SKENÈ
Journal of Theatre and Drama Studies
2:1 2016
C atharsis, Ancie nt and M o d e r n
SKENÈ Journal of heatre and Drama Studies
Executive Editor
General Editors
Editorial Board
Managing Editor
Assistant Managing Editor
Copyeditors
Advisory Board
Guido Avezzù.
Guido Avezzù, Silvia Bigliazzi, Alessandro Serpieri.
Simona Bruneti, Lisanna Calvi, Nicola Pasqualicchio,
Gherardo Ugolini.
Lisanna Calvi.
Francesco Lupi.
Marco Duranti, Flavia Palma, Carlo Vareschi, Tobia Zanon.
Anna Maria Belardinelli, Anton Bierl, Enoch Brater,
Jean-Christophe Cavallin, Marco De Marinis,
Tobias Döring, Pavel Drábek, Paul Edmondson, Keir Douglas
Elam, Ewan Fernie, Patrick Finglass, Enrico Giaccherini,
Mark Griith, Stephen Halliwell, Robert Henke,
Pierre Judet de la Combe, Russ McDonald,
Guido Paduano, Franco Perrelli, Didier Plassard,
Donna Shalev, Susanne Woford.
Copyright © 2016 SKENÈ
All rights reserved.
ISSN 2421-4353
No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any means
without permission from the publisher.
Andrew L. Ford*
Catharsis, Music, and the Mysteries
in Aristotle
Abstract
Of the many meanings of catharsis available to Aristotle, two have predominated in
scholarly atempts to say what the word means in the Poetics when “the catharsis of
pity and fear produced by pity and fear” is deined as the aim of tragedy. he past
thirty years have seen a concerted efort among scholars of the Poetics to overturn
Jacob Bernays’s appeal to Aristotle’s use of catharsis in his Politics (1342a10-11) with
its medical meaning of ‘purgation’ as the basis of his theory that tragedy provides a
harmless ‘outlet’ for emotions; against this, Plato’s notion of intellectual ‘puriication’
as a kind of catharsis has been invoked to argue that the workings of the tragic art
were fundamentally cognitive and resulted in the ethical ‘clariication’ of the audience.
he present essay proposes that Aristotle’s theory of tragedy was deeply informed
by another meaning of the word in his day: the ecstatic release provided by certain
mystery cults. Ater underlining Aristotle’s familiarity with such rituals, it draws on
Walter Burkert’s Ancient Mystery Cults to bring out suggestive commonalities between
mystery initiations and theatre. he ‘telestic’ ‘initiations’ (τέλη) aimed not at the
aterlife but at alleviating fears and anxieties of initiates; both their secret nocturnal
ceremonies and public choral processions were dramatic and highly theatrical, with
an essential role played by ecstasy-inducing ‘sacred tunes’. In order to discern the
relevance of telestic catharsis to the Poetics it is necessary not to focus solely on the
deinition of tragedy in chapter 6 but to appreciate the anthropological approach to
the poetic arts in chapter 4. his context supplies, if not a fully worked out model of
tragic catharsis, a broad-based explanation of how human beings might respond to
imitations of terrible things with pleasure and proit.
Olympias of Macedon, daughter of a king of Epirus and wife of Philip II,
acquired among the ancients a reputation for religious fanaticism. According
to Plutarch (Alexander, ch. 2), she stood out even among the women of
northern Greece – whence the Bacchae had descended to wreak chaos on
hebes, and where Maenads had dismembered blameless Orpheus – in
their addiction to archaic rituals connected with Orpheus and Dionysus
(ἔνοχοι τοῖς Ὀρφικοῖς οὖσαι καὶ τοῖς περὶ τὸν Διόνυσον ὀργιασμοῖς ἐκ τοῦ
πάνυ παλαιοῦ, ibid. 2.7). Olympias’s atachment to rites that brought on
ecstatic frenzy bordered on barbarism and even included furnishing tame
snakes to her fellow celebrants (ἡ δ’ Ὀλυμπιὰς μᾶλλον ἑτέρων ζηλώσασα
τὰς κατοχάς, καὶ τοὺς ἐνθουσιασμοὺς ἐξάγουσα βαρβαρικώτερον, ὄφεις
* Princeton University –
[email protected]
© SKENÈ Journal of Theatre and Drama Studies 2:1 (2016), 23-41
http://www.skenejournal.it
24
Andrew L. Ford
μεγάλους χειροήθεις ἐφείλκετο τοῖς θιάσοις κτλ., ibid. 2.9).1 Evidently an
adept snake-handler, she would join in the wild dancing at those ceremonies
with snakes entwined about her body and would provide her co-celebrants
with the same to brandish in their processions. Plutarch notes that the
spectacle was terrifying to men and speculates that this may be the reason
that Philip stopped sleeping with her.
Stories involving the parentage of great kings are bound to be politicized
and then distorted, but I am less interested in the prejudices of Plutarch’s
sources than in how Olympias’s conduct may have struck her son when he
was in his early teens. If the young Alexander were already contemplating
how to administer the empire he would soon win, he might have turned
to his tutor to ask what if anything should be done about such alarming
religious practices. Ater all, Euripides had suggested in his Bacchae, a play
composed for the Macedonian court, that an autocrat who tried to repress
the more barbarous aspects of Dionysiac cult was bound to meet disaster, and
not least when its devotees were to be found in the royal palace itself. But
Alexander’s more sober tutor was likely to have replied along the following
lines: “A susceptibility to feelings of religious ecstasy (ἐνθουσιασμός) is
something that all people are capable of feeling, just as everyone is disposed
to feel pity or fear, though people difer in the degree of their susceptibility;
now Olympias is obviously one of those people who are, so to speak, in the
grip of such states (κατοκώχιμοί), and for them the mystery rituals with
their frenzy-inducing sacred tunes (ἱερὰ μέλη) produce a catharsis that
puts them back on their feet again ater violently arousing their emotions
(ἐξοργιάζουσι), almost as if they had gone to a doctor and been treated for
an ailment; and along with the relief comes a certain pleasure. Everyone can
feel a kind of katharsis (τινα κάθαρσιν) at that kind of music, along with a
pleasant feeling of relief, to one degree or another; ater all, music has the
power even to charm snakes. But the resultant pleasure is harmless, a feeling
of relief, and is nothing for a prince to trouble himself over very much. Still,
if one desires a more thorough account of these maters, one might consult
my works on poetry”.
Alexander’s tutor, of course, was Aristotle, and the response above is,
I submit, a fair pastiche of a famous passage from the seventh chapter of
Politics book 8 in which the philosopher discusses which kinds of tunes and
musical modes (harmoniai) are to be permited in a well organized state (8.7,
1341b32-1342a18):
ἐπεὶ δὲ τὴν διαίρεσιν ἀποδεχόμεθα τῶν μελῶν ὡς διαιροῦσί τινες τῶν ἐν
φιλοσοφίᾳ, τὰ μὲν ἠθικὰ τὰ δὲ πρακτικὰ τὰ δ’ ἐνθουσιαστικὰ τιθέντες, καὶ
My translation adapts Perrin’s Loeb 1919: 228-9. On Olympias, see Carney 2006: ch.
6, esp. 93-4. All translations from Greek are mine unless otherwise stated.
1
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
25
τῶν ἁρμονιῶν τὴν φύσιν <τὴν> πρὸς ἕκαστα τούτων οἰκείαν, ἄλλην πρὸς
ἄλλο μέλος, τιθέασι, φαμὲν δ’ οὐ μιᾶς ἕνεκεν ὠφελείας τῇ μουσικῇ χρῆσθαι
δεῖν ἀλλὰ καὶ πλειόνων χάριν (καὶ γὰρ παιδείας ἕνεκεν καὶ καθάρσεως – τί
δὲ λέγομεν τὴν κάθαρσιν, νῦν μὲν ἁπλῶς, πάλιν δ’ ἐν τοῖς περὶ ποιητικῆς
ἐροῦμεν σαφέστερον – τρίτον δὲ πρὸς διαγωγὴν πρὸς ἄνεσίν τε καὶ πρὸς
τὴν τῆς συντονίας ἀνάπαυσιν), φανερὸν ὅτι χρηστέον μὲν πάσαις ταῖς
ἁρμονίαις, οὐ τὸν αὐτὸν δὲ τρόπον πάσαις χρηστέον, ἀλλὰ πρὸς μὲν τὴν
παιδείαν ταῖς ἠθικωτάταις, πρὸς δὲ ἀκρόασιν ἑτέρων χειρουργούντων καὶ
ταῖς πρακτικαῖς καὶ ταῖς ἐνθουσιαστικαῖς. ὃ γὰρ περὶ ἐνίας συμβαίνει πάθος
ψυχὰς ἰσχυρῶς, τοῦτο ἐν πάσαις ὑπάρχει, τῷ δὲ ἧττον διαφέρει καὶ τῷ
μᾶλλον, οἷον ἔλεος καὶ φόβος, ἔτι δ’ ἐνθουσιασμός· καὶ γὰρ ὑπὸ ταύτης τῆς
κινήσεως κατοκώχιμοί τινές εἰσιν, ἐκ τῶν δ’ἱερῶν μελῶν ὁρῶμεν τούτους,
ὅταν χρήσωνται τοῖς ἐξοργιάζουσι τὴν ψυχὴν μέλεσι, καθισταμένους ὥσπερ
ἰατρείας τυχόντας καὶ καθάρσεως· ταὐτὸ δὴ τοῦτο ἀναγκαῖον πάσχειν καὶ
τοὺς ἐλεήμονας καὶ τοὺς φοβητικοὺς καὶ τοὺς ὅλως παθητικούς, τοὺς δ’
ἄλλους καθ’ ὅσον ἐπιβάλλει τῶν τοιούτων ἑκάστῳ, καὶ πᾶσι γίγνεσθαί τινα
κάθαρσιν καὶ κουφίζεσθαιμεθ’ ἡδονῆς.
[Since we accept the classiication of tunes made by some philosophers into
the ones expressive of ethical states, the action-oriented, and those arousing
religious passion (ἐνθουσιαστικά), with the various harmoniai assigned to
them according to their natural kinship with each, and since we say that
music ought to be employed not for the sake of a single beneit but for several
(for it serves the purpose of education and of catharsis – the term catharsis
we use for the present without elaboration but will discuss it more fully in
the work on poetry – and, thirdly, for occasions of leisure to provide relief
and release of stress), it is therefore clear that we should make use of all the
harmoniai, but not all in the same way; the most ethical ones should be used
for education, and the active and passion-arousing kinds for listening to when
others are performing. For any experience that occurs violently in some souls
is found in all, though with diferent degrees of intensity—for example pity
and fear, and also religious ecstasy (ἐνθουσιασμός); for some persons are
especially susceptible (κατοκώχιμοί) to this form of emotion, and under the
inluence of the sacred tunes (ἱερὰ μέλη) we see these people, when they use
tunes that thoroughly arouse the soul’s emotions (ἐξοργιάζουσι), being put
back on their feet as if they had received medical treatment and been purged
(ὥσπερ ἰατρείας τυχόντας καὶ καθάρσεως); the same experience then must
come also to the compassionate and the timid and to other emotional people
in general in such degree as befalls each individual of these classes, and all
must undergo a kind of katharsis (τινα κάθαρσιν) and a pleasant feeling of
relief. (Trans. by H. Rackham, adapted)]
he passage is famous because its discussion of catharsis is the best gloss
we have from Aristotle himself on the meaning of that word in the Poetics,
where it caps the deinition of tragedy in chapter 6 (1449b22-7):
περὶ δὲ τραγῳδίας λέγωμεν ἀναλαβόντες αὐτῆς ἐκ τῶν εἰρημένων τὸν
26
Andrew L. Ford
γινόμενον ὅρον τῆς οὐσίας. ἔστιν οὖν τραγῳδία μίμησις πράξεως σπουδαίας
καὶ τελείας μέγεθος ἐχούσης, ἡδυσμένῳ λόγῳ χωρὶς ἑκάστῳ τῶν εἰδῶν ἐν
τοῖς μορίοις, δρώντων καὶ οὐ δι’ ἀπαγγελίας, δι’ ἐλέου καὶ φόβου περαίνουσα
τὴν τῶν τοιούτων παθημάτων κάθαρσιν.
[Let us speak about tragedy, taking up from what we have said a deinition
of its nature: tragedy, then, will be an imitation2 of an action that is serious
and complete, having some magnitude, with seasoned language employed
separately in its separate parts, with the performers acting and not narrating,
bringing to completion through pity and fear the catharsis of such emotions.]
Although Aristotle promised in the Politics a “fuller discussion of catharsis in
the work on poetry”,3 this brief mention is, apart from a passing reference to
Orestes’ ritual ‘puriication’ (1455b15), the only occurrence of the term in the
Poetics. And yet an understanding of the concept it names seems to be crucial
to understanding the Poetics since its use here implies that the “catharsis of
pity and fear” is something of a inal cause for Aristotle, naming the function
that tragedy, and by extension poetry, serves in human life. Accordingly,
what the catharsis in Poetics chapter 6 means has been a source of contention
since the Renaissance, with some holding that tragedy ‘purges’ us of harmful
and unwanted emotions and others arguing it ‘puriies’ and even ‘clariies’
our moral sentiments; in this debate much has turned on the question of how
to apply the evidence from Politics or even whether to apply it at all.
In the passage quoted from Politics 8.7, Aristotle is concerned to argue
that those kinds of rhythms, modes and melodies that were classiied by
the musical experts of his day as arousing religious frenzy (ἐνθουσιαστικά,
1341b34) have their uses in civic life, but such music is not appropriate
everywhere. For example, he had argued earlier in the book that in school
such music, along with the aulos on which it was played, actually interfered
with learning; he says that the aulos, a reed instrument the Greeks found
passionately arousing, produces “a passionate rather than ethical experience
in its auditors and so should be used on those occasions that call for catharsis
rather than learning”,4 It would seem, then, that the business of enthusiastic
2
I use the term ‘imitate’ and its congeners merely as a convenience to designate
the family of words related to μιμεῖσθαι. his is not to deny the obvious fact that in
Aristotle’s conception the ‘mimetic arts’ are arts of representing people in action, not
‘copying’ them.
3
Pol. 1341b38-40: τί δὲ λέγομεν τὴν κάθαρσιν . . . ἐν τοῖς περὶ ποιητικῆς ἐροῦμεν
σαφέστερον.
4
Ibid. 1341a17-24: ἔτι δὲ οὐκ ἔστιν ὁ αὐλὸς ἠθικὸν ἀλλὰ μᾶλλον ὀργιαστικόν, ὥστε
πρὸς τοὺς τοιούτους αὐτῷ καιροὺς χρηστέον ἐν οἷς ἡ θεωρία κάθαρσιν μᾶλλον δύναται
ἢ μάθησιν. Excellent commentary on the passages from the Politics is provided by Kraut
1997: 192-3, 202, 208-12.
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
27
music was a lot more like rock and roll than like Bach.5 Hence it is worrying to
some that following our passage from 8.7 the preeminent example Aristotle
gives of an occasion that calls for “catharsis rather than learning” (κάθαρσιν
μᾶλλον . . . ἢ μάθησιν) is the theatre: in the sequel to the passage quoted
Aristotle explains that where enthusiastic music on the aulos will provide a
kind of relief (πρὸς ἀνάπαυσιν) for the spectators (8.7, 1342a16-22):
διὸ ταῖς μὲν τοιαύταις ἁρμονίαις καὶ τοῖς τοιούτοις μέλεσιν ἐατέον
<χρῆσθαι> τοὺς τὴν θεατρικὴν μουσικὴν μεταχειριζομένους ἀγωνιστάς·
ὁ θεατὴς διττός, ὁ μὲν ἐλεύθερος καὶ πεπαιδευμένος, ὁ δὲ φορτικὸς ἐκ
βαναύσων καὶ θητῶν καὶ ἄλλων τοιούτων συγκείμενος, ἀποδοτέον ἀγῶνας
καὶ θεωρίας καὶ τοῖς τοιούτοις πρὸς ἀνάπαυσιν.
[herefore harmoniai and tunes of this (kathartic, ‘enthusiastic’) kind must
be allowed for those who deal with music as professionals in the theatre; for
the audience is double, partly free and educated and partly vulgar, composed
of cratsmen and labourers and the like; performances and spectacles should
be provided for the later sort to give them relaxation.]
As Aristotle, with an unappealing jaundiced eye, sees it: working for others
and trading with all comers have a distorting efect on soul that warps its
evaluation of what is pleasurable; nonetheless, he thinks labourers deserve
in their leisure a music that “produces the pleasure that is naturally suited
to their natures”.6
he discussion of ritual catharsis in the context of theatre in Politics 8
has engendered a controversy especially since Jacob Bernays (1857) used it
to argue for an ‘outlet’ theory of catharsis, taking advantage of Aristotle’s
description of the efects of musical catharsis as “like receiving medical
treatment and being purged” (1342a10-11: ὥσπερ ἰατρείας τυχόντας
καὶ καθάρσεως). Bernays’ model of purging excessive feelings has been
criticized for its un-Aristotelian, negative view of the emotions and for its
un-Aristotelian reliance on a homeopathic model of medicine; but to my
mind his essay remains nonetheless a powerful rebutal to more recent
atempts to atribute to Aristotle, as many scholars since have been wont
to do, a view of tragic catharsis as an essentially cognitive process in which
the spectator experiences an ethical ‘clariication’, to borrow, as this view
does, a metaphorical use of catharsis in Plato.7 In short, there is a return to
Schadewaldt (1955: 153) takes the passage quoted from Pol. in the previous note
as a decisive refutation of the idea that the experience of tragedy reines our moral
sentiments; so too Ford 2004: 325-8. For modern atempts to resist this conclusion
see Lord 1982: 112, Janko 1987: 182-3.
5
6
7
Arist. Pol. 1342a25-6: ποιεῖ δὲ τὴν ἡδονὴν ἑκάστοις τὸ κατὰ φύσιν οἰκεῖον.
E.g. Soph. 227c. 230c; Phaedo 67c, 69b; cf. Golden 1992 and Nussbaum 1992: 270, 273.
28
Andrew L. Ford
a Lessing-like view that the inal cause of poetry for Aristotle is a moral
kind of catharsis in the sense of ‘puriication’.8 his return would seem to be
ruled out if we understand the catharsis provided by tragedy in the Poetics
in terms of the cathartic, enthusiastic music of religious ritual described
in the Politics, for in a suggestive fragment Aristotle is said to have held
that the purpose of undergoing mystic initiation is not to learn anything
(μαθεῖν) but to experience something (παθεῖν), to undergo a change of
mental state (διατεθῆναι) that enables one to cope with life.9 Rather than
going into the Politics again in detail (see Ford 2004), I wish to see what
diference it makes if we relect that of the many meanings that catharsis
could bear – simple cleaning, ritual cleansing, medical purgation10 – ritual
catharsis through music was an experience with which the Stargirite was
quite familiar. I propose that Bernays was right to reject Lessing’s view
of tragedy as ‘a moral house of correction’, but we need not take on the
physiological reductiveness of Bernays’ model (Destrée 2011: 49-51); ater
all, medical purgation is only an analogy in Politics 8 (ὥσπερ). But puting
Aristotle’s account of ritual catharsis beside the Poetics highlights suggestive
commonalities between mystery initiations and theatre, and should at
the least make us hesitate before projecting onto Aristotle an enlightened
disdain for such barely civilized religious impulses. Finally, I will address the
more important objections that have been raised against bringing the ritual
perspective of the Politics into the Poetics.
he mystical ceremonies Plutarch describes were focused on Dionysus
and his votary Orpheus, while Aristotle’s mention of the ‘sacred tunes’ of
Olympus points rather to the rites of the Great Mother by her atendants,
the Corybants.11 But both Bacchants and Corybants belong to the same subgroup of sacramental mystery rites called ‘telestic’; these were ‘initiations’
(τέλη) in which ‘ministrants’ (τελοῦντες) invoked divine powers to serve the
needs of ‘initiands’ (τελούμενοι) (Linforth 1946; Dodds 1957: 77-80). We get
a fuller picture of such rites as they were conducted in Athens at about the
same time from Demosthenes’s On the Crown of 330 BC.
Aeschines, Demosthenes’ opponent, had a mother something like
Olympias and On the Crown mocks him for helping her with her initiations.
Recent interpretations with bibliography of catharsis as leading to moral
improvement: Halliwell 2011: 236-60; 2002: 172-6. Dissenting voices include Lear (1988)
and Ferrari (1999).
9
Arist. fr. 15, Rose: καθάπερ Ἀριστοτέλης ἀξιοῖ τοὺς τελουμένους οὐ μαθεῖν τι δεῖν
ἀλλὰ παθεῖν καὶ διατεθῆναι, δηλονότι γενομένους ἐπιτηδείους. Cf. Burkert 1987: 69, 89.
10
For recent studies of the ritual and medical meanings of catharsis in Aristotle’s day,
see Hoessly (2001) and Vöhler and Seidensticker (2007).
11
Pol. 8.7, 1342a8-9: ἐκ τῶν δ᾽ ἱερῶν μελῶν; cf. 1340a8-14 on the aulos tunes of
Olympus, which were acknowledged to make listeners ecstatic.
8
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
29
According to Demosthenes, Aeschines read a sacred book while she performed
the ritual and helped the celebrants with their preparations, which involved
ritual cleansing (καθαίρων), libations, dressing in fawn-skins and carrying
sacred paraphernalia. As for the actual ceremonies involved, Walter Burkert
has ofered a speculative reconstruction:12 the nocturnal rite was private and
began with the initiands seated by a mixing bowl and smeared with mud;
out of the dark an initiatory priestess appeared as if a terrifying demon; once
cleansed, the initiates rose to their feet and exclaimed “I escaped from evil, I
have found the beter” (ἔφυγον κακόν, εὗρον ἄμεινον), to which by-standing
participants like Aeschines added the ritual high piercing cry (ololyge) as
though greeting the epiphany of a divine being. he sacred drama was
followed on the next day by a public one as the group of celebrants formed
a sacred band (thiasos) and paraded through the streets carrying their sacred
objects; garlanded and brandishing snakes above their heads, they cried out
mystical sacred names, Euoi and Saboi; their dancing and their triumphant
rhythmic cries proclaimed that “terror ha[d] become manageable for the
initiate” (Burkert 1987: 97).
Both the fearful ceremonies of the night before and the public choral
performance on the following day are highly theatrical, with a close
“interdependence of performers and onlookers” in both cases (ibid.: 113).
And accompanying it all was a special kind of music designed to induce the
state of enthusiasmos in initiates: the ‘sacred tunes’ atributed to the mythical
composer Olympus of Phrygia were played on the arousing Phrygian aulos
to an insistent rhythm provided by drums, tambourines, and cymbals; the
combination of music, singing, shouting, and dance brought the initiands
into a state in which they felt themselves to be possessed. At the end of
it all, the initiates had a feeling of “calm and tranquillity and their minds
were at peace” (Linforth 1946: 156). his was a life-changing experience
for those being initiated as well as a stirring (and apparently alarming)
one to onlookers. It remains to ask, however, how far Aristotle thought the
psychological experience in initiatory ritual was comparable to the catharsis
of pity and fear in the theatre of Dionysus. We begin with describing the
efects atributed to telestic rites.
Scholars of Greek religion place the rituals with which we have been
concerned in a special class of rites whose function was not solely to honour
gods but to invoke their powers to secure beneits meeting speciic needs
of the ‘initiands’ (τελούμενοι) (Linforth 1946: 155; Burkert 1987: 18-19). In
contrast to, for example, the Eleusinian mysteries which prepared initiates
for the aterlife, the teletai associated with Dionysus and the great Mother
Burkert 1987: 96-7, combining On the Crown 18.259-60 with False Embassy 19.199,
249, 281.
12
30
Andrew L. Ford
ofered practical beneits in this life: health, wealth, and good fortune
were promised, and in addition the initiatory ceremony itself provided, as
Aristotle intimates, a kind of therapeutic relief from some undeined psychic
distress. Indeed Burkert (1987: 97, 113) speaks of these mysteries as inducing
a “psychic transformation” and “a veritable change of consciousness” in the
participants.13 As evidence for the psychology underlying Aristotle’s musical
catharsis Burkert (ibid.: 113) cites a text on music by the late author Aristides
uintilianus:14
διὸ καὶ τὰς βακχικὰς τελετὰς καὶ ὅσαι ταύταις παραπλήσιοι λόγου τινὸς
ἔχεσθαί φασιν, ὅπως ἂν ἡ τῶν ἀμαθεστέρων πτοίησις διὰ βίον ἢ τύχην ὑπὸ
τῶν ἐν ταύταις μελῳδιῶν τε καὶ ὀρχήσεων ἅμα παιδιαῖς ἐκκαθαίρηται.
[Accordingly they say that there is a certain logic to Bacchic and similar rites
whereby the feelings of anxiety (πτοίησις) felt by less educated people, caused
by their way of life or some misfortune, are cleared away (ἐκκαθαίρηται)
through the melodies and dances of the ritual in a joyful and playful way.]
Aristides supports Aristotle’s recommendation in Politics to use ‘enthusiastic’
music in the theatre as a way of giving relief to the lower sorts of spectators;
but the case of Olympias shows that cratsmen and non-citizen labourers
were not the only clients for initiatory experts (οἱ τελοῦντες). Plato can add
to the picture, for, as I.M. Linforth (1946: 154-7) showed, the Corybantic
rites were familiar to Plato and his readers. In the Phaedrus Socrates praises
those forms of madness whose source is not pathological but divine. he
forms of “divine madness” include poetic inspiration, divine prophecy and
the madness which cures “diseases and the greatest suferings in certain
families, on account of some ancient cause of wrath”.15 When Plato speciies
that these suferings tend to run in certain families that incurred divine
wrath in the distant past, we hear I think the explanations purveyed by the
itinerant priests, the argutai and manteis, who sought wealthy patrons in old
Athenian families. In contemporary terms we would say that a susceptibility
to anxiety and nervous disorders that can be cured by rites of initiation
appears to be a genetic disposition running in certain families for whom a
form of psychotherapy can alleviate the efects of trauma buried in the past.
Bukert compares (1987: 97) Plato’s description in Republic 560d-e of how an
oligarchic personality can be converted to a democratic one as a kind of mystical process:
an emptying of the soul and a puriication (κενώσαντες καὶ καθήραντες) atended by a
jubilant chorus crowned with wreaths. On the ith-century background to the tragic
emotions in Plato and Aristotle, see Cerri 2007: 78-95.
14
Aristides uintilianus, 3.25.14-19; see Barker 1989: 531. On translating πτοίησις in
the text as “anxiety”, see Burkert 1987: 171, n. 156.
15
Phaedr. 244d: νόσων γε καὶ πόνων τῶν μεγίστων, ἃ δὴ παλαιῶν ἐκ μηνιμάτων
ποθὲν ἔν τισι τῶν γενῶν. Cf. Phaedr. 265b, Laws 815c and Burkert 1987: 19.
13
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
31
Here we can turn at last to the Poetics and ask what the tragic “catharsis
of pity and fear produced by pity and fear” has in common with “the
thoroughgoing arousal of violent emotion and the feeling of relief mixed
with joy that comes over all who resort to telestic rites” (Pol. 1342a14-15). On
this question I believe that progress is to be made not by bearing down once
again on the notorious deinition of tragedy on chapter 6 and trying to limit
catharsis to a single technical sense, but by turning to chapter 4, Aristotle’s
excursus into the origins of the poetic arts as a whole. Ater establishing
the kinds and forms that the poetic art has assumed in his day through
an inductive diaeresis illing chapters 1-3, Aristotle turns in chapter 4 to
consider how poetry arose, a subtle speculation that I will take up in three
chunks. He begins (1448b4-9):
Ἐοίκασι δὲ γεννῆσαι μὲν ὅλως τὴν ποιητικὴν αἰτίαι δύο τινὲς καὶ αὗται
φυσικαί. Τό τε γὰρ μιμεῖσθαι σύμφυτον τοῖς ἀνθρώποις ἐκ παίδων ἐστὶ καὶ
τούτῳ διαφέρουσι τῶν ἄλλων ζῴων ὅτι μιμητικώτατόν ἐστι καὶ τὰς μαθήσεις
ποιεῖται διὰ μιμήσεως τὰς πρώτας, καὶ τὸ χαίρειν τοῖς μιμήμασι πάντας.
[It is probable to suppose that two causes brought about the art of poetry in
general, and these were natural ones. For imitating is an inborn activity of
human beings from childhood, and they difer from all other animals in being
the most imitative of all and they learn their irst lessons from mimesis, and
everyone enjoys imitations.]
he crucial feature of this discussion is that Aristotle takes an anthropological
approach to poetry. he anthropologist looks for ‘causes’ (aitiai) that are rooted
in human nature, and Aristotle does not even mention the old traditions that
poetry was a git of the Muses or Apollo. He hits on two primary causes of
poetry: our natural instincts to imitate and to take pleasure in imitations. For
poetry to have arisen naturally it was necessary not only that homo sapiens
be natural imitators, but also that that they take pleasure in the imitations of
others, for a poet needs an audience. Aristotle is speculating here (ἐοίκασι)
on maters of great antiquity, but he has reasons to give in support of his
assumptions. As proof that human beings are natural imitators he points to
the fact that children irst learn by imitating; the fact that this is the way we
get our irst lessons (τὰς μαθήσεις . . . τὰς πρώτας) suggests that imitating is
instinctive rather than learned behaviour.
To conirm the second proposition, that everyone enjoys imitations,
Aristotle reasons from everyday experience (1448b9-19):
σημεῖον δὲ τούτου τὸ συμβαῖνον ἐπὶ τῶν ἔργων· ἃ γὰρ αὐτὰ λυπηρῶς ὁρῶμεν, τούτων τὰς εἰκόνας τὰς μάλιστα ἠκριβωμένας χαίρομεν θεωροῦντες,
οἷον θηρίων τε μορφὰς τῶν ἀτιμοτάτων καὶ νεκρῶν. αἴτιον δὲ καὶ τούτου, ὅτι
μανθάνειν οὐ μόνον τοῖς φιλοσόφοις ἥδιστον ἀλλὰ καὶ τοῖς ἄλλοις ὁμοίως,
ἀλλ’ ἐπὶ βραχὺ κοινωνοῦσιν αὐτοῦ. διὰ γὰρ τοῦτο χαίρουσι τὰς εἰκόνας
32
Andrew L. Ford
ὁρῶντες, ὅτι συμβαίνει θεωροῦντας μανθάνειν καὶ συλλογίζεσθαι τί ἕκαστον, οἷον ὅτι οὗτος ἐκεῖνος· ἐπεὶ ἐὰν μὴ τύχῃ προεωρακώς, οὐχ ᾗ μίμημα
ποιήσει τὴν ἡδονὴν ἀλλὰ διὰ τὴν ἀπεργασίαν ἢ τὴν χροιὰν ἢ διὰ τοιαύτην
τινὰ ἄλλην αἰτίαν.
[And experience afords a sign of the truth of this [that we enjoy imitations]:
for images of things that we look upon with pain give us pleasure to
contemplate when they are very precisely rendered, for example, the shapes
of disgusting animals and of corpses. And the cause of this is that learning
is not only extremely pleasant for philosophers, but for others too, though
they share in it only to a litle extent. For this reason people are pleased when
they look at images, because it is possible for them to learn something as they
consider them (θεωροῦντας), and to deduce (συλλογίζεσθαι) what each thing
is, for example that this man is that man (οὗτος ἐκεῖνος). Since, if someone
happens not to have seen (the thing represented) before, the imitation will
not please qua imitation, but on account of its ine workmanship or colouring
or some other such cause.]
Aristotle has observed no person who does not like imitations and infers that
this is because it is always atended by a form of learning, for “all people have
a natural appetite to understand” and “learning is naturally sweet”.16 But in
explaining the pleasure we take in imitations as a kind of learning Aristotle
opens a door for those who would say that, despite what is suggested in the
Politics, the Poetics advances a theory of art which holds that the pleasure
tragedy gives is one of learning something about the world. If imitations
please us because they aford a kind of learning, it might follow that the
true aim of the imitative arts is to teach. When one adds that the diference
between poetry and history is that poetry represents not particular facts
but the kinds of things that happen (ch. 9), the pleasure tragedy gives its
audience may be that of learning (even ‘deducing’, on a narrow construction
of sullogizesthai) paterns of human behaviour from the structured plots of
plays. his is a widespread current understanding of the Poetics.17
But such views misconstrue this passage by making the process too
intellectual. Aristotle’s use of θεωροῦντας for ‘considering’ an image is not
16
Metaphys. 980a.21: πάντες ἄνθρωποι τοῦ εἰδέναι ὀρέγονται φύσει. Cf. Rhet. 1371b41: “learning is sweet, as is wondering . . . as it leads to learning” (ἐπεὶ δὲ τὸ μανθάνειν τε
ἡδὺ καὶ τὸ θαυμάζειν . . . ὥστε μανθάνειν τι συμβαίνει). Plato similarly deined ‘wonder’
as “the peculiar pathos of the philosopher”: μάλα γὰρ φιλοσόφου τοῦτο τὸ πάθος, τὸ
θαυμάζειν: heaet. 155d.
17
E.g. Golden (1992: 5-29) and Keesey (1979), both proposing a very intellectualist
account of tragic pleasure (see Nussbaum 1992: 281); more nuanced, though still fundamentally cognitive, versions of how viewing tragedies can lead to ethical development
are Halliwell 1986: 198-9; 2002: 177-88, 221; Janko 1987: 187; 2011: 372-7; Beliore 1992:
345-53; Nussbaum 1992; Depew 2007. For a penetrating critique of these approaches, see
Destrée 2011.
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
33
to be confused with philosophical ‘contemplation’, θεωρία, the highest form
of human intellection (Eth. Nic. 10.8, 9). Nor does sullogizesthai point to some
rigorous process of reasoning. All that Aristotle seems to have in mind is
that when we ‘consider’ a portrait we ‘deduce’ in the sense of igure out that
it is meant to represent a particular person (or thing) in the world, as ‘that
painting is a painting of Socrates’. Aristotle’s phrase ‘this man is that man’
(οὗτος ἐκεῖνος) is not to be glossed as the formal conclusion of a conscious
process of reasoning, as ‘QED’; it is more like an ‘Aha!’ prompted by a sudden
realization: in the Rhetoric the best metaphors provoke a quick recognition
that “this thing is that thing” (τοῦτο ἐκεῖνο: Rhet. 3.10, 1410b19); in comedy,
it is a colloquial exclamation that can be glossed ‘Jesus, Maria und Joseph’
(Radermacher 1954: 327 on Frogs 318). he expression is suggestively used
by Plato in connection with the mysteries at the climax of Diotima’s long
speech to ‘initiate’ Socrates into the mysteries of love in the Symposium
(209e-210e; cf. Burkert 1987: 153, n. 13): “this is that” (τοῦτο ἐκεῖνο) says
Diotima at the moment when the much-labouring initiate inally realizes
the object of the his or her toils, the inal vision of love. his demotic, quasimystical reaction is closer to what is experienced by those who, in Aristotle’s
eyes, have but a moderate love of learning. It is a basic operation, but it is
one that can go missing, as in Aristotle’s following counterexample in which
spectators consider a painting or sculpture of an object with which they
are unfamiliar: such persons may enjoy the colours of the paintings or the
working of the bronze for their own sake, but they will be unable to treat
the object on a basic level as an imitation of something they know. Aristotle
makes the same point a litle later when he says, “if someone smeared the
most beautiful pigments on a surface at random, he will not give as much
pleasure as one who executes an image in black and white”.18
It has been objected that to identify the subject of a painting is not learning
much, and that we should rather see here an intimation of an idea drawn
out of chapter 9, that because poetry is more concerned with universals
than history it can be the occasion of a kind of philosophical learning. On
this view, we do more than learn this painting is of that original but learn
something general about the original (Else 1957: 132; Dupont-Roc and Lallot
1980: 165; Sifakis 1986: 216; Halliwell 2001: 90-3). But in chapter 4 Aristotle
is expressly thinking of learning at a general, low level that is available to all,
for the point he is proving is that “everyone delights in imitations” (cf. Lear
1988: 307). As Malcolm Heath (2009a: 63-4) has observed, the function of the
verb sullogizesthai is to mark this kind of pleasure in imitations as one that
is available only to human beings. (Were it otherwise, mimetic animals like
1450a39-50b3: εἰ γάρ τις ἐναλείψειε τοῖς καλλίστοις φαρμάκοις χύδην, οὐκ ἂν
ὁμοίως εὐφράνειεν καὶ λευκογραφήσας εἰκόνα.
18
34
Andrew L. Ford
apes would have developed imitative arts.) Chapter 4, then, does explain our
enjoyment (chairein) of imitations by taking it as a form of learning, but we
are not justiied in assuming that learning is the essential or sole pleasure
that imitations may aford. Moreover, individuals will vary greatly in the
pleasure they take in learning: in Poetics 4 and in a passage from Parts of
Animals (645a7-17) oten cited with it, Aristotle makes a distinction between
the common, popular pleasure in learning and the rarer pleasures taken by
those who are “by nature” philosophers. No doubt Aristotle thought learning
a very great pleasure, but it is one restricted to few (see Ford 2015: 15-17).
A small amount of love of learning is all that is needed for spectators to
assent to a mimetic illusion and say, “hat’s Agamemnon!” and thereater
to be open to tragedy’s proper pleasure of arousing pity and fear through
imitating his rise and fall.
he inal chunk of Aristotle’s speculation into the origins of poetry picks
up from where he let of (1448b20-4):
κατὰ φύσιν δὲ ὄντος ἡμῖν τοῦ μιμεῖσθαι καὶ τῆς ἁρμονίας καὶ τοῦ ῥυθμοῦ
(τὰ γὰρ μέτρα ὅτι μόρια τῶν ῥυθμῶν ἐστι φανερὸν) ἐξ ἀρχῆς οἱ πεφυκότες
πρὸς αὐτὰ μάλιστα κατὰ μικρὸν προάγοντες ἐγέννησαν τὴν ποίησιν ἐκ τῶν
αὐτοσχεδιασμάτων.
[Since imitating is something natural to us, as are harmonia and rhythm (for
it is obvious that metre is rhythm cut in pieces), in the beginning those who
were most naturally inclined toward these things gave birth to poetry litle
by litle from improvisations.]
Aristotle adds a further cause to explain how poetry arose, the natural
ainity we have, which is highly developed in those who become artists,
for rhythm and harmonia. his ainity for music on our part is not one of
the two natural causes of poetry, but a contingent determining condition of
the art: it might have turned out that, like some animals, we were naturally
insensitive to rhythm and harmonia; other things being equal, we would in
that case still have mimetic arts – this the two natural causes are suicient
to guarantee – but our poetry would have no meter or music (nor, of course,
would we have the arts of the aulos and kithara). A tone-deaf people can still
tell stories about characters acting and sufering.
Because our musical aptitudes have only contingently shaped the
evolution of the poetic art, Aristotle regards them as something appealing
but ‘extra’, like a sauce on a meat. Hence he is wont to speak of adding music
and/or metre to logos as a ‘seasoning’ or a ‘sweetening’ (1449b28-9: λέγω δὲ
ἡδυσμένονμὲν λόγον τὸν ἔχοντα ῥυθμὸν καὶ ἁρμονίαν). Nonetheless, these
extras have come to be indispensible in some art forms, as in the deinition
of tragedy which stipulates that it should make use of ‘seasoned’ language
in its various parts (1449b25-6: ἡδυσμένῳ λόγῳ χωρὶς ἑκάστῳ τῶν εἰδῶν
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
35
ἐν τοῖς μορίοις). By this Aristotle means that speech seasoned with rhythm
will be used in the (mostly) trimeter dialogue, while speech seasoned with
rhythm and harmonia are used in the μέλη, ‘songs’, of the play.
Given our physical constitution, it was natural that these appealing forms
of speech should enter into the pleasing art of poetry in an appropriate way.
When dramatic dialogue evolved out of primordial choral songs, for example,
“nature herself found the appropriate metre” (αὐτὴ ἡ φύσις τὸ οἰκεῖον μέτρον
εὗρε) because the iambic trimeter is closest to normal speech (1449a22-28).
he same natural processes were at work when early epic poets hit on the
“heroic” hexameter from trial and error (1459b32: τὸ δὲ μέτρον τὸ ἡρωικὸν
ἀπὸ τῆς πείρας ἥρμοκεν), because the stateliest and weightiest of the metres
(1459b34: τὸ γὰρ ἡρωικὸν στασιμώτατον καὶ ὀγκωδέστατον τῶν μέτρων
ἐστίν) harmonizes with heroic themes. he formal embellishments of speech
in poetry are secondary causes, accidents of our natures that required time
for poets to learn how best to exploit; but nature was driving the process
and such embellishments are to be disregarded at the author’s peril: today
it would seem “uniting” (ἀπρεπής) to compose an epic in any other metre
(1459b36-39).
A more powerful embellishment than adding rhythm to speech in verse
was music, which blended harmoniai – including the stirring ones Aristotle
speaks of in Politics – into the mix. Aristotle declares songs, μέλη, the most
important of tragedy’s embellishments (1450b15-16: ἡ μελοποιία μέγιστον
τῶν ἡδυσμάτων) and accordingly includes song as one of the constitutive parts
of tragedy (1450a9). It follows that not only is μελοποιία, the ‘composition
of songs,’ one of the principal ways that the tragic art is distinguished from
epic (1449b32-4), it also “in no small part” makes tragedy a superior art form
to music-less epic, for music makes the pleasures of tragedy most vivid and
palpable.19
It is with our instincts for rhythm and harmoniai mentioned in chapter
4, I submit, that the passage from Politics has most to do. For the same
“enthusiastic harmoniai” played on the aulos to such powerful efect in the
mysteries were also used on the stage. To be sure, it would be reductive
to simply equate theatrical and ritual catharsis, and in rejecting Bernays’s
medical account of tragic catharsis and the idealizing one as ‘clariication’ I
do not propose simply to put ritual catharsis in its place. here is a diference
between a telestic ritual and a drama in a theatre, even if the later was
dedicated to the god Dionysus. But the connection between Politics 8 and
Poetics suggests that they are analogous forms of experience, and one may
see this hinted at even in the deinition of tragedy: in chapter 6, Aristotle
19
Ibid., 1462b16-17: οὐ μικρὸν μέρος τὴν μουσικήν [καὶ τὰς ὄψεις], δι’ ἧς αἱ ἡδοναὶ
συνίστανται ἐναργέστατα.
36
Andrew L. Ford
says not simply that tragedy ‘brings about’ the catharsis of pity and fear, but
that it brings this catharsis to completion, it “drives the process to an end”
(περαίνουσα: Poet. 1449b28; cf. LSJ s.v.). his would seem to describe, but
in a reduced form, the process of musical catharsis in ritual in which “the
sacred tunes thoroughly arouse the soul’s passions” (Pol. 1342a9-10: τοῖς
ἐξοργιάζουσι τὴν ψυχὴν μέλεσι).
One objection to the association of telestic and dramatic catharsis is that
it might seem to imply that, as Gerald Else (1957: 440) put it, “we come
to the tragic drama (unconsciously, if you will) as patients to be cured,
relieved, restored to psychic health. But . . . Aristotle is presupposing
‘normal’ auditors, normal states of mind and feeling, normal emotional and
aesthetic experience”. Certainly Aristotle’s mixed theatrical audience is not
pathological (Heath 2014); but he testiies that even “normal” people respond
to such music, and we have seen that telestic ritual drew on all social levels.
he diference between Olympias and Aristotle is perhaps compendiously
noticed in Politics 8.7 where people who are not addicted to orgiastic music
are said to experience only a “kind of catharsis” from the music (1342a15:
τινα κάθαρσιν). Nor is another objection made to Bernays’s medical analogy
pertinent: Elizabeth Beliore (1992: 260-78) has been especially insistent
that, since the medical thought with which Aristotle was familiar worked
on allopathic principles, any notion of a catharsis that ‘cured’ the passions
by arousing the passions was unthinkable. But I think it unwise to press
Aristotle for a too precise model of telestic catharsis. If these skeptics were
to ask Aristotle how he can believe in a homeopathic efect in religion or in
the arts, as an erstwhile member of Olympias’s household he could reply in
the words Mark Twain is said to have used when he was asked if he believed
in infant baptism: “Believe it? Heck, I’ve seen it!”.
I have said that I do not propose telestic catharsis as the model for tragic
experience, and would add that perhaps we should not focus so exclusively
on that word as a key to Aristotle’s views on the function of art. Catharsis
is, ater all, one of a series of terms to describe the pleasurable experience
aforded by tragedy. In chapter 4 he uses the general term ‘enjoying’
(χαίρειν) to describe the natural human pleasure provoked by imitations
(1448b9).20 Soon ater, he describes our feeling when recognizing a painting
It is worth comparing the similar general meaning given to the noun charis in
Plato’s analysis of the correct response to works of musical art. Atempting in Laws
667b-d to deine how a judge will distinguish ine from foul music, he uses charis to name
the “enjoyableness” that atends such activities as learning or eating, but distinguishes
this as less important than the pleasure (hedone) that a serious person (spoudaios) will
take in correct eating (as in dietetics) or correct learning (leading to truth). So too the
image-making arts are “enjoyable” but this is not the same as their being quantitatively
and qualitatively correct. In music “enjoyable” feeling is only a common response and
20
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
37
as “pleasure” (ἡδονή, 1448b18) and “delighting” (εὐφράνειν, 1450b2). he
same verb for delight is used of a tragedy by Agathon (1451b23; cf. 1451b25),
but of course Aristotle’s most important concept for literary purposes is the
“proper pleasure” that belongs to a given poetic genre, whether it be comedy
or tragedy (1445a36: ἡδονὴ . . . οἰκεία). he “proper pleasure” of tragedy
is one that it alone is naturally suited to provide (1459a21). his pleasure
should be the poet’s polestar, disregarding any chance pleasure that may
be available (1462b13: τὴν τυχοῦσαν ἡδονὴν), for “one must not seek every
pleasure from tragedy but the one that is proper to it” (1453b11: οὐ γὰρ
πᾶσαν δεῖ ζητεῖν ἡδονὴν ἀπὸ τραγῳδίας ἀλλὰ τὴν οἰκείαν).
But how does all this stress on pleasure and Aristotle’s recognition of the
powerful emotional impact of tragedy it with the fact that in chapter 4 he
puts learning at the root of the pleasure of mimesis? Are we to apply some
kind of Horatian dulce/utile dichotomy and conclude that the tragedian’s
goal is to teach and that the embellishments are just a way to make the lesson
appealing? But to say that we enjoy imitations because deciphering them is
a form of learning is far from identifying the “pleasure proper to tragedy”
with learning. Heath (2001) argues that the natural pleasure of learning from
mimesis cannot be the ‘characteristic’ (oikeia) pleasure of tragedy since it is
available from other forms of imitation as well; for all the mimetic arts give
pleasure, including painting and dance, and one would hardly take Aristotle
seriously as a critic if he reduced our enjoyment of those forms to ethical
inferences. Heath persuasively concludes that Aristotle’s laconic text in
chapter 4 does not foreclose the conclusion that “learning is not the sole,
and perhaps not even the main pleasure that Aristotle expected poetry to
provide” (Heath 2001: 19-20).
he telestic catharsis described in the Politics, then, is best set against
Aristotle’s anthropological account of the susceptibilities of human nature
in Poetics ch. 4. Indeed, this chapter may be what he primarily had in mind
in the Politics when he referred to “the work on the art of poetry” (τὰ περὶ
ποιητικῆς: 1341b40) for a fuller discussion of catharsis. Scholars who have
focused only on Poetics ch. 6 have speculated that the promised fuller
discussion appeared in the lost second book of that treatise, or perhaps in
another work on the topic, the On Poets. But by taking the full sequence
of chapters 4-6 together we can understand how the catharsis of tragedy
emerges from Aristotle’s account of the full range of human responses to
art and music, in which his experience with telestic catharsis seems to have
provided a suggestive analogue. he entire discussion does supply, if not a
not suicient to recognize truly ine music. he later requires judging the relation of
representation to object represented to know if “the truth” has been represented.
38
Andrew L. Ford
detailed account of catharsis, an explanation of how humans might respond
to imitations of terrible things with pleasure and proit.
Without proposing a fully worked out model for tragic catharsis, I have
argued that with this word Aristotle meant to point to the powerful reaction,
not fully assimilable to cognitive relection, that such plays at their best
uniquely aroused. his is not to say that his idea of a good tragedy was a
thrill-packed spectacle with one car crash ater another. We can see this from
the relatively marginal role he assigns to opsis, ‘spectacle’ in arousing the
pleasure of tragedy: even though he acknowledges its power to ‘stir the soul’
(1450b17: ψυχαγωγικόν), he considers it extraneous to the poet’s art properly
understood. And the work of Stephen Halliwell has especially brought out
how that art depended on tightly constructed and plausible plots, with all
the elements of the play working together toward a single efect. he tragic
art was not a mater of stirring up the audience’s passions in any way that
came to hand, but the subtle art of contriving to arouse in the audience “the
pleasure that comes from pity and fear through mimesis” (1453b12: τὴν ἀπὸ
ἐλέου καὶ φόβου διὰ μιμήσεως . . . ἡδονὴν). A great deal of artistry was
required on the poet’s part, and no litle critical atentiveness on the part of
the audience. But the experience as a whole issued in something that was
more like undergoing a mystic initiation than coolly appraising or observing
a show. Now it might strike some critics that to compare the experience of
tragedy, and mutatis mutandis of literature generally, to mystical initiation
is to neglect what is most artful and sophisticated in what our texts have
to ofer. It may seem paradoxical that these complex, subtly crated works
of art should have been thought to serve to elicit such a comparatively
mindless purpose. I would rather say that the Greek tragic poets show real
inventiveness and skill in forging such inely made instruments of catharsis;
it is to their credit and to that of their audiences – whose tastes were not only
catered to but tutored by the poets – that this visceral, irresistible response
could be aroused by such reined works of art.
It should be clear that the implications of this view need not be that
Aristotle took an aesthetic view of tragedy as opposed to a moralizing one.
Certainly, he held that poetry was for pleasure: whatever catharsis may be,
it is a species of pleasure, a peculiar one arising from witnessing pitiable and
frightening events. But the kind of intense reaction that catharsis seems to
betoken is hardly disinterested enough to be called ‘aesthetic’ in the sense
of a pleasure taken in art for the sake of art. It must also be admited that
Aristotle does not analyse this pleasure very deeply (Heath 2001) and his
narrow focus on pleasure has been faulted for ignoring the political and
social contexts in which the plays were irst performed (Hall 1996). Simon
Goldhill (2000) includes Aristotle in his deconstruction of any atempt to
claim that tragedy has a purely aesthetic value. Goldhill (2000: 39) allows
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
39
that “‘[p]leasure’ may be one explicit aim of tragic theatre (as it is for the
arenas of cricket or football or pornography or tourism)”, but insists that
“it is simply inadequate to use such an aim as the overriding determining
criterion for understanding the cultural politics of the Great Dionysia (as
it would be for cricket or football or pornography or tourism)” (emphasis
mine). here is no doubt that, as Hall (1996) and Goldhill (2000) show
(see also Goldhill 1987), the production of tragedies at the Athenian civic
festivals was an eminently political afair. But Goldhill’s declared aim is
“understanding the cultural politics” of tragedy, while Aristotle’s, as I have
argued, is trying to take an anthropological approach to the phenomenon,
trying to understand tragedy as a universal human art, a development of
uniquely human faculties, abilities, emotions and susceptibilities (cf. Ford
2015; Heath 2009b). Doubtless, Aristotle was no more able than the rest of us
to escape the blind spots of his political conditioning (complex as that would
have been for the Metic from Stagira), and his conceptions of our nature as
political animals was bound to be inluenced by (Metic?) ideology. But for
this writer of many books on politics, the very act of taking a broad view in
Poetics was precisely an atempt to see beyond the undeniable ideological
functions of the plays (which is implicit throughout the history of poetry in
Poetics ch. 5 and explicit in Politics 8) and to do justice to the full range of
their powers, among which something like telestic enthusiasm must igure.
My inal remark concerns what I consider the weakest, but by no
means the rarest version of the cognitive approach to tragedy as ethically
broadening, and this is to imagine that we can learn something about life
from tragedy that can help and even protect us. hat line of thinking is litle
beter than the spectator who leaves the premiere of Oedipus Rex concluding,
“Well, if I ever get such a prophecy as Oedipus did, I’ll be sure to marry
a younger woman and I’ll keep my temper around older men”.21 It is not
only Aristotle but the whole tragic tradition that knows that the person who
strolls out of the theatre of Dionysus thinking such thoughts is the ripest
target for a tragic downfall that there is. It is hard to setle on a single thing
that tragedy teaches, but one thing that no tragedy gives us is a paradigm
from which we can draw lessons to make us (more) safe. he very conidence
that philosophers place in the power of reason, the very assurance they place
in their ‘clariied’ moral ideas, are the exact targets of tragedy. If the sight of
people no worse than you broken does not make you (virtually/mimetically)
afraid for your life, afraid that there is a recognition coming when you will
realize you had no idea that you were going in the opposite direction than
you had hoped, what you have experienced is not what Aristotle experienced
when he described the experience of tragedy.
21
Cf. Depew 2007: 145.
40
Andrew L. Ford
Works Cited
Barker, Andrew (1989), Greek Musical Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, vol. 2.
Beliore, Elizabeth (1992), Tragic Pleasures: Aristotle on Plot and Emotion, Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Bernays, Jakob [1857] (1979), “Aristotle on the Efects of Tragedy”, trans. by
Johnathan and Jennifer Barnes, in Jonathan Barnes, Malcolm Schoield and
Richard Sorabji (eds), Articles on Aristotle, London: Macmillan & Co.: 154-65,
vol. 4.
Burkert, Walter (1987), Ancient Mystery Cults, Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard
University Press.
Carney, Elizabeth (2006), Olympias: Mother of Alexander the Great, New York and
London: Routledge.
Cerri, Giovanni (2007), La poetica di Platone: una teoria della comunicazione, Lecce:
Argo.
Depew, David (2007), “From hymn to tragedy: Aristotle’s genealogy of poetic kinds”,
in Eric Csapo and Margaret C. Miller (eds), he Origins of heater in Ancient
Greece and Beyond: From Ritual To Drama, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press: 126-49.
Destrée, Pierre (2011), “La purgation des interprétations: conditions et enjeux de la
catharsis poétique chez Aristote”, in Jean-Charles Darmon (ed.), Litérature
et thérapeutique des passions. La catharsis en question, Paris: Hermann: 41-63.
Dodds, Eric Robertson (1957), he Greeks and the Irrational, Berkeley and Los
Angeles: University of California Press.
Dupont-Roc, Roselyne and Jean Lallot (1980), Aristote: La Poétique, Paris: Seuil.
Else, Gerald F. (1957), Aristotle’s Poetics: he Argument, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Ferrari, Giovanni R.F. (1999), “Aristotle’s Literary Aesthetics”, Phronesis, 44: 181–98.
Ford, Andrew (2004), “Catharsis: he Power of Music in Aristotle’s Politics”, in
Penelope Murray and Peter Wilson (eds) (2004), Music and the Muses: he
Culture of “Mousikē” in the Classical Athenian City, Oxford: Oxford University
Press: 309-36.
— (2015), “he Purpose of Aristotle’s Poetics”, Classical Philology, 110 (1): 1-21.
Golden, Leon (1992), Aristotle on Tragic and Comic Mimesis, Atlanta: Scholars Press.
Goldhill, Simon (1987), “he Great Dionysia and Civic Ideology”, he Journal of
Hellenic Studies, 107: 58-76.
— (2000), “Civic Ideology and the Problem of Diference: he Politics of Aeschylean
Tragedy, Once again”, he Journal of Hellenic Studies, 120: 34-56.
Hall, Edith (1996), “Is there a polis in Aristotle’s Poetics?”, in Michael Stephen Silk
(ed.), Tragedy and the Tragic: Greek heatre and Beyond, Oxford: Oxford
University Press: 295-309.
Halliwell, Stephen (1986), Aristotle’s Poetics, Chapel Hill: University of North
Carolina Press.
— (2001), “Aristotelian Mimesis and Human Understanding”, in Øivind Andersen
Catharsis, Music and the Mysteries in Aristotle
41
and Jon Haarberg (eds), Making Sense of Aristotle: Essays in Poetics, London:
Duckworth: 87-107.
— (2002), he Aesthetics of Mimesis: Ancient Texts and Modern Problems, Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Heath, Malcolm (2001), “Aristotle on the Pleasures of Tragedy”, in Øivind Andersen
and Jon Haarberg (eds), Making Sense of Aristotle: Essays in Poetics, London:
Duckworth: 7-23.
— (2009a), “Cognition in Aristotle’s Poetics”, Mnemosyne, 62: 51-75.
— (2009b), “Should here Have Been a Polis in Aristotle’s ‘Poetics’?”, he Classical
uarterly, 59 (2): 468-85.
— (2014), “Aristotle and the Value of Tragedy”, British Journal of Aesthetics, 54 (2):
111-23.
Hoessly, Fortunat (2001), Catharsis. Reinigung als Heilverfahren. Studien zum Ritual
der archaischen und klassischen Zeit so wie zum Corpus Hippocraticum,
Götingen: Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht.
Janko, Richard (ed.) (1987), Aristotle. Poetics I, Indianapolis: Hacket.
— (2011), Philodemus, On Poems, Books 3-4, with the Fragments of Aristotle, On Poets,
Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Keesey, Donald (1979), “On Some Recent Interpretations of Catharsis”, he Classical
World, 72 (4): 193-205.
Kraut, Richard (1997), Aristotle “Politics” Books VII and VIII, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Lear, Jonathan (1988), “Catharsis”, Phronesis, 33: 327-44.
Linforth, Ivan M. (1946), “he Corybantic Rites in Plato”, University of California
Pubications in Classical Philology, 13: 121-62.
Lord, Carnes (1982), Education and Culture in the Political hought of Aristotle, Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.
Nussbaum, Martha (1992), “Tragedy and Self-Suiciency: Plato and Aristotle on
Fear and Pity”, in Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), Essays on Aristotle’s Poetics,
Princeton: Princeton University Press: 261-90.
Perrin, Bernadote (trans.) (1919) Plutarch, Lives Volume VII, Loeb Classical Library,
Cambridge, MA and London: Harvard University Press.
Radermacher, Ludwig (ed.) (1954), Aristophanes “Frösche”, Vienna: Rohrer.
Schadewaldt, Wolfgang (ed.) (1955), “Furcht und Mitleid”, Hermes, 83: 129-71.
Sifakis, Gregory Michael (1986), “Learning from Art and Pleasure in Learning: An
Interpretation of Aristotle Poetics 4 1448b8-19”, in John H. Bets, James T.
Hooker, and John Richard Green (eds), Studies in Honour of T.B.L. Webster,
vol. 1, Bristol: Bristol Classical Press: 211-22.
Vöhler, Martin and Bernd Seidensticker (eds) (2007), Catharsiskonzeptionen vor
Aristoteles, Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter.