© SpazioFilosofico 2016 – ISSN: 2038-6788
Lenart Škof
AN INTERVAL OF GRACE: THE TIME OF ETHICS
Abstract
In the preliminary introduction, we point to Schopenhauer’s ethics and philosophy of religion and to his
peculiar understanding of the notion of freedom as grace. On the basis of this constellation, we then start
with three Meadian analyses. We first introduce the topics of space and touch in the discussion of
Mead’s philosophy of intersubjectivity and the related problem of an ethical temporality. We try to
demonstrate the importance of the so called “interval” in ethics, understood in a temporal as well as
spatial sense. For this purpose, we offer three Meadian meditations by reading (in both a philosophical
and a religious way) Ludwig Feuerbach’s, Jean-Louis Chrétien’s, and Watsuji Tetsurō’s texts and by
relating them to Mead’s original inception of the philosophy of intersubjectivity. Finally, by reading
Benjamin Libet’s Mind Time in an ethical register, we argue for a “theological” extension of Mead’s
philosophy also by indicating the nature of the ethical “interval” and the related phenomenon of ethical
temporality as grace.
“Yet, as Aristotle shows, the interval is never abolished,
only forgotten. There always remains an intervening body
between our flesh and what it touches, a three-dimensional
layer of air or water” (Chrétien 2004, pp. 87f.).
“This interval – and this medium – is first of all nature, as
it remains left to itself: air, water, earth, and sun, as fire and
light. Being par excellence – matter of the transcendental”
(Irigaray 2008, p. 19).
“Libet’s work has focused on temporal relations between
neural events and conscience. He is famous in part for
discovering that we unconsciously decide to act well before
we think we’ve made the decision to act” (S.M. Kosslyn,
Foreword, in Libet 2004, p. x).
1. Introduction
In my previous analyses of ethical gestures I have tried to reflect upon, in my opinion,
one of the most important problems in ethics, namely, the constitution of an ethical
211
interiority. On this issue, I have first written two papers on Schopenhauer, discussing the
role of body in his metaphysical conception of ethics. I have also brought
Schopenhauer’s thought closer to American pragmatism, to James’ radical empiricism
specifically. Why Schopenhauer? Allow me to briefly outline my interpretation. In his On
the Basis of Morality, Schopenhauer writes the following:
“With these allusions to the metaphysics of ethics I must rest content, although an important step
remains to be taken. But this presupposes that a further step be taken in ethics itself, which I could not
do, because the highest aim of ethics is limited to jurisprudence and moral philosophy in Europe, and
here no one knows, or indeed will admit, what is beyond these” (Schopenhauer 1998, p. 214).
Usually we think that for Schopenhauer, the ethics of compassion and sympathy (and
thus, a kind of pre-critical intersubjective ethics) can only be affirmed metaphysically by
acknowledging the Will in the world and its total denial in ourselves through the ascetic
practice (i.e. the quietening of the will, which means surpassing the ego(t)istic will in
ourselves). As a result, I realize that the others are actually the same as me and thus feel
compassion with their suffering. But in this metaphysical model (designed in a clear antiKantian manner) there is a lacuna: namely, the body felt in its immediacy is for
Schopenhauer the first object in the epistemological constitution of the self as will. My
body is to me, paradoxically, the first external object. This is clearly traceable in the
fourth book of The World as Will and Representation, where we are faced with the following
ethical paradox: in the moment before we feel that the other has been wronged or before
we act compassionately towards the other (i.e. “see” or “recognize” their pain) we always
already feel the “secret presentiment” (geheime Ahndung) inside (our body) – as a “sting of
conscience” (Gewissensbiß). When I realize that the others are the same as me, I already
share in their pain. This suffering is “wholly direct and even instinctive (instinktartig).”
(Schopenhauer 1969, p. 163) And ultimately, this is to Schopenhauer the exact essence
of freedom, which is again understood as grace.
Now, some recent developments in scholarship devoted to G.H. Mead’s philosophy
have raised his thought to an equal standing in relation to other key philosophers, not
only in American pragmatism but also in the context of Western philosophical tradition.
Besides the undisputed role that Mead’s thought has played in social sciences, it is clear
that his philosophy has much to offer with regard to some key contemporary
epistemological and ethical problems. Erkki Kilpinen, for example, has recently
convincingly argued that Mead would need to be recognized as the forerunner of Lakoff
and Johnson’s philosophical project (Philosophy in the Flesh, 1999), calling Mead an
empirically responsible philosopher. With his and other similar attempts, Mead’s philosophy
has become a part of the epistemological tradition dealing with the embodied mind.
Others still have read Mead in an intercultural key or discussed some interesting
comparative possibilities concerning the attunement of the body or the mind-body
problem (e.g. Steve Odin in his paper on Mead in “Philosophy of East and West”, 42
(3/1992), or philosophers using Shigenori Nagatomo’s thought for their philosophies).
But Mead’s most important contribution to philosophy is undoubtedly his theory of
intersubjectivity. In my presentation, I wish to offer three epistemological meditations
on these Meadian themes.
212
© SpazioFilosofico 2016 – ISSN: 2038-6788
In one of my previous analyses of Mead (Škof 2015), I offered an interpretation of
ethical temporality in Mead. I elaborated on the temporality of gesture and tried to
approach the problem of intersubjectivity by relating Mead’s philosophy to Kierkegaard
and Derrida’s concepts of subjectivity, interiority, and time. I argued that only by
reflecting upon the inner logic of ethical temporality we can balance the inner structure
of his thought, which can be done precisely by securing the ethical interval between
interiority as a philosophical core of Mead’s philosophy and the role that exteriority and the
social self played in various psychological or sociological interpretations of his thought.
In the present attempt, I would like to further develop this argument by introducing into
the discussion about Mead’s philosophy of intersubjectivity the topics of space and touch.
For this purpose I will offer three Meadian meditations by reading Ludwig Feuerbach,
Jean-Louis Chrétien and Watsuji Tetsurō’s texts and by relating them to Mead’s original
inception of the philosophy of intersubjectivity. I will try to demonstrate the importance
of an interval in ethics, both in the temporal and spatial senses. In that, I will also refer
to Benjamin Libet’s book Mind Time, a fascinating account on the epistemological gap or
interval, which deserves our attention. Finally, I will argue for a “theological” extension
in Mead’s original constellation by indicating the analogy or nature of the interval as
love, compassion, or grace.
Much like Mead’s role used to be underemphasised by the tradition of philosophy,
Ludwig Feuerbach, too, was long considered a transitional philosopher to whom many
authors ascribed significance for the later development of certain philosophical topics,
such as criticism of religion, materialism, sensibility, etc., but to whom the Western
tradition, nevertheless, did not wish to award a place of honour among other
philosophical giants of the West. However, with the epistemological pre-eminence of
skin and touch and his original philosophy of sensibility, Feuerbach paved the way
towards the first Western theory of intersubjectivity. In the present analysis I will
delineate the epistemological space of sensitivity in Feuerbach and compare it to Mead’s
genesis of an intersubjective self – in terms of gestures and as based on the primacy of
“contact experience” in Mead. In his “phenomenology” of gesture, Mead ascribes great
importance to the hand, which also opens interesting possibilities of interpreting him as
a “haptic philosopher” (a remark made by his student David L. Miller; note also an
elaboration of “hand” in Heidegger – as a gesture, carrying out the bodily-felt
dimensions of meaning, as David Kleinberg-Levin asserts).
On the other side, there is Jean-Louis Chrétien, who in his Call and Response (1992)
deals precisely with the bodily scheme as proposed by some interpreters of Mead.
Chrétien’s epistemological credo (“I never start by saying ‘I’, I start by being ‘thou-ed’ by
the world”), together with his rehabilitation of touch (and space) is what I find to be a
most interesting possibility today for extending both Feuerbachian and Meadian
concepts of self to the contemporary philosophy of intersubjectivity. But Chrétien, in
the ethical line of his argument, also mentions a related “nothingness” of self as a
possibility for negating the old Biblical saying “I am, and there is no one besides me”
(Isaiah 47:10). While here, both in his concept of touch as well as nothingness of the self,
interesting intercultural possibilities open, it is through Watsuji Tetsurō’s thought that I
intend to eventually show the importance of the concept of aidagara (“relatedness”,
213
“betweenness”) and climate, interpreted both as space and touch/contact, for the
understanding of Mead’s philosophy.
2. Coming to the Stage of Ethics
Let me begin my reflection with a highly interesting citation from Kakyō, Zeami’s most
important work on Japanese aesthetics. Zeami Motokiyo (1363–1443) was a Japanese
aesthetician, actor and playwright, influenced by Zen. Kakyō is his important work on the
essence of Noh theatre. Symbolically, a reflection on theatre can, in my opinion,
represent the essence of our intersubjective relations. The citation reads as follows:
“When [the actor] enters stage in a sarugaku [performance] and begins the [opening] speech or issei
[passage], there will be a peak for that moment. [Too] early is wrong. [Too] late will also be wrong.
To being with, [the actor] leaves the greenroom, walks onto the hashigakari, [the bridge connecting
the backstage to the main stage,] and stops; he [then] takes in all directions, and he should speak just
when the audience holds with anticipation the thought, ‘ There, he’s going to speak!’ This is ‘the
opportune moment [that] corresponds to the feeling [of the audience]’, whereat [the actor] speaks after
having caught the spirit of the audience. If this opportune moment is even a little bit late, the spirit of
the audience will once again relax, and when he begins to recite after that, it will not correspond to
everyone’s feeling. This opportune moment is, simply, [a reflection of] the [receptive] ch’i of the
spectators. What is called ‘the opportune moment that is the ch’i of the spectators’ is a peak that the
actor perceives by his intuition. This is the critical moment when [the actor] draws everyone’s rapt
attention just to this state of concentration. It is one of the [most] important moments of a given day[’s
performance]” (Zeami 1982, pp. 461f.).
This paragraph of Zeami is extraordinary: it brings to the fore the most important
elements of the intersubjective and gestural conversation I wish to analyse in this
presentation: the threshold between the Noh actor and audience (me and other(s) in
Meadian terms), indicating the conversational (breath-)space (aidagara in Watsuji, air and
water in Aristotle’s On the Soul, 423a 221 and, as we will see, in Chrétien) between them,
and, importantly – in tune with Zen philosophy –, the role of breath in this process. For a
Noh actor it is decisive to appear on stage precisely at the moment when his audience
would expect him to appear – and raise his voice. He has to come to the stage and raise
his voice accordingly to the “spirit of the audience” (German Gemeingefühl ). This points
at temporal as well as spatial problems of all intersubjective relations: if he is too late,
“Let us assume that every body has depth, i.e. has three dimensions, and that if two bodies have a
third body between them they cannot be in contact with one another; let us remember that what is
liquid is not independent of body and must be or contain water, and that if two bodies touch one
another under water, their touching surfaces cannot be dry, but must have water between, viz. the
water which wets their bounding surfaces; from all this it follows that in water two bodies cannot be in
contact with one another. The same holds of two bodies in air – air being to bodies in air precisely
what water is to bodies in water – but the facts are not so evident to our observation, because we live in
air, just as animals that live in water would not notice that the things which touch one another in water
have wet surfaces. The problem, then, is: does the perception of all objects of sense take place in the
same way, or does it not; e.g. taste and touch requiring contact (as they are commonly thought to do),
while all other senses perceive over a distance?” (Aristotle, On the Soul, 423a 22-423b 4; Engl. transl.:
Aristotle 1984, p. 673).
1
214
© SpazioFilosofico 2016 – ISSN: 2038-6788
only for a moment, the common atmosphere/collective mood is lost. If he is there too
early, again, the link with the audience is interrupted or broken. The actor must be a
master of this threshold: he must know/sense intuitively, in his interiority and from the
breaths and hearts of the audience, the exact time-space of his vocal appearance – a vocal
gesture that, of course, is always an intersubjective or social act already.
Now, this short paragraph of Zeami shows the essence of what I understand as a
fundamental layer of all intersubjective relations and especially ethics: the threshold (in
theological-ethical terms, it will later be related to grace) as our time-space-between, as
based on bodily signs in the course of our contact experience. We know that in Mead’s
philosophy from Mind, Self and Society, our body is itself a bridge to the other. We are also
“reading the meaning of the conduct of other people, when, perhaps, they are not aware
of it […] just the glance of an eye, the attitude of the body […]” (Mead 1967, p. 14)2. But
the bridge is always already a threshold that we need to address, both by intuition and
cognition. Mead himself points to the first (pre-cognitive) layer in his 1914 Lectures in
Social Psychology, in the chapter Imitation and Imagination, when he states that we can discern
various bodily signs in ourselves/our self, which can help us first establish the threshold
or difference between the ego and the alteri, and then also bridge the gap to the other –
such as an “organic sensation, cyclopean eye, feeling in the throat that accompanies
articulation, kinaesthetic and visceral ideas […]” (Miller 1982, p. 65). All these elements
are in the closest proximity to similar empirico-organic or process philosophies and
theologies of our age. But their first predecessor was Feuerbach. Let us now first take a
closer look into his philosophy.
3. Constitution of the Other in Feuerbach, Chrétien and Watsuji,
as related to Mead’s Conversation of Gestures
Now, through some recent scholarship on Mead it has become clear that his philosophy
is complementary to the field of embodied cognition or embodied mind. Moreover, in
the Introduction to his already mentioned 1914 and 1927 class lectures, D.L. Miller calls
Mead both a process philosopher and, even more importantly, a haptic philosopher3. In
relation to the concept of the so-called “contact experience” in Mead, this is of great
importance for my analysis. Namely, in this line of reasoning, we can easily think Mead’s
original constitution of the conversation of gestures in the language of the philosophy of
skin (Feuerbach), touch (Chrétien) and the betweenness of persons (Watsuji; also a
climate or fūdo). But even more importantly, all these reflections inaugurate a completely
different layer in the relation between the “I” and the “me”, between my self and the
selves of the others, which now constitutes my social self. As K.J. Booth (2013, p. 137)
argues, in this process “there must be a basic level of consciousness that is
developmentally prior to taking the attitude of the other and that develops into selfconsciousness” (here it would be interesting to point to B. Libet’s experiments, but I will
2
See also n. 9. On this aspect see W. Bergmann and G. Hoffmann’s (1985) chapter G.H. Mead und die
Tradition der Phänomenologie, p. 110.
3
I am indebted to Roman Madzia for kindly reminding me of this remark (on “haptic” see Miller’s
Introduction (1982, pp. 12 and 22)).
215
elaborate on them later). He refers to Shigenori Nagatomi’s well-known distinction
between the subject-body and the object-body, where the former is the body in the
sense of epistemic centre of our consciousness. We can acknowledge this as a basic
postulate for securing the place of interiority in our social selves. But what kind of logic
constitutes this interiority? At this point, one step further has to be taken. We know that
for Mead both attitude and gesture are fully embodied. But how does Mead, being a
haptic philosopher, understand our intersubjective relations between embodied
individuals or bodies that touch one another? I wish now to take a detour through three
other philosophers and present three meditations on a Meadian theme only to be able to
return to Mead and try to offer some answers to this question.
a) Ludwig Feuerbach
I have mentioned Schopenhauer at the beginning of this paper. His role in the history of
philosophy has often been regarded as transitional, and the same can be said of Ludwig
Feuerbach. But there is a more important similarity between the two that also
distinguishes them from other mainstream idealistic philosophers of the 18th and 19th
centuries (Berkeley and Hume, Fichte, Kant and Hegel, but not Schelling). The role of
the body in the constitution of the world of representation in Schopenhauer has been
explained earlier.
According to Hans Joas (1985, p. 2), Mead is “the most important theorist of
intersubjectivity between Feuerbach and Habermas.” But is there an even more
substantive link between Feuerbach and Mead? Feuerbach’s theory of intersubjectivity is
not defined in “Meadian” terms, of course. But there are two important facts I wish to
discuss: the very constitution of the other, on the one side, and the role of the
body/skin, on the other. Analogous to Mead’s constitution of the intersubjective/social
self via “I” and “me”, is Feuerbach’s statement, at the end of Principles of Philosophy of
Future, that the true dialectic is posited not as a monologue of a solitary thinker to
himself, but as a continuous dialogue between “I” and “Thou”. Moreover, Feuerbach
bases his philosophy of sensibility on the elements of Nature. To these he adjoins the
human being as another element of Nature, along with organs or body parts (eyes, head,
heart, stomach, sexual organs) among which, in the preeminent position as the
fundamental organ of perception, appears none other than the skin. Feuerbach as a
haptic philosopher? Perhaps – for the philosophy of sensibility (or rather sensitivity)
begins in the body, especially in the skin/touch. In an exceptional passage from his 1841
work entitled Some Comments on the “Beginning of Philosophy” of Dr J.F. Reiff, Feuerbach
states the following:
“Through the body, the Self is not the Self, but rather an object. Being-in-the-body means being-inthe-world. So many senses – so many pores. The self is nothing other than the porous self.”4
The porous nature of our self now indicates something extremely important: our self
(which is basically understood as the sentient being) is only constituted objectively or
socially through its fundamental intersubjective act: just like we depend epistemologically
4
For citations and elaboration on this see my Breath of Proximity (Škof 2015, p. 78).
216
© SpazioFilosofico 2016 – ISSN: 2038-6788
on Nature (the role of elements and sensitivity), we depend ethically-socially on others.
Feuerbach adds something else to this constellation: it is precisely and only through our
intersubjective and social acts that we experience something infinitely bigger than we
and our finite selves are: which is love (or grace)5. This excess of love in Feuerbach is
precisely the missing link of all previous ethics: the interval of love/grace – as already
shown by Schopenhauer and now posited by Feuerbach for the first time in the history
of philosophy – as an intersubjective act. Löwith reminds us that even before I am
aware, “I have already left Nature, the unconscious, founded on the Dasein of the Other”
(Löwith 1976, p. 49).
To wind up this short reflection: in my book on intersubjectivity I have shown that
there exists a profound proximity between Feuerbach and process philosophy or
theology. Carol Christ, a process-oriented thinker, reflects upon our
intersubjective/social relations as follows:
“In the process view, the world is a web of changing individuals interacting with and affecting each other, cocreating the world. Relationships are the building blocks of life. In them we grow and develop. In them we experience
the joy of living. In them we are traumatized and suffer. Without them, we would not be. Personal
relationships are embedded in a web of structural relationships that shape societies and cultures. The
world is social through and through. When others are suffering, we suffer. When others are happy, we feel
their joy. […] If the air we breathe is clean, we may breathe more deeply. If it is poisoned, we may
grasp for breath, cough, and eventually become ill” (Christ 2003, pp. 69ff.; my emphases).
We are now close to what I later refer to as the so-called riddle in the ethics of
sympathy, based on our observations. But I have to take another step – towards the
reflection on touch in the philosophy of Jean-Louis Chrétien.
b) Jean-Louis Chrétien
If we insist on the significance of contact experience in Mead, and put Feuerbach’s
theory of sensibility (skin, sense organs, and nature) qua intersubjectivity into an epoché
for a moment, then Chrétien’s philosophy of contact/touch as a key novelty in recent
phenomenology (and philosophy in general) is of great importance for any constitution
of intersubjective relations. Firstly, for Chrétien, we only live to respond – to the other,
to our closest environment, and to God. In this, for him, the body is the highest
representation of the spirit. But the most important of all experiences is the
tactile/haptic experience, or touch. In this constellation, the call, our voice, our
conscious response and act, always comes too late, or in Chrétien’s words:
“Does the call, upon which we have meditated at such length in our preceding chapters, not indeed
always come too late, if it finds us already constituted without it, before it, in the silence of a sensing
that is originally turned toward the self, even when the self is affected by another?” (Chrétien 2004, p.
84).
5
For this reason, Joas is probably not perfectly accurate in his statement that Feuerbach in his thought
is only encountering the other in a contemplative way (Joas 1985, p. 13). I think that the constitution of
intersubjectivity in Feuerbach already opens a path towards practical ethics, which, of course, is
cosmologically underpinned. But Joas is certainly right in pointing at the corporeality of subjects, being
in their everyday practical intersubjective relations (ibidem, p. 14).
217
The priority of our self-constitution is based on the self-receptivity of touch. Translated into
Meadian terms, our desire to emit any kind of vocal gesture is already constituted prior
to any reflexivity, in a milieu of touch. In Chrétien, touch exceeds tact, since it is not
limited to a mere contact. In the paragraph by Aristotle, we have seen that no animal is
deprived of touch and that “the sense of touch is inseparable from life itself” (ibidem, p.
85). Through touch we enter into relationships with others, since the experience of
touch is a basic experience of contact (or, its precondition and milieu) that we all have in
our life affairs. But it is important to acknowledge, as also Aristotle would already know,
that the interval between us and others is never abolished, that our touch, paradoxically,
never touches and thus, as it were, safeguards the difference and autonomy of the other
person. The touch is of course present in a manner by which we generally address (same
as in Feuerbach) our sensitivity. But there is another paradoxical element in the touch: as
a sense organ (i.e. skin) it is oriented towards the outer world, for, as an organ, it
“cannot be nor become an object to itself” (Chrétien 2004, p. 120)6. Here the
intersubjective process begins (structurally, this is analogous to both Feuerbach and
Mead):
“I feel myself only by favor of the other. It is the other who gives me to myself insofar as the return
to myself and to my own actions or affections always supposes this other. The most intimate sensation,
the sensation of my own sensitive life in act, is also the most open, and its intimacy is deployed only
through its openness. To feel oneself is not a beginning, but a response to the appeal made by a
sensible that is other than myself and that elicits the exercise of my acts. I never start by saying ‘I’, I
start by being ‘thou-ed’ by the world” (Chrétien 2004, p. 120).
This statement, written in the phenomenological language, is very close to Mead’s
constitution of gesture as a social act. But perhaps it is only in its excess that the logic of
touch can really be understood. In his final words in the chapter Body and Touch, Chrétien
goes as far as to refer to the touch of God: Saint John of the Cross, namely, speaks of
“God’s touch” and interprets it as the “‘merciful hand of the Father’ with which he
touches the Son.” (ibidem, p. 130) This is a caress, an ethical gesture of sympathy and
compassion. And it is Aquinas who understands this touching as grace, an excess we
cannot understand or – properly speaking – condition. Isn’t Mead’s elaboration of
sympathetic gesture in the closest proximity to this mystical constellation? He states:
“The other is a different person and, being different, his suffering is different from mine, but he is a
suffering being to whom I react immediately” (Mead 1967, p. 62).
It is now time to address our third example, Watsuji Tetsurō’s philosophy of aidagara.
c) Watsuji Tetsurō
In his excellent study of Mead and Watsuji Tetsurō’s (1889-1960) philosophy and
communitarian ethics, Steve Odin (1992) points to a deep structural proximity between
6
Earlier in his phenomenological constitution of the touch, Chrétien mentions W. Wundt and his
elaboration of touch as Gefühlssinn, and stresses the inappropriateness of the term Tastsinn for touch
(Chrétien 2004, p. 104).
218
© SpazioFilosofico 2016 – ISSN: 2038-6788
both thinkers7. For Watsuji, the main problem in philosophy is related to the question of
personhood (ningen) and betweenness (or, relatedness; aidagara) – as our social self. For
him the substance is multiple, not solitary. Influenced by Heidegger, Watsuji’s
philosophy aims at addressing the neglected problem of spatiality (as we know,
temporality was in the forefront of Heidegger’s analyses). As Odin (1992, p. 479) states,
“the notion of self as a substance with a fixed essence is abandoned for a relationally
defined self which is fluid, shifting, open, decentred, multiple, and social in nature.”
Since Watsuji’s philosophy is closely linked to Japanese aesthetics, it is of no coincidence
of course that there is a close analogy between the constellations of Zeami’s Kakyō on
the one hand and Watsuji’s on the other. Watsuji (as a Confucian and a Buddhist) has
devoted his entire thought to the communitarian problem in ethics: being-with-others in
community is now the basic mode of our self-constitution. In his analysis, Odin shows
this in a convincing manner, also by addressing all of the most important elements of
Mead’s philosophy8. It is also important to acknowledge – as Odin (1992, pp. 490f.)
presents to us in his paper – various essays and analyses on the topic of Buddhist
emptiness (śūnyatā) and the interrelated existence as an organismic process in Whitehead
and American pragmatism.
But to be able to go one step further and prepare the ground for an analysis of
Feuerbach, Chrétien and Watsuji with Mead, I would like to take a closer look at
Watsuji’s work Climate (Fūdo), which gathers all of the most important themes of his
philosophy and relates them to a unique cosmological constellation, which is
nevertheless similar to our pragmatist process-oriented thinking in Whitehead, Dewey or
Mead. For Watsuji, climate “includes both society and living nature,” (p. 495) and
aidagara as an interval (and the main “function” of climate) is structured on the basis of
the Buddhist ontological mode of emptiness – which thus “empties” our self and
establishes a new space of interrelatedness or betweenness of persons. Some critics saw
this as a weakness of Watsuji’s theory, possibly leading to fascism or strong
communitarianism as compared to Mead and his model, based on communicative or
symbolic interaction. But in a more positive reading, the climate as an interspace can be
of great value for our intersubjective relations. It can become the matrix of a new ethics,
based on touch, sympathy and humility. Norman Wirzba (2010) addresses humility as a
key consequence of Chrétien’s philosophy of touch: we have to empty ourselves of our
egotistic nature of the mode I am and there is no one besides me, and enter the ethical
relations with other based on humility, and thus reciprocity and responsiveness: “I feel
myself only by the favor of the other” (Wirzba 2010, p. 235) and, even more
importantly, “We need the space between self and other, so that we can learn to act on
another’s behalf” (ibidem, p. 247). This space is the climate of our intersubjective relations,
based on contact experience and touch. For Watsuji (1992, pp. 12-20), climate is what
constitutes and underpins our self-understanding. We can never begin with a Cartesian
or even Kantian gesture since we are always situated in an interspace – i.e. climate. Here
we must return to Feuerbach: his philosophy of the elements as natural habitats of our
In this chapter, I will also refer to Watsuji Tetsuro’s Fūdo – Wind und Erde (1992).
It can, of course, be of no coincidence that Mead’s closest pragmatist colleague, John Dewey, was
entitled by Chinese philosophers upon his lecturing in China as “Second Confucius.” On this, see Hall
and Ames (1999); see also J. Grange (2004), J. Dewey (1973) and J. Ching-Sze Wang (2007).
7
8
219
body-self (especially water and air) and also the related Aristotle’s echo in Chrétien – as an
insistence on a medium (also consisting of water or air) between our “touch” and its
“object” is now the main argument for a new understanding of an ethical constellation
of gestures in Mead, as well. There is an analogy with our example from the Japanese
Noh theatre – as in art and our conversational processes, so in atmospheric phenomena:
according to Watsuji, we cannot feel the cold of the outer world or exist in it without
always already being exposed. Analogically, we live in a social climate with its rituals. But
the question still remains: which impulse in ourselves enables us to enter intersubjective
relations, or, how is it possible to move our hand toward the other within the
betweenness, time-space (aidagara, climate) of an ethical gesture? These are the questions
that I wish to address in the final part of my essay.
4. An Interval of Grace
“For there to be gift event (we say event and not act),
something must come about or happen, in an instant, in
an instant that no doubt does not belong to the economy
of time, in a time without time, in such a way that the
forgetting forgets, that it forgets itself, but also in such a
way that this forgetting without being something present,
presentable, determinable, sensible, or meaningful, is not
nothing” (Derrida 1992, p. 174).
We have seen that in Chrétien’s phenomenology the basic intersubjective constellation
(“I start by being ‘thou-ed’ by the world”) is accompanied by the notion of humility
(emptying of our self), in a space that we both/all share. In the final part of my
presentation I intend to argue that behind the scene, as it were, there appears a possibility in
Mead for an inauguration of a space of interiority where our “social” time
(communication as a mode of reciprocity or reflection of the reactions of others in me
based on one-dimensional or successive time) similarly reverses into an ethical time – as
an impossible time of grace as gift and hospitality. This grace, or this absolute and
impossible gift, as Derrida (1992, p. 166) observes, “interrupts economy” and thus does
not permit us to lean on any vulgar form of the economy of exchange and reciprocity.
Economy is circular, says Derrida. Intersubjectivity based on economy and exchange is
also circular. But the gift of ethical gesture in us is an interruption, an impossible act that
inaugurates the time and space of interiority9. Only within the atmosphere of this
interruption is an ethical act possible.
Let me point out an interpretation of the problem of consciousness offered by
American neurophysiologist Benjamin Libet (2004) in his famous work Mind Time. In
this book, Libet convincingly argues that there is a 500 msec delay in our conscious
sensory awareness between our subjective feeling and its unconscious beginning in the
brain. This surprising observation of Libet’s bears important consequences on our
9
On this space and Kierkegaard as related to Mead, see my exploration in Breath of Proximity (ch. 4.5 on
Mead).
220
© SpazioFilosofico 2016 – ISSN: 2038-6788
knowledge of human agency, free will and the very logic of the awareness of our
conscious (including ethical) acts. The very essence of his argument goes as follows:
“If you tap your finger on a table, you experience the event as occurring in ‘real time.’ That is, you
subjectively feel the touch occurring at the same time that your finger makes contact with the table. But
our experimental evidence strongly supports a surprising finding that is directly counter to our own
intuition and feelings: The brain needs a relatively long period of appropriate activations, up to about
half a second, to elicit awareness of the event! Your conscious experience or awareness of your finger
touching the table thus appears only after the brain activities have become adequate to produce the
awareness” (Libet 2004, p. 33).
According to Libet, we are therefore always a bit late in our conscious activities or
responses. There is a gap (an interval) between reported and real time. This causes the
fundamental problem of defining “the present moment” in ourselves: it seems that “the
experience is actually one of an event 0.5 sec in the past” (ibidem, p. 88)10. In my opinion,
this scientific evidence of Libet’s also supports an ethical intervention at the very core of
various theories related to Mead’s symbolic interactionism.
Let me return to my introductory example: we have seen that in Schopenhauer there
is a gap between our conscious (in ethical terms egoistic) act, which follows my will (and
is, in turn, part of the metaphysical Will), and our pure altruistic action (like sympathy,
compassion, agápe or caritas), which is based on the denial of the Will. This gap cannot be
explained in logical terms, and is only possible when the very rational (volitional) logic is
reverted: in order to be able to act ethically, we have to deny our will. It is precisely in
this act of the denial of the Will that Schopenhauer (1969, p. 404) discloses freedom qua
grace (and quotes Malebranche: “la liberté est un mystère”)11. Interestingly enough, like
Schopenhauer, Libet, too, has been charged with the original sin of annihilating free will
in humans. But these charges are based on a vulgar understanding of free will. Both
Schopenhauer and Libet share one extremely important insight: that we act before we
have consciously decided to act. Translated into ethics of intersubjectivity, and in
relation to our constellation above (with Feuerbach, Chrétien and Watsuji as three peaks
in our new interpretative space), this means that there is a shared ethical space in our
interiority or within our ethical core that we can call the climate or atmosphere of ethics.
Beyond the more common inside-outside divide where dualistic logic leads us towards old
dualisms, we rather seek for a processual ethics of reciprocity (call, response,
anticipation, common climate), but with one important feature: that ultimately, our
ethical act and our touching of the other (with the touch/direct/contact experience
understood more broadly and not merely in the sense of “tact” and tactile experience) is
always already situated within an ethical interval or gap in a time-space.
Note also this example, which is already more closely related to the problem of ethics: “You are
driving along in your car at 30 mph on a city street. Suddenly, a young boy steps into the street in front
of your car, chasing a ball. You slam your foot on the brake pedal to bring the car to a screeching halt.
Were you consciously aware of the event before stepping on the brake? Or was that an unconscious
action that you became aware of after you hit the brakes?” (Libet 2004, p. 90).
11
“For just what the Christian mystics call the effect of grace and the new birth, is for us the only direct
expression of the freedom of the will.”
10
221
Let us remind ourselves once more of our example from Kakyō: I think Mead is
actually very close to this constellation: our act is always attuned to the very response of
the other. Mead does not use words such as the ch’i of the audience (society), but from
his thought it is evident that he knows perfectly well we have to secure our inner space
or interiority (embodied mind, embodied cognition) to be able to enter, as it were, the
stage of epistemology or ethics. Upon discussing sympathy, in his 1914 class lectures,
Mead gives an interesting passage:
“The idea of looking into the eyes of one who is suffering involves an inner idea. […] The other is a
different person and, being different, his suffering is different from mine, but he is a suffering being to
whom I react immediately. Other individuals exist for us as having inner ideas, which in a certain sense
we can never penetrate. […] It is because the material is the same that other persons have an inner idea
of us. […] The child is conscious of the hard floor long before he is aware of the introdermal self that
is injured by the hard floor” (Miller 1982, p. 62).
I will end my interpretation here. In this synchronistic reading of Mead’s philosophy I
wanted to explore the possibility of another time-space in ethics, one closely related to
Mead’s fundamental insights, but still situated within the excess, surplus, gap, or interval
which cannot simply be explained by ordinary epistemological tools that Mead had been
using in his works. There is a further need to explore this secret and paradoxical timespace of ethics, and today I have only taken the first step in that direction. We can never
become other persons and this fact secures their and our autonomy and freedom. There
always exists an interval between us, one that Aristotle mentioned in his On the Soul. But
there is another gap or interval, one that cannot be observed epistemologically since it
evades its very logic: it is best visible in a caress, and the behind the scene logic, as it were.
Like the actor from Kakyō, who must know, even before coming on stage, what he is to
expect from the audience, we too, precognitively know well before his appearance how
we would act. But the mystery of all ethics that I wanted to point to with this essay, lies
precisely in this infinitely short moment before our ethical act. Finally, I will call this
moment an interval of grace.
Bibliography
- ARISTOTLE (1984), The Complete Work of Aristotle, vol. 1, ed. J. Barnes, Princeton
University Press, Princeton NJ 1984.
- W. BERGMANN-G. HOFFMANN (1985), G.H. Mead und die Tradition der Phänomenologie, in
H. JOAS (ed.), Das Problem der Intersubjektivität, Suhrtkamp, Frankfurt a.M. 1985, pp. 93130.
- K.J. BOOTH (2013), Embodied Mind and the Mimetic Basis for Taking the Role of the Other, in
F.T. BURKE-K.P. SKOWROŃSKI (eds.), George Herbert Mead in the Twenty-First Century,
Lexington Books, Lanham MD 2013, pp. 137-148.
- J. CHING-SZE WANG (2007), John Dewey in China: To Teach and to Learn, SUNY Press,
New York NY 2007.
222
© SpazioFilosofico 2016 – ISSN: 2038-6788
- J.-L. CHRÉTIEN (2004), The Call and the Response, Engl. transl. A.A. Davenport,
Fordham University Press, New York NY 2004.
- C. CHRIST (2003), She Who Changes, Palgrave Macmillan, New York 2003.
- J. DERRIDA (1992), Given Time: The Time of the King, in “Critical Inquiry”, 18(2/1992),
pp. 161-187.
- J. DEWEY (1973), John Dewey, Lectures in China, 1919-1920, ed. and transl. by R.W.
Clopton and T.-C. Ou., The University Press of Hawaii, Honolulu HI 1973.
- J. GRANGE (2004), John Dewey, Confucius and Global Philosophy, State University of New
York Press, New York NY 2004.
- D.L. HALL-R.T. AMES (1999), The Democracy of the Dead: Dewey, Confucius, and the Hope for
Democracy in China, Open Court Publishing, Chicago and Lasalle IL 1999.
- L. IRIGARAY (2008), The Way of Love, Continuum, London 2008.
- H. JOAS (1985), G.H. Mead: A Contemporary Re-Examination of His Thought, Engl. transl.
R. Meyer, The MIT Press, Cambridge MA 1985.
- B. LIBET (2004), Mind Time: The Temporal Factor in Consciousness, foreword by S.M.
Kosslyn, Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA 2004.
- K. LÖWITH (1976), Ludwig Feuerbach, in E. THIES (ed.), Ludwig Feuerbach,
Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt 1976, pp. 33-61.
- G.H. MEAD (1967), Mind, Self and Society, The University of Chicago Press, ChiacagoLondon 1967.
- D.L. MILLER (1982), The Individual and the Social Self: Unpublished Work of George Herbert
Mead, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago IL 1982.
- S. ODIN (1992), The Social Self in Japanese Philosophy and American Pragmatism: A
Comparative Study of Watsuji Tetsurō and George Herbert Mead, in “Philosophy East and
West”, 42 (3/1992), pp. 475-501.
- A. SCHOPENHAUER (1969), The World as Will and Representation, Engl. transl. E.F.J.
Payne, Dover, New York NY 1969.
- A. SCHOPENHAUER (1998), On the Basis of Morality, Engl. transl. E.F.J. Payne, Hackett
Publishing Company, Indianapolis-Cambridge 1998.
- L. ŠKOF (2015), Breath of Proximity: Intersubjectivity, Ethics and Peace, Springer, Dordrecht
2015.
- W. TETSURO (1992), Fūdo – Wind und Erde, German transl. D. Fischer-Barnicol and O.
Ryogi, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt 1992.
- N. WIRZBA, (2010), The Witness of Humility, in B.E. BENSON-N. WIRZBA (eds.), Words of
Life, New Theological Turns in French Phenomenology, Fordham University Press, New York
2010, pp. 233-251.
- ZEAMI (1982), Kakyō: Zeami’s Fundamental Principles of Acting: Part Two, Engl. transl. M.J.
Nearman, in “Monumenta Nipponica”, 37(4/1982), pp. 459-496.
223