intrasubjectivity).6
We argue that it is ontologically more accurate and interpretively more useful to
understand beliefs as embodied in actors not primarily as ideas and representations but
rather in capacities for action. An action-based formulation, in this respect, avoids the first
problem by making belief an intrasubjective cause of action in the form of expectations
and anticipations of situational contingencies, often manifested as “belief in” one’s capacity
to engage in an action. It avoids the second problem by conceiving of belief-formation as
Dilthey’s development of verstehen recommends a similar mode of analysis: to “objectify” the contents
of life as the logic of ideas; this “spiritual object” then gives access to the “psychic nexus” of action
(Dilthey 1985: 106-107, 187). The best example of the “logic of ideas” approach remains Weber’s
Protestant Ethic thesis. Here, the intrasubjective effects on “self-confidence” (or the creation of what
Weber calls the “inner habitus” of Puritans) of systematic work in a calling is taken to be the deductive
conclusion reached by actors who believe in both the idea of Predestination and Luther’s decree of the
moral value of work (Weber 2002[1904-05]: 64ff, 202). Interestingly, the logical analysis of delimited
“concepts” identified through language in this sense was Gottlob Frege’s method of “extruding thoughts
from the mind,” and it stands at the the basis of analytic philosophy. It remains distinct in this respect
from the competing approach developed by Frege’s young rival, Edmund Husserl, and his
phenomenology (Dummett 1996).
4
5
Below, we argue that our model of belief-formation serves to highlight important preconditions for
the exercise of other processes that form beliefs outside of decision, specifically authority (Martin 2002)
and emotion (Collins 2004).
6
Henderson (1993) claims that the Davidsonian “reasons” framework should be treated as a “nomic
generalization” that is continuous with all action-explanations.
a non-representational “conditioning” or habituation process that attunes actors to the
conditions under which action is likely to unfold in the future (Bourdieu 1990: 50;
Bourdieu 2000: 218; Peirce 1905[1991d]: 337; Joas 1996: 197). We contend that,
together, this belief in action model offers a more intuitive treatment of how beliefs form
and how they affect action than the one made available by the FP accounting scheme.7
In what follows, we first outline the pragmatist and practice-theoretical accounts of belief,
both of which have rarely been the target of discussion among scholars in either tradition,
and use it to construct the basis for our alternative model. We then establish the appeal
for that model in three ways: first, by drawing it together with cognitive/motor
development among infants as a close analogue for a practice-based belief-formation
process; second, by developing a typology of “belief states” that account for the same
intrasubjective or “folk-psychological” states that provide the intuitive appeal of DBO and
interpretivist accounts; and third, by reinterpreting two case studies of processes that
involve belief, but which can be enhanced by recasting them using belief in action: first,
the seemingly irrational decision-making of poor teens to have children out of wedlock
(Edin and Kefalas 2005) and, second, the process of religious conversion (or “choosing to
believe”) among poor men (Smilde 2007).
2 Pragmatism and Practice Theory: Belief as Durable Habit
Pragmatism is not generally recognized for making a contribution to an understanding of
the notion of belief, although it is clear that the concept of belief and the belief-formation
process were significant for classical pragmatist arguments (Habermas 1971: 119-121;
Rochberg-Halton 1986; Joas 1993: 60-61).
In recent work in the theory of action, pragmatism has been primarily used as a resource
to combat the goal-based understanding of action characteristic of Parsonian and DBO
models. As pragmatist critics have noted (see especially Joas 1996: 157f; Whitford 2002;
Gross 2009; Silver 2011), this explanatory strategy relies on a teleological definition of
As Geertz (1975) argues, “common sense” is essentially a perseverative accounting system constructed
of presuppositions invulnerable to disconfirmation. It does not encompass intuitability. Common sense
accounts (like FP) can be highly intuitive, but only as post-hoc explanatory schemes that are “totalizing”
in their application (Geertz 1975: 16). Here we distinguish common sense from intuition as
anschaulichkeit (“intuitive accessibility”) or what field theorists (drawing on Gestalt psychologists) claim
is a form of action-explanation that “[allows] others to inhabit a coherent world [and] ‘get’ the principles
at work” but without the filtering effect of a nomic accounting scheme like FP (see Martin 2011: 334ff).
7
intentionality that makes the determinants of action (the deductive logic of desires, beliefs,
opportunities) “prior to the actual action.” Sociological RAT is therefore no different from
Parsons’ “voluntarist” theory of action as both make desires and beliefs exogenous to
action (Whitford 2002: 336). Here, pragmatist critics rely on Dewey’s (1939: 33ff) claim
that consciousness of desires and “ends-in-view” arises only when action stops “going
smoothly.”
Otherwise,
“vital
impulses and acquired habits...operate
without the
intervention of an end-in-view or purpose.” The desires and ends that provide the basis
for active “goal-setting” are not located in an “act of the intellect prior to the actual
action”; they are instead “the result of a reflection on aspirations and tendencies that are
pre-reflective and have already always been operative” (Joas 1996: 158).
For the pragmatists, the intentionality that both RAT and Parsonian (voluntarist) models
treat as independent of action emerges in the self-reflective control applied to already
ongoing courses of action. Desires, ends, and interests are situationally-bound and only
explicitly thematized in “problem-situations” that challenge the “automatic procedure of
action” (Joas 1996: 129; Whitford 2002: 355). What is missing from the neo-pragmatist
critique, however, is a reconsideration of the role of belief in action from a
non-representationalist perspective. For this task, it is Peirce who provides the most
promising starting point.
2.1 Peirce on Belief
The focus on the “problem-situation” as the occasion for having the desires, ends and
interests is ultimately rooted in the pragmatist notion of inquiry. This relates directly to a
pragmatist reframing of the concept of belief, a task that was launched in Peirce’s earliest
essays. According to Peirce, belief refers to a sense of certitude or “fixity” about habits.
The “essence of belief” is the “establishment of habit,” or the establishment “in our nature
of a rule of action” (Peirce 1992[1878]: 129) or “cerebral habit… which will determine
what we do in fancy as what we do in action” (Peirce 1992[1880]: 201; Peirce
1998[1905]: 333). Consequently, “the feeling of believing is a more or less sure indication
of there being established in our nature some habit which will determine our actions”
(Peirce 1992[1877]: 114).
It is not surprising, then, that Peirce founded pragmatism in the spirit of challenging
alternative explanations for a process he referred to as belief “fixation,” which involved the
acquisition of habits having the quality of “self-evident certitude” (Peirce 1992[1877];
Bernstein 1971: 174-75; Rochberg-Halton 1986). In non-pragmatist accounts, fixation
may be produced by tenacity (e.g. refusing to do anything that challenges established
belief), authority (e.g. religious or political enforcement of belief), or the “a priori method”
characteristic of Descartes (Peirce 1992[1877]: 116ff; 1992[1878]: 125-26). For Peirce, the
problem of each of these belief fixation methods is that they can’t acknowledge the
capacity to change any fixated trait, including “instincts” (Rochberg-Halton 1986: 10). In
this sense, all beliefs are potentially dubitable (there are no “indubitable” certainties)
because they are acquired from the world. As acquired capacities, all beliefs remain
fundamentally open to creative transformation as long as we remain capable of
experiencing a sense of doubt about them.
Peirce defines doubt as the opposite of belief: “doubt is an uneasy and dissatisfied state”
that arises from a lack of fully effective application of habits in action (Peirce 1992[1877]:
114). As we “body forth” pre-formed habits we may experience an “irritation of doubt”
due to the resistance of the world and the failure of effective action. This recurrent phase
is characterized by a “shattering of belief” (Joas 1996: 128; Peirce 1992[1877]: 114).
“Inquiry” refers here to the struggle to retain a “state of belief” by establishing a more or
less fixed set of habits (Peirce 1992[1877]: 114). It is a method of “fixating” (or forming)
belief that does not involve tenacity, authority or a priori reasoning.
Thus, understood broadly in Peirce’s formulation, inquiry is a process of belief-formation
rooted in the creative adaptation of habits to the situation-specific conditions of their
application. Importantly, as Peirce continues, inquiry as belief-formation involves a dialectic
between “self-reproach” (doubt) and “self-control” (belief) (Peirce 1998[1905]: 337). As
habits
meet
situations
that
present
problems,
actors
experience
a
feeling
of
“self-reproach.” Actors respond inquisitively when they deploy habits that facilitate a sense
of “self-control” in the situation (Joas 1996: 129).
When faced with a challenge to action, then, actors creatively attempt to develop new
habits that reestablish situational control and thus belief. Peirce (1998[1905]: 337)
describes this as the “self-preparation for action on the next occasion.” Further action may
encounter unanticipated challenges, which renews the process of creative formation of
novel modes of action through inquiry. Eventually, through the continuous iteration of this
process, modes of acting begin to approach “that fixed character, which would be marked
by the entire absence of self-reproach” (Peirce 1998[1905]: 337). This stage is
characterized by the “ultimate state of habit to which the action of self-control ultimately
tends, where no room is left for further self-control,” or what Peirce calls “the state of
fixed belief, or perfect knowledge” (ibid, our italics) of the action-environment. Most
importantly, the general dynamic at work, involving a dialectic between doubt and belief,
anchored in action, and linked to securing belief (“self-control”) through the creative
formation of habits, is also characteristic of later pragmatist thought as the principal
mechanism responsible for the formation of belief (see Dewey 1938: 104ff; 1905: 393ff;
James 1983[1890]: 913-914, 946ff).
2.2 The Self-Fulfilling Nature of Belief
Before addressing the relevance of more contemporary pragmatist theorizing for our
argument, it is helpful, particularly given how counterintuitive Peirce’s notion of belief as
unreflective habit might seem, to elaborate its implications for a classic sociological
argument involving belief: Merton’s (1948) elaboration of the “self-fulfilling prophecy.”8
In the canonical statement of the argument, beliefs modulate action in such a way that
actors alter reality to fit them. The “initial definition of the situation” (e.g. “the bank is
going to fail”) sets off a wave of action (withdrawing money from the bank) that
eventually changes the situation to mirror the initial belief (the bank fails) (Merton 1948:
194-95). This reverses the “normal” relationship between belief and reality in the
representationalist account, since beliefs are supposed to reflect reality rather than reality
reflecting belief. In this sense, the self-fulfilling prophecy is one of those curious cases in
the (normative) sociology of belief where we can observe the “subversion of rationality”
(Elster 1983).
However, rather than being a deviation from the “normal case,” we propose that the
modal form of belief in action is essentially self-fulfilling. For this statement to go from
assertion to substantive proposal requires that we abandon the representationalist
understanding of belief in favor of Peirce’s notion, in which beliefs subsist in habits and are
only derivatively representational. This suggests that normally the future-orientation of
8
Hedstrom and Swedberg (1998: 18) refer to the self-fulfilling prophecy as perhaps the “most famous
of all mechanisms-based theories in sociology.”
action is realized via non-reflective anticipations of the immediate future; in other words,
actors enact a present based on beliefs about the forthcoming. This implies no
commitment to beliefs as representations but rather to anticipated lines of action as
concrete actualizations.
The key is to realize that actors engage in situations “as if” certain things were already
present or certain events had already happened (Merleau Ponty 2002 [1962]: 512).
Elaborating this point, the temporality of action requires that actors “self-posit” what they
believe will be present (as reality) in the forthcoming moment (Tavory and Eliasoph 2013;
Mische 2009; Bourdieu 2000; Emirbayer and Mische 1998).9 In this sense, belief in
action has a “self-fulfilling” tendency operating as a medium of commitment to an
anticipated reality. Belief in action thus partakes of the “pre-verbal taking-for-granted” of
the world that is a precondition for practical action, manifesting itself in the capacity to
find “immediate adherence” with a distinct set of possibles available in a field of action
(Bourdieu 1990: 68).
Importantly in this respect, action is always action in situations, and these situations carry
their own objective tendencies that are empirically and analytically separable from the
intrasubjective reality of belief (Martin 2003: 44; Silver 2011; see also Campbell 1996:
159-60).10 This means that belief, as a kind of practical “prophecy,” can also fail in its
commitments and anticipations.11 This “failure,” however, is not a demonstration of the
actor’s incompetence or irrationality (as implied by strong rational choice theory), but a
revelation of the practical rationality of the actor (Ermakoff 2010). At each moment,
9
As Tavory and Eliasoph (2013: 913) point out this is particularly evident in conversation analysis,
where turn-taking requires that actors “begin formulating their talk milliseconds before the other
person’s turn ends” or begin acting according to an anticipatory belief about reality and not in pure
(quasi-empiricist) reaction to it.
10
Pragmatists have recommended that “the situation” replace the “means-ends schema” characteristic
of the DBO model as the “primary category of the theory of action” (Silver 2011: 108; see also Joas’
1996: 160). While we accept the pragmatists’ claims for the “non-neutrality of situations,” we argue
further that the conditions present in situations find a more global organization as the local environment
of a larger field, with the relationship between actor and situation being the “encounter of two histories”
(Bourdieu 2000: 150ff, 160; see also Martin 2011: 317).
11
This is a practical case of the classic phenomenon dealt with by Festinger et al (1956) in the case of
standard (reflective) “belief systems.” Our proposed prediction is the same as that of cognitive
dissonance theory: when practical prophecy fails, actors stick (at least for medium term) with their
beliefs rather than giving them up.
multiple possibilities for action are potentially realizable; yet once one of them is actualized
in belief, others are closed off. Anticipated reality can thus “fall out of sync” with the
situation, with actors attempting to bootstrap themselves into the immediate future under
the now “unreal” sway of previous anticipations. This breaks (for the moment) the tacit
complicity between beliefs and the micro-anticipated reality.
We claim that these instances of belief-situation mismatch are of crucial theoretical
interest, and not only because they bring the actor’s prereflexive contribution to the reality
of the situation into relief, making it available for empirical inspection. These moments are
also the occasion of creativity, in the pragmatist sense of actors “reconstructing” their
involvement in a situation to restore or repair a state of “unreflective belief” (Joas 1996).
As we elaborate below, belief-situation mismatch may also result in a condition of chronic
lag and misfiring of dispositions and habits---“hysteresis” (Bourdieu 1988: 157)---or even
the complete withdrawal of belief from the world and the resulting chronic inability to act
in relation to situations (“radical doubt”).
2.3 Belief and Creativity
The pragmatist account emphasizes that belief originates in practice, with “believing” a
form of commitment rooted in the development of habits. To further clarify this point,
consider the role that belief plays in what is likely the most influential strain of pragmatism
in contemporary social theory---Joas’ pragmatic “theory of situated creativity”:
...all perception of the world and all action in the world is anchored in unreflected
belief in self-evident facts and successful habits. However, this belief, and the
routines of action based upon it, are repeatedly shattered; what has previously been
a habitual, apparently automatic procedure of action is interrupted … This is the
phase of real doubt. And the only way out of this phase is a reconstruction of the
interrupted context (Joas 1996: 128, our italics).
Contrary to “situationalist” readings of Joas’ argument, actors are not creative in order to
solve emergent problems involving “how to organize action over time” (Swidler 2001:
82). Actors are creative, rather, in order to restore their unreflected beliefs built on habit
whenever these are thrown into doubt by situational challenges. While this often does
involve
actors creatively developing or deploying modes of action, the central
(non-teleological) motivation behind episodes of creativity involves actors restoring their
implicit (intrasubjective) sense of belief. Under this account, the self-fulfilling prophecy of
action is routinely realized via the “unreflected belief in self-evident facts and successful
habits” (Joas 1996: 128).
To the extent that actors succeed in creatively altering their circumstances, “something
new enters the world: a new mode of action” (Joas 1996: 129). When confronting
challenges due to the resistance of situations, the effect is analogous to the “dissolution of
belief by surprise” in Peirce’s sense. The expected response is a reconstruction of the
situation involving a belief-based anticipation of “new or different aspects of reality” (Joas
1996: 129). Yet this process of belief-formation is “essentially a by-product”---in the sense
that if it was teleologically intended it would not have come about (Elster 1983: 53ff)---of
the actor’s effort to restore her pre-reflexive and unreflected “fixity” of belief by
generating new modes of action.
2.4 Pragmatism and the Plasticity of Belief
If there is a shortcoming in the pragmatist model of belief it involves its “shallow”
conception of the ontogenetic (developmental) consequences of habituation. The
pragmatist account ends up downplaying the partial indubitability and inertial tendency of
all habits and, by consequence, the inherent “stubbornness” of belief. In this way, the
pragmatist account comes close to presuming that all habits are equally open to creative
transformation (even habits that seem instinctual or equivalent to a priori categories). This
problem is evident even in theoretical efforts that emphasize the embodiment, and thus
the seeming durability, of habit/beliefs.
Joas (1996), for instance, emphasizes the corporeality of habits and capacities for action,
as well as aspirations, tendencies, and goals. Insofar as “situation-relatedness is constitutive
of action,” the actor’s vague disposition toward goals and aspirations, and their unreflected
belief in the routinized habits mobilized towards these “ends-in-view,” are all effects of the
“personal body of the human being” (Joas 1996: 161). Joas dismantles RAT assumptions
regarding the dependence of action on non-corporeal (representationalist) elements,
making habits the main support for action. These habits are acquired via the “actor’s
instrumentalization of his [sic] body” in the development of a particular body schema (Joas
1996: 175).
An important precedent for this argument is James’ emphasis on the interaction between
the development of habits and the “plasticity” of the human brain. Habits involve “extreme
facility paths which do not easily disappear” as they are “grooved into” the plastic
structure of the brain (James 1983[1890]: 112). Plasticity refers here to the “possession of
a structure weak enough to yield and influence, but strong enough not to yield all at once.
Each relatively stable phase of equilibrium in such a structure is marked by what we may
call a new set of habits” (James 1983[1890]: 110).
As we “groove out” habits in the
plastic structure of the brain (principally, it seems, through repetitive action), those habits
achieve an embodied type of fixity, in turn making unreflected belief itself a function of
their degree of embodiment (James 1890[1983]: 130). Importantly, both James’ and Joas’
accounts imply that the human actor is more malleable and “plastic” than they are inertial.
The past does matter for the present, but this is always a revisable past.
However, this provisional malleability prevents pragmatists from developing a coherent
theory of belief, especially as belief links to subjectivity (Bernstein 1971: 197). We can see
an extension of this line of critique in contemporary debates in cultural theory (Vaisey
2008; Lizardo and Strand 2010; see also Campbell 1996) revolving around Swidler’s
model of the culture/action link: namely, the relative neglect of the issue of actor-level
motivation in favor of an emphasis on the situational utility of cultural “tools.” In both
cases, a pragmatist-inspired model is faulted for not specifying “what is it that exercises
the control” in a belief-formation or belief in action process (Bernstein 1971: 197). This
analytic blind-spot prevents pragmatist theorists from considering whether the actor might
not change or preserve a belief (or habit) without mitigating doubt and reconstructing a
problem-situation (Dalton 2004). For our purposes this means that pragmatism is limited
in the kind of insights it can provide about the intrasubjective causes of action.
To address this shortcoming, we draw on sources that provide us with a more robust
conception of enculturation, namely “strong” practice theory (Bourdieu 1990; Wacquant
2004; Lizardo and Strand 2010).12 Our basic proposal is that actors are durably imprinted
12
The distinction between strong practice theory and what we might call “weaker” practice theory is
that while the latter version focuses on specific social practices that are analytically distinguishable from
by the “continuous, unconscious conditioning that is exerted through conditions of
existence” (Bourdieu 1990: 50). If beliefs are unreflective habits, then not all beliefs are of
the same nature and not all beliefs are equally liable to revision via creative action. In the
same way, actors do not retain a “constant” capacity for creative retooling at all points in
the life-course (Bourdieu 2000). The accumulation of durable habits puts constraints on
the acquisition of new ones. Accordingly, rather than being immediately altered or
changed when faced with a problem-situation, habitualized beliefs lead the actor to
respond in a way that capitalizes on whatever remaining commonalities the present
situation has with previously encountered ones. This means that action capacities acquired
through “conditionalization” do remain indubitable in the pragmatist sense, or at the very
least resistant to doubt in the face of short and even medium-term situational resistance.
2.5 Practice Theory and the Durability of Belief
The rise of belief as a central concern in practice theory can be seen in the evolution of
Bourdieu’s thinking on the issue. Between the publication of the Outline of the Theory of
Practice (1977[1972]) and (its revision) The Logic of Practice (1990[1980]), Bourdieu’s
early (structuralist-inspired) concern with rule-following and strategies was almost entirely
replaced by a new focus on the unconscious schemas constitutive of “embodied belief.”
This is evidenced most clearly in the chapter added to the later book: “Belief and the
Body.”
The key contrast Bourdieu develops is between his notion of “practical belief” and both a
RAT (exemplified by Elster 1983) and voluntarist (Sartrean) philosophy of action. These
last are taken as standpoints that put conscious decision-making (either in terms of the
generation of belief ex nihilo in the existentialist case, or belief-change by “rational”
adaptation to the world in the RAT case) at the basis of an actor’s involvement with the
world. The basis of Bourdieu’s critique is that, like all normative models of action,
existentialism and RAT project an idealization of the relationship between belief and action
into their action descriptions. One way to avoid this trap is to deny that “decision” is the
default relation between actors and their commitments to either ideas or actions
individual actors (who are “carriers” of practices in this regard), strong practice theory is concerned
with a transposable capacity to practice or generalized way of practicing (see Reckwitz 2002).
(Bourdieu 1990: 46ff; Bourdieu 2000: 220). Against this, Bourdieu substitutes “belief” as
the default relation between actors and these commitments.
Thus, a committed action implies the existence of a belief that supports that action; but
the type of intrasubjectivity present here does not involve a decision to believe or act.
Rather, actors believe when they maintain a relationship of “immediate adherence” (not
“mediated” by representations) to a field of possible action (Bourdieu 1990: 68). The
notion of belief as an unverbalized disposition generative of action-commitments is not
separable from an account of belief-formation aimed at accounting for the sources of
“adhesion” to acquired beliefs. Of crucial significance is the “early and lasting insertion”
of an actor “into a condition defined by a particular degree of power [and the] experience
of the possibilities offered or denied by that condition” (Bourdieu 2000:217; see also
Martin 2011: 314ff).
Actors who are durably conditioned acquire a disposition for what Bourdieu calls “being
fundamentally realistic” (2000: 217; our italics).13 This means that actors cannot will
themselves to believe in something, or, more precisely, believe in themselves doing
something, that does not fall within the ambit of possibles available from this (formative)
position. Rather, a relationship of “immediate adherence” applies to those possibles that
appear realistic in relation to what is “statistically common to members of the same class”
(Bourdieu 1990: 60).
Based on repetitive exposure to structured regularities, beliefs “pre-reflexively [aim]” at
things that will be present in forthcoming moments. The formation of durable beliefs
from the recurrent experiential patterns that characterize an actor’s occupancy of a
position in this sense ensure that forthcoming, probable, or possible actions are made
“quasi-present” or real ex ante to her. They possess “the same belief status… as what is
directly perceived” (Bourdieu 2000:207).14
13
The sense of reality attained through attunement to “objective chances” is most readily apparent in
negative instances when people fail to acquire a “minimum hold on reality” (see Bourdieu 1979[1963]:
62-69).
14
This touches upon many issues found in longstanding debates over the “habitus” concept in
Bourdieu’s practice theory (see Lizardo 2004). Yet while the habitus is likewise formed of dispositions
that are “objectively compatible and pre-adjusted” to the conditions of its formation, here we avoid that
discussion for the same reason that Bourdieu distanced himself from his early (1977[1972];
1990[1980]) formulation of habitus. In his last statement on the notion of habitus, far removed from the
When considering action-environments that go beyond the immediate situation, we can
think of belief as indexing membership in a field, as a kind of “practical faith” that is a
condition of entry (Bourdieu 1990: 50, 66ff). In this sense, belief is the basis for taking
seriously what happens there. As it involves an anticipatory claim on what reality should
be like, this kind of faith must also remain immune to the “logic of decision” and instead
be acquired through belief-formation. To choose or decide is an “act of commission” that
takes place according to belief-based assumptions that bootstrap the actor into her
decisions by omitting all but a few possibilities from which to choose.
Outside of exceptional circumstances, actors do not rely on a reflective examination of
expected consequences in order to develop “rational anticipations” or a “rational degree of
belief” (Bourdieu 2000: 219; Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992: 131). In this respect, “[t]imes
of crises, in which the routine adjustment of subjective and objective structures [e.g.
between expectations and chances, the basis of realistic belief] is brutally disrupted,
constitute a class of circumstances when indeed ‘rational choice’ may take over, or at least
among those agents who are in a position to be rational” (Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992:
131).15 The opposition here parallels the opposition between scholastic reason (or the
absence of realism) and practical reason (or realistic belief) (see Bourdieu 2000: 12ff).
To summarize, belief is best thought of as a relational condition of pre-reflexive,
socially-patterned adherence to objects, ideas, and future sets of action. In principle, this
includes every “possible” future confronted by the actor as these possibilities are
distributed across positions in a field. Belief requires a durable level of enactive
involvement with the world shaped by it own time trajectory. Belief is also a function of
habits that are relatively malleable by creative action whenever they are disrupted (Joas
influence of the post-war Parisian intellectual field, Bourdieu (2000: 210) pares it down almost entirely
to refer to “that presence of the past in the present which makes possible the presence in the present of
the forthcoming.” In certain essential respects, belief (in its nearly analogous effect on action) replaces
the role of habitus in Bourdieu’s later work.
15
Ermakoff (2010: 541) builds on this insight when he notes the existence of a unique “decisional
conjuncture” that enables “a conscious mode of action whereby actors select a course of action after
having assessed the probable consequences of alternative options.” This formulation, however, misses
the central condition for this kind of decision-making: the absence of belief that makes a “conscious
decision” possible because it breaks the tendency toward realism (as a realistic claim on the future) and
thus enables the perception of, and reflective evaluation between, all available options (instead of only
those that are “realistic”).
1996). However, because persons acquire beliefs in a time-ordered fashion during their
lifespan, not all beliefs are created alike: some are malleable, but some are less so. Durable
beliefs exercise a conservative effect in situations that call for change before retooling or
creative adaptation can become a feasible project. In both cases, however, belief is a
constitutive aspect of action. As part of its temporal passage through environments that
(as a rule) change faster than actors can adapt, action must be exercised as (or led
forward on the tracks of) beliefs that anticipate forthcoming moments.
3 Belief-Formation, Habituation, and Asynchronicity
So far we have argued that belief is a species of (more or less) durable habit, and that
because of this durability belief may fall out of synchronicity with environmental
regularities, such that the time-scale of belief needs to be analytically and empirically
separated from the time-scale of the world. While the contrast with FP might make these
claims seem like exotic propositions, in this section we show that the pragmatist and
practice-theoretical intuitions of (1) belief as a species of habit, (2) belief-formation as a
habituation process, and (3) the durability of belief as an inertia exercised by past habits in
fast-changing present situations are redeemed by a rather unusual (but ultimately very
good to think with) line of empirical research: psychology on the dynamics of motor
cognition in infants.
4.1 A not B
Recent research in developmental psychology shows that expectations and beliefs “about”
the world are routinely formed without the need to postulate the existence of mental
models of the natural and social environments, nor the need to presume that persons
“run” those models inside their head in order to form expectations. The key theoretical
breakthrough has come from the reconsideration from a “dynamic cognition” perspective
(see Thelen and Smith 2002) of an old, well-established empirical regularity—in fact, the
most widely studied phenomenon in the entire field of developmental psychology (Thelen
and Smith 2002: 282)—first discovered by Jean Piaget in the early 1950s.
Following Piaget’s original setup (see Piaget 1954: 58), a young infant (usually between 7
and 12 months) is shown a desirable physical object (an attractive toy) which the
experimenter hides in plain view of the child (behind a small curtain or under a bucket)
located at one of two clearly visible locations (locations A and B) which contain visually
identical obstructions (a screen) or containers (a bucket) behind or within which the toy
can be hidden from view. After a short delay (usually a few seconds), the experimenter
allows the infant to search or grab for the object in order to recover it.
Not surprisingly, the infant searches at the location where she saw it hidden. The
experimenter then takes the object from the infant and once again hides it behind the
obstruction at location A. The experimenter waits for the infant to grab for and retrieve
the object again. This same sequence of events is repeated for a pre-determined number
of trials. After this number has been reached the experimenter then takes the object away
from the infant and hides it behind the obstruction at location B, while making sure that
the infant watches her do this. She then allows the child to reach for the toy again. Even
though the infant saw the object being hidden at location B, however, she invariably
reaches behind the obstruction at location A, appearing surprised (and upset!) that the
object she grabs for is not there.16
Piaget famously referred to this phenomenon—now known as the “A-not-B error”—as
evincing a lack of “object permanence” at the cognitive level and thus providing key
evidence that the adult’s conceptualization of objects is absent in the child at this stage. He
reasoned that young infants lacked a cognitive “scheme” or concept for objects, which he
defined as “the belief that objects persist in space and time independent of one’s own
perceptual and motor contact with them” (Smith 2005: 280, italics added). Infants failed
to understand that objects are self-contained totalities, which are constrained to have fixed
and mutually exclusive locations in space and remain independent from their own actions
and perceptions. According to Piaget, without this concept the sensory evidence showing
the shift in location was meaningless to the infant, as it could not be filtered through an
appropriate object scheme. Piaget’s explanation for the “A-not-B error” thus relies on the
same sort of explicit representationalist account that we have critiqued above.
4.2 Smith and Thelen’s Dynamic Cognition Approach
Smith (2005) and Thelen (2000) (see Smith et al. (1999) for a review of the evidence)
provide a more satisfactory theoretical interpretation of the phenomenon. They explain the
16
For a demonstration of the A not B paradigm, see:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?feature=player_embedded&v=lhHkJ3InQOE.
“error” as emerging from “repetitive perceptual-motor activity in novel or difficult
contexts.” In their account, “repetitive activity strengthens the memory for a particular
action, thereby increasing the likelihood that the action will be repeated again. The more
consistent and repetitive the initial perceptual-motor acts, the more likely the perseverative
behavior” (Thelen 2000: 18). Thus, in the Smith-Thelen rendering, rather than stemming
from the lack of an object scheme, the A-not-B error results from the acquisition of a set
of motor-schematic dispositions to act in particular way.
We propose that this explanation of the A-not-B error provides convergent evidence
consistent with the fundamental pragmatist insight that belief is specified as a habit that
emerges from repetitive experience. It is also consistent with the insight that beliefs are
perceptual and sensory-motor, and non-propositional in the traditional sense. In this sense,
the error occurs because past embodied expectations and “practical beliefs” about the
stability of the world are violated when the experimenter “conspires” to suddenly change
the external makeup of the situation. However, they remain ecologically rational in natural
settings where actors are able to slow down the environmental pace of change so that it
comes to correspond with their beliefs (Martin 2010).
The act of grabbing is best conceived as a motivated, belief-based judgment generated by
the infants own “projection” into the current state of affairs of a belief in a possible future,
which is conditioned to correspond at a pre-reflexive, directly embodied level with her
past experiences in that particular action context. The fact that the infant may have
perceived a change in the current setup of the phenomenally experienced world does not
help her inhibit the most powerful, already habituated belief that the object is still located
in the original A location.
In this way, success or failure in the A not B task depends on processes that occur in real
time (not in the suspended time of ideational deliberation) and which are keyed to
generating action in the world. This explanation does not require–like Piaget’s original
account did–any resort to the notion of an “object concept.” More importantly, the belief
that the object is at a given location is not a self-contained proposition stored in the
infant’s head, but an active pattern of movements, sensory stimulation and motor-schemes
activated through her presence in the local setting. The “belief” that the world is a certain
way is thus “stored” directly in the contextually habituated pattern of perception and
postural schemes that have been instantiated in the past leading up to the present
moment. This means that “the motor plan, necessary in any account of infants’ actual
performance in this task, in and of itself, implements a ‘belief’ on the part of the system
that objects persist in space and time.” In this manner, “sensory-motor processes create a
stability in the system that from the outside might look like a belief about objects but that
is instead embedded in--not mediating between--processes of perceiving and acting”
(Smith 2005: 281-282).
Importantly, Smith and Thelen note that the multiple object locations provide the infant
with “…a continuous field of decision possibilities depending on the location and differing
salience of the two targets at A and B.” In this manner we can think of the decision to
grab as “a cognitive act. It is based on motivation, recent and longer term memory, and
the qualities of the immediate visual input. It is also an embodied act” (Smith 2005: 20,
our italics). Decision-making from this perspective is not the result of reasoning from an
explicit set of beliefs that contain a “model of the world” but from treating the world as
consistent with a history of environmental conditioning.
Of course, it is conceivable that the A-not-B error is simply an artifact of the immature
cognitive system of the infant and therefore not applicable to adult cognition. However,
Thelen (2000: 24) argues that this is not the case. Instead, it, and other perceptual and
motor processes characteristic of the developing infant, should be seen “not as only stages
or weigh stations to higher forms of cognition but truly as the dynamic grounding of
cognition throughout the lifespan.” Smith (2005: 288) concurs, noting that “[t]he A not B
error may not be so important for what it tells us about infantile incompetence as for
what it tells us about cognition [in general] as fundamentally bound to the real-time bodily
processes through which we act in a physical world.”
5 A Typology of States of Belief
While the A-not-B error reveals the source of non-representational belief, it also depicts
the elementary form in which belief relates an actor to a situation through anticipation.
The effect of both successful anticipation through belief and the misfiring of belief are put
on stark display in the experiment, particularly when the infant “grabs and misses.” With
beliefs formed to anticipate the object in the A location, the infant mismatches with the
situation when the object is placed in the B location. In what follows, we build on this
rudimentary framework---which we treat as an accurate phenomenological description of
belief in action---to distinguish four types of belief-based relationship between actors and
the potentially asynchronous conditions that, as pragmatists and field theorists agree,
necessarily situate the performance of action.17 Our goal here is to offer this as a
replacement to the standard
problematic of accounting for “degrees of belief” by
focusing on the level of “commitment” actors have to a given belief-system (Rydgren
2009; Borhek and Curtis 1975). We propose instead that illusio, creativity, hysteresis and
radical doubt index different levels of fit between beliefs and situations.
Importantly, we do not eliminate the folk-psychological vocabulary, neither do we
completely collapse belief into action.18 Rather, the practical categories constitutive of the
FP intentional lexicon (“believing,” “hoping,” “wanting,” “being interested in,” “being
motivated by,” “doubting,” “being uncertain,” “second guessing”) can be rethought as
pragmatic indicators of the degree of integration between actors and their conditions of
action, in the same manner that the infant’s response to the A-not-B error reveals her
degree of belief-based integration with her conditions of action, consisting in this case of
beliefs keyed toward the A location and the object placed in either the A or B location.
Under this formulation, folk-psychological attitudes that the representationalist model
treats as antecedent causes of action become instead an experiential outcome or corollary
of empirically specifiable factors retrieved from the relation between a believing
(habituated) actor and a dynamically unfolding situation, revealing a fundamental
compatibility between these two “vocabularies of belief” (see Leschziner and Green 2013:
135). We argue that within the broader framework of belief in action, both are applicable
to two different types of belief/situation mismatch: the first involving action with a
dispositional orientation, and the second involving action with a reflexive orientation. In
this sense, our classification of ideal-typical belief-action relations only dispenses with the
substantive folk-theoretical assumption that internal mental representations must play a
role in producing normatively or culturally-sanctioned action.
17
Martin puts this well when he claims that “the only way to reach conditions we cognize and wish for
is to make use of conditions that we have not wished for” (2003: 45; see also Merleau-Ponty
2002[1962]: 509).
18
This means we recognize the “incorrigibility” of “first-person contemporaneous reports of thoughts
and sensations” (Rorty 1970: 413; see also Martin 2011: 290).
Figure 1 distributes the four types of belief-situation relationships on two axes: first,
according to whether they involve a belief/situation match (when practical beliefs
anticipate and “objectively fit” situational exigencies) or mismatch (when these beliefs
conflict with or misfire relative to those conditions); and second, whether they involve a
dispositional (prereflexive, automatic, nondeclarative) orientation to action or a reflexive
(conscious, intentional, declarative) orientation.
<<<<<<Figure 1 here>>>>>
5.1 Illusio
Illusio is the baseline (or optimal) condition in which practical beliefs self-fulfill a reality
that maintains a tight correspondence (or “ontological complicity”) with the objective
tendencies found in situations. In this regard, the actor’s belief in her capacities for action
is durable to the extent that what she “confers upon… as things” through anticipation
actually assume the “form of things” in the forthcoming moment (Merleau-Ponty 2002
[1962]: 512).19
In this condition, conscious deliberation (or deduction from explicit belief principles) does
not motivate action. Rather, action is dispositionally motivated by felt imperatives made
present through relationships in a field of action and actors with the capacity to respond
to them (Martin 2011: 270). Among other things this results in an actor’s pre-reflexive
and non-negotiable sense that her motivated action is worth doing. As Bourdieu describes
it, illusio is a “way of being in the world” that “constitutes the field [of action] as the space
of a game” (2000: 135).
The folk psychological vocabulary that fits this condition includes those traits that appear
most constitutive of the actor’s subjectivity, such as the pragmatic category of
“self-identity” (Brubaker and Cooper 2000). In addition, the trustworthiness of beliefs as
shaped by the successful interplay of habit and environment results in the (Weberian) folk
psychology of “having an interest” and being guided by a “value” (Bourdieu 1990: 66).
19
The actor doesn’t, in this sense, “grab and miss.”
These “values” should not be taken as evidence of a subjective choice on the part of the
actor or determination by a cultural model or norm-instituting structure. Rather, they
indicate a relational dynamic at work in which practical belief (temporally structured)
allows for perceptual and practical fluency toward an “end-in-view” that organizes a field
of action. The more fluent the action, the more valued the goal becomes (Reber, Schwarz
and Piotr 2004).
Thus, instead of saying that “we all strive for X because it is an instantiation of some
value,” when the condition of illusio applies it is more accurate to say that “what we call a
value is something that we happen to be striving for” (Martin 2011: 250). More generally,
identity is not a culturally-derived “self-understanding” consciously held by the actor,
presumably at all times (see Brubaker and Cooper 2000: 17). Instead, it designates her
practical sense of “social position” as acquired through belief-based participation (perhaps
only at one time) in a “non-problematic” field of action.
The “socially situated family group” is (in normal circumstances) the initial site for the
constitution of a relationship to the world with illusio (Bourdieu 2000: 164ff). The
practical beliefs that enable this initial illusio are transformed as actors move between this
“domestic field” and others. The “transformation through which one becomes a miner, a
farmer, a priest, a musician, a teacher, or an employer is long, continuous and
imperceptible...” Yet the end-state (in ideal circumstances) is a condition of illusio that
obtains in relationship to a secondary environment as a non-problematic field (Bourdieu
2000: 165). When actors have been firmly imprinted in the family with a disposition for
“being fundamentally realistic,” that end-state recovers a more primitive illusio (she feels
“in the right place”) as the actor self-fulfills a reality to which she is “as pre-adapted as
possible” (Bourdieu 1990: 61).20
5.2 Creativity
Like illusio, creativity also involves a belief-situation match, though it involves a reflexive
orientation toward action. In other words, a reality is self-fulfilled through belief in action
that is only partially pre-reflexive. Creativity is linked closely with “indeterminate” or
“unsettled” (Dewey [1938] uses the terms interchangeably) situations that lack the
20
Everything else being equal, barring transformative changes to the secondary environment or political
and economic forces that preclude the actor’s re-creative fulfillment of illusio.
certitude of illusio. A heightened degree of consciousness (or “conscious control” of
action) and deliberation characterizes this condition, as actors adapt or change habits in
order to “make concrete” deep-seated, dispositional commitments. In this sense, illusio is a
necessary condition for creativity: “No creative action would be possible without the
bedrock of pre-reflective aspirations towards which the reflection on the concretization of
values is oriented” (Joas 1996: 163).
Thus the “fundamental belief” (which Joas also classifies as “corporeal”) in a field of
action drives actors’ efforts to be creative in ways that retain a dispositional state of illusio.
For instance, chefs in a culinary field can deliberate over and develop new recipes while
not deliberating over their fundamental (and unwilled) belief in the field; actors in a sexual
field can deliberately augment their appearance in order to improve their sexual appeal
without questioning their pre-reflexive commitment to the sexual field (Leschziner and
Green 2013).
The folk psychology that applies to this condition is characterized both by attentiveness
and increased awareness of environmental affordances. As Dewey writes, the creative
“pattern of inquiry” is marked most of all by an actor having “ideas” (the passive voice is
important here): “Ideas are anticipated consequences (forecasts) of what will happen
when certain operations are executed under and with respect to observed conditions”
(Dewey 1938: 109). They involve deliberation about possible consequences. In creative
situations, actors get ideas in correspondence with a close “observation of the facts” at
hand and their suggested meanings. “The more the facts of the case come to light in
consequence of being subjected to observation, the clearer and more pertinent become
the conceptions of the way the problem constituted by these facts is to be dealt with”
(Dewey, ibid).
Elsewhere, Dewey (1905) gives the example of hearing a “fearsome noise” and not
knowing its source. The actor becomes highly attuned to her surroundings in this
situation and has ideas about what the noise might be. Ultimately she concludes that the
noise is just a shade tapping against a window and not a prowler, and is therefore
“practically indifferent to [her] welfare” (395). The actor’s heightened perception and
flow of ideas ends as her habitual engagement (as unreflected belief) in the situation
returns, and she has no further need to forecast ideas about possible scenarios (see also
Joas 1996: 128-29). A creative situation like this can last “a fraction of a second, an hour
or long years,” that is, until the indeterminacy that sparked the situation is settled once
again (Peirce 1991[1878]: 128).
But can creative situations can be willingly created or do they instead have to be sparked
by a “surprise” that leads to an unwilled dissolution of belief? We can shed light on this
question by noting that deliberate creativity is built on a foundation of prereflexive belief.
Chefs in a culinary field or players in a sexual field may be deliberately creative, but their
motivation requires an unwilled situational shift. More precisely, the motivation to be
creative is a “felt imperative” associated with a position that is threatened or undergoing
change: for instance, a competing chef comes up with a new recipe or the aging process
threatens a person’s sexual appeal (Leschziner and Green 2013).
The presumption is that creativity (even deliberate creativity) follows on the heels of a
dissolution of belief by “surprise” or, in the same manner, when a new dynamic of
imperatives is introduced into the field (Peirce 1992[1878]: 129). This removes the
realistic bias from actor beliefs (their hold on the field) by enabling their recognition of a
broader array of possibilities, thus allowing them to deliberately forecast ideas about
possible scenarios. A further instance is when actors have yet to form realistic beliefs.
This creativity is evidenced by new entrants to a field and involves breaking the “patterns
of regularity” (or “laws”) that are the aggregate effect of realistic belief in action (Martin
2011: 331; see also Gross 2009: 373).
5.3 Hysteresis
On the surface, hysteresis may seem closely related to creativity; however, where creativity
ultimately involves the effort to “concretize” or self-fulfill deep-seated aspirations that
constitute a “fundamental belief,” hysteresis is highlighted by the absence of creativity in
the face of objective forces that block a correspondence between the reality that actors
attempt to self-fulfill and the objective tendencies of the situation. In contrast to illusio,
what an actor “confers upon… as things” through anticipatory beliefs don’t assume the
“form of things” in the forthcoming moment (Merleau-Ponty 2002 [1962]: 512). As a
result, and like the habituated infant, the actor “grabs and misses.”
This kind of scenario is “most clearly seen when the sense of a probable future is belied
and when dispositions ill-adjusted to the objective changes because of a hysteresis effect
(Marx’s favorite example of this was Don Quixote) are negatively sanctioned because the
environment they encounter is too different from the the one to which they are objectively
adjusted” (Bourdieu 1990: 62; our italics).21 As actors attempt to self-fulfill a reality
“preadjusted” to specific conditions, they retain a dispositional orientation to action and
their involvement in the situation can therefore feel like illusio.
Yet that capacity to
respond to this new set of effects (dynamically structured in a field) becomes stark in this
instance, as (to an observer) what actors try to self-fulfill clashes so directly with the
objective tendencies a situation makes available or “calls for.” The practical beliefs that
allow actors to smoothly anticipate the tendencies in one objective environment act as a
sunk cost in this different environment (see Martin 2011: 266).
The “shock” that comes from this is unlike the “surprise” that applies to creativity. As
Bourdieu puts it (with the paradigmatic case of the student revolts of May ‘68 in mind),
the “hysteresis effect” does not lead to creativity that can retool a habit in the face
immediate pressures, but rather to an attitude of “total refusal… an anti-institutional cast
of mind [denunciating] the tacit assumptions of the social order, a practical suspension of
doxic adherence … and a withholding of the investments which are a necessary condition
for its functioning” (1984: 144).
The clash between practical beliefs that are “hysteretical” because they are pre-adapted to
a past environment and ill-adjusted to the present, but unable to be changed or retooled,
puts actors in a “critical state.”
This disrupts the “pre-perceptual anticipations and
expectations which form the basis of … the perceptions and actions of common sense”
(Bourdieu 1988: 182). The result is often a state of cynicism, as the actor is afforded a
“margin of freedom” from objective conditions and participates in a situation while
cognizant of how it fails belief.
Yet hysteresis also puts actors in a position in which
“critical discourses” that attempt to discursively break an “immediate adherence” to the
21
Don Quixote tilted at windmills believing he was slaying giants. Chivalry seemed possible according to
Quixote’s beliefs, and he self-fulfilled a reality guided by the archaic logic of the chivalrous quest.
Naturally he expected to be rewarded for his knight-errantry. Yet the stark incongruity between his
hysteretical beliefs and the reality of Habsburg Spain renders his behavior baffling (for Sancho) and
hilarious (for observers). Spectacularly disconfirmed in his pursuit though unable to shake his beliefs,
Quixote returns to his village to immerse himself once again in the romantic literature that formed his
beliefs and where, for this reason, he can alone “feel at home.”
world can become compelling (Bourdieu 2000: 236). However, whatever effect this
representational belief system has on action is conditional on the actor’s already having
been placed in a “critical state” because of hysteresis.
Indeed, in situations (globally)
characterized by the radical degree of mismatch found in hysteresis, other sources of
non-decisionist belief-formation, including social authority and emotional effervescence,
become particularly effective (Martin 2002; Collins 2004).
5.4. Radical Doubt
The state of radical doubt brings the actor’s disposition to be “fundamentally realistic” into
stark relief. Here, the belief-situation mismatch does not arise from beliefs that are out of
sync with the temporality of the situation (as in hysteresis), but rather from the complete
absence of a realistic commitment to the world. Without a realistic attunement to the
chances available in a situation, which provides a practical fluency with forthcoming
moments, everything seems possible, as no particular set of possibilities seem “inscribed in
the present.”
Lacking any sens de l’avenir, actors confront a fully contingent field of action and respond
with an entirely reflexive orientation to action. Able to entertain and perceive all options,
they cannot practically self-fulfill the reality of any of them (see Merleau-Ponty
2002[1962]: 507ff). In this instance, they lack the “minimum hold on the present” made
available through realistic belief “which is the precondition for a deliberate effort to take
hold of the future” (Bourdieu 1979[1963]: 69).
The folk psychological vocabulary that applies to the radical doubt condition is
characterized most of all by a wildly incoherent sense of identity---an “identity crisis”
(Brubaker and Cooper 2000: 2)---that lacks the durability and consistency of a “sense of
position.”
Actors pass easily from wild fantasy to dejected resignation, as they are not
practically sensitive to the qualities of action-environments. A kind of generalized
“anomie” applies to the condition of radical doubt, as there is no force (like sense of
position or habit) that can lend the actor a coherent subjectivity sustainable across time
(see Martin 2011: 319-20).
In contrast to hysteresis, actors do not pass into a “critical state” in this condition. Lacking
an “open and rational temporal consciousness,” they cannot develop “actions, judgments
and aspirations in relation to a life-plan.” They tend to “escape into daydreams or fatalistic
resignation” rather than entertain revolutionary aspirations (Bourdieu 1979[1963]: 62).
Radical doubt appears most often in instances of social displacement and rapid social
change.
These are instances when the objective environment changes so radically that
even hysteresis (as an attempt to preserve the past) cannot allow a relative hold on reality.
Bourdieu’s theorization of radical doubt is rooted in his ethnology of colonial Algeria
during the 1950s (see Bourdieu 1979[1963]), a time when Kabyle peasants confronted
the wholesale “uprooting” of their traditional lifestyle as a result of the “modernizing
forces” of capitalism and colonial authority, not to mention colonial war.
Ironically, the condition of radical doubt he describes shares distinct characteristics with
the “scholastic” condition, or the condition of being freed from the “immediate urgencies”
of practice and therefore able to remake the world as a “problem of representation”
(Bourdieu 2000: 16ff). This is the situation in which rational choice seems possible
because, removed from the foreclosing effects of belief, which allows commitment by
omitting options, all options can be perceived (Ermakoff 2010). However, and like radical
doubt in this respect, the scholastic “lack of realism” paralyzes action. Being aware of all
the options or (likewise) being unable to automatically omit any options in both cases
forbids a practical handhold on situations and their objective tendencies.22
6 Accounting for Belief in Action Substantive Settings
Given the largely conceptual treatment provided here, the reader may ask whether there is
a substantive explanatory incentive for going along with the seemingly counter-intuitive
approach to belief underlying this typology. More specifically, the key question becomes
whether we can retain the concept of belief while distancing it from the FP accounting
scheme’s focus on deductive logic and internal mental representation. To demonstrate that
we can, consider the following two phenomena: first, the “mystery” of why poor women
in the United States have become increasingly likely to do something that clearly goes
against “their best interest” (as conceived by the usual institutional authorities): conceiving
22
In many ways, the fictional actor of mathematical decision theory, going through all objective
possibilities in a dispassionate way, is a radical doubter. Research in the neuroscience of decision-making
reveals that such a radically “rational” actor is also a radically impaired actor. Perceiving all possibilities
as equally plausible futures results in paralysis rather than decision (Bechara and Damasio 2005).
children out of wedlock, sometimes at an age (mid to late teens) that would simply be
unthinkable to their middle-class counterparts; second, the decision of poor men
confronting the “microsocial problems” of life in the barrios of Caracas, Venezuela to
convert to Evangelical Protestantism and the mystery of whether people (like them) can
“really decide to believe in a religion because it is in their best interest to do so?” (Smilde
2007: 7).
6.1 “Choosing” to be a (Poor) Mother
Edin and Kefalas (2005: 5) have rightly referred to the first problem as the “biggest
demographic mystery of the last half of the twentieth century.”23 The question here
becomes is early childbearing an action driven by belief?
In the traditional formulation in cultural sociology, beliefs link to identity (and
subsequently motivation) as reflexive propositions that take the self as an object (“I believe
that I am…”) having explicit action projects located in the phenomenologically distant
future (e.g. “aspirations,” “goals,” “plans”). In most accounts, this reflective “belief that” is
seen as directly linked to action.
In the account that we propose, beliefs link primarily to habitualized capacities which are
normally non-reflexive and only secondarily to reflective statements of identity. In other
words, through habitualization and conditionalization persons acquire beliefs in the form
of dispositions for action (“I believe that I can…”) which need not (but may) be linked to
discursively formulated identities in order to generate coherent lines of action. In addition,
once fixated via habituation and the related acquisition of action-capacities, these beliefs
will play an independent role beyond the reflective inferences that an outside observer
might draw based on reflective beliefs communicated through language.
If belief were defined in the traditional sense (e.g. belief that conceiving children before
marriage is the right thing to do or belief that marriage is not a necessary component of
the definition of family), then this early childbearing among inner-city poor women would
not seem like a belief-driven action. After spending five years eliciting the reflexive
self-understandings of poor inner city young women, Edin and Kefalas found that these
women were no different than their middle-class counterparts (2005: 6). Most aspired to
23
And, presumably, the first decade of the 21st century.
get married and believed that an intact household was the best place to raise a child.
Holding on to the representational (or propositional) conception of belief would therefore
only deepen the mystery.
What Edin and Kefalas’s research reveals is not that the reflexive valuation of children
drives the early conception behavior; instead, most of the performative acts of valuation
are post-hoc as revealed by the fact that they invariably take the form of if-then
counterfactuals. Edin and Kefalas (2005: 11) refer to this as an “odd logic”: if I didn’t have
children, then “I’d be dead or in jail,” or “I’d still be out partying,” or “I’d be messed up
on drugs,” and so on. Children emerge as the solution to the dilemma of avoiding
pre-figured (negative) outcomes for women placed in a tough situation. This logic would
indeed be “odd” if it was descriptive of the actual decision-making process of Edin and
Kefalas’s informants.
But as we have argued, this “logic” is descriptive of nobody’s decision-making process for
the simple fact that belief does not link to the future assignment of outcome probabilities
in the way described by standard decision theory. This in fact falsifies the way belief enters
into the explanation by reversing the underlying process. For instance, in Edin and
Kefalas’s telling, the reader is invited to draw the inference that inner-city poor women are
motivated to have children early in life because children are seen as the means of avoiding
the counterfactual negative outcomes reported in the interview context. In this way, we
are right back to the flawed representationalist model of belief. Fortunately, Edin and
Kefalas’s own exemplary empirical work reveals that it is not belief as a reflective
assessment of the link between childbearing (as an action) and the “utility” associated with
the probability of two counterfactual worlds (one with children; the other without) that
drives the “decision” to have children.
First, it is clear that there is no single point at which a “decision” to have children is made.
Instead, various micro-activities joined into a single “flow of action” (e.g. front-stoop
flirting, “jumping” into unprotected sexual relationships during the early stages of
courtship) almost inexorably lead to pregnancy without childbearing arising as an explicit
goal. 24 This does not mean that childbearing is not anticipated, it is just that this
24
As Edin and Kefalas (2005: 7) note “children are seldom conceived by explicit design, yet are rarely
pure accident either.”
anticipation treats it almost as a fait accompli rather than as a phenomenologically distant
goal that requires effort, planning, and “motivation” to reach (Silver 2011).
Second, and in one of the most perceptive parts of their empirical work, Edin and Kefalas
note how the act of childbearing cannot be decoupled from a non-reflexive, habitualized
belief, acquired early in life, in the capacity to be a good (capable) mother. In this way,
while inner-city poor women may not differ much from middle-class women at the level
of reflective belief, they are worlds apart at the level of the non-reflective beliefs
underlying their capacity to mother (as an activity). This kind of belief, as we have argued,
should be kept distinct from their reflexive capacity to think of themselves “as mothers”
(as a reflexive self-identity).
Edin and Kefalas admit as much when they note that the key issue is not about belief in
culturally approved symbols (e.g. “the sanctity of marriage”) that accounts for the
“demographic mystery” of inner-city poor women’s early childbearing behavior. Instead, it
is the (usually non-reflective) belief in their capacities to mother: “In motherhood, young
women who live in the city’s hardscrabble core can find a powerful source of validation,
for they believe that childrearing is something they can be good at, a meaningful and
valued identity they can successfully realize” (Edin and Kefalas 2005: 176).
Note that in this analytic description, reflective identity is put in the right place in the
causal process as an outcome of pre-existing beliefs possessed by the actor as a set of
proficiencies for (successful, fluid) action in relation to a field (“the neighborhood”) and a
set of valued social objects (children). This interpretation is not only more empirically
consistent with the evidence, but also more phenomenologically consistent with the way in
which informants describe their own flow of action and decision-making.
6.2 Choosing to Believe
We have argued that a belief-in-action approach sidesteps the representationalist
problematic of the relation between belief and intention (or “deciding to believe”). Under
this formulation, belief-formation can never result from an act of choice, since this would
imply that persons adopt beliefs not because they have the right “reasons” but due to
extraneous consequences unrelated to the validity of the belief. This represents a problem
for representationalist (and voluntarist) accounts because it means that if a person believes
by choice, then there must be some mechanism that allows them to forget that they ever
made that choice in order for their state of belief to be genuine (Williams 1973; Bourdieu
1990: 50).
We argued that this is a misleading problematic that appears when conceptualizing belief
as an abstract representation (“propositions”) towards which persons have a given
attitude. Once belief is conceptualized as a species of habit, it is easy to see that by the
time a person is assenting to abstract propositions, they already believe in a way that is
more fundamental than assent to the abstract statement. Because belief is always rooted in
concrete situations, assent to propositional statements is always derivative and only
connected to action after the fact.
Smilde (2007: 100ff) in his exemplary study of Protestant converts in Venezuela tackles
this problematic head on. Surprisingly, he opts to confront Elster’s (1983: 51) challenge
directly, arguing that it is in fact possible to choose to believe (Smilde 2007: 8). In
Smilde’s argument, Evangelical converts, via a cultural process of narrative reconstruction,
are able to forget their decision to believe, thus meeting Elster’s (largely hypothetical)
condition for a situation in which a belief could be both intentional and binding.
Smilde’s argument is ambitious and provocative, and seemingly at odds with the enactive
approach that we advocate. However, we argue that this seeming incompatibility is more
illusion than substance. While Smilde presents his theoretical solution---cultural narratives
of supernatural agency provide a mechanism via which belief-decisions can be erased---as
an empirical conclusion from his field research, it is important to note that this conclusion
is largely speculative. Nowhere does Smilde actually witness such a memory-erasure event
if only because the very nature of the mechanism proposed (involving reconstruction from
a stated narrative) dooms it to be an ex post postulation introduced by the analyst.
Crucially, by making a cultural narrative play the “Orwellian” (Dennett 1991: 125) role of
master rewriter of the past, Smilde comes perilously close to a model of culture as a
mystifying veil hiding the subject’s own complicity in her self-deception, a formulation that
he decisively (and correctly) rejects at the outset (Smilde 2007: 10-11). Even more
importantly, Smilde’s theoretical solution is an ingenious fix applied to a non-problem: the
intention-erasure account is largely unnecessary given his own conceptualization of the
belief-formation process,
which is much closer to belief in action than to a
representationalist account.
Precisely because Smilde rejects a pure “contemplative” account of belief there is no need
to presume that persons choose to believe in the first place, and that this choice is later
elided under the weight of a supernatural agency narrative. For instance, Smilde (2007:
143) acknowledges that via the interplay of “canonicity and particularity” persons never
really assent to belief systems as abstract (representationalist) meaning systems. Instead,
the “[e]vangelical narrative predicates religious significance of the evangelistic encounter
itself.” In this respect assent to the belief system is generally “an assent to a definition of
the present situation more than an abstract leap of faith.” This assent is not contemplative,
but largely situational (Smilde 2007: 144ff).
In this respect, a more parsimonious account would take his (newly Evangelical)
informant’s phenomenological description of her belief-formation process as involving
very little subjective volition. Under this description, persons never “choose” to believe, but
are instead “called” to believe by an external force. Instead of assenting they “surrender,”
are “called,” or are “chosen” to believe (Smilde 2007: 146). These narratives, rather than
“minimizing” the individual’s responsibility for her belief, and thereby increasing that
belief’s external validity, actually point to the fact that a person ends up in a “state of
belief” precisely because by the time they reflect on the process, the external validity of the
belief is no longer problematic because it has been enacted.
7 Conclusion
In this paper, we have developed a novel conceptualization of belief that draws on
pragmatism and practice theory. Our formulation aims to move the predominant
understanding of belief away from the representationalist or folk-psychological accounting
scheme and toward one rooted in practical and embodied action in the world. In our
proposed belief in action model, the notion of belief is recast as anticipatory or
synchronized involvement in situations in which the intrasubjective sense of belief becomes
a function of the successful enactment of habit.
Belief is thus enacted in a field of
objective tendencies, constituted by the “pushes and pulls” that serve as the non-neutral or
“dynamic” conditions that provide action with an irreducible temporality.
Within this
temporal flow, actors attempt to “self-fulfill” a reality via the practical enactment of belief,
bringing to fruition something that may or may not have reality in a forthcoming moment.
Variable “degrees” of unreflective belief result from this process depending on how
successfully actors synchronize with situational tendencies. We’ve developed this
framework by showing how four ideal-typical variations in the belief-situation relationship
can be identified according to how they provide the emergent conditions for the types of
experiences tracked, with varying degrees of success, by the folk-psychological vocabulary.
One way to read our argument is as a kind of “replacement” critique of the FP accounting
scheme characteristic of almost all forms of social-scientific explanation of action. DBO
and soft rational choice theories of action are the most explicitly folk-psychological,
although the latent influence of this action-accounting scheme extends to all interpretive
approaches to the explanation of action. We argued that the most problematic feature of
folk psychology is its commitment to a representationalist “symbol manipulation” model
of cognition, in which the interaction between actor interiority and cultural systems
involves deductive logic. By contrast, our approach develops a new way of thinking about
the relationship between the actor, her capacity for action, and the conditions found in her
situation or field of action that go beyond the representationalist problematic. In this
paper, we have attempted to capture these insights by reframing the process of
belief-formation
as
non-decisionist,
involving habituation or conditionalization to
environmental characteristics and tendencies, through which actors acquire beliefs as they
acquire capacities for action.
There are two ways to judge our efforts to at least partially replace the representationalist
model of belief with belief in action. First, from a pragmatist standpoint the main problem
with folk psychology is that it functions as an indubitable principle that pins
action-explanations to a foundation (Brandom 2013). Our account attempts to establish a
critical distance from folk psychology. As Peirce would argue, doubting FP in this regard
engages the possibility of scientifically (e.g. democratically) “fixating” new criteria for
developing meaningful accounts of action. Second, and relatedly, our approach
demonstrates that the effort to establish intrasubjective validity (“at the level of meaning”)
for sociological accounts of action need not ignore “first-person” reports of action (and
even abstractions like folk psychology itself) while still objectivating them as part of social
circumstances. The Weberian ambition of rendering other subjectivities intelligible is
realized here through a non-dualistic and, we claim, empirically plausible way of making
understanding synonymous with explanation.
Figure 1. Belief/Situation Relationships and Corresponding Folk-Psychological States
References
Archer, Margaret. 1995. Realist Social Theory The Morphogenetic Approach. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Bechara, Antoine, and Antonio R Damasio. 2005. "The somatic marker hypothesis: A
neural theory of economic decision." Games and Economic Behavior 52: 336-372.
Bernstein, Richard.. 1971. Praxis and Action. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania
Press.
Bhaskar, Roy. 1998. The Possibility of Naturalism. London: Routledge.
Borhek, James and Richard Curtis. 1975. A Sociology of Belief. New York: John Wiley
& Sons.
Boudon, Raymond. 1997. “What theory of rationality for the Social Sciences: The
“cognitivist model.” Society and Economy in Central and Eastern Europe 19:
75-105.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977[1972]. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1979[1963]. Algeria 1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1984. Distinction. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1988. Homo Academicus. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1990. The logic of practice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre. 2000. Pascalian meditations. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Bourdieu, Pierre, and Loïc Wacquant. 1992. An invitation to reflexive sociology.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Brandom, Robert. 2013. “An Arc of Thought: From Rorty’s Eliminative Materialism
to his Pragmatism.” Pp. 23-31 in Richard Rorty: From Pragmatist Philosophy to
Cultural Politics. New York: Bloomsbury Press.
Brubaker, Rogers and Frederick Cooper. 2000.
Society 29: 1-47.
"Beyond ‘Identity’." Theory and
Campbell, Colin. 1996. The Myth of Social Action. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Collins, Randall. 2004. Interaction Ritual Chains. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Churchland, Paul. 1981. "Eliminative materialism and propositional attitudes." The
Journal of Philosophy 78: 67-90.
Clark, Andy and Peter Millican (eds). 1999. Connectionism, Concepts and Folk
Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Dalton, Benjamin. 2004. "Creativity, habit, and the social products of creative action:
Revising Joas, incorporating Bourdieu." Sociological Theory 22: 603-622.
Davidson, Donald. 1980. “Mental Events.” Pp. 207-225 in Essays on Actions and
Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Dewey, John. 1905. “The Postulate of Immediate Empiricism.” Journal of Philosophy,
Psychology and Scientific Methods 2: 393-399.
Dewey, John. 1938. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt.
Dewey, John. 1939. Theory of Valuation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Dilthey, Wilhelm. 1985. “The Formation of the Historical World in the Human
Sciences.” Pp. 101-174 in Wilhelm Dilthey Selected Works: Volume 3. Edited by
Rudolf Makkreel and Firthjof Rodi. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Dummett, Michael. 1996. Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Edin, Kathryn, and Maria Kefalas. 2005. Promises I Can Keep: Why Poor Women Put
Motherhood Before Marriage. Univ of California Press.
Elster, Jon. 1983. Sour Grapes: Studies in the Subversion of Rationality. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Elster, Jon. 1984. Ulysses and the Sirens: Studies in Rationality and Irrationality.
Cambridge University Press.
Emirbayer, Mustafa, and Ann Mische. 1998. "What is agency?" American Journal of
Sociology 103: 962-1023.
Ermakoff, Ivan. 2010. "Theory of practice, rational choice, and historical change."
Theory and Society 39: 527-553.
Festinger, Leon, Henry Riecken, and Stanley Schachter. 1956. When Prophecy Fails.
New York: Harper.
Fodor, Jerry.. 1987. Psychosemantics. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Geertz, Clifford. 1973. The Interpretation of Cultures. New York: Basic Books.
Geertz, Clifford. 1975. “Common sense as a cultural system.” The Antioch Review
33: 5-26.
Goldthorpe, John. 1998. “Rational action theory for sociology.” British Journal of
Sociology 49: 167-192.
Gross, Neil. 2009. "A pragmatist theory of social mechanisms." American
Sociological Review 74: 358-379.
Godfrey-Smith, Peter. 2005. "Folk psychology as a model." Philosophers’ Imprint 5:
1-16.
Habermas, Jurgen. 1971. Knowledge and Human Interests. Boston: Beacon Press.
Hedström, Peter. 2005. Dissecting the Social. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hedström, Peter and Richard Swedberg. 1996. "Social mechanisms." Acta Sociologica
39: 281-308.
Henderson, David. 1991. Interpretation and Explanation in the Human Sciences.
Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
James, William. 1983[1890]. The Principles of Psychology. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Jepperson, Ronald and John Meyer. 2011. “Multiple Levels of Analysis and the
Limitations of Methodological Individualisms.” Sociological Theory 29: 54-73.
Joas, Hans. 1993. Pragmatism and Social Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Joas, Hans. 1996. The creativity of action. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Lave, Jean. 1994. Cognition in Practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Leschziner, Vanina, and Adam Isaiah Green. 2013. "Thinking about Food and Sex:
Deliberate Cognition in the Routine Practices of a Field." Sociological Theory 31:
116-144.
Lizardo, Omar. 2004. “The cognitive origins of Bourdieu's habitus." Journal for the
Theory of Social Behaviour 34: 375-401.
Lizardo, Omar, and Michael Strand. 2010. "Skills, toolkits, contexts and institutions:
Clarifying the relationship between different approaches to cognition in cultural
sociology." Poetics 38: 205-228.
Martin, John Levi. 2011. The explanation of social action. Oxford University Press.
Martin, John Levi. 2003. "What Is Field Theory? " American Journal of Sociology
109: 1-49.
Martin, John Levi. 2002. "Power, Authority, and the Constraint of Belief Systems."
American Journal of Sociology 107: 861-904.
Mische, Ann. 2009. "Projects and possibilities: Researching futures in action."
Sociological Forum 24: 694-704.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2002[1962]. The Phenomenology of Perception. London:
Routledge.
Merton, Robert. 1948. “The Self-Fulfilling Prophecy.” The Antioch Review 8:
193-210.
Morgan, Stephen. 2005. On the Edge of Commitment. Stanford University Press.
Parsons, Talcott. 1938. “The role of ideas in social action.” American Sociological
Review 3: 652-664.
Parsons, Talcott and Edward Shils. 1951. “Values, Motives and Systems of Action.”
Pp. 47-249 in Toward a General Theory of Action. Edited by Talcott Parsons and
Edward Shils. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1992[1877]. “The Fixation of Belief.” Pp. 109-124 in The
Essential Peirce. Vol 1. Edited by Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1992[1878]. “How to Make Our Ideas Clear.” Pp. 124-142
in The Essential Peirce. Vol 1. Edited by Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1992[1880]. “On the Algebra of Logic.” Pp. 200-210 in The
Essential Peirce. Vol 1. Edited by Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1998[1905]. “What Pragmatism Is.” Pp. 331-346 in The
Essential Peirce. Vol 2. Edited by Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Piaget, Jean. 1954. The Construction of Reality in the Child. New York: Basic Books.
Reber, Rolf, Norbert Schwarz, and Piotr Winkielman. 2004. "Processing fluency and
aesthetic pleasure: is beauty in the perceiver's processing experience?." Personality
and Social Psychology Review 8: 364-382.
Reckwitz, Andreas. 2002. "Toward a Theory of Social Practices: A Development in
Culturalist Theorizing." European Journal of Social Theory 5: 243-263.
Reed, Isaac. 2011. Interpretation and Social Knowledge. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Rochberg-Halton, Eugene. 1986. Meaning and Modernity: Social Theory in the
Pragmatic Attitude. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Rorty, Richard. 1970. “Incorrigibility as the Mark of the Mental.” Journal of
Philosophy 67: 399-424.
Rosenberg, Alexander. 1995. Philosophy of Social Science. Boulder, CO: Westview.
Rydgren, Jens. 2009. “Beliefs.” Pp. 72-93 in P. Hedstrom and P. Bearman (Eds.) The
Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology. Oxford University Press.
Shapiro, Lawrence. 2011. Embodied Cognition. London: Routledge.
Silver, Daniel. 2011. "The Moodiness of Action." Sociological Theory 29: 199-222.
Smilde, David. 2007. Reason to Believe: Cultural Agency in Latin American
Evangelicalism. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Smith, Linda. 2005. “Cognition as a dynamic system: Principles from embodiment.”
Developmental Review 25: 278–298.
Smith, Linda, Esther Thelen, Robert Titzer, and Dewey McLin. 1999. “Knowing in
the context of acting: The task dynamics of the A-not-B error.” Psychological
Review 106: 235–260.
Swidler, Ann. 2001. Talk of Love: How Culture Matters. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Tavory, Iddo, and Nina Eliasoph. 2013. "Coordinating Futures: Toward a Theory of
Anticipation." American Journal of Sociology 118: 908-942.
Thelen, Esther. 2000. “Grounded in the World: Developmental Origins of the
Embodied Mind.” Infancy 1: 3-28.
Thelen, Esther and Linda Smith. 2002. A Dynamic Systems Approach to the
Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
Turner, Stephen. 1983. “Weber on Action.” American Sociological Review 38:
506-519.
Vaisey, Stephen. 2008. "Socrates, Skinner, and Aristotle: Three Ways of Thinking
About Culture in Action." Sociological Forum 23: 603-613.
Wacquant, Loïc. 2004. Body & Soul. New York: Oxford University Press.
Weber, Max. 1946. “The Social Psychology of the World Religions.” Pp. 267-302 in
From Max Weber. Edited by Hans Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Weber, Max. 1949. The Methodology of the Social Sciences. Chicago: Free Press.
Weber, Max. 1978. Economy and Society, Volume 1. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Whitford, Josh. 2002. "Pragmatism and the untenable dualism of means and ends:
Why rational choice theory does not deserve paradigmatic privilege." Theory and
Society 31: 325-363.
Williams, Bernard. 1973. “Deciding to Believe.” Pp. 136-151 in Problems of the Self.
London: Cambridge University Press.