POSTCOLONIAL THEORY AND
THE 'POST-' CONDITION
Aijaz Ahmad
The End of History is the death of Man as such.
Alexandre Kojeve
The issue of 'postcolonial theory' shall detain us at some length presently.'
So, let me start by reflecting on the other term in the title of the discussion
at hand: the Post Condition. The phrase itself is taken from Niethammer
was
whose book on the past careers of the concept of 'posthi~tory'~
published in Hamburg barely a few months after Francis Fukuyama, the
philosopher from Rand Corporation, published his famous essay which he
then went on to revise and expand into the even more famous book that
outlines his own tamer version of Koj6ve's philosophically magisterial
statement on fin de l'histoire? In political persuasion, philosophical stance
and structure of argument, the two authors could hardly be more dissimilar.
It is uncanny, therefore, that both should have been concerned - Fukuyama
as advocate, Niethammer from a position at once antagonistic and nuanced
- with those strands in European intellectual history which have been fond
of announcing that History has already ended. Since we hear so much these
days about the End of History and its 'metanarratives of emancipation' from Fukuyama in one register, but in many more registers from postmodernist, deconstmctivist and postcolonialist positions - it might be useful to
begin by reflecting briefly on some of the political origins of this postist
philosophical reflex.
The origins of the idea are obviously traceable to Hegel but then enunciations of this kind, often in versions very different from anything Hegel
might have said or thought, became particularly loud and bewilderingly
various at two distinct historical junctures: during the 1930s - in the midst
of revolution, depression, fascism and world war - and then in the present
period of capitalist triumphalism. Meanwhile, the repertoire of posthistorical imaginings has been refracted through complex and competing
traditions of thought, and it would be a mistake to identify it all with a
singular political stance. In Hegel's reflections on the French Revolution,
354
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
of course, this idea of the 'End' had the predominant meaning of 'Purpose'
or 'Vocation': the proposition, in other words, that History had finally
found its vocation in the Idea of Liberty which had become the irreversible
ground on which collective human struggles were henceforth to be fought.
By the 1930s, however, in the times of National Socialism, three
competing versions were to emerge in definitions of posthistoire. In Nazi
apologetics, the Third Reich itself was portrayed as the Endstate, still in
the process of its universalisation, towards which history was said to have
been tending. Secondly, those who were later disillusioned with the Reich,
either with the manner of its progression or with its demise, were then to
cultivate a posthistorical melancholy, becoming deeply sceptical not only
about the feasibility of collective social projects of any kind but also about
what Spengler had already called 'rose-coloured progress,' so that modes
of withdrawal ranged from stoical a-sociality, to (to use a Foucauldian
phrase for our own purposes) Care of the Self, to quasi-aristocratic
clericism of Being.'
But, then, in a completely different kind of variant, some of the most
powerful thought that arose among the German intelligentsia in opposition
to the Nazis, notably the writings of Horkheimer and Adorno, identified a
little too easily a critique of the technologically efficient barbarism of the
Nazis with a global Eclipse of Reason and Art - identified that particular
barbarism, indeed, with a cage-like entrapment in the technological reason
of the Modern as such. Adorno's remorseless avant-gardism in matters of
Art and Literature, as the reliable refuge from technological Reason and
popular culture alike, is of a piece with the stringent pessimism of Minima
Moralia and a pervasive sense that collective politics of a revolutionary
kind is really impossible in the face of the 'massification' of modern
culture; 'mass' and 'popular' are, in the writings of Horkheimer and
Adorno, words of punctual and irredeemable degradation. What Bourdieu
calls Heidegger's 'ultra-revolutionary conservatism' and 'aristocratic
populism' meet their contrary and complement, in Adorno's writings, in
the form of an avant-gardist aristocratism, in which Art seems often to
serve the same function as that of Being in Heidegger's 'effects of priestly
prophe~y'.~
In this version, the Third Reich, and the pervading technological Reason of which the Reich is seen to be the chief embodiment,
spells out the end of History, then, not as its realization, as Nazi apologists
would have it, but as its final negation, spelling out the impossibility of
either the thinking or the making of History as an emancipatory project in
any foreseeable future.
Let us be more precise, though. For much of the leftwing philosophy
that came of age in Western Europe between Petrograd and Munich,
especially around the years that brought the Depression and the Hitlerite
triumph, political reality was grim three times over: Nazi barbarism, surely,
AIJAZ AHMAD
355
but also the dashing of Bolshevik possibilities and revolutionary hopes in
Stalin's USSR, and the descent of what one knew as 'liberal capitalism'
into the Depression on the one hand, great intensification of consumerist
fetishism on the other. Faced with such a history, and even though he
probably did not quite comprehend the extent of Stalinist revision of
Bolshevism, Gramsci, in the loneliness of a fascist prison, did remain
attached to the formula he had made his own, 'optimism of the will,
pessimism of the intellect'. In contrast, Adorno, who himself seems never
to have been intrinsically part of a mass movement, even a defeated one,
could identify 'optimism' only with the aesthetic intensities and narrow
plenitudes of avant-garde Art; History, in the older philosophical sense of
a project in which the emancipation of some was inextricably linked with
the emancipation of all, seemed now to have virtually no prospects.
This avant-gardist and academic elitism as a reaction to political disillusion was of course to return on a much wider scale, this time among the
Parisian intellectuals who became dominant in the aftermath of May 1968,
especially as many of them moved from the Far Left to make their peace
with a new and neo-liberal conservatism. The striking feature of this return
of cultural elitism, however, was that all those themes of the Frankfurt
School - antinomies of the Enlightenment, Eclipse of Reason, the ambiguities of Progress, the massification of culture, the decline of revolutionary
possibility - which had produced such disturbance and even moral
pessimism for Adorno and Benjamin, were now re-staged as sources of
pleasure and signs of a new freedom, as if this new sense of living in the
aftermath of the end of meaning, the death of the social, etc., produced an
unprecedented range of possibilities for play - as if Adorno was being reread through Daniel Bell, Marshall McLuhan, and Donald Duck. In one
major aspect, the hallmark of the postmodern aesthetic is that what was
experienced as a source of anguish in the Modernist aesthetic is now staged
in the register of infinite gratification. Furthermore, the postmodern is
posthistorical in the precise sense of being a discourse of the end of
meaning, in the Derridean sense of infinite deferral of all meaning in
language and philosophical labour alike, as well as in the Lyotardian sense
both of what he calls 'incredulity toward the metanarratives of emancipation' as well as the assertion that there can be no criteria for choosing
between different 'language games' that are external to the respective
'games' as such. Characteristically, this postmodern philosophical
consciousness distinguishes itself from an earlier, largely existentialist
sense of meaninglessness and the Absurd by positing its own discourse of
the end of meaning as a happy liberation from the Logos as such.
We thus have not one but two claims regarding the End of History.
There is the quasi-Hegelian claim put forth by Fukuyama which itself
makes a strong gesture of reconciliation with Nietzsche, as we shall see.
356
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
But there is also the deconstructivist, postmodernist claim which has a
much more complex lineage: connected not with Hegel but with Heidegger
- and through Heidegger, with the philosophical atmosphere of postWeimar Germany - and descended more or less directly from Nietzsche,
but from a Nietzschean strand rather different than the one that Fukuyama
invokes. These are philosophically different claims, with distinct modes of
argumentation. Yet there are resemblances as well, the most striking of
which is that neither is able or willing to think of a possible future for
humanity that would be basically different than today's neo-liberalist
triumph and consequent universalisation of commodity fetishism. But,
then, how is it that philosophers as different as Fukuyama and the
postmoderns reach more or less the same conclusion? A common
commitment to the existing modalities of capitalist democracy is obviously
the more substantial link, but there are also commanding influences,
notably that of Kojtve, that remind us of some shared philosophical origins
for the two strands in posthistorical thinking today, however divergent they
may be in other respects.
Now, Fukuyama himself foregrounds his debt to Kojtve, and the fact
that this influence has been filtered through Leo Strauss and Allan Bloom
is also well known. That Kojtve should exercise his influence on a section
of the U.S. intelligentsia through such solidly reactionary interlocutors is
itself significant, and goes some way in explaining how Fukuyama's
argument which purports to take seriously Hegel's Master-Slave Dialectic
does nevertheless move effortlessly to the jubilant conviction that capitalist
democracy, headed by the United States, had not only triumphed over its
chief adversaries, principally communism, but had also proved itself to be
something of a terminating point in the political evolution of h~mankind.~
What is less widely appreciated is the extent and contradictory nature of
Kojtve's influence in Paris, from the early 1930s onward. His Seminar on
Hegel, mainly on the Phenomenology, which lasted from 1933 to 1939,
was one of the defining events that made Hegel so central a figure in
French philosophical debates for the next two decades or so. But it was a
very special reading of Hegel, filtered equally through Marx and
Heidegger; Kojkve may well be credited with introducing Heidegger to the
French intelligentsia. Indeed, the pairing of Marx and Heidegger, which
became such a convention in Derridean deconstruction, is traceable
directly to Kojtve, with the key difference that the deconstructivists tend to
drop Hegel altogether and claim to 'radicalize' Marx through the superior
authority of Heidegge~~
This 'radicalization' of both Hegel and Marx
through the application of Heidegger - whose thought Karl Jaspers,
Kojtve's teacher and Heidegger's own one-time friend, was to find 'in its
essence unfree, dictatorial, uncommunicative'8 - was one side of the story.
During that same phase, Kojtve had been, along with Baudrillard, a
AIJAZ AHMAD
357
Communist? Meanwhile he was also in sympathetic touch with the wellknown far-left group, Socialisme ou Barbarie, which included both Lyotard
and Castoriadis, and which Walter Benjamin was also to contact through
Georges Bataille, a key member of Kojbve's seminar. Indeed, Kojeve was
to have a decisive influence on both Bataille and Lacan, who were among
his favourite students and were to emerge much later as seminal figures in
poststructuralist thought.''
What we are tracing here is not something as direct as a uniform intellectual or political lineage but a certain milieu, a complex ideological
matrix, almost an atmosphere, and certain modes of thought that coalesced
and collided with each other in complex ways. Heidegger seems to have
been a central figure (Kojtve conducted his seminar on Hegel in one
auditorium while Henri Cobin expounded on Heidegger's Being and Time
in an adjoining one). Even though Fukuyama's book has merely one index
entry for Heidegger it is safe to say that he too is connected, through the
influences of Bloom and Strauss, with precisely that intellectual milieu of
radical conservatism during the interwar years in Germany whose
ideological moorings Niethammer illuminates and which included
Heidegger and Schmitt as quite central figures. Kojbve himself was greatly
influenced by Heidegger's philosophy but there is no indication that he
ever drew close to National Socialism, even though his intellectual
relations with Carl Schmitt, his close partnership with Leo Strauss, and his
philosophical fascination with violence" would seem to indicate that the
matter of Kojevian formation is not easy to disentangle from that whole
intellectual climate that smacks of a widespread authoritarian temper. The
matter is rendered even more complex by the fact that if Lyotard and
Derrida, whom no one can conceivably accuse of Nazi sympathies, have
led the campaign in France to protect Heidegger against any discussion of
his work for the Nazis and his subsequent refusal to publicly account for
that association, in Germany that same role has been played, among others,
by Ernst Nolte. Nolte also takes up specific themes from Heidegger's proNazi political declarations in the course of his revisionist effort to
'normalize' the Nazi experience as an 'understandable' response to the rise
of Stalin in the Soviet Union and as one element among others in what
Nolte, echoing many Nazi apologists in the past, calls 'an international
civil war'.
Finally, there is the matter of the fundamental shifts in Kojbve's own
career and outlook, which reminds one of so many others. The Kojtve
that we first encounter as the teacher of the legendary seminar fancied
himself a communist, interpreted Hegel's treatment of the twin histories of
religion and philosophy through Marxist categories of alienation, false
consciousness and, above all, labour. As Roth puts it about that period in
his thought, 'For Kojtve the dynamic of mastery and slavery is the motor
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
of History: domination sets history in motion and equality will end it.''= In
that reading, we actually get two versions of what Kojkve callsfin de l'histoire. In one version, we are said to be living in a posthistorical period in
the sense that a project of Equality has been set in motion historically by
the French Revolution and philosophically by Hegel, and all that remains
is the practical completion of that project - to which in any case there are
no alternatives. In a stronger version, the End of History could only come
with the end of class struggle and the triumph of 'slave ideologies', i.e. the
triumph of equality over hierarchy, which is then identified squarely with
the EndState of 'classless society'.
By the 1950s, as Kojbve recreated himself in the guise of an illustrious
civil servant, three major shifts took place. One, class struggle and with
that the struggle for 'recognition' was now said to be essentially over in
countries of advanced capitalism where most of the surplus value, he said,
was returned to the worker: '. . . the United States has already reached the
final stage of Marxist 'communism', since, in effect, all the members of a
'classless society' can appropriate whatever appeals to them, without
working more than they feel like doing,' and 'the American way of life was
the one fitted for the posthistorical period.'13 Second, however, this End of
History was identified with a Weberian sense of complete rationalization
of society and a sense of nausea, emptiness and boredom of the kind that
was made fashionable in France at that time through disparate fictions of
Sartre, Camus, Franqoise Sagan et al. Third, KojBve's interests shifted
increasingly from the philosophy of History to the making of Discourses,
and the tonality of his prose also shifted, accordingly, to a register
distinctly non-Hegelian and surprisingly similar to that of the poststructuralists: '"The definitive annihilation of Man properly so-called" also
means the definitive disappearance of Discourse (Logos) in the strict
sense,' he was to write in a note to the 1969 edition of his book on
Hegel.l4
Two features of this career are worth reiterating. On the one hand, the
vertigo of these shifts reminds one, inevitably, of the careers of those
luminaries of French postmodernity whom Daniel Singer once bluntly
called 'bastards of May' and 'Maoist t~rncoats."~
But, then, it also clarifies
for us that Fukuyama, who picks up one strand of Nietzsche while the
postmoderns pick up several others, is loyal to KojBve twice over: he picks
up KojBve's treatment of the Master-Slave Dialectic from the 1930s but
then severs that account from Kojbve's Heideggerian Marxism of that
period, recombining it with the two-faced quality of Kojbve's thought of
the 1950s: the celebration of the United States as the EndState which
terminates History, but also a lament far the End of History as a Weberian
rationalization and the reign of mediocrity. It is on this ground of Kojevian
doubleness (duplicity?) that Lyotard's End of all Metanarratives meets
AIJAZ AHMAD
359
Fukuyama's End of History, and that postmodernity itself becomes yet
another version of fin de I'histoire, not in Hegel's sense of History discovering its Vocation as Pursuit of Equality and Freedom but in the much more
recent and tawdry sense of living, jubilantly, in the aftermath of the end of
meaning itself.I6This complexity in the philosophical lineages of 'The Post
Condition' suggests to us that Fukuyama's thought is by no means sui
generis and that much of his intellectual formation, political corlviction and
worldview he in fact shares with some of the dominant strands in
postmodernity, whether or not he is in any obvious sense sympathetic to
those modes of Parisian brashness. It is not only that Lyotard repackages
in French philosophical language what we once used to hear from Daniel
Bell and others; it is also the case that Kojkve's influence in Paris and
beyond has included a lot more than Fukuyama, so that if one of the main
registers of Fukuyama's declaration of the End of History sounds
somewhat like ~votard'sdeclaration of 'the end of all metana&atives' or
Baudrillard's aniouncement of 'the death of the social', the resemblance is
not merely incidental.
This is of course not to deny that Fukuyama's discourse is very
peculiarly knotted, with an unbridgeable inner contradiction; for, he
attempted to reconcile two contrasting tendencies within the larger philosophical tradition, as they are indicated even by the two terms that he took
into the title of his book, 'The End of History', and 'The Last Man'. It
might appear, at first sight, that the figure of -'the Last Man' seamlessly
represents the moment at which History itself comes to an End. In the
actual structure of Fukuyama's argument, however, there is a considerable
slippage. The rhetoric of the 'End of History' he takes from Hegel, to assert
that what we are witnessing in our own time, in the 1990s, is that muchawaited outbreak of liberty which Hegel had first glimpsed in the figure of
the Man on Horseback at Jena and which has now taken, on Fukuyama's
account, its final form in the global triumph of neo-liberal capitalism, and
in the terminal defeat of its adversaries. The rhetoric of 'the Last Man', by
contrast, is descended from the Nietzschean rejection of the intellectual
lineages of Humanism and the Enlightenment, as well as his elitist
rejection not only of what later came to be known as 'consumer society'
but also popular power of any kind. In this way, the narrative of Modernity
itself becomes a secular, enraged, agnostic narrative of the Fall of Man, and
a narrative, therefore, of the coming of universal mediocrity, the bleakness
of it all hardly relieved by the persistence of a spiritual aristocracy
comprised of a few such as Nietzsche himself, not to speak of latter-day
Nietzscheans.
That Hegelian starting-points in Fukuyama's thought should eventually
lead to Nietzschean conclusions is a paradox almost too delicious. Upon
reflection, though, this upshot seems less surprising since Hegel and even
360
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
Kojhve are filtered, in Fukuyama's thought, through an intellectual
tradition whose own structure was inseparable from that ideological
crucible of the 1930s when not only a hatred of communism but deep
distrust of liberal democracy itself became quite compelling in sections of
the European intelligentsia under pressure from National Socialism. The
figure of 'The Last Man', in Fukuyama's configuration, is thus somewhat
Janus-faced. Thanks to the coming of liberal democracy, this Last Man, in
his Occidental location, has known true liberty, in the form of a universal
recognition granted by the liberal state, and, supplementing the satisfactions of socio-political recognition, he has known also the satisfactions that
come with consumerist plenitude. He now seeks emancipation not through
Reason but from Reason, not through History butfrom History, in the shape
of that Dionysian and privatized Freedom which Foucault has more
recently called 'regimes of pleasures.' These satisfactions of universal
recognition and consumerist plenitude have, however, even within the
ultimate self-realization of the Occident, a catch built into them. The
dilemma of liberal democracy, the secret even of its eventual selfdestruction, is, according to Fukuyama, that any practice of universal
equality can only produce a state of universal mediocrity, because mutual
'recognition' of each by all can be universalized only by accepting the
lowest possible denominator for what merits equal recognition. The
triumph of liberal democracy is thus for Fukuyama an end of history in two
quite different senses.
One very strong sense, of course, is that the Occidental states and
societies of advanced capitalism are said to be entirely comfortable in their
affluence and the liberal order; that they are relieved by the defeat of their
adversaries and no longer imagine any other future for themselves; that the
triumph of liberal capitalism is, so far as one can see, definitive. But the
second sense then immediately follows: this very End of History seems to
produce nothing but an infinity of futurelessness, mediocrity,
consumerism, a levelling of all distinctions, equalizing of all political wills
in the form of universal franchise, a desert-like future of full homogeneity.
He cites Leo Strauss's telling interrogation of Kojkve: is it really possible
to dissolve Hegel's Master-Slave opposition without producing sheer
equality and homogeneity? Fukuyama indicates his support of Strauss's
position through three key assertions. One, that since equality can only be
based on universal mediocrity, what the human will truly wants is a
belonging not to universal equality but to a special community of its own,
within a complex system of numerous such communities; not the liberal
democracy of universal citizenship, but a heterogeneous system of
mutually exclusive communities wherein one takes the satisfaction of
recognition only by those whom one recognizes as one's peers. Second,
quoting Nietzsche's description of the state as 'the coldest of all cold
AIJAZ AHMAD
361
monsters', Fukuyama asserts that there is far greater human satisfaction in
membership in an immediate, directly experienced community than in the
equal citizenship within a state; 'politics' is thus dissolved into 'society'
and 'society' itself into its constituent units, in an infinite play of heterogeneities. So far does Fukuyama go in this direction as to suggest that the
authoritarian regimes which have supervised such stupendous capitalist
growth in East Asia may well be humanly more satisfying in so far as they
rest not on universal equality in the political domain but on integral and
mutually discrete communities within the larger capitalist society.
Far from being a purely triumphalist account, thus, Fukuyama's
discourse is in fact self-divided between profound allegiance to liberal
capitalism and equally strong temptation to reject it in favour of dictatorial
regimes; and the discourse is self-divided also between the polarities of a
certain Hegelian optimism about the March of History as an unfolding of
the Idea of Liberty on the one hand, and, on the other, the overwhelming
Nietzschean scepticism about the very conceptions of History and Liberty
as possible or even desirable emancipatory collective projects. These
contradictory philosophical positions he tries to uphold, simultaneously, in
view of his own central propositions, which, as it happens, tend to mutually
cancel out each other. Ideologically, he is fully committed, in the first
instance, to an unrestrained celebration of the free market and its global
triumph; in this rhetoric, 'free market' is the essence of Liberty as such. At
the same time, however, he also declares that the emergence of
consumption as the primary ground for the exercise of freedom in today's
mass capitalist society, whether in the Occident or in East Asia, degrades
the Idea of Freedom as such. The Last Man that has been produced at the
End of History, thanks to the global triumph of neo-liberal capitalism, is
then, by Fukuyama's own account, a mass of humanity beset by
mediocrity, authoritarian rule, and voracious appetite for sheer
consumption. Thus it is that even the textures and tonalities of his prose
oscillate between a neo-liberalist triumphalism and a posthistorical melancholy. This too is logical, since this bureaucrat-philosopher of the
American Empire thinks of himself, formally, as a Hegelian, but
encounters at the End of History the figure not of Hegel but of Nietzsche.
Now, Fukuyama takes himself to be neither postmodern nor
postcolonial. Unlike so many postmoderns and postcolonials, from Derrida
to Spivak, he claims for himself no radical, leftwing credentials in the
politics of today. Unlike Lyotard, Kristeva, Glucksman and many other
'New Conservatives' of French postmodernity, Fukuyama has no past as a
Trotskyist, Maoist or whatever. He has no qualms about the fact that he is,
and has always been, a man of the Right and an advocate of neo-liberalist
capitalism; much of his life has been spent, after all, between the U.S. State
Department and the Rand Corporation. I begin with Fukuyama in this
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
context for somewhat different reasons.
The first of these reasons is, in today's intellectual climate, the hardest
to state, namely that I find Fukuyama as a thinker comparatively more
substantial and engaging than those, such as Lyotard and Baudrillard, who
have provided so much of the jargon of postcolonial theory. This I say
despite the fact that Fukuyama strikes me as being, in the final analysis,
wrong on virtually every major count. He is right, for instance, though
hardly original, in asserting that capitalism is more universally dominant
and more securely entrenched today than at any other point in this century;
but he is wrong to equate this capitalist triumph with the outbreak of
Equality and Universal Recognition. What has been universalized is
neither a universal state of the common good, nor an equalized access to
goods and services, but integrated markets for the circulation of capital and
the expropriation of labour, and, in the cultural domain, universalisation of
the ideology of commodity fetishism.
Indeed, if you subtract commodity fetishism, hardly anything remains
in the culture of actually existing capitalism that is fundamentally universalistic. Indeed, the history of this capitalism shows that the dissolution of
traditional communities and the mobility of populations under capitalist
pressures produce not a universal culture of broadly shared human values
and radical equalities, but highly malleable processes of decomposition
that constantly recompose identities of nation, race, ethnicity, and religious
group, not to speak of freshly fashioned claims of tradition and primordiality. One might even speculate that the great intensification of identity
politics and of multi-culturalist ideology and policy demonstrates, in some
crucial respects, the living reality of how much contemporary capitalism is
in the process of giving up on the idea of Universal Equality even in its
advanced zones. The modem state even in these zones may well get reorganized as so many islands of ethnic identity supervised by the benign but
ever vigilant gaze of the one ethnicity that is so dominant that it need not
define itself as ethnicity. Thus, Fukuyama is wrong even on this count:
communitarian ideology as a complement of industrial capitalism is by no
means an attribute of East Asia alone; it is ascendant within North America
itself; meanwhile, the more strident versions of communitarianism are
blowing apart legacies of secular civil government in countries as diverse
as Algeria, Egypt and India; and yet, the idea of self-governing religious
communities as an alternative to secular citizenship in the modern nationstate is gaining ground in that branch of postcolonial theory which calls
itself Subaltern Studies, as is clear from the recent writings of its principal
figures."
This is a reversal, in fact, of historic proportions. The idea of universal
equality was until quite recently the most potent ideological force in the
struggles against European imperialism and against the Eurocentric
AIJAZ AHMAD
racisms which have been the necessary supplements of that imperialism.
Now, Fukuyama of course advises us that it is precisely the aspiration for
universal equality that is producing a culture of universal mediocrity, while
Lyotard and his postcolonialist followers such as Gyan Prakash, a late
entrant in the Subalternist paradigm, have taken to assuring us that the idea
of universality is itself Eurocentric and simply one of those metanarratives
of Emancipation that have been rendered obsolete by the entry of the world
into postmodernity, and that the only refuge from Eurocentricity and
racism is to be sought in philosophical and cultural relativism.ls For all his
Hegelian starting-points, Fukuyama's idea that recognition from one's
exclusivist community is the only recognition worth having belongs
squarely in the postmodernist world of relentless relativism, absolutisation
of difference, and refusal to acknowledge that anything other than goods
and services could define a horizon of universality or normative value.
Fukuyama thus shares many of the themes and convictions of philosophical postmodernity, especially the ones that are the most valued in
postcolonial theory, as, for example, his conviction that the heterogenous
is intrinsically superior to values of universality and equality; his wavering
but eventual preference for self-referential communities over the
integrative projects for creating a modern, democratic and secular state; the
Nietzschean tenor of his conclusions about the Modem, etc. Even so, his
sustained engagement with Hegel, though mediated through KojBve, still
strikes me as being philosophically more arresting; and, in the political
domain, he is quite evidently not much worse than the postmodern kinds
of American pluralism and pragmatism as represented, for example, by
Richard Rorty.I9 Meanwhile, there is something very honest and almost
charming about Fukuyama's somewhat belated perception that what he
took to be the outbreak of Liberty has produced a human condition fundamentally dehumanized and sordid, so that his declaration of the End of
History, poised as it is against the narrative of the Fall of Man, appears to
be far more ambivalent, bordering almost on the tragic, as compared to the
celebratory tones in which Lyotard and his postcolonialist followers speak
of the end of all metanarratives. But then, keeping with the temper of the
times, Fukuyama's eclecticism quite matches that of the postmoderns; and,
just as the typical postcolonial theorist routinely invokes contrary systems
of thought to uphold a singular position in something of a philosophical
pastiche, Fukuyama too finds it equally plausible to invoke, within a single
line of argument, Hegel and Nietzsche together, not only in their generality
but with reference precisely to those ideas about History and Reason in
which the two are the most opposed. .
This extended comment on Fukuyama has seemed necessary because
the fact of so substantial a convergence between postmodemity, which
purports to be a discourse of the Left, and Fukuyama, who confidently
364
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
announces himself as a partisan of neo-liberal conservatism, should give
us, I believe, some pause. Lyotard's posthistorical euphoria and
Fukuyama's posthistorical melancholy are rooted in the shared conviction
that the great projects for emancipatory historical change that have
punctuated this century have ended in failure. When they speak of this
failure, both have in mind, I think, the same three markers - anti-imperialist nationalism; leftwing social democracy; and communism - which
Lyotard dismisses contemptuously as mere metanarratives of Reason and
Progress, and Fukuyama regards as threats to Occidental civilization itself;
what they do share is a sense of immense relief at the defeat. That the
defeat of these three projects for positive historical change, these three
ways of conceiving the universality of our common needs, has been
decisive is, I think, beyond doubt. And, a charitable way of thinking about
postmodernism and postcolonialism may well be that the prefix 'post' in
these terms not only partakes of a generalised 'post-' condition but
contains within it a sense of that ending, even if that sense of endings
produces in most of them not a sense of loss but a feeling of euphoria.
What is striking about this euphoria, however, is that while the collapse
of those three projects of universal emancipation is celebrated so very
inordinately, postmodernity and its postcolonial offshoots hardly ever
name that which has triumphed in consequence of those defeats. Even if
we grant the word 'metanarrative', it is, I believe, necessary to state that
only the metanarratives of Emancipation have met with defeat; the most
meta- of all metanarratives of the past three centuries, the creeping annexation of the globe for the dominance of capital over labouring humanity,
has met, during these same decades, with stunning success, in a very
specific form, namely the form of neo-liberal conservatism. During
precisely the period when the great struggles for redistribution of incomes
downwards were defeated, the offensives for redistribution of incomes
upwards did succeed - and succeeded spectacularly. The defeat of the socalled 'Metanarratives of Emancipation' produces among the postmoderns
not mere incredulity towards them, as Lyotard puts it, but also great
pleasure; indeed, what was lived as loss, tragedy and disorientation in the
aesthetics of Modernity, is lived in the postmodern philosophy and
aesthetics as pure pleasure, and perhaps even as a postmodern equivalent
of the Kantian Sublime. By contrast, the triumph of the Metanarrative of
Universal Subjugation produces in most of the postists no great disturbance. Fukuyama is superior on all counts: he names the victor, namely
liberal capitalism; he identifies openly with that victory, camouflaging
nothing; and yet, unlike the postists, he experiences this victory of his own
side as if a handful of ashes had been thrust into his mouth. You can't really
expect much more from a conservative, when so many radicals grant you
so very little.
AIJAZ AHMAD
My main reason for so extended a comment on the basic formation of
this 'Post Condition' can now be stated more directly: if philosophical
postmodernity is by now at least one of the dominant if not the dominant
form of Euro-American social and political thought, what is now called
'postcolonial theory' is itself one among many of the contemporary
postmodern discursive forms - or, more accurately, a self-reflexive cultural
style within philosophical postmodernity. Chronologically, of course, the
term 'postcolonial' first arose much earlier, during the 1970s, in a wideranging political discussion, in which a number of people, from Hamza
Alavi to John Saul, had participated, and to which I had myself
contributed, in the 1980s, something of a footnote. Details of that
discussion need not detain us at present. However, I did recapitulate the
main contentions in a recent
mainly to show how very different and
how much more specific the meaning of this term had been before it was
appropriated for literary and cultural studies and was then put to work as a
cross-disciplinary postmodern hermeneutic. Participants in that debate had
been concerned with, first, a specific temporal moment, namely the wave
of decolonisations in the aftermath of the Second World War; second, a
specific structure of power, namely the type of state that arose in the newly
independent countries; and, third, the theoretical problem of re-conceptualising the Marxist theory of the capitalist state with reference not to the
state of advanced capital but to the state that arose out of the histories of
colonial capital, in the moment of decolonisation. The whole debate was
centred, in other words, on a very specific problem of political theory,
pertaining to a particular historical conjuncture.
The striking feature of the culturalist theory of postcoloniality as it
arose more recently, after the Euro-American academy had been
worked over by French Poststructuralism, is that it had none of the virtues
of that debate but all its defects - and many more besides. The
colonial/postcolonial binary is now used as a foundational category not just
for certain states in particular countries but for trans-continental, transhistorical making of the world in general. The range of citations may be
omitted for now. Suffice it to say simply that as one reads through a variety
of postcolonial critics - Bill Ashcroft, Gareth Griffiths, Helen Tiffin, Vera
Kutzinski, Sara Suleri Goodyear, Edward Said, Homi Bhabha, Ann
McClintock, Gayatri Spivak, and others - the term gets applied to virtually
the whole globe, including, notably, the USA, Australia, New Zealand,
South Pacific Islands, the states arising out of the collapse of the Soviet
Union and Yugoslavia, not to speak of the whole of Asia, Africa and Latin
America. In some usages, the term applies to the historical period inaugurated, more or less, in 1492; in more outlandish writings, it applies to much
older formations, such as the Incas and the China of Imperial dynasties. A
number of the critics claim that any resistance to colonialism is always,
366
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
already postcolonial, so that in these usages postcoloniality envelopes
colonialism itself as well as all that comes after it, becoming something of
a remorseless universality in which certainly the whole of the modern
experience, sometimes the pre- and postmodern experiences as well,
appear as some many variants of this universality.
When applied to the world, in other words, this remarkably elastic
'postcoloniality' seems to encompass virtually everything. When applied
as a designation for theories and critics, however, the same term
'postcolonial' contracts very sharply, and refers to not all theoretical work
done today, nor to all critics writing in these postcolonial times, but to a
very small number of critics with recognisably shared points of theoretical
departure. We thus have a telling discrepancy: immense globalisation of
the object of analysis on the one hand, and, on the other, the constitution
of a very small academic elite for deciphering that globalised object. This
discrepancy leads then to a situation in which at the end of so huge a
dispersal, 'postcolonialism' becomes, at least in one version, simply a
hermeneutic of reading, a cultural style. As Helen Tiffin would have it:
postcolonialism too might be characterized as having two archives. The first archive here
constructs it as writing (more usually than architecture or painting) grounded in those
societies whose subjectivity has been constituted in part by the subordinating power of
European colonialism - that is, as writing from countries or regions which were formerly
colonies of Europe. The second archive of postcolonialism is intimately related to the first,
though not co-extensive with it. Here the postcolonial is conceived of as a set of discursive
practices, prominent among which is resistance to colonialism . . .
Very often it is not something intrinsic to a work of fiction which places it as
postmodern or postcolonial, but the way in which the text is discussed.''
The way the two terms 'postmodern' and 'postcolonial' get conflated here
as virtual synonyms, both constituted as such not by some quality intrinsic
to the text but simply by the mode of discussion, is indicative of a much
broader postcolonialist procedure. Then, there is the characteristic literary
critical habit of construing postcolonialism itself as an 'archive' as well as
the typical gesture of treating resistance to colonialism as a 'discursive
practice' which is already 'postcolonial.' Gareth Griffith says something
similar, in a similarly expansive tone:
postcoloniality of a text depends not on any simple qualification of theme or subject
matter, but on the degree to which it displays postcolonial discursive features. What these
features may be is again open to interpretation as are those of any discourse which seeks
to constitute itself as discrete, but I might suggest that such concerns as linguistic
displacement, physical exile, cross-culturality and authenticity or inauthenticity of
experience are among the features which one might identify as characteristically
p~stcolonial.~
Now, it is not at all clear to me why the phenomenon of physical exile or
the philosophical issue of authentic experience, which far exceed the
historical experience of colonialism, should be regarded as 'characteristi-
AIJAZ AHMAD
cally postcolonial.' What is nevertheless striking about these later formulations by both Tiffin and Griffiths, who had earlier co-authored with
Ashcroft the founding text of Australian postc~loniality,~
is that both
regard postcolonialism as a kind of textual hermeneutic. The entire field of
the application of this hermeneutic, regardless of subject matter, becomes
postcolonial by virtue of its being read in a certain way; and both Tiffin and
Griffiths regard postcolonialism itself as a specific discourse which nevertheless has neither a specific object nor definable set of non-discursive
features; it is, at any given point, what it says it is.
That postcolonial theory is a postmodern hermeneutic Homi Bhabha
has stated with uncharacteristic clarity: 'I have chosen to give poststructuralism a specifically postcolonial provenance.'" We may recall also that
the three most influential postcolonial critics - Edward Said, Gayatri
Spivak and Homi Bhabha - derive their respective inspirations, if not
wholesale methodologies, from three quite distinct but more or less equally
influential tendencies in French poststructuralism: Foucauldian Discourse
Analysis, Derridean deconstruction, and Lacanian psychoanalysis. Said of
course has become far more equivocal about Foucauldian invocations since
the writing of Orientalism; even so, the mark of their mutual difference,
not in just methodological preference but even in the texture of their
respective prose styles, is precisely that each subscribes to a different
tendency in the arrangements of the postmodern hermeneutic hagiography.
What, then, is postcolonial theory? As a starting-point I would suggest
that to the extent that it is a theory at all, postcolonial theory is marked not
by the specificity of its object, since its object is infinitely dispersed and
indeterminable, but by its hermeneutic procedure, above all as style. With
regard to literary postcoloniality, then, we could say that the emergence of
postcolonial theory since the late 1980s signifies the dissolution of certain
limited pedagogical objects - such as Third World Literature, Colonial
Discourse, New Literatures in English, even Comparative Literature in the
strict sense - and their reconstitution under the signs of cultural and philosophical postmodernities. This involves extending the meaning of
'postcolonialism' to include any and all structures of power and
domination, while, in another direction, also dissolving the difference
between procedures of literary study and methodologies of historical study,
so that Subaltern Studies, whose founder, Ranajit Guha, was quite aptly
described by Edward Said as a p~ststructuralist~~
itself gets renamed as,
'Postcolonial Criticism' by one of the younger members of the Group,
Gyan Prakash, who directly invokes the authority of Lyotard, Demda and
Spivak as he, and others, move to assimilate Subalternism to
Postmodernism and Postcoloniality. This postcolonialist dissolution of the
category difference between History and Literature, although in this case
philosophically much more naive, reminds one nevertheless of Habermas's
368
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
telling criticism of Derrida's similar dissolution of the category difference
between Literature and Philosophy, which has the effect of expanding the
sovereignty of rhetoric over the realm of the logical and greatly privileging
the poetic function of language over other cognitive functions.
I just referred to the dissolution of such things as Third World Literature
or Colonial Discourse Analysis, and their re-constitution under the sign of
postcoloniality. How recent this process is can be gauged from the fact that,
while Robert Young's very up-to-the-minute book of 1990 has separate
chapters on Said, Spivak and Bhabha, it has no index entry for words like
'postcolonialism', 'postcolonial' etc, even though it does have twelve
entries for the term 'third world' and twenty-two for the term 'colonial
discour~e'.~~
Within a couple of years, however, Arif Dirlik was noting in
Critical Inquiry that 'Postcolonial has been entering the lexicon of
academic programs in recent years, and over the last two years there have
been a number of conferences and symposia inspired by related vocabulary.' He also notes, again quite correctly, that intellectuals hailing from
one country, namely India, 'have played a conspicuously prominent role'
in the 'formulation and dissemination' of this vocabulary, pointing out that
Postcolonial is the most recent entrant to achieve prominent visibility in the ranks of those
'post' marked words ... claim[ing] as its special provenance the terrain that in an earlier
day used to g o by the name of the Third World. It is intended, therefore, to achieve an
authentic globalisation of cultural discourses by the extension globally of the intellectual
concerns and orientations originating at the central sites of Euro-American cultural
criticism ... The goal, indeed, is no less than to abolish all distinctions behveen center and
periphery as well as all other 'binarisms' that are allegedly a legacy of colonial(ist) ways
of thinking and to reveal societies globally in their complex heterogeneity and contingency."
This formulation of Dirlik reinforces at least three points I have emphasized. That 'postcoloniality' is only the latest of the concepts arising within
'The Post Condition'. That the object is not to produce fresh knowledges
about what was until recently called the Third World but to re-structure
existing bodies of knowledge into the poststructuralist paradigms and to
occupy sites of cultural production outside the Euro-American zones by
globalizing concerns and orientations originating at the central sites of
Euro-American cultural production. And, that the objective in much of this
criticism, notably that of Homi Bhabha, is to dissolve all enduring
questions of imperialism and anti-imperialism into an infinite play of
heterogeneity and contingency.
This latest turn in cultural criticism is something of a point of culmination in a much longer process, starting in the mid-1970s, which I
examined at very great length in my book, In Theory. I shall not try to
recapitulate that argument here. Suffice it to say merely that my own book
of course came much later, but a sense of menace - the sense that postmodernist appropriation of non-European histories and texts would be the
inevitable result of postmodernist dominance within the Euro-American
academe - had been there much earlier, virtually inscribed in the very
making of that dominance, and one of the earliest to read the signs was the
Indian feminist scholar, Kumkum Sangari, in her essay 'Politics of the
Possible,' published in 1987 but first drafted, judging from the footnotes,
three years earlier.t8Toward the end of that essay, she speaks first of what
she calls
the academised procedures of a peculiarly Western, historically singular, postmodern
epistemology that universalizes the self-conscious dissolution of the bourgeois subject,
with its now famous characteristic stance of self-irony, across both space and time.
She then goes on:
postmodernism does have a tendency to universalize its epistemological preoccupations a tendency that appears even in the work of critics of radical political persuasion. On the
one hand, the world contracts into the West; a Eurocentric perspective (for example, the
post-Stalinist, anti-teleological, anti-master narrative dismay of Euro-American Marxism)
is brought to bear upon 'Third World' cultural products; a 'specialized' scepticism is
camed everywhere as cultural paraphernalia and epistemological apparatus, as a way of
seeing; and the postmodern problematic becomes the frame through which the cultural
products of the rest of the world are seen. On the other hand, the West expands into the
World; late capitalism muffles the globe and homogenizes (or threatens to homogenize)
all cultural production - this, for some reason, is one 'master narrative' that is seldom
dismantled as it needs to be if the differential economic, class, and cultural formation of
'Third World' countries is to be taken into account. The writing that emerges from this
position, however critical it may be of colonial discourses, gloomily disempowers the
'nation' as an enabling idea and relocates the impulses of change as everywhere and
nowhere.. .
Further, the crisis of legitimation (of meaning and knowledge systems) becomes a
strangely vigorous 'master narrative' in its own right, since it sets out to rework or
'process' the knowledge systems of the world in its own image; the postmodern 'crisis'
becomes authoritative because... it is deeply implicated in the structure of institutions.
Indeed, it threatens to become just as imperious as bourgeois humanism, which was an
ideological maneuver based on a series of affirmations, whereas postmodernism appears
to be a maneuver based on a series of negations and self-negations through which the West
reconstructs its identity ... Significantly, the disavowal of the objective and instrumental
modalities of the social sciences occurs in the academies at a time when usable knowledge
is gathered with growing certainty and control by Euro-America through advanced
technologies of information retrieval from the rest of the world.
I have quoted at some length because a number of quite powerful ideas are
summarised here, even though some phraseology (e.g., 'the West reconstructs its identity') indicates the Saidian moment of their composition.
Kumkum Sangari was in any case possibly the first, certainly one of the
first, to see how a late capitalist hermeneutic, developed in the metropolitan
zones, would necessarily claim to be a universal hermeneutic, treating the
whole world as its raw material. This goes, I think, to the very heart of the
point I made earlier about the aggrandizements of postcolonial theory as it
takes more and more historical epochs, more and more countries and conti-
370
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
nents, under its provenance, while it restricts the possibility of producing a
knowledge of this all-encompassing terrain to a prior acceptance of
postmodernist hermeneutic.
The work of Homi Bhabha is a particularly telling example of the way
this kind of hermeneutic tends to appropriate the whole world as its raw
material and yet effaces the issue of historically sedimented differences.
Indeed, the very structure of historical time is effaced in the empty play of
infinite heterogeneities on the one hand, and, on the other hand, the
relentless impulse to present historical conflicts in the terms of a
psychodrama. In the process, a series of slippages take place. The
categories of Freudian psychoanalysis which Lacan reworked on the
linguistic model were in any case intended to grapple with typologies of
psychic disorder on the individual and familial plane; it is doubtful that
they can be so easily transported to the plane of history without concepts
becoming mere metaphors. This problem Bhabha evaporates by offering a
large number of generalizations about two opposing singularities, virtually
manichean in their repetition as abstractions in conflict: the coloniser and
the colonised, each of which appears remarkably free of class, gender,
historical time, geographical location, indeed any historicisation or
individuation whatever. Both of these abstract universals appear as bearers
of identifiable psychic pressures and needs which remain remarkably the
same, everywhere. The colonizer, for example, is said to always be
unnerved by any of the colonised who has in any degree succeeded in
adopting the colonizer's culture. Translated into concrete language, it
would mean that colonizers were not afraid of mass movements resting on
the social basis of a populace very unlike themselves but by the upper
class, well educated intellectual elite that had imbibed European culture.
What historical evidence is there to show any of that? Bhabha is
sublimely indifferent to such questions of factity and historical proof
presumably because history in that mode is an invention of linear time
invented by rationalism, but more immediately because one allegedly
knows from psychoanalysis that the Self is not nearly as unnerved by
absolute Otherness as from that Otherness that has too much of oneself in
it. What is truly unnerving, in other words, is seeing oneself in mimicry
and caricature. That the hybridized colonial intellectual mimics the
coloniser and thereby produces in the coloniser a sense of paranoia is,
according to Bhabha, the central contradiction in the colonial encounter,
which he construes to be basically discursive and psychic in character. The
mimicry that Naipaul represents as a sign of a sense of inferiority on the
part of the colonised, becomes, in Bhabha's words, 'signs of spectacular
resistance.' The possibility that revolutionary anti-colonialism might have
unnerved the colonial power somewhat more than the colonial gentlemen
who had learned to mimic the Europeans, Bhabha shrugs off with
AIJAZ AHMAD
371
remarkable nonchalance: 'I do not consider the practices and discourses of
revolutionary struggle as the other side of "colonial discourse." '"
Alongside this particular notion of 'mimicry' as 'spectacular resistance', the other idea that is central to Bhabha's discourse on
postcoloniality is that of hybridity, which presents itself as a critique of
essentialism, partakes of a carnivalesque collapse and play of identities,
and comes under a great many names. In essence, though, it takes two
forms: cultural hybridity, and what one might call philosophical and even
political hybridity. The basic idea that informs the notion of cultural
hybridity is in itself simple enough, namely that the traffic among modem
cultures is now so brisk that one can hardly speak of discrete national
cultures that are not fundamentally transformed by that traffic. In its generality this idea can only be treated as a truism, since a generalisation of that
order cannot in any specific sense be wrong. The steps that follow this
truism are more problematic, however. At two ends of this same argument,
this condition of cultural hybridity is said to be (a) specific to the migrant,
more pointedly the migrant intellectual, living and working in the Western
metropolis; and, at the same time (b) a generalised condition of
postmodernity into which all contemporary cultures are now irretrievably
ushered. The figure of the migrant, especially the migrant (postcolonial)
intellectual residing in the metropolis, comes to signify a universal
condition of hybridity and is said to be the Subject of a Truth that
individuals living within their national cultures do not possess. Edward
Said's term for such Truth-Subjects of postcoloniality is 'cultural
amphibians'; Salman Rushdie's treatment of migrancy ('floating upward
from history, from memory, from time', as he characterizes it) is likewise
invested in this idea of the migrant having a superior understanding of both
cultures than what more sedentary individuals might understand of their
own culture^.^' By the time we get to Bhabha the-celebration of cultural
hybridity, as it is available to the migrant intellectual in the metropolis, is
accented even further:
America leads to Africa; the nations of Europe and Asia meet in Australia; the margins of
the nation displace the centre ... The great Whitmanesque sensorium of America is
exchanged for a Warhol blowup, a Kruger installation, or Mapplethorpe's naked bodies."
In Bhabha's writing the postcolonial who has access to such monumental
and global pleasures seems to have a taken-for-grantedness of a male,
bourgeois onlooker, not only the lord of all he surveys but also enraptured
by his own lordliness. Telling us that 'the truest eye may now belong to the
migrant's double vision':2 we are given also the ideological location from
which this 'truest eye' operates: 'I want to take my stand on the shifting
margins of cultural displacement - that confounds any profound or
'authentic' sense of a 'national' culture or 'organic' intellectual . . .'"
Having thus dispensed with Antonio Gramsci - and more generally with
372
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
the idea that a sense of place, of belonging, of some stable commitment to
one's class or gender or nation may be useful for defining one's politics Bhabha then spells out his own sense of politics:
The language of critique is effective not because it keeps for ever separate the terms of the
master and the slave, the mercantilist and the Marxist, but the extent to which it overcomes
the given grounds of opposition and opens up a space of 'translation': a place of hybridity
... This is a sign that history is happening, in the pages of theory ..."
Cultural hybridity ('truest eye') of the migrant intellectual, which is
posited as the negation of the 'organic intellectual' as Gramsci conceived
of it, is thus conjoined with a philosophical hybridity (Bhabha's own
'language of critique') which likewise confounds the distinction between
'the mercantilist and the Marxist' so that 'history' does indeed become a
mere 'happening' - 'in the pages of theory' for the most part. These
hybridities, cultural and philosophical, lead then to a certain conception of
politics which Bhabha outlines in his essay 'The Postcolonial and the
Postmodern: The Question of Agency' where we are again told that 'The
individuation of the agent occurs in a moment of di~placement"~
because
'contemporary postcolonial discourses are rooted in specific histories of
cultural di~placement.'~~
This pairing of hybridity and agential
displacement then calls forth a politics of 'contingency' while contingency
is defined 'as the defining term of counter-hegemonic strategies'. This
elaboration of hybrid, displaced, contingent forms of politics is accomplished with the aid of a great many writers including Ranajit Guha
('Guha's elaborations of rebel consciousness as contradiction are strongly
suggestive of agency as the activity of the contingent'y and Veena Das.
The latter reference should detain us somewhat, since it comes with a
direct quotation from Das, greatly approved by Bhabha, which denies that
there may be such a thing as an enduring caste consciousness to which one
might refer in order to understand any particular caste conflict, of the kind
that is so common in present-day India. I therefore quote both Bhabha and
Das as she herself is quoted by Bhabha:
In her excellent essay 'Subaltern as perspective' Das demands a historiography of the
subaltern that displaces the paradigm of social action as defined by rational action. She
seeks a form of discourse where affective and iterative writing develops its own
language... This is the historical movement of hybridity as camouflage, as a contesting,
antagonistic agency functioning in the time lag of sign/symbol, which is a space inbetween the rules of engagement. It is this theoretical form of political agency I've tried
to develop that Das beautifully fleshes out in a historical argument: 'It is the nature of the
conflict in which a caste or tribe is locked which may provide the characteristics of the
historical moment; to assume that we may know a priori the mentalities of castes and
communities is to take an essentialist perspective which the evidence produced in the very
volumes of Subaltern Studies would not support.'"
Setting aside the matter of the 'a priori' (no one has argued in favour of
'a priori' knowledges), the striking feature of Das' perspective is its
AIJAZ AHMAD
373
advocacy that when it comes to caste conflicts each historical moment
must be treated as sui generis and as carrying within itself its own explanation - unless one is willing to be accused of that dirty thing,
'essentialism'. That any understanding of a particular conflict must include
an understanding of its particularity is so obvious as to be not worth
repeating. What Das is advocating here is not just that obvious point but
that the understanding of each conflict be confined to the characteristics of
that conflict. What she denies radically is that caste mentalities may indeed
have historical depth and enduring features prior to their eruption in the
form of a particular conflict. What is denied, in other words, is that caste
is a structural and not merely a contingent feature in the distribution of
powers and privileges in Indian society, and that members of particular
castes are actual bearers of those earlier histories of power and dispossession, so that the conflicts in which castes get 'locked' (to use Das's own
telling word) are inseparable from those histories, no matter how much a
particular expression of that enduring conflict may be studied in its
uniqueness.
In terms of his own logic, though, Bhabha is right. Das's denial that
there might be such a thing as a caste mentality and her assertion that all
historical moments are sui generis is entirely consistent with Bhabha's own
assertion that explanations for human action must be non-rational and that
historical agents are constituted in displacement. Such premises preclude,
I would argue, the very bases of political action. For, the idea of a collective
human agent (e.g., organised groups of the exploited castes fighting for
their rights against upper caste privilege) presumes both what Habermas
calls communicative rationality as well as the possibility of rational action
as such; it presumes, in other words, that agencies are constituted not in
flux and displacement but in given historical locations.
However it may look from North America, and whatever 'the truest eye'
of the migrant may choose to see, the fact of the matter is that History does
not consist of perpetual migration, so that the universality of
'displacement' that Bhabha claims both as the general human condition
and the desirable philosophical position is tenable neither as description of
the world nor as generalised political possibility. He may wish to erase the
distinction between commerce and revolution, between 'the mercantilist
and the Marxist', and he is welcome to his preferences; but that hardly
amounts to a 'theory' of something called postcoloniality. Most individuals
are really not free to fashion themselves anew with each passing day, nor
do communities arise out of and fade into the thin air of the infinitely
contingent. Among the migrants themselves, only the privileged can live a
life of constant mobility and surplus pleasure, between Whitman and
Warhol as it were. Most migrants tend to be poor and experience
displacement not as cultural plenitude but as torment; what they seek is not
374
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
displacement but, precisely, aplace from where they may begin anew, with
some sense of a stable future.
This discussion of Bhabha came up in the context of my suggestion that
the core of postcolonial theory, as it is enunciated by its principal architects, Bhabha and Spivak in particular, is a major instrument for
establishing the hermeneutic authority of the postmodern over cultural
materials retrieved from outside the advanced capitalist countries. The
realignment of the subalternist paradigm, in the field of historical research,
with the core of postcolonial theory, and the immense approval that the
paradigm now receives in the United States, is a significant element in this
particular globalisation of the postmodern. This I shall now want to illustrate with some observations about Gayatri Spivak's famous - possibly
most famous - essay, 'Can the Subaltern Speak?'39It is a very long essay,
and summarizing it is in any case not my intention. I simply want to trace
a certain logic within Spivak's broader purpose.
Spivak begins with a long and spirited criticism of Foucault and
Deleuze on the ground that their delineations of the structures of Power are
fatally flawed because they treat Europe as a self-enclosed and self-generating entity, by neglecting the central role of imperialism in the very
making of Europe, hence of the very structures of Power which are the
objects of analyses for such as Foucault and Deleuze. The point is
unexceptionable and Spivak argues it with much verve, though in justice it
must be said that Said had made precisely that point about Europe a decade
earlier, at great length, in Orientalism; and that by the time Spivak
published her essay in 1988, Said had also criticized Foucault for
neglecting the issue both of European imperialism and of the resistances to
imperialist power outside Europe. Spivak was right but she was basically
extending a well-known argument. The criticism of Foucault and Deleuze
was then followed, in another section of the essay, by a considerable
discussion of widow immolation, a discussion inspired by Lata Mani's
earlier research on what she has called the Colonial Discourse on Sati.40
There are of course several other digressions, on Marx, Freud, First and
Third World feminisms, essentialism, Ranajit Guha and so on. It is only
after reading over two-thirds of the essay that we begin to sense the real
object of the writing - which is as follows.
It may be difficult now to recall that in the mid-80s, when this essay was
written, the chief authority of French poststructuralism in the Anglophone
countries was not Derrida but Foucault, and claims were often made about
how much Foucault helped us understand history and politics. It appears
from Spivak's quotations that this praise of Foucault was frequently
coupled with some unfavourable reference to Derrida. She quotes
Eagleton, Said and Perry Anderson as emphasizing Demda's lack of
engagement with politics. It now transpires that the whole object of
AIJAZ AHMAD
375
Spivak's own essay is to show that even though Foucault does talk about
politics frequently he nevertheless presents arguments that are constitutively flawed, and that although Derrida is usually unconcerned with
history or politics his deconstruction nevertheless provides a far superior
way of reading into historical and political archives. The discussion of the
British colonial ban on widow immolation in the early 19th century is
organised, thus, to demonstrate the superiority of the Derridean
hermeneutic over the Foucauldian.
The clinching argument comes in the last two pages of the essay,
however, where Spivak summarises what little she knows about the suicide
of an unmarried Bengali woman during the 1920s, about whom she has
heard through, as she puts it, 'family connections.' The evidence is, in
other words, non-archival and so little is known of the event that the motive
behind the suicide must remain indeterminable; we only know that when
she died she was menstruating, which shows that it was not as if she had
had illicit sex and killed herself because of having become pregnant. This
dead woman, whom Spivak calls 'the suicide text', becomes for her, in the
first instance, the final proof of Derrida's insistence on the limits of textuality, on the undecidability of meaning, on how much readers need to be
ironically aware of their own role in assignment of final meanings to any
text at all. In the second instance, the woman, or rather 'the suicide text,'
illustrates for Spivak how the real subaltern can never speak, so that any
claims about subaltern consciousness are always a rationalization
exceeding what can be known. In the third instance, however, and even
though we have no access to the consciousness of this 'suicide text,' the
fact that she was menstruating at the time of her suicide shows that she had
with her own body inscribed herself as the very opposite of the immolated
wife in rituals of sati, since menstruating wives are ritually forbidden from
immolating themselves. We are then told in a more or less triumphal tone
at the end of the essay that this acute understanding of the 'suicide-text'
Derridean deconstruction makes possible in a way that Foucauldian
discourse theory cannot.
Now, what I find most striking about this essay is the two-way operation
of this postcolonialist hermeneutic: on the one hand, the deaths of
unknown Bengali women who were unable to leave behind them any
evidence about their own actions can nevertheless be staged in the
language of high theory as evidence to settle a dispute which is internal to
high theory, the dispute about the relative merits of Derrida and Foucault;
on the other hand, the superiority of deconstruction can be established over
the 'suicide text' by reading it both as absolute silence and as insurgent
inscription. Equally striking, of course, is the fundamental thesis of the
essay, namely that the true subaltern is the one who cannot speak for
herself and whose history therefore cannot be written. This conclusion
376
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
about the generalised condition of subalternity is certainly excessive in
relation to the evidence produced in the essay, in the sense that most people
would not want to draw so extreme a conclusion on the basis of some stray
remarks about widow immolation and a brief resume of a particular
suicide. But the issue of the silence of the subaltern and the consequent
impossibility of a history of the subaltern gets invoked among the subalternists frequently. So, it might be useful to ask who the subaltern is and
how Spivak defines it. Indeed, since the term 'subaltern' comes into
contemporary parlance from a Gramscian variety of Marxism and since
Spivak identifies herself as a Derridean Marxist feminist, we may want to
approach her definition of subalternity through a brief reference to her
treatment of a theme familiar in Marxism.
'Imperialism,' Spivak says, 'establishes the universality of the mode of
production narrati~e.'~~
Here we encounter, of course, the astonishing
literary-critical habit of seeing all history as a contest between different
kinds of narrative, so that imperialism itself gets described not in relation
to the universalisation of the capitalist mode as such but in terms of the
narrative of this mode. Implicit in the formulation, however, is the idea that
to speak in terms of modes of production is to speak from within terms set
by imperialism and what it considers normative. In the next step, then,
Spivak would continue to insist on calling herself an 'old-fashioned
Marxist' while also dismissing materialist and rationalist accounts of
history, in the most contemptuous terms, as 'modes of production narratives'. This habit would also then become a regular feature of the 'subaltern
perspective' as Spivak's gesture gets repeated in the writings of Gyan
Parkash, Dipesh Chakrabarty and others.
This distancing from the so-called 'modes of production narrative' then
means that even when capitalism or imperialism are recognised in the form
of an international division of labour, any analysis of this division passes
'more or less casually over the fully differentiated classes of workers and
peasants, and identifies as the truly subaltern only those whom Spivak calls
'the paradigmatic victims of that division, the women of the urban subproletariat and of unorganised peasant labour.'" It is worth saying, I think,
that this resembles no variety of Marxism that one has known, Spivak's
claims notwithstanding. For, there is surely no gainsaying the fact that such
women of the sub-proletariat and the unorganised peasantry indeed bear
much of the burden of the immiseration caused by capitalism and imperialism, but one would want to argue that 'the paradigmatic victims' are far
more numerous and would also include, at least, the households of the
proletariat and the organised peasantry. Aside from this definitional
problem, at least three other moves that Spivak makes are equally significant. First, having defined essential subalternity in this way, she answers
her own famous question - Can the Subaltern Speak? -with the proposition
that there is no space from where the subaltern (sexed) subject can speak."
What it means of course is that women among the urban sub-proletariat and
the unorganised peasantry do not assemble their own representations in the
official archives and have no control over how they appear in such archives,
if they do at all. It is in this sense that the sati, the immolated woman,
becomes the emblematic figure of subaltern silence and of a self-destruction
mandated by patriarchy and imperialism alike. As Spivak puts it: 'The case
of suttee [suti] as exemplum of the woman-in-imperialism would . . mark
the place of 'disappearance' with something other than silence and nonexistence, a violent aporia between subject and object status.'"
Now, it is not at all clear to me why the self-immolating woman needs
to be regarded as the 'exernplum of the woman-in-imperialism' today any
more than such self-immolating women should have been treated in the
past by a great many colonialists - and not only colonialists - as representing the very essence of Indian womanhood. Why should the
proletarianization of large numbers of poorer women, or the all-India
productions of the bhadramahila, or the middle class nationalist woman,
not be treated as perhaps being at least equally typical of what Spivak calls
'woman-in-imperialism?' Even so, the argument that the essence of female
subalternity is that she cannot speak is itself very striking since in this
formulation of the situation of the subaltern woman, the question of her
subjectivity or her ability to determine her own history hinges crucially not
on her ability to resist, or on her ability to make common cause with others
in her situation and thus appear in history as collective subject, but on her
representation, the terms of her appearance in archives, her inability to
communicate authoritatively, on one-to-one basis with the research
scholar, perhaps in the confines of a library. This is problematic enough.
But, then, the implication is that anyone who can represent herself, anyone
who can speak, individually or collectively, is by definition not a subaltern
- is, within the binary schema of subalternist historiography, inevitably a
part of the elite, or, if not already a part of the elite, on her way to getting
there." This is of course remarkably similar to the circular logic we find in
Foucault, where there is nothing outside Power because whatever
assembles a resistance to it is already constituting itselfas a form of Power.
But it also leaves the whole question of subaltern history very much in the
lurch. If the hallmark of the true, the paradigmatic subaltern is that she
cannot speak - that she must always remain an unspoken trace that simply
cannot be retrieved in a counter-history -and if it is also true that to speak
about her or on her behalf when she cannot speak for herself amounts to
practising an 'epistemic violence', then how does one write the history of
this permanently disappeared?
Spivak seems to offer four answers that run concurrently. First, there
seems to be a rejection of narrative history in general, often expressed in
.
378
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
the form of much contempt for what gets called empirical and positivist
history, even though it remains unclear as to how one could write history
without empirical verification; nor is it at all clear just how much of what
we know as history is being rejected as 'positivist'; at times, certainly, all
that is not deconstructionist seems to be categorised as positivist or some
such. Second, in the same vein of emphasizing the impossibility of writing
the history of the real subalterns, Spivak criticises those earlier projects of
subalternism, including implicitly such writings of Ranajit Guha as his
works on peasant insurgency", which sought to recapture or document
patterns of subaltern consciousness even in their non-rationalist structures.
She criticises such projects on the grounds, precisely, that any claim to
have access to subaltern consciousness and to identify its structures is
prima facie a rationalist claim that is inherently hegemonizing and imperialist. As she puts it, 'the subaltern is necessarily the absolute limit of the
place where history is narrativised into
and 'there is no doubt that
poststructuralism can really radicalize the old Marxist fetishisation of
consciousness.' That scornful phrase, 'old Marxist fetishisation,' on the
part of someone who often calls herself an 'old-fashioned Marxist' and
whom Robert Young unjustly rebukes for taking too much from 'classical
Marxism,' of course takes us back to the Derridean claim that deconstruction is a 'radicalisation' of Marxism and Bourdieu's retort to this
Heideggerian 'second-degree strategy.'
Be that as it may. In terms of method, the previous formulation is of
course the more arresting, so let me repeat it: 'the subaltern is necessarily
the absolute limit of the place where history is narrativised into logic.' The
programmatic move of theoretical anti-rationalism is stated here in
methodic terms: while the statement appears to be merely anti-Hegelian,
what it in effect rejects, in relation to subalternity, is the very possibility of
narrative history, with its reliance on some sense of sequence and structure,
some sense of cause and effect, some belief that the task of the historian is
not simply to presume or speculate but to actually find and document the
patterns of existing consciousness among the victims as they actually were,
and a dogged belief, also, that no complete narrative shall ever be possible
but the archive that the dominant social classes and groups in society have
assembled for their own reasons can be prised open to assemble a counterhistory, 'people's history', a 'history from below'. E. P. Thompson's great
historical narratives on the Making of the English Working Class, on
patterns of 18th Century English Culture, on the social consequence of
industrial clock time for those who were subjected to it, come readily to
mind in this context. I don't think it would serve Professor Spivak's
purposes to dissociate herself from that tradition altogether, but the actual
effect of her deconstructionist intervention in matters of writing the history
of the wretched of this earth is to make radically impossible the writing of
AIJAZ AHMAD
379
that kind of social history, whether with reference to the social classes of
modern capitalism or in the field of literary analysis.
Such, then, are the burdens of the Post Condition, even for those who
may recoil at the Fukuyamaist variant.
NOTES
1. This is the text of a lecture delivered at York University, Toronto, on 27 November 1996.
Footnotes and some clarifications have been added for publication.
2. Lutz Niethammer, Posthistoire: Has History Come to an End? (London, 1992) [German
original, 19891.
3. Francis Fukuyama, 'The End of History?', The National Interest, Summer 1989; and F.
Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man (London, 1992). Fukuyama's version is
much tamer than Kojbve's lectures of the 1930s on Hegel's Phenomenology, from which
he draws the interpretation of the Master-Slave Dialectic. By the 1950s, Kojbve too had
come to view the postwar United States as the EndState of equality and liberty, as we shall
see.
4. Niethammer is particularly good on this second category of the posthistorical intellectuals. Heidegger hardly ever uses the term but his enthusiastic participation in the Nazi
project and subsequent withdrawal into what I have here called 'clericism of Being' is
illustrative of the sociological shift from one category to the second. On ambiguities of
this episode, Habermas's criticism has never been properly answered, even though the
literature on the subject is vast. See his chapter on Heidegger in The Philosophical
Discourse of Modernity (Cambridge, Mass., translation copyright 1987) and, especially,
his later essay 'Work and Weltanschauung: The Heidegger Controversy from a German
Perspective', in Jurgen Habermas, The New Conservatism: Cultural Criticism and the
Historians' Debate (Cambridge, Mass., 1989). See also Pierre Bourdieu's The Political
Ontology of Martin Heidegger (London, 1991; French original 1988) which deserves to
be better known. Both authors are notable for engaging the question of the relationship
between Heidegger's thought and his Nazi affiliation in a manner that neither denies nor
absolutizes the autonomy of philosophical thought. It needs also to be said that there is
hardly anything in Heidegger's later and much overrated writings on the question of
technology which is not already prefigured in Spengler's Man and Technics, first
published in 1931, roughly at the time when Heidegger was strengthening his association
with such other conservative thinkers of fascist political orientation as Carl Schmitt and
the Junger brothers.
5. See Bourdieu, op. cit., pp. viii, 49, 96.
6. Allan Bloom, Fukuyama's teacher, was an intimate of Leo Strauss and the English editor
of Kojbve's work on Hegel. See, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, trans. James H.
Nicholls Jr. (ed.), Allan Bloom, Ithaca, N.Y. 1969. Strauss, in turn, had been a friend of
Kojbve's since the 1930s (the two sharing an early admiration for Heidegger) as well as
of Carl Schmitt, legal theorist and one-time fascist. When Strauss published his famous
work on vranny, Kojhe responded, on his friend's invitation, with his essay, 'Qranny
and Wisdom' to which too Strauss then replied. For relevant texts of this interlocution, see
the edition of On Tyranny prepared by Victor Gourevich and Michael Roth (New York,
1991). Kojbve declares in that essay that 'of all possible statesmen, it is the tyrant who is
incontestably the most apt to receive and apply the advice of the philosopher.' The observation unwittingly offers a curious commentary on the fact that Kojbve spent roughly the
last two decades of his life as an official of the French government and that Fukuyama,
the self-declared disciple of Kojbve, works for the Rand Corporation and the U.S. State
Department.
7. Demda reasserts this status of deconstruction as a 'radicalization' of Marxism in his
THE SOCIALIST REGISTER 1997
recent Spectres of M a n (London and New York, 1994). But the claim goes back to
Heidegger himself. As Bourdieu remarks: 'Of all the manipulative devices in Letter on
Humanism none could touch the 'distinguished' marxists as effectively as the seconddegree strategy consisting in ... talking the language of a 'productive dialogue' with
Marxism, the typically Heideggerian strategy of an (artificial) overcoming through
radicalization' (Bourdieu, op. cit., p. 94; italics and parentheses in the original). For my
own brief comment on Demda's use of this Heideggerian device, see my 'Reconciling
Demda: "Spectres of Marx" and Deconstmctive Politics', in New Left Review, no. 208,
November-December 1994; reprinted in Aijaz Ahmad, Lineages of the Present (New
Delhi, 1996).
8. Cited in Habermas, The New Conservatism, op. cit., p. 142, from a report that Jaspers
submitted in 1945 to the denazification committee established at the University of
Freiburg, where Heidegger had sewed as a rector under the Nazis.
9. After the War, however, a commission of the French Communist Party was to indict
Kojhve's philosophy for a 'fascistic tendency.'
10. For Kojbve's influence on Lacan, see Anthony Wilden, Language of the Self(Baltimore,
1968). As Wilden aptly remarks: 'Lacan's early use of the Hegelian notion of desire
repeats Kojevian formulas. There are. in fact few contemporary readings of Hegel which
do not owe a considerable debt to KojCve's commentary, and he himself owes an equal
debt to Heidegger . . . Although it is sometimes difficult to tell whether it is Kojbve,
Heidegger or Hegel who is speaking. Lacan's works seem often to allude directly to
Kojbve' @p. 193-4). See also the brief excursus on Kojbve in Elisabeth Roudinesco,
Jacques Lacan & Co., A History of Psychoanalysis in France 1925-1985 (London, 1990).
Remarking on the fact that Kojbve's reading of Hegel was so 'original' that it often bore
little resemblance with what Hegel had actually written, Roudinesco goes on to say: 'It
was not by chance that Lacan discovered in Kojkve's discourse the wherewithal to effect
a new interpretation of an original body of thought. At Kojkve's side he learned how to
make Freud's text say what it does not say.' (p. 138)
11. Niethammer refers to Kojbve's account of the structures of the modem world as 'bloodthirsty' (p. 91) and Descombes speaks of his 'terrorist conception of history.' See Vincent
Descombes, Modern French Philosophy, Cambridge, 1980 (French original 1979); p 14.
12. Michael S. Roth, Knowing and History: The Resurgence of French Hegelianisrnfrom the
1930s through the Poshvar Period (Princeton, 1988), p. 102.
13. Cited in Niethammer, p. 67.
14. Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, op. cit., p. 16011, (italics and parentheses in the
original).
15. Daniel Singer, 'Be Realistic: Ask for the Impossible.' Nation (31 May 1993).
16. The jubilation is itself is in fact characteristically postmodern. Nietzsche himself had a
much more grim and ironic sense of it all. As he put it in Thus Spake Zarathustra, in the
section from which Fukuyama takes part of his title:
'One has one's little pleasures for the day and one's little pleasures for the night: but
one has a regard for health.
"We have invented happiness," say the last men, and they blink.'
17. See, for instance, Partha Chatterjee, 'Secularism and Toleration,' Economic and Political
Weekly, vol. XXIX, no. 28,9 July 1994. For a critique of a whole range of narrow communitarianisms prevailing in India today, see KumKum Sangari, 'Politics of Diversity:
Religious Communities and Multiple Patriarchies,' Economic and Poliical Weekly,
Volume XXX,nos 51 & 52,30 December 1995.
18. Cyan Prakash, 'Postcolonial Criticism and Indian Historiography,' Social Tat, no 31/32,
1992.
19. For a discussion of the convergence between pragmatism and postmodernity, see Sabina
Lovibond, 'Feminism and Postmodernism', New Left Review, no. 178 (NovemberDecember 1989) and 'Feminism and Pragmatism: A Reply to Richard Rorty', New Left
AIJAZ AHMAD
381
Review, no. 193 (May-June 1992).
20. Aijaz Ahmad, 'Postcolonialism: What's In a Name?' in Roman de la Campa, E. Ann
Kaplan & Michael Sprinker (eds.), Late Imperial Culture (London, 1995).
21. Helen Tiffin, in Ian Adam and Helen Tiffin (eds.), Past the Last Post (Calgary, 1990), p.
vii.
22. Gareth Griffiths, 'Being there, being There, Kosinsky and Malouf,' in Adam & Tiffin,
ibid, p. 154.
23. Bill Ashcroft, Gareth Griffiths and Helen Tiffin, The Empire Writes Back: Theory and
Practice of Postcolonial Literatures (London, 1989).
24. Homi K. Bhabha, The Location of Culture (London, 1994), p. 64.
25. Edward Said, Culture and Imperialism (London, 1993), p. 296. In an extraordinary pair
of hindsights within a single sentence, Said first describes Guha's book of 1963 as 'archeological and deconstructive,' thus taking in both Foucault and Denida quite nicely, and
then goes on to specify 1826 as the year when the Act of Permanent Settlement was
passed.
26. Robert Young, White Mythologies: Writing History and the West (London, 1990).
27. Arif Dirlik, 'The Postcolonial Aura: Third World Criticism in the Age of Global
Capitalism', Critical Inquiry, Winter 1994, p. 329.
28. Kumkum Sangari, 'The Politics of the Possible', Cultural Critique, no. 7 , Fall 1987.
29. The argument on the next few pages follows closely a section of my essay 'The Politics
of Literary Postcoloniality' in Race & Class, vol. 36, no. 3, 1995.
30.The quoted phrases here are from Said's essay 'Third World Intellectuals and
Metropolitan Culture,' in Raritan, Winter 1990; and from Salman Rushdie, Shame (New
York, Vintage edition, 1984), p. 91.
31. Homi K. Bhabha (ed.), Nation andNarration (London, Routledge, 1990), p. 6.
32. Homi Bhabha, The Location of Culture (London, Routledge, 1994), p. 5.
33. Location, p. 21.
34. Ibid., p. 25.
35. Ibid, p.185.
36. Ibid., p.172.
37. Ibid., p.187.
38. Ibid., pp. 192-3. Das is quoted from R. Guha (ed.), Subaltern Studies VI (Delhi, Oxford
University Press, 1989).
39. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, 'Can the Subaltern Speak?', in Cary Nelson and Lawrence
Goldberg (eds.), Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture (Chicago, 1988).
40. One among many published versions of this material may be found in Cultural Critique,
no. 7, Fall 1987.
41. 'Can the Subaltern Speak?', op. cit., p. 298.
42. Gayatri Spivak, 'The Rani of Sirmur,' in Francis Barker et a1 (eds.), Europe and its Others
(Colchester, 1985).
43. 'Can the Subaltern Speak?', op. cit, p. 308.
44. Ibid., p. 306.
45. As she puts it elsewhere, 'If the subaltern can speak then, thank God,the subaltern is not
a subaltern any more.' See Sarah Harasym (ed.), Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, The
Postcolonial Critic: Interviews, Strategies, DDiogues (London & New York, 1990);
p. 158.
46. Ranajit Guha, Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India (Delhi, 1983).
47. Gayatri Charavorty Spivak, In Other Worlds: Essays in Cultural Politics (New York &
London, 1988), p. 207.