Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
In this paper, I analyse EE I 6, where Aristotle presented a famous methodological digression. Many interpreters have taken this chapter as advocating a dialectical procedure of enquiry. My claim is that Aristotle does not keep a dialectical attitude towards endoxa or phainomena in this chapter. In order to accomplish my goal, I shall show that EE I 6 does not provide enough evidence for the dialectical construal of it, and that this construal, in turn, hangs on some assumptions brought out from other Aristotelian works (EN and Top.), which do not provide good evidence either. By the examination of these assumptions, I intend to show that Aristotle is not carrying out any sort of dialectic, especially dialectic conceived as conceptual analysis seeking to save phainomena or endoxa. DOI: https://doi.org/10.14195/1984-249X_20_7
Dialogue, 1982
The last half-century has witnessed a resurgence of interest in Aristotle's Topics and his theory of dialectic-culminating in J. D. G. Evan's book about Aristotle's concept of dialectic; the decision to devote the entire Third Symposium Aristotelicum to the Topics; and the appearance of a small but steady stream of articles, several of which are now conveniently bound together in the first volume of Articles on Aristotle, edited by Barnes, Schofield, and Sorabji. 1 These studies provide two somewhat incompatible views of Aristotle's dialectic. On the one hand, it is argued that dialectic-as a method parallel but inferior to demonstration-was superseded by the discovery of the scientific method, 2 or that dialectic-as a method of discussing first principles and of eliciting assent during debate-is at best a propadeutic to philosophic inquiry. 3 These assessments are a consequence of the view that, what-1 J. D. G. Evans, Aristotle's Concept of Dialectic (Cambridge, 1977); G. E. L. Owen, ed., Aristotle on Dialectic: The Topics (Proceedings of the Third Symposium Aristotelicum) (Oxford, 1968); J. Barnes, M. Schofield, and R. Sorabji, eds., Articles on Aristotle (London, 1975). See the works mentioned in notes 2 to 9, below. 2 F. Solmsen, "Dialectic without the Forms," in Aristotle on Dialectic (above, note 1), 55 (dialectic's "extraordinary and almost appalling loss of status"), and P. Huby, "The Date of Aristotle's Topics and its Treatment of the Theory of Ideas," Classical Quarterly, N.S. 12 (1962), 72, note 1,76,79-80. This view of dialectic's lossof status is usually connected to the belief that the Topics is one of Aristotle's early works (see Huby, "Date of Aristotle's Topics," and W. D. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1923), 56-57, 59). Solmsen, however, maintains that Aristotle had "a very clear idea" of the difference between dialectical and demonstrative arguments when he wrote the Topics, even though the Posterior Analytics was probably written later ("Dialectic without the Forms," 55). 3 J. Brunschwig, Aristote: Topiques (Livres I-IV) (Paris, 1967), xi-xii; Solmsen, "Dialectic without the Forms," 53-54.
Archai , 2023
The purpose of this paper is an attempt to delimitate what the dialectical syllogism looks like in Aristotle's Topics. Aristotle never gave an example of a dialectical syllogism, but we have some clues spread over books I and VIII of the Topics which make it possible to understand at least what within a dialectical debate is a dialectical syllogism. The interpretation advanced here distinguishes the logical order of the dialectical argumentation from the order of the debate. This distinction enables us to have a better understanding of what is and how the dialectical syllogism is identified in the debate. In addition, we can solve some interpretative difficulties other interpretations could not solve, and have a more solid grasp of how endoxa are used in a dialectical debate.
Phronimon, 2006
Nicomachean Ethics [EN! It is widely agreed that Aristotle's explicit account of his methodology in EN is the method of dialedic. However, it hos been argued that Aristotle does not consistenfly pradice this mefhod and often appeals fo mefaphysical principles in his ofher fexfs fo consfrud his moral fheory. As aresuIt, if has been c/aimed fhat Arisfofle nof on/y diverges from his dialedical method, but also confradids his dodrine of the aufonomy of distind branches of philosophical enquiry.
Philosophiegeschichte und logische Analyse/Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy 11 (2008), 151-62
Advances in the History of Rhetoric, 2015
Among Aristotle's arts of argumentation, two are directly linked to archai, or first principles. Analytic deduces from them and dialectic tests their veracity. This article situates rhetoric as likewise useful for philosophical investigation in Aristotle's own system by demonstrating how the Rhetoric assigns to rhetorical practice attributes that are uniquely related to the archai-without which investigations into and based on them would be impossible. That is, given the primary nature of the first principles as described by Aristotle, the strategic use of metaphor is the only intellectual machinery he has for articulating, disseminating, and gaining acquiescence for them.
philosophy.unc.edu, 2009
The 'Nicomachean Ethics' is generally thought to be a "dialectical" work, aimed at resolving 'aporia' in a set of 'endoxa', which it takes as its starting-point. I argue that Aristotle's aim in the treatise is, rather, to produce definitions of key ethical terms, and that his starting-points are limited to evaluative and discriminative judgments of a certain sort, which are demanded by the nature of the discipline and are not 'endoxa'. I discuss also how the definitions are reached (focusing on the cases of the virtues of character) and the roles that 'aporiai' do play in the process.
Argumentation, 1998
Aristotle's conception and use of ta endoxa are key points to our understanding of Aristotelian dialectic. But, nowadays, they are not of historical or hermeneutic importance alone, as, in Aristotle's treatment of endoxa, we still see a relevant contribution to the modern study of argumentation. I propose here an interpretation of endoxa to that effect: namely, as plausible propositions. This
43ο Συμπόσιο Βυζαντινής και Μεταβυζαντινής Αρχαιολογίας και Τέχνης, Αθήνα, 24-26 Μαΐου 2024
Revista CNJ, 2023
Association of Jewish Libraries, 2024
Convergence Across the Bay, 2021
Arianna Esposito et Airton Pollini (éd.), Cités nouvelles, villes des marges. Fondations, formes urbaines, espaces ruraux et frontières de l’archaïsme à l’Empire, 2023
Revista Meio Ambiente E Sustentabilidade, 2014
Urban Studies Special Issue: Long-Term Intergenerational Perspectives on Urban Sustainability Transitions, 2024
Jurnal Bina Desa, 2023
Особенности фразовых частиц в языке Гоюй и уточнения к общей концепции фразовых частиц Курдюмов В. А. Особенности фразовых частиц в языке Гоюй и уточнения к общей концепции фразовых частиц Курдюмов В. А. Особенности фразовых частиц в языке Гоюй и и уточнения к общей концепции фразовых частиц , 2024
La guerra de Sucesión en Cuenca 1700-1714 Familias, élites de poder y movilidad social, 2021
IRJET, 2020
Nano Letters, 2012
Afyon Kocatepe Üniversitesi Sosyal Bilimler Dergisi , 2024
Revista CENIC …, 2008
The Journal of Clinical Endocrinology & Metabolism, 1996
Journal of Cardiology and Therapeutics, 2014
Active Web, British HCI Day Conf., Staffordshire Univ, 1999
Geophysical Journal International, 2017
Revista Española de Cirugía Oral y Maxilofacial, 2011