�
�
�
����������������������������������
��������������������������������
������������������������������
������������
�
���������
�
�
����������
���� ��������
����
�������������
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
�
���������������������������������������������������
���������������������
�
�����������������������
�
���������������������
��������������������������������
������������������������������
�
�
�������������������������������������
�
�
�
������������������������������� ��������� �������������������������
�����������������������������������������������
�
�
���� ������� ���������� � ��� ����� ��� ����� ������������ ���� ��� ������������ ������� ��� ��
��������������������������������������������������������������������������������������
�������������� ���������� ��� ���������� �������� ������ ������������ ��� ��������� ����� ����
�����������
5
Willingness to Trust as a Virtue in Argumentative
Discussions
JOSÉ ÁNGEL GASCÓN
Universidad Nacional de Educación a Distancia (UNED), Spain
[email protected]
The virtue of critical thinking has been widely emphasised,
especially the habit of calling into question any standpoint.
While that is important, argumentative practice is not possible
unless the participants display a willingness to trust.
Otherwise, continuous questioning by one party leads to an
infinite regress. Trust is necessary in order to allow for
testimony and expert opinion, but also to exclude
unwarranted suspicions that could damage the quality of an
argumentative discussion.
KEYWORDS: authority,
testimony, trust
deliberation,
expert
opinion,
1. INTRODUCTION
The capacity to scrutinise arguments and to call claims into question is
doubtless a fundamental quality for a virtuous arguer. Argumentation
theory and critical thinking—the word ‘critical’ is symptomatic here—
have correctly emphasised the importance of that skill. Moreover, the
extent to which criticism and doubt are allowed in an argumentative
discussion is an indication of the quality of the process. For this reason,
for example, one of the rules of the pragma-dialectical model of critical
discussion states that (van Eemeren & Grootendorst, 2004, p. 144):
Rule 6:
b. The antagonist may always attack a standpoint by calling
into question the propositional content or the justificatory or
refutatory force of the argumentation.
However, van Eemeren and Grootendorst explain that, although rule 6
gives the antagonist the right to call into question any standpoint, the
antagonist is not obliged to do so (2004, p. 151). Indeed, such an
91
D. Mohammed & M. Lewiński (eds.) (2016). Argumentation and Reasoned Action: Proceedings of the 1 st
European Conference on Argumentation, Lisbon, 2015. Vol. I, 91-107. London: College Publications.
92
José Ángel Gascón
obligation would easily lead to a dead end in the discussion. If the
opponent calls into question every reason that the proponent puts
forward, both arguers will be unable to make any progress in the
discussion. In order to avoid this problem, of course, argumentation
theorists consider the notion of shared premises or common ground, a
“zone of agreement” on the basis of which it could be possible to
“conduct a fruitful discussion” (p. 60). Van Eemeren and Grootendorst
recognise that (p. 139): “A critical discussion is impossible without
certain shared premises and without shared discussion rules.”
Nevertheless, even if the arguers do not share enough common
ground, this fact only does not prevent an argumentative discussion
from being possible and fruitful. The common ground may often be
sufficiently broad to allow engagement in successful discussions, but
sometimes it is not. In those cases, other resources can make the
discussion possible. For example, arguers frequently present
testimonies and arguments from authority as reasons in support of their
standpoints. Such reasons are not part of the common ground, but they
frequently pave the way towards agreement. The effectiveness of
testimonies and appeals to authorities depends on a fundamental
component of argumentation: trust.
Even though the actual practice of argumentation largely relies
on trust—and trust is given great value in studies on mediation—this
component is not frequently present in philosophical accounts of
argumentation. Furthermore, Daniel Cohen (2013) argues that
argumentation theory is biased toward scepticism. According to Cohen,
argumentation theory, by having as a fundamental principle that
everything is arguable, and by promoting a set of skills that can be easily
abused, might make it too easy for the sceptic to reject knowledge. A
virtue approach to argumentation, suggests Cohen, with “its focus on
how arguers argue, its distinction between skills and virtues, and its
embrace of the difference between rational and reasonable arguing,”
(pp. 10-11) can help us understand these biases and learn from them. I
believe Cohen is right and I will present one of the virtues that, in my
view, could make arguers more reasonable: willingness to trust.
In this paper I intend to show why the presence or absence of
trust is crucial in every discussion, how it influences the course of the
discussion, and why it is so important that arguers be willing to trust
each other. Obviously, trust is not the same as credulity, and being
willing to trust does not mean being open to believe anything and
anyone. Therefore, an explanation of the virtue of willingness to trust
must address the question of when it is wise to trust and when it is not.
In the following sections, I attempt to cast some light on those issues.
Willingness to trust as a virtue
93
2. WHAT IS TRUST?
Trust is a more widespread attitude than we might think, even though
sometimes we are willing to trust when we should not, or are not
willing to trust when there is no reason for suspicion. We not only trust
friends, with whom we have a very close relationship and share past
experiences, to tell us the truth; we also trust our doctor, whom we
might barely know, to be genuinely concerned about our health and to
have the necessary knowledge to treat us. When we ask for directions to
a complete stranger in the street, we trust him or her to be sincere. We
only worry about trust when our expectations are not fulfilled and
someone disappoints us, but usually the presence of trust is not noticed
when everything goes as expected.
People's views on trust are enormously varied, and
unfortunately there is also a large variety of academic views on trust—
views from philosophy, psychology and sociology. However, the good
news is that here we do not need a general account of trust, but rather
an explanation of the presence and importance of trust in
argumentative discussions. For this reason, I will use only those
theoretical concepts that are relatively uncontroversial and can help us
understand why willingness to trust is an argumentative virtue.
What most conceptions of trust have in common is that they
characterise it as an expectation, that is, a belief or attitude (Asen, 2013,
p. 4; Govier, 1997, p. 32). The psychologist Julian Rotter defined
interpersonal trust as “a generalized expectancy held by an individual
that the word, promise, oral or written statement of another individual
or group can be relied on” (1980, p. 1). This might be a useful
characterisation of trust for argumentation theory, which suits better
our present needs than other definitions that make reference to beliefs
about the general goodness of people or to optimism about the future—
even though those definitions might be in general preferable because
they capture the open-ended character of trust (Govier, 1997, p. 13).
It is also commonly accepted that trust involves beliefs about the
other person's competence and motivation (Fricker, 2007, p. 45; Govier,
1998, p. 6; Hardin, 2006, p. 36). When we trust someone, we believe
that he or she is competent enough to do what we expect him or her to
do, and that he or she has the appropriate motivations—that, for
example, he or she is not acting entirely in his or her own interests and
this benefits us by chance (Hardin, 2006, p. 67).
It is also useful, regardless of the account of trust one adopts, to
think of trust in terms of commitment (Hardin, 2002, p. 5). Suppose I
expect a friend to meet me at the airport tomorrow morning, but I have
not told him so and he is not aware of my expectations. Or suppose I
94
José Ángel Gascón
have the unrealistic expectation that my friend—a nurse—will cure my
chronic illness, even though he has repeatedly told me that he cannot do
that. In both cases, my friend cannot be said to have disappointed me if
he does not do what I expect him to do. The reason is very simple: he
has not committed himself to do that. This is also the reason why people
can be trustworthy in areas where their knowledge is limited, so long as
they know their limits and do not commit themselves to do what they
cannot do.
Finally, virtually all theorists agree that trust involves a risk.
Even though this condition leaves out some uses of “trust”—such as
when somebody, probably a poet or a philosopher, says “I trust the sun
to rise tomorrow”—it seems that trust entails uncertainty. As Hardin
says (2002, p. 12): “More generally, one might say trust is embedded in
the capacity or even need for choice on the part of the trusted.” It does
not make sense, for instance, to say that I trust my sister not to spend all
my money on a ridiculously expensive car if she does not have access to
my bank account. Trusting involves being vulnerable to some extent
(Hardin, 2002, p. 46): “If I trust you to act on my behalf, I set myself up
for the possibility of disappointment, even severe loss.”
Trust, then, is an attitude based on beliefs about a person. It is
therefore a cognitive concept (Hardin, 2002, p. 10). This has important
implications: since we cannot freely decide to believe or not a
proposition, it follows that we cannot choose whether or not to trust. Of
course, I can decide to cooperate with someone I do not trust, or to
pretend that I trust him or her, but that does not make trust more real.
Thus Hardin argues (2002, p. 59):
I just do or do not trust to some degree, depending on the
evidence I have. I do not, in an immediate instance, choose to
trust, I do not take any risk in trusting. Only actions are
chosen—for example, to act as I would if I did in fact trust or
to take a chance on your being trustworthy beyond any
evidence I have that you will be trustworthy.
While Trudy Govier includes not only beliefs but also feelings in her
characterisation of trust, she also claims that we cannot choose to trust
(1997, p. 45):
Trust is based on beliefs and feelings that, though sometimes
alterable after critical reflection and deliberation, cannot be
created or abolished at will.
Willingness to trust as a virtue
95
Actually, this fact can be seen as a reason in support of a virtue-based
normative account of trust. We cannot choose to trust someone to do
something in an immediate instance, as Hardin says. However, our
trusting or not largely depends on our character—apart, of course, from
the other person's trustworthiness—so we can cultivate a character
that make us trust the right people in the right situations. We can
become sensible to what the other person's knowledge and motivations
are, of his or her commitments, and of the risks involved. Klemens
Kappel, who also rejects the idea that we can decide to trust,
acknowledges that (2014, p. 2026): “I can, of course, decide to cultivate
epistemic trust in you, or at least I could decide to try to cultivate a
certain pattern of epistemic trust.”
Moreover, even if we could choose to trust in a particular
situation, there are just too many factors to be taken into account by
general rules or principles. If willingness to trust is to be studied from a
normative perspective, a sensibility to the specificity of every situation
seems more appropriate—the kind of sensibility that is entailed by
virtue. In addition, if—as we have seen—trust is based on beliefs, then
we can benefit from the insights provided by virtue epistemology.
3. IS IT WISE TO TRUST?
In the last section it was pointed out that we cannot choose to trust or
not in a particular situation. There is an additional limitation regarding
trust: in the real world it is impossible for any of us never to trust
anybody. As Trudy Govier says (1997, p. 62): “There is no real
alternative to trusting other people for the truth.” From the moment we
are born, trust is a precondition of knowledge and even of our having
any experience at all. Govier says (p. 61):
Such trust can be argued to be a priori because there is a sense
in which it is logically prior to experience itself. It is prior
because it is a condition of experience.
Without trust, we could not even be sure of information as basic as our
birthday or our real name, for we do not have direct evidence of that—
we must trust our parents, our doctor, the institution that issued our ID
card, or what have you. Children are predisposed to unquestioningly
trust their parents and other people, and that makes them grow and
learn (Govier, 1998, p. 68). Govier even places trust at the foundation of
meaningful communication (p. 8): “we must believe that the other says
what he means and means what he says.”
96
José Ángel Gascón
Of course, the fact that we cannot dispense with trust altogether
does not imply that we must childishly believe everybody. As Hardin
notes (2002, p. 71), “infant trust would be stupid in an adult.” As we
grow up, we learn to question some—perhaps many—of the beliefs that
we have acquired. We develop the capacity of reasoning and of asking
ourselves whether someone is trustworthy, and by asking questions
about the people's trustworthiness we obtain knowledge that
determines our degree of trust (Hardin, 2002, p. 71). As we grow up,
then, our unquestioning trust becomes a more nuanced and reasonable
capacity for trust.
Apart from the degree of trust, we must also take into account
what we trust the other person to do. Trust not only involves a truster
and a trusted, it also takes place in a particular situation or action.
Nobody trusts anybody without restriction. We might, for example, trust
a friend to take care of our car, but do not trust her to give us back two
thousand dollars if we lend the money to her. Therefore, trust can be
considered as a three-part relation: a person trusts someone to do X
(Hardin, 2002, p. 9).
When we have a virtuous willingness to trust, we are sufficiently
sensitive to know who we can trust, to what degree, and to do what.
Here I will focus on the kind of trust that several argumentative settings
require. As we will see in the next sections, this includes believing the
claims of trustworthy experts and witnesses, accepting the arguments of
trustworthy arguers, and being willing to cooperate with trustworthy
partners in a deliberation.
Trusting in this sense will be wise if it involves a prudential
assessment of the components that we saw in the previous section,
especially the “sort of person the other is, with regard to motivations
and to competence” (Govier, 1997, p. 4), and the risks involved in the
particular situation. Our past experience with the other person is, of
course, useful as well; for example, we will not continue to trust
someone who repeatedly disappoints us (Hardin, 2002, p. 72).
Sometimes, however, we will have no past experience with the other
person, as when we deal with complete strangers. The most obvious
example is asking someone for directions in the street. In those cases,
we tend to believe the information that the strangers give us because
the risks involved are very low—the worst-case scenario would be for
us to get lost. If, however, we are the editors of a journal, we would not
accept a stranger's paper in the street, for the risks are higher—our
reputation is at stake.
As Trudy Govier puts it, “trust makes a leap” (1997, p. 47).
Whether or not we are willing to make that leap depends on the
elements mentioned above, but in any case we will be vulnerable to
Willingness to trust as a virtue
97
some extent. For this reason, our willingness to trust also depends on
our character, on whether we are “self-confident and secure enough to
cope with disappointments and adapt to changing circumstances”
(Govier, 1997, p. 29). The question, then, is not whether or not it is wise
to trust, but when and to what extent.
4. TRUST IN ARGUMENTATION
4.1. Appeals to expert opinion and testimony
Are arguments from expert opinion legitimate? Is it wise to trust
experts? Recently, Moti Mizrahi (2013) argued that arguments from
expert opinion are all weak, in the sense that their premises provide
little or no support for their conclusion. He cites several studies that
show—among other things—that, statistically, experts' predictions are
only slightly more accurate than mere chance, and that experts' findings
are likely to be refuted after a few years (p. 64). Therefore, given that
the fact that an expert holds a claim p does not make p significantly
more likely to be true, all arguments from expert opinion must be weak.
Mizrahi's article was followed by a response from Markus Seidel
(2014). Seidel points out that our dependence on expert opinion is so
strong that arguments in support of the absolute rejection of appeals to
expert opinions, like Mizrahi's, are self-undermining. He argues that,
even in order to support the conclusion that arguments from expert
opinion are weak, we need to resort to some kind of argument from
expert opinion (p. 213):
Mizrahi is relying on the expertise of others in conducting
empirical studies on expertise in order to come to his claim
that there is empirical evidence for the conclusion that
arguments from expert opinion are weak arguments.
I believe Seidel is right. As Trudy Govier points out (1997, p. 54): “We
can check some claims and reports made by other people, but only by
relying on the claims and reports of still other people.” But Mizrahi's
contention is actually a little more complex and interesting than that.
Mizrahi makes clear that, according to him, arguments from expert
opinion are those which do not rely on empirical evidence or even
agreement among experts at all (2013, p. 71):
In other words, once we take into account considerations of
evidence for p and whether or not p is consistent with
common knowledge in a field, then an argument from expert
opinion is no longer just an appeal to expert opinion. Rather, it
98
José Ángel Gascón
is an appeal to expertise, evidence, and agreement among
experts.
Hence, it seems that, according to Mizrahi, an argument from expert
opinion relies solely on the expert's claiming that p, and taking into
account any other consideration would entail adding premises to the
argument and therefore rendering it a different type of argument. This,
however, is a rather limited conception of the argument from expert
opinion. It seems to lead us away from reasonable trust and closer to
blind faith. Moreover, I believe it is misleading in two respects. Firstly, it
overlooks the fact that, even if the expert opinion is based on empirical
evidence, some degree of trust is still required for the argument to be
convincing. Thus, for example, Mizrahi did not personally conduct the
studies he cites in support of his position (2013, p. 76): “Granted, I did
not conduct any experimental studies on expertise. Luckily, I don't have
to. Others have done the hard work already.” How do we know that the
research was properly conducted? And that the results are not forged?
Results often admit of several interpretations, why should we accept the
author's interpretation as the best? Responses to this questions always
depend partly on our degree of trust in the expert. Of course, trusting
does not mean blindly believing anything any expert says; but, as Seidel
holds, “reasonably scrutinizing authorities should not lead us to a
rampant scepticism about expertise” (2014, pp. 192-193).
Secondly, the fact that issues about empirical evidence and
agreement among experts are taken into account does not mean that the
argument put forward is not a genuine appeal to expert opinion. Those
components can be an intrinsic part of the strength of the argument
from authority, even though they are not premises of the argument. For
example, Douglas Walton proposes the following scheme (1997, p. 210):
E is an expert in domain D.
E asserts that A is known to be true.
A is within D.
Therefore, A may (plausibly) be taken to be true.
Walton takes into account further information in the critical questions
he proposes for the evaluation of the strength of the argument from
authority (p. 223):
Expertise question: How credible is E as an expert source?
Field question: Is E an expert in the field that A is in?
Opinion question: What did E assert that implies A?
Trustworthiness question: Is E personally reliable as a source?
Willingness to trust as a virtue
99
Consistency question: Is A consistent with what other experts
assert?
Backup evidence question: Is A's assertion based on evidence?
Critical questions, then, are not part of the argument scheme; they are
not premises. Instead, they are part of the dialectical framework for the
evaluation of arguments from expert opinion (p. 158). This shows how
we can consider empirical evidence and agreement among experts as
relevant components of the strength of the argument from expert
opinion, without necessarily incorporating them into the argument as
premises and, contrary to what Mizrahi claims, without turning it into a
different type of argument. By doing this, we can better understand that
appeals to expert opinion involve both reasonable scrutiny and trust.
Similar considerations support the legitimacy of arguments from
testimony. Govier (1993, p. 93) defines testimonial claims as “those
which describe or purport to describe a particular person's
observations, experience and related memories.” The epistemologist
John Hardwig (1991, p. 698) argued that beliefs based on testimony
might be not only unavoidable but also epistemically superior to beliefs
based on empirical evidence. The reason is that, individually, we cannot
gather all the necessary empirical evidence in support of every one of
our beliefs. Therefore, if only first-hand empirical evidence should be
taken into account as reasons in support of our beliefs, most of our
reasons would be very poor. However, we all have very good evidence
for at least some of our beliefs—especially if we have witnessed an
event or are experts in some domain—that constitutes our reasons. If
we take into account testimonial evidence, that means that we take into
account other people's reasons, including the experts' and witnesses', so
we will have much better reasons that justify our beliefs. Thus, Hardwig
states his principle of testimony (p. 697):
If A has good reasons to believe that B has good reasons to
believe p, then A has good reasons to believe p.
A will not believe that B's testimony gives him or her good reasons to
believe p, Hardwig adds (1991, p. 700), unless A trusts B.1 But, actually,
Hardwig was not referring to testimonies of common people, or to
laymen's trust in experts, but to the very scientific enterprise (p. 706):
Kappel (2014) proposes a reliabilist interpretation of Hardwig's ideas,
according to which epistemic trust implies the existence of a reliable beliefforming process that is discriminating and defeater-sensitive. However, he is
concerned with the conditions for justification and the definition of knowledge,
and here I focus on internal traits that make an individual virtuous.
1
100
José Ángel Gascón
“Often, then, a scientific community has no alternative to trust, including
trust in the character of its members.”
The question, then, is whether or not to trust a person that
presents his or her testimony in a particular situation. An argument
based on testimony belongs to the kind of arguments that Douglas
Walton names arguments from position to know, and the critical
questions that he proposes—where a stands for the other person and A
stands for what he or she claims—are (2006, p. 86):
Is a in a position to know whether A is true (false)?
Is a an honest (trustworthy, reliable) source?
Did a assert that A is true (false)?
Hence, Walton's critical questions for arguments from authority as well
as for arguments from position to know provide helpful guidelines for
deciding whether to trust someone in a particular situation. Note,
though, that critical questions are neither clear-cut rules nor an
algorithm that yields a unique answer. They are very useful as a guide,
and they are questions that the respondent can ask to the proponent,
but they cannot remove the need for practical wisdom and sensibility to
particular situations. Willingness to trust is, after all, a virtue.
4.2. Arguments that rely on trust
The acceptability of the conclusion of certain arguments, then, is a
matter of trust—and, I would add, this also happens sometimes with
some premises in any kind of argument. But in some cases the inference
relies on trust as well. In his response to Bowell and Kingsbury (2013),
who argued against the legitimacy of a virtue approach to
argumentation, Andrew Aberdein (2014) claims that facts about the
arguer are sometimes relevant to the evaluation of his or her argument.
Bowell and Kingsbury themselves provide a compelling example (p. 27):
Suppose someone tries to convince me that Tom is not fluent
in German, on the grounds that Tom is a New Zealander and
only 2% of New Zealanders are fluent in German. This looks
like a good enough inductive argument. However, there could
be information that I lack which would undermine the
argument without falsifying the premises; for example, the
information that Tom is the New Zealand ambassador to
Germany. Given this, facts about the arguer might matter. [...]
Is the arguer the sort of person who would tell me if he knew
that Tom was the New Zealand ambassador to Germany, or is
he the sort of person that would delight in tricking me into
Willingness to trust as a virtue
101
thinking that the New Zealand ambassador to Germany
doesn’t speak German?
Bowell and Kingsbury argue that either the argument put forward is
inductively strong regardless of whether information is being hidden, or
it actually contains the unstated premise “There is nothing unusual
about Tom that bears on the likelihood of his speaking German”.
However, when discussing arguments from expert opinion, we saw how
the strength of the argument can be assessed without including every
criterion as a premise in the argument. This case is very similar in this
regard. In particular, here the strength of the argument depends in part
on our trusting the arguer not to hide information from us.
The great majority of arguments we normally use are defeasible,
that is, their conclusion is plausibly true and the inference may lose its
strength if new evidence appears. For this reason, virtually any
defeasible argument will be more convincing if it is put forward by
someone whom we trust to share all the information he or she has with
us, even if that information could undermine his or her own position.
One and the same argument might be more convincing if presented by a
trustworthy arguer than if presented by someone untrustworthy—and
for good reasons.
Consider another, probably more realistic example. A petroleum
company intends to extract crude oil in a populated region, and after
some empirical research it publishes a report supporting the conclusion
that there will be no undesirable consequences for the population or the
environment. Some of the inhabitants read—and understand—the
report, and although the data is consistent with other, impartial reports
and they have no other information about the possible environmental
impact of the extractions, they distrust the company’s arguments. They
do not accept them because of the company’s obvious interests and
because that company has omitted relevant information from its reports
in the past. Perhaps they are not convinced that there will be
undesirable consequences either, but they suspend judgement instead
of accepting the conclusions of the report. The inhabitants do not accept
the arguments because they do not trust the company—and, in this case,
surely it is not their fault.
4.3. Deliberations and trust
Deliberations are a kind of argumentative dialogue that is intended to
resolve on a course of action or a normative issue. Robert Asen (2013, p.
5) defines deliberation as “an encounter among interlocutors who
engage in a process of considering and weighing various perspectives
102
José Ángel Gascón
and proposals for what they regard as issues of common concern.” I will
discuss certain dimensions of trust that are probably more crucial in
deliberations than in other kinds of argumentations.
Trust is doubtless an essential basis of successful and
satisfactory deliberations. However, trust should not be considered as a
necessary condition for deliberations—they benefit from trust, but they
can also take place in the absence of trust and subsequently foster it. As
Asen holds (p. 15): “People need not wait for trust to deliberate. Instead,
deliberation itself may serve as a means by which we come to trust
others, and our trust may become stronger with practice.” Several
factors, circumstances, or behaviours promote trust. In this section, I
will present them as signals, that could warrant our trusting someone in
the context of a deliberation, and to which we should be sensitive.
Whether or not to trust our partners in a deliberation is not so
much a matter of the outcomes of the process as of the process itself. If
the process of deliberation is conducted in a way that makes everyone
involved feel included, recognised, and respected, the deliberation will
very likely be satisfactory to all. Thus (Asen, 2013, p. 8):
Relations of trust may enable affirmative answers to questions
that participants regularly confront in deliberation: Can I
believe what other people say? How shall I evaluate their
evidence? Are they listening to me? Will the other people
involved in the deliberation heed our decision? Trust
strengthens deliberation not by ensuring an outcome, but by
committing participants to the process of producing a
deliberative outcome, namely, a judgment.
Asen (2013, p. 9) proposes four attitudes that help build trust in
deliberation: flexibility, forthrightness, engagement, and heedfulness.
Firstly, it seems intuitively correct that a participant in a deliberation
who is flexible about his or her beliefs and proposals conveys a sense
that he or she is genuinely concerned about reaching an agreement.
Flexibility allows the arguer to acknowledge the others, to form his or
her views in collaboration with them, and to recognise different
positions as reasonable and justified (p. 10). Secondly, forthrightness
means that the arguer is honest, that he or she means what he or she
says, makes plain his or her motives and goals, offers reasons in support
of his or her position, and does not deceive or hide information. This is
perhaps the quality that is most directly relevant to trustworthiness, for
it is the arguer's honesty what is often called into question in
deliberations—for example, by accusing him or her of having a hidden
Willingness to trust as a virtue
103
agenda. Thirdly, trustworthy arguers try to engage each other's
perspectives, learning about (p. 12):
different perspectives, including understanding why people
hold their beliefs, how these beliefs may be different from and
similar to one's own, how people may take a different route to
a shared judgment, and how similar starting points may lead
to different interpretations and judgments.
And, finally, when an arguer displays heedfulness by truly paying
attention to what the others have to say, he or she shows that
deliberation matters and that, for example, it is not just a means of
trying to “provide political cover for a decision that already has been
made”, and that he or she will not “conduct their future actions without
any reference to relevant deliberations” (pp. 13-14).
5. THE DANGERS OF UNGROUNDED DISTRUST
Why speak of the dangers of distrust? Is it not more dangerous and
more frequent to overly trust people? Gullibility is no doubt a vice in
argumentation, but perhaps it is only indicative of the absence of the
virtue of critical thinking. When discussing the virtue of willingness to
trust, the related vice, I believe, is not gullibility but ungrounded
distrust or suspicion. Rotter explains (1980, p. 4):
If trust is simply believing communications, then high trust
must be equated with gullibility. However, if we redefine trust
as believing communications in the absence of clear or strong
reasons for not believing (i.e. in ambiguous situations) and
gullibility as believing when most people of the same social
group would consider belief naïve and foolish, then trust can
be independent of gullibility.
Actually, there are reasons to define trust as independent of gullibility.
Rotter continues:
In fact, anecdotal evidence suggests that it is the low truster
who is taken in by the disarming dishonesty of the con artist
and is the frequent victim of con games.
Thus, surprisingly, it seems that one of the dangers of distrust is that it
could lead to gullibility. Actually, there might be a very good explanation
for that. As has been argued, absolute distrust is not a real alternative;
we all need to trust in some people in order to have not only knowledge,
104
José Ángel Gascón
but also most of our beliefs and experiences. For this reason, low
trusters cannot distrust everybody; instead, they do not trust in most
people. They trust in a small number of people only, and that makes
them dependent on fewer sources of knowledge and therefore they
cannot check the reliability of many of those sources (Govier, 1997, p.
130). Low trusters are, then, more uncritical and more prone to error.
Consider the case of people who do not trust scientists. When
arguing with someone who does not consider scientific opinions as
expert opinions, he or she will not accept any appeal to those
authorities. In reality, however, those people are bound to trust other—
alleged—authorities. Complete distrustfulness, as has been argued, is
impossible. So what usually happens is that those people—so-called low
trusters—put their trust instead in homoeopaths, astrologists, religious
authorities, or the like. This means that they put their trust in fewer
people, becoming more dependent on them than high trusters are on
the more numerous people they trust. This path is even more manifest in
the case of people who believe in conspiracy theories. Ironically, an
initial attitude of low trust leads to gullibility.
A second danger of ungrounded distrust does not directly affect
the arguer himself or herself—as happens when it causes gullibility—
but the others. The problem arises when we distrust certain people due
to prejudice and stereotypes. When this distrust is widespread, those
people's voices are silenced in practice and there is a real risk that their
experiences, beliefs, and proposals are not taken into account. Feminist
authors have drawn our attention to this problem, which has been
called rhetorical disadvantage (Govier, 1993) or testimonial injustice
(Fricker, 2007).
We frequently deal with strangers or hear their testimonies and
opinions—for example, on television and in newspapers—and we have
to decide whether or nor not to trust them without much evidence. In
order to make a judgement in such circumstances, we commonly resort
to stereotypes, which function as heuristics and are not necessarily bad
(Fricker, 2007, p. 32). Some of those stereotypes, however, are
unreliable, are maintained in the face of counter-evidence, and
undermine the speaker's credibility. They are prejudiced judgements
that distort the hearer's perception of the speaker (p. 36). According to
Miranda Fricker, the testimonial injustice that results from prejudiced
judgements “excludes the subject from trustful conversation” (p. 53),
but unfortunately it is “a normal feature of our testimonial practices” (p.
43).
Trudy Govier (1993) explains that prejudice and stereotypes can
act in any of the four different levels of assessment of testimonies. First,
one can dismiss a testimony because it is assumed that the speaker is
Willingness to trust as a virtue
105
not serious—he or she is just joking or being ironic. Presumably the
prejudice here involves our own ways of communication (p. 97):
“Standards of rationality, seriousness, and maturity incorporate norms
that are not neutral as regards age, gender, race, class, culture, and
style.” In the second place, assuming the speaker is serious, he or she
may be considered not to be truthful on the basis of stereotypes
regarding the social group to which he or she belongs. Thirdly, some
stereotypes can similarly attribute a lack of competence to that social
group, and hence to the speaker in question. And, finally, even assuming
that the speaker is serious, truthful and competent, one can ultimately
decide not to accept his or her testimony because it contradicts some of
our beliefs. While it is normally a good practice to question beliefs that
somehow contradict our own—and, of course, to question our own
beliefs at the same time—Govier explains that this norm can make us
reject the testimonies of people who have different experiences (p. 98):
To the extent that A is a person different from B in experience,
social standing, gender and so on, B is likely to have
established beliefs and preconceptions different from those of
A. Ironically the very features that make A's testimony
necessary, intellectually interesting, and important to B may
also serve to render it unbelievable.
If general principles and norms might cause those problems, what can
be done? Prejudices need not be conscious beliefs from which we infer
that certain speaker is not trustworthy. Instead, they are often a sort of
“background theory” that affects our perception of people's credibility
(Fricker, 2007, p. 71). Fricker argues that the “model for judgement” in
the testimonial sphere “is perceptual, and so non-inferential” (p. 72).
For this reason, Fricker advocates a virtue approach to epistemic
testimony, which does not rely on sets of rules but on “a sensitivity to
epistemically salient features of the situation and the speaker's
performance” (Ibid.). Rules and norms might, of course, be useful as
general guidelines, but they are not the whole story. For example,
among other things, virtue involves feeling the appropriate kind of
emotions. I conclude with Fricker's own words (p. 80):
When it comes to epistemic trust, as with purely moral trust, it
can be good advice to listen to one's emotions, for a virtuous
hearer's emotional responses to different speakers in different
contexts are trained and honed by experience. The feeling of
trust in the virtuous hearer is a sophisticated emotional radar
for detecting trustworthiness in speakers.
106
José Ángel Gascón
6. CONCLUSION
I have emphasised the importance of being willing to trust and the
different dimensions of trust in argumentative situations. Yet, of course,
trusting anyone, trustworthy or not, is not wise. In fact, it could be
dangerous or even morally wrong. Trusting a complete stranger to take
care of a baby would be not only foolish but also reprehensible. When
referring to the problem of declining trust, discussed by many scholars,
Hardin says (2002, p. 30): “Commonly, the best device for creating trust
is to establish and support trustworthiness.”
It is also very difficult—and probably a bad idea—to have even
slight trust in some especially dangerous circumstances. The degree of
trust that one can afford, as has been said, depends on the risks
involved, and some particular situations might dramatically raise the
risks of even small degrees of trust. Trudy Govier presents a particularly
extreme example (1997, p. 134):
If relatives simply disappear, if one is starved, beaten, and
tortured, if friends and colleagues may be spies for a brutal
regime, people are unlikely to be high trusters, and a
recommendation to trust more makes little sense.
Therefore, in the absence of trustworthiness or in risky situations,
willingness to trust the trustworthy person will not make any difference.
Why not focus on trustworthiness then? The reason is that
trustworthiness alone is not sufficient; a sensibility to trustworthiness,
or disposition to believe the trustworthy person, is also necessary. As
has been explained, ungrounded distrust can seriously harm the course
of a discussion, and trustworthiness cannot solve this problem.
REFERENCES
Aberdein, A. (2014). In defence of virtue: The legitimacy of agent-based
argument appraisal. Informal Logic, 34(1), 77-93.
Asen, R. (2013). Deliberation and trust. Argumentation and Advocacy, 50(1), 217.
Bowell, T., & Kingsbury, J. (2013). Virtue and argument: Taking character into
account. Informal Logic, 33(1), 22-32.
Cohen, D. H. (2013). Skepticism and argumentative virtues. Cogency, 5(1), 9-31.
van Eemeren, F. H., & Grootendorst, R. (2004). A systematic theory of
argumentation. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Fricker, M. (2007). Epistemic injustice: Power and the ethics of knowing. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Willingness to trust as a virtue
107
Govier, T. (1993). When logic meets politics: Testimony, distrust, and rhetorical
disadvantage. Informal Logic, 15(2), 93-104.
Govier, T. (1997). Social trust and human communities. Montreal: McGillQueen’s University Press.
Govier, T. (1998). Dilemmas of trust. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.
Hardin, R. (2002). Trust and trustworthiness. New York: Russell Sage
Foundation.
Hardin, R. (2006). Trust. Malden, MA: Polity Press.
Hardwig, J. (1991). The role of trust in knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 88(12),
693-708.
Kappel, K. (2014). Believing on trust. Synthese, 191, 2009-2028.
Mizrahi, M. (2013). Why arguments from expert opinion are weak arguments.
Informal Logic, 33(1), 57-79.
Rotter, J. B. (1980). Interpersonal trust, trustworthiness, and gullibility.
American Psychologist, 35(1), 1-7.
Seidel, M. (2014). Throwing the baby out with the water: From reasonably
scrutinizing authorities to rampant scepticism about expertise.
Informal Logic, 34(2), 192-218.
Walton, D. (1997). Appeal to expert opinion: Arguments from authority.
University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Walton, D. N. (2006). Fundamentals of critical argumentation. New York:
Cambridge University Press.