THIS IS A DRAFT. DO NOT CITE.
Forthcoming in the Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Memory
Sven Bernecker and Kourken Michaelian, eds.
Locke and Reid on Remembering
Rebecca Copenhaver
Lewis & Clark College
1 Introduction
As I write this, I remember the first time I saw the statue of David Hume on Edinburgh’s Royal
Mile. But what exactly am I remembering? We commonly think of such memories as about the
past, and in particular, about past experiences. On this view, what I remember now are
sensations, feelings, thoughts, and ideas that I had on the day I saw Hume’s statue. The objects
of memory, on this story, are past experiences. But if we travel three hundred years into the past,
we find two philosophers—John Locke and Thomas Reid—whose theories of memory and the
role it plays in our lives are very different from these common assumptions about memory.
Locke presents remembering as an activity that may be, but need not be, about the past. His
remembering is a roomy notion. It includes recollection, but also contemplation, attention,
reverie, daydreaming, and study. This remembering needs past experience because it needs ideas
that have been already been formed. But remembering is not directed at the past or mainly about
the past. Remembering renews an acquaintance with things already apprehended. But the
acquaintance has uses not tied to the past: contemplating a problem, navigating an environment,
attending to a story, or planning for the future. What such activities need is not just present ideas
formed in response to present impressions; another thing they need, according to Locke, is
remembering.
Like Locke, Reid holds that remembering renews acquaintance with things already apprehended.
For both philosophers, then, remembering requires a past which, for Locke, it need not address.
Both Reid and Locke see remembering as releasing us from a persistent specious present that
would keep the world always new, yet leave it always alien. Without remembering, the present
would stay incomprehensible and the future would remain unimaginable. Remembering makes
the world less strange, reestablishing connections to things already experienced, helping make
sense of the present, and enabling a vision of the future.
Despite his agreements with Locke, Reid’s account of memory is more restricted: his version of
remembering is just to conceive of past events that have been witnessed, as having been
witnessed. Moreover, Reid imbeds memory within his direct realism: remembering directs us, in
the first instance, not to experiences of the world—past or present—but to the world itself.
Perception relates directly to present events and things; remembering preserves this relation by
renewing acquaintance with things and events previously apprehended.
1
2 Locke on Memory
Thus the ideas, as well as children, of our youth, often die before us: and our
minds represent to us those tombs, to which we are are approaching; where
though the brass and marble remain, yet the inscriptions are effaced by time, and
the imagery moulders away. The pictures drawn in our mind, are laid in fading
colors.
Locke
An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
Book II, Chapter X, Section 5
Locke, using a common distinction, divides the human mind’s powers into thinking and volition.
“The power of volition is called the will,” and it acts by willing. “The power of thinking is called
the understanding,” and it acts by perceiving (Locke 1975: 128).1 Locke’s ‘perception’ is
broader than ours. It includes all the powers of thinking—discerning, judging, reasoning,
imagining, and knowing—but also what we now call ‘perception.’ This is Locke’s word for the
power to form ideas in response to sensible objects. Sensible objects make impressions on our
bodies, thereby affecting us through the senses. In response, the understanding forms sensations,
which are ideas of sensible qualities: “yellow, white, heat, cold, soft, hard, bitter, sweet…”
(Locke 1975: 104-106; 117; 226-227). The power to form sensations or ideas of sense in
response to sensible objects belongs to the understanding, not the will: we do not exert this
power voluntarily (Locke 1975: 118). Whether an idea is a sensation depends on its origin – on
whether the idea makes it “entrance…into the understanding by the senses” or by another route
(Locke 1975: 226-227).
We know about these activities because we have the power to form not just ideas of sense but
also ideas of reflection. When the mind points outside—toward sensible objects, sensations are
formed. But when “the mind turns its view inwards upon itself, and contemplates its own
actions…,” ideas of reflection are the result. We reflect by observing our own mental operations
and producing ideas in response to them. By sensing, we have distinct ideas of “white and red, a
square or a circle…” By reflecting, we have distinct ideas of attention, dreaming, reasoning,
judging, willing, and remembering – in short, “the different states of mind in thinking” (Locke
1975: 104-105; 226-228).
Perceiving—the power of thinking—includes what we would now call sensory perception. It
also includes remembering, another activity of the understanding. Locke identifies three broad
types of memory. These are (1) remembrance—which includes recollection, contemplation,
reverie, attention, study, dreaming, and ecstasy; (2) retention; and, most controversially, (3)
consciousness of past actions and thoughts.
In Book II of the Essay, Locke presents two accounts of remembering separated from one
another by eight chapters on different topics: ideas of space, duration, extension, number and
others. Both discussions of remembering—Chapter 10 “Of Retention,” and Chapter 19 “Of the
Modes of Thinking”—present taxonomies, but they do not match each other. Did Locke write
these two chapters to discuss the same topic—remembering—or did he intend distinct accounts
2
of retention (in Chapter 10) and remembrance (in Chapter 19)? Despite the mismatch, the two
chapters tell the same story about remembering, an account distinct from what Locke says about
consciousness of past thoughts and actions. Chapter 19, the later of the two presentations, is
about remembrance, and its framework is Locke’s distinction between ideas of sense and of
reflection, along with their origins.
Ideas of sense are of sensible qualities that originate in response to impressions made by sensible
objects on our bodies. Seeing a cloudless sky gives rise to a distinct idea of blue. The idea’s
origins make it a sensation: its immediate occasion is an impression made by sensible objects on
the senses. Ideas of reflection, by contrast, are of mental operations originating in response to
impressions made on our minds by those operations. When someone reflects on how she solves a
puzzle, for example, she may form a distinct idea of reasoning. Again, what makes this idea one
of reflection is its origin—from an impression made on the mind by the mental activity reflected
upon. All of our ideas have their origin either in sensation or in reflection (Locke 1975: 104-106;
118-119).
Once an idea of sense has emerged from an impression—say the sensation of blue while
admiring the afternoon sky—such an idea can be formed again without help from any sensible
objects or impressions. I may have the idea of blue without any blue things affecting my senses.
Likewise with ideas of reflection: ideas about reasoning, once originated, no longer need puzzles
to stimulate them.
This ability—to form an idea of sensation or reflection without the impressions and objects to
which these ideas originally responded—is what Locke calls remembrance (Locke 1975: 226).2
Locke’s taxonomy in Chapter 19 classifies several types of remembrance by degree of activity.
Recollection, contemplation, attention, and study are the more active forms of remembrance. The
more passive forms include dreaming, reverie, and ‘extasy’ (Locke 1975: 227-228).
Recollection is a success term for a voluntary effort to form an idea, like trying to recall the face
of an old friend, and accomplishing it. One type of contemplation (reverie is the other) is also
voluntary. Ideas are elusive—fleeting, successive, and non-continuous. In order to be well
contemplated, an idea must be “held…long under attentive consideration”—as when one
considers the idea of a triangle by way of grasping the Pythagorean theorem. Attention is also a
form of remembrance, whereby an idea is noticed “and, as it were, registered.” Registering ideas
enhances remembering: it strengthens the ability to form ideas in the absence of impressions.
Particular acts of remembrance—recollection, attention, and contemplation—reinforce
remembrance in general.
The most active remembrance is study. Locke also calls it ‘intention’, emphasizing the mind’s
persistent engagement in a voluntary effort that “will not be called off by the ordinary
solicitation of other ideas.” When studying “with great earnestness, and of choice,” the mind
considers an idea “on all sides,” while noticing its “relations and circumstances; and views every
part so nicely that it shuts out all other thoughts and takes no notice of the ordinary impressions
made then on the senses, which at another season would produce very sensible impressions.”
Even for adults, the world is often a blooming, buzzing confusion. But in study, the mind fixes
on an idea, freed for a moment from the the inexorable succession of ideas suggested by the
3
senses. Like attention and contemplation, study focuses on ideas voluntarily. The price is less
attention to and recall for the ideas of sense that we might have registered had we not been in
intense study.
Reverie is another type of contemplation—in one way the opposite of study, though like it in
another. Study is willed and active, reverie is passive and involuntary: we lapse into reverie. Like
study, however, reverie effaces ideas of sense and reflection that might otherwise command
attention. Worries and fantasies, ideas replaying and repeating willy-nilly: these are distractions,
blocking what might be noticed in other circumstances. Ecstasy falls between reverie and
dreaming, and Locke has little to say about it. He calls it ‘daydreaming,’ leaving it “to be
examined” whether “dreaming with eyes open” is just a metaphor.
The contents of dreams are the clearest case of ideas formed without the impressions and objects
from which they originated. Dreams are disconnected from sense and reflection, or nearly so,
and so they are disconnected from the world. In dreams, ideas come and go involuntarily,
unprovoked by impressions. Dreamers are “retired as it were from the senses…,” able to “sleep
out whole stormy nights, without hearing the thunder, or seeing the lightening, or feeling the
shaking of the house.” Because dreams are sequences of ideas—confused, indistinct, dim, and
obscure though they may be—dreaming is a form of thinking, of perceiving in Locke’s
vocabulary. The succession of ideas stops only in dreamless sleep, which “closes the scene quite
and, puts an end to all appearances.” While Descartes holds that thinking is the principal attribute
of a mental substance, Locke claims that the mind need not always think. The variety of different
types of remembrance—from earnest study to impassive dreaming—shows that thinking is an
activity or operation, not an essence: activities come in degrees; essences do not.
Locke’s taxonomy of remembrance is strange in one striking way. Except for recollection, no
type of remembrance is actually about the past, at least not explicitly. We may contemplate,
attend, study, ruminate, daydream, and dream about the past, but we need not. Often, we
contemplate problems that needs solving, attend to things before us, study absorbing stories,
ruminate on what we need to do, daydream about the future, and dream fantastical worlds. We
may turn to the past to contemplate, attend, study, ruminate, daydream, or dream. But present
problems need contemplation; many things need attention right now; vexed issues can be
studied; constant worries are fodder for rumination; future fantasies are today’s daydreams,
nightmares to follow; in dreams begin tomorrow’s responsibilities. Remembrance is neither
directed towards, nor principally about the past.
Yet remembrance needs past experience. In particular, every act of remembrance, no matter the
type, requires an idea previously had from a sensory impression or from an impression of
reflection. This requirement is a version of the Previous Awareness Condition (PCA), developed
and examined by Sydney Shoemaker among others, particularly in relation to episodic memory:
memories that are constrained by the necessary condition that the person remembering was
witness or agent to what is remembered (Shoemaker 1970; Parfit 1985; Malcom 1977).
Episodic memories are often contrasted with semantic memories, such as remembering that
Amelia Earhart was the first woman to fly solo across the Atlantic Ocean. The PAC that holds
for episodic memory does not constrain semantic memory: those who never witnessed Earhart’s
4
flight, remember (not just know) that Emilia Earhart was the first woman to fly solo across the
Atlantic. Semantic memories, nonetheless, are subject to a different PAC. Remembering that
Earhart made the first solo Atlantic flight requires previous knowledge of this fact. Absent that
previous knowledge, a belief that Earhart was the first woman to fly solo across the Atlantic
would not be a memory.3
Locke’s forms of remembrance also have a PAC: each type of remembrance consists in having
an idea formed previously in response to impressions of sense or reflection. In other words, ideas
had by contemplating, attending, studying, ruminating, daydreaming, and dreaming must be
ideas had already, in the past, formed from an original impression (Locke 1975: 227-228; 153).
This PAC is necessary but insufficient for remembrance, which needs something else: that in
contemplation, attention, study, and so on, ideas may be present when the impressions that
originated them are absent. Such ideas need not be initiated or sustained by impressions of the
kind that first produced them. In fact, no impression at all needs to be present, even if
remembrance occurs while various impressions occur all around them. Many objects and events
surround a person deep in study, making impressions on the senses, yet the studious train of
ideas, if it is studious, holds itself apart from those all-too-present impressions. In dreams, there
are no present impressions at all. Remembrance lost in dreams is “retired as it were from the
senses,” in a flood of ideas severed entirely from sense and reflection (Locke 1975: 227-228).
Putting the two conditions together: remembrance is (1) having ideas formed previously in
response to impressions and (2) having them independently of the impressions that were
originally there when forming them. Along with the power to form ideas of sense or reflection in
response to impressions comes the power to form such ideas again—with or without the
originating impressions. Since these impressions precede any remembrance of the ideas in
question, the remembering mind, while receiving various present impressions, needs—for a
remembrance that may not be about the past—past experiences (Locke 1975: 227-228).
Remembrance has a past and needs a past, but it need not be about the past.
The earlier discussion of memory in Locke’s Book II, in the chapter “Of Retention,” presents a
similar account of remembering with a different taxonomy. Here too, awareness of the past is not
required for remembering; remembering requires ideas already acquired, but no longer needs the
impressions that originally produced them. In this chapter, Locke studies two types of retention:
contemplation and memory.
Contemplation—also described in Locke’s first taxonomy—is more or less familiar: it sustains
an idea of sensation or reflection by voluntary effort, even after the initiating impression has
vanished, sunk in the stream of transient impressions whose flow never stops (Locke 1975: 149155). The second type of retention—memory—is more elusive.
Locke introduces memory with two comparisons, both strictly metaphorical. First, memory is a
storehouse of ideas, “a repository” where the mind “lay[s] up those ideas, which at another time
it might have use of.” But ideas are impermanent, and their flow is inexorable: except in
dreamless sleep, they keep coming, one after another, though each is transitory; contemplation
may keep them at hand longer, but only briefly. And ideas, as particulars, can originate only
5
once. Since they “cease to be anything, when there is no perception of them…,” they cannot
really be put into storage, and once they “cease to be anything”, they cannot come back into
existence. The impermanence and particularity of ideas puts a new constraint on remembering:
remembering is not having the very same token idea twice or more; remembering is having a
new and distinct idea which is a token of the same type as an old idea: in this way a token idea,
new and in the present, can have a past—the past of its type—without referring to the past
(Locke 1975: 150).
To keep his storehouse metaphorical, Locke claims that “this laying up of our ideas in the
repository of the memory, signifies no more but this, that the mind has a power, in many cases,
to revive perceptions, which it once had, with this additional perception annexed to them, that it
has had them before” (Locke 1975: 150, emphasis added). Memory is an activity that the mind
performs, not a container located in it, spatially or otherwise. That much is clear. But the
contents of this metaphorical container (1) have been had before and (2) are had now as having
been had before. Since the difference between (1) and (2) is not a token/type distinction, that
relation cannot explain these requirements.
On the other hand, Locke may not be committed to the position that memory requires two
ideas—a past idea and a present idea of that idea as past. Following the storehouse metaphor
comes a second metaphor, this time about painting: memory is now “an ability in the mind, when
it will, to revive [ideas] again…and as it were paint them anew on itself, though some with more,
some with less difficulty; some more lively, and others more obscurely.” Memory is an artist,
making new ideas out of familiar materials: old ideas already had. Taken literally, the artist
needs two ideas to make memory: the freshly painted idea and the old idea newly revived.
But the painter is a metaphor, from which Locke moves to a more abstract comparison:
remembering is like seeing. The ability to remember brings “into sight” objects now unseen by
any sense. Once again, an idea, had in the past, acts in the present while severed from its past.
And thus it is, by the assistance of this faculty [memory], that we are said to have
all those ideas in our understandings, which though we do not actually
contemplate, yet we can bring into sight, and make appear again, and be the
objects of our thoughts, without the help of those sensible qualities, which first
imprinted them there (Locke 9175: 150).
Locke’s brief encounter with the painter suggests that there may be more to memory than the
past possession of one idea and the forming of a new one without help from the originating
impressions. Consider this: walking down the street, I have an idea of a flavor but no present
impressions of taste. Long ago, I had another such idea, though I do not realize it now: the taste
of an unusual brand of toothpaste made a strong impression on me—an impression now
vanished. But the color of a passing car is exactly the color of the long-forgotten toothpaste: the
color revives the idea of its particular flavor. Why I have this idea I do not know, nor do I
recognize it as an idea I have enjoyed in the past. This seems less like remembering than having
an idea out of the blue. Even though I had a related idea long ago, the new idea is not at all
familiar.
6
Locke counters unfamiliarity with familiarity. The painter’s idea is new, but it captures
something recognized as past. Having ideas of the same kind, and having them without their
originating impressions, is not enough. The mind must also take “notice of them, as of a former
impression, and renew its acquaintance with them, as with ideas it had known before” (Locke
1975: 153). Having two ideas—one idea, and then another idea about having had that idea
before—is not the point. Instead, an original idea formed in response to impressions is an
apprehension. This apprehension makes it possible—by grounding a power or ability—to form
an idea of the same kind as the past idea but with or without its originating impression, thereby
renewing an acquaintance with what was previously apprehended.
Acquaintance comes in degrees. The sensible objects surrounding us and the mental operations
on which we reflect are more or less familiar (Locke 1975: 150-152). We renew and strengthen
acquaintance with things not only through repeated impressions but also by remembering, which
gradually makes the world familiar. Without remembering—reacquainting ourselves with things
previously experienced, even in their absence—we would be trapped in a specious present.
Things would press on us again and again, and each idea formed in response would be new and
strange, giving us no purchase on the world. Without memory, endless impressions would be
mere chaos. Memory, therefore, “is necessary in the next degree to perception. It is of so great
moment, that where it is wanting, all the rest of our faculties are in great measure useless: and we
in our thoughts, reasonings, and knowledge, could not proceed beyond present objects…”
(Locke 1975: 153).
The most familiar ideas are those “oftenest refreshed”—those most important for renewing our
acquaintance with the world. They include “the original qualities of bodies, viz. solidity,
extension, figure, motion, and rest,” along with secondary qualities such “as heat and cold.” Also
crucial are our basic mental operations and the most general “affections of all kinds of being”
such as existence, duration, and number. Remembering makes the world familiar and us at home
in it.
So what does Locke mean by remembering? He means that remembered ideas are ideas of the
the same kind as ideas previously had, but the remembered ideas are had independently of the
impressions from which the original ideas were formed, so that remembered ideas renew
acquaintance with what was apprehended when the corresponding ideas were formed originally.
Remembering navigates a present world stocked with familiar objects, making us easy with the
workings of our own minds and helping us plan a future.
When Locke’s treatment of memory comes up, the usual problem is personal identity. Locke’s
story about that inspired the Memory Theory (MT) of personal identity, which equates personal
identity with memory: sameness of episodic memory is necessary and sufficient for sameness of
persons. Here I am not concerned with theories of personal identity—neither Locke’s, nor the
MT (see Chapter 14 of the present volume). I am concerned with the activity on which Locke
claims personal identity depends: “that consciousness, which is inseparable from thinking…by
[which] everyone is to himself, that which he calls self…” Is this consciousness the same as
remembering or different?
7
Consciousness—the activity that constitutes identity— can only be about the present, according
to Locke: consciousness is “always as to our present sensations and perceptions” (Locke 1975:
115; 335-336). This secures the present identity of persons, what makes “self to itself now”
(emphasis added). And this identity may persist, as long as the activity responsible for it—
consciousness—persists. Consciousness persisting over time ensures persistence of persons. Yet
consciousness is not remembering: in the first instance, consciousness is aware of present
thought and actions, present sensations and perceptions. These present ideas need not have been
had before. From a first encounter with a strange thing comes an impression from which a new
idea emerges. Consciousness, for a time, attends the new idea. But remembering works on old
ideas and renews acquaintance with the world. Consciousness and memory both serve purposes
essential to thinking, but the purposes they serve are different.
Locke describes consciousness as “extending backwards,” however, to past thoughts and actions.
Is consciousness not confined to the present? Are we conscious of past thoughts, actions,
sensations, and perceptions? That would surely be remembering. What else could it be? But the
consciousness that “extends backwards” need not be about past sensations, perceptions, thoughts,
or actions. Alternatively, consciousness can only be present, but a possible object of present
consciousness is an idea that renews acquaintance with something apprehended in the past.
Consciousness needs remembering to “unite existences” into the same person. When ideas are
remembered, they become conscious presently, but they are the same in kind as ideas had
previously, ideas present to conscious at some past moment.
Remembering joins present consciousness with past consciousness. But remembering is not
consciousness of the past. And consciousness as such does not require remembering. Because we
remember, however, acquaintance with things apprehended consciously in the past may be
renewed in present consciousness, thereby joining one consciousness with another and uniting
“remote existences into the same person…” (Locke 1975: 340-345). Without remembering, there
could be no re-acquaintance with objects of past consciousness, which would put the continued
existence of persons at risk. But this does not make consciousness the same as remembering.
3 Reid on Memory
It is by memory that we have an immediate knowledge of things past: The senses
give us information of things only as they exist in the present moment; and this
information, if it were not preserved by memory, would vanish instantly, and
leave us ignorant as if it had never been.
Reid
Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man
Essay III ‘Of Memory’, Chapter 1
We move now almost one hundred years to a different account of memory, inspired in opposition
to a picture of the mind its author identified with Locke. Thomas Reid called this picture he
opposed, ‘the ideal theory,’ or the ‘theory of ideas.’ At its core is the Lockean position that the
immediate objects of perception are ideas (Locke 1975: 134). By contrast, Reid argues that the
mind is directed in the first instance not to itself or its own ideas, but to the world. Accordingly,
8
he presents a direct realist theory of memory: when we remember, the mind is directed not
towards ideas—be they ideas experienced in the past, or ideas of past experiences—but to the
events we experienced in the past.
The interpretation on which Locke’s remarks on personal identity should be read as a kind of
Memory Theory (MT), despite his claim that personal identity consists in consciousness, is not
new. In the Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man (1785), Reid complains that “it is
impossible to understand the meaning of this, unless by consciousness be meant memory…”
(Reid 2002: 277). Reid is famous for his Brave Officer objection to MT (Reid 2002: 276).
However, the objection is not original to Reid. It appears in Berkeley’s Alciphron: or, the Minute
Philosopher (1732) and Reid himself attributes the example to George Campbell.4 Reid’s
criticism of MT is that it confuses truisms about the evidential relationship between memory and
personal identity with metaphysical conclusions about what makes a person identical with herself
over time. But even this insight is not new with Reid; it evokes the discussion in Butler’s
influential dissertation “Of Personal Identity,” (1736). What is original to Reid is his own
positive account of memory, and we may investigate this independently of questions concerning
personal identity.5
Though Reid constructs his account of memory in opposition to the theory of ideas, and though
he views Locke as a leading proponent of that theory, he shares with Locke the position that
remembering renews our acquaintance with things we apprehended in the past. It is an activity
that renders things familiar by reestablishing our connections to the things previously
experienced.
Things remembered must be things formerly perceived or known. I remember the
transit of Venus over the sun in the year 1769. I must therefore have perceived it
at the time it happened, otherwise I could not now remember it. Our first
acquaintance with any object of thought cannot be by remembrance. Memory can
only produce a continuance or renewal of a former acquaintance with the things
remembered (Reid 2002: 255).
Reid is interested primarily in episodic memory: the sort of memory whose PAC is that a person
(episodically) remembers an event only if she was witness or agent to the event remembered.
Reid could not have remembered the transit of Venus over the sun in the year 1769 unless he had
witnessed it. I cannot remember the transit of Venus in 1769 because I was not witness to it, not
having been born yet. I may have a semantic memory of the transit of Venus; I remember that
Venus crossed the sun in 1769. I learned this fact from reading Reid’s account of the event. My
semantic memory that Venus crossed the sun in 1769 is grounded in my previous awareness of
this fact. But I have no previous awareness of the event itself—Venus crossing the sun in 1769—
and so I cannot remember the 1769 transit of Venus.
The PAC on episodic memory is a necessary but insufficient condition: if I have an experience as
of having witnessed the transit of Venus in 1769 but I was not in fact witness to the event
(having been born in 1971), then such an experience is not an episodic memory. On the other
hand, I have been agent or witness to many events of which I have no episodic memory. I
witnessed the Perseid Meteor Shower in 1980, though I do not episodically remember the event.
9
I remember that I saw the Perseid Meteor Shower in 1980—my family tells me I was there—but
I do not remember the meteor shower itself.
So central for Reid is the the kind of remembering that requires previous awareness of the events
remembered that he does not count semantic memory as a form of remembering, properly
speaking (Reid 2002: 264). When I remember that Venus crossed the sun in 1769, I have a belief
or knowledge, rather than a memory. Reid distinguishes such beliefs from the phenomenon of
remembering because even when they are true and justified, they do not play a role in preserving
past apprehension of events. By contrast, Reid remembers not only the transit of Venus in 1769
but also that Venus crossed the sun in in 1769. Unlike my belief that Venus crossed the sun in
1769, Reid’s belief that Venus crossed the sun in 1769 preserves his past apprehension of the
event itself. Though expressed propositionally, his belief that Venus crossed the sun in 1769 does
not report a semantic memory. It reports his previous awareness of the transit of Venus and
preserves his past apprehension of the event; it reports an episodic memory.
According to Reid, remembering preserves past apprehension of events to which we were agent
or witness. Remembering is not a current apprehension. It is not a current apprehension of a past
experience, nor is it a current apprehension of a past event. We remember events, not experiences
of events. And we do not remember events by re-apprehending them. Rather, a past
apprehension is itself preserved in remembering. According to Reid, it is impossible to
apprehend events in the past: apprehension is confined to the present (Reid 2002: 23; 253). Acts
of apprehension establish a direct relation to a present event (or object, or mental operation). The
direct relation established by apprehension is then preserved by acts of remembering the event
apprehended. Remembering is directed not towards past apprehension, but to what was presented
in the past apprehension: namely, the event itself (Reid 1997: 28).
Remembering preserves past apprehension by conceiving of an event previously apprehended
and believing, of this event, that it happened to me. This belief is unlike the beliefs that express
semantic memories. This belief is a constituent of the act of remembering. According to Reid,
memory consists in a conception of a past event and a belief about that past event, that it
happened to the person who is represented in that memory as agent or witness (Reid 2002: 228,
232, 254, 257). This conception-belief structure mirrors the structure of other complex mental
operations that are directed at objects, such as perception, which is directed at things presently
before me, and consciousness, which is directed at my own mental operations. Each of these
operations consist in a conception and belief; the operations differ from one another because the
objects conceived differ, as do the beliefs about those objects (Reid 1997: 197). The conception
that is a constituent of memory is of an event previously apprehended. The other constituent of
memory is a belief, of the event conceived, that it happened. In particular, it is a belief that the
event happened to me (or was witnessed by me), where the ‘me’ is indexed to the person who is
represented in the memory as agent or witness to the event.
Reid’s direct realist theory of remembering joins his direct realist theory of perception. Memory,
like perception, is directed towards the world rather than our experiences of the world. When I
perceive, I do not perceive my own ideas or experiences; I perceive things in the world. When I
remember, I do not remember my past experiences; I remember the events I experienced in the
past. In remembering those events, I do not currently apprehend them. Memory is time-travel
10
only metaphorically. Rather, because I apprehended events in the past, I have the ability to
preserve a direct relation to these events, by now conceiving of them as having happened to me.
In remembering such events, I have access to more than what I presently perceive. Remembering
presupposes past apprehensions but is not directed towards them. Rather, it is directed towards
the world, a world with which I am able to reconnect by remembering the events that happened
there, because I was there. We experience the world by perceiving it and remembering our path
through it.
4 Conclusion
Locke and Reid hold that remembering renews acquaintance with the world by preserving our
relation to the things of which we were aware in the past. In remembering, we renew our
acquaintance with what we formerly apprehended. Remembering requires us to have a past, but
its role in our mental economy is firmly rooted in the present and future. By it, we navigate a
world in which we are increasingly at home. Were we unable to remember, we would ever be to
the world as strangers in a strange land.6
References
Berkeley, G. (2008) Philosophical Writings, D.M. Clarke (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Butler, J. (2006) The Works of Bishop Butler, D.E. White (ed.), Rochester, NY: University of
Rochester Press.
Copenhaver, R. (2006) “Thomas Reid’s Theory of Memory,” History of Philosophy Quarterly
23(2): 171-187.
Copenhaver, R. (2014) “Reid on Memory and Personal Identity,” in E.N. Zalta (ed.) The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, URL =
<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/reid-memory-identity/>.
James, W. (1890) The Principles of Psychology, New York: Henry Holt.
Locke, J. (1975) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, P.H. Nidditch (ed.), Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Malcolm, N. (1977) Memory and Mind, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
Parfit, D. (1985) Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Reid, T. (2002) Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man, D.R. Brookes (ed.), University Park,
PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.
Reid, T. (1997) Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense, D.R. Brookes
(ed.), Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
11
Shoemaker, S. (1970) “Persons and their Pasts,” American Philosophical Quarterly, 7(4): 269–
285; reprinted in Shoemaker, S. (1984), Identity, Cause and Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 19–48.
Van Cleve, J. (2015) Problems from Reid, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Further Reading
Hamilton, A. (2003) “Scottish Commonsense About Memory: A Defence of Thomas Reid’s
Direct Knowledge Account,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81(2): 229-245.
Lännström, A. (2007) “Locke’s Account of Personal Identity: Memory as Fallible Evidence,”
History of Philosophy Quarterly 24(1): 39-56.
Owens, D. (1996) “A Lockean Theory of Memory Experience,” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 56(2): 319-332.
Van Woudenberg, R. (2004) “Reid on Memory and the Identity of Persons,” in T. Cuneo and R.
Van Woudenberg (eds.) The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Weinberg, S. “The Metaphysical Fact of Consciousness in Locke’s Theory of Personal Identity,”
Journal of the History of Philosophy 50(3): 387-415.
Biographical Note
Rebecca Copenhaver is a Professor of Philosophy at Lewis & Clark College, where she has
taught since 2001. Her research interests are in modern philosophy and philosophy of mind. She
is writing a book on Thomas Reid’s science of mind.
1
I have modernized spelling and capitalization but not punctuation in quotations from Locke’s
Essay.
2
In Book II, Chapter 19, Locke presents remembrance in terms of ideas of sense only, though it
is clear from the remainder of the chapter that remembrance includes ideas of reflection as well.
3
I am grateful to Sydney Shoemaker for this insight.
4
See (Van Cleve 2015: 258, n20).
5
For a similar but more extensive treatment of Reid’s theory of memory, see (Copenhaver 2006;
Copenhaver 2014).
6
I thank Shaun Nichols and Brian P. Copenhaver for comments and suggestions on earlier
drafts.
12