Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
New Directions in the Philosophy of Memory
…
10 pages
1 file
The (dis)continuism debate in the philosophy and cognitive science of memory concerns whether remembering is continuous with episodic future thought and episodic counterfactual thought in being a form of constructive imagining. I argue that settling that dispute will hinge on whether the memory traces (or "engrams") that support remembering impose arational, perception-like constraints that are too strong for remembering to constitute a kind of constructive imagining. In exploring that question, I articulate two conceptions of memory traces-the replay theory and the prop theory-that return conflicting answers to whether remembering is constructive imagining. The prop theory's vision of traces is suggestive of continuism, while the replay theory's is a natural fit for discontinuism. Which view of traces is in fact correct remains undetermined by current empirical work. Nevertheless, it may already be possible to reach a compromise in the (dis)continuism debate, through the development of a conciliatory continuist causal theory. This view-only outlined here-accepts the continuismfriendly prop theory of traces, while still requiring that genuine remembering fulfills an appropriate causation condition, as required by the kinds of causal theories of remembering typically favored by discontinuists.
Voluntas, 2019
Frontiers in Psychology
This paper aims to provide a psychologically-informed philosophical account of the phenomenology of episodic remembering. The literature on epistemic or metacognitive feelings has grown considerably in recent years, and there are persuasive reasons, both conceptual and empirical, in favour of the view that the phenomenology of remembering-autonoetic consciousness, as Tulving influentially referred to it, or the feeling of pastness, as we will refer to it here-is an epistemic feeling, but few philosophical treatments of this phenomenology as an epistemic feeling have so far been proposed. Building on insights from the psychological literature, we argue that a form of feeling-based metacognition is involved in episodic remembering and develop an integrated metacognitive feelingbased view that addresses several key aspects of the feeling of pastness, namely, its status as a feeling, its content, and its relationship to the first-order memories the phenomenology of which it provides.
Trans-Kata, 2021
Only humans seem to have the ability to project themselves into their past or future. This mental phenomenon, called autonoetic consciousness, proves the interrelation of memory, imagination, emotion, intelligence and consciousness as a way of creating self-images. The current paper constitutes an integrative study on memory from a theoretical perspective. The first part presents the most known neuroscientific viewpoints on the memory process, along with the pathological case of patient HM, who lost his memory following the removal of his hippocampus. The second part provides a humanistic perspective on recollection to demonstrate its compatibility with the neurological processes of storing information and forming memories. The final part conveys the phenomenon of recollection from the perspective of identity crisis in Kazuo Ishiguro's novels, as a case study in memory literature. According to memory theories to date, identity cannot exist outside the process of recording and recalling past experiences. Despite the fallible nature of recollection, human beings return to their past in order to give a healthy meaning to their present.
Understanding human life, 2022
Whenever we face a new problem, we recall the similar ones we encountered in the past, so we try to solve it with all the information available to us. Memory therefore serves to reveal our life story. This requires us to take a closer look at how memory plays such a role, and at the scientific methods used to demonstrate it. In his 1879 article on “Psychometric experiments,” Galton paved the way for such scientific study. His work made it possible to develop more satisfactory psychological approaches to the recollection of past events. By contrast, his approach to visual memory (1880) yielded far more questionable results. Examining the various psychological approaches to memory, we show that it was almost a century later that the cognitive approach to psychology took up these earlier studies to provide information on autobiographical memory. In particular, the problem of memory failures is critical for the use of autobiographical memory in a number of social sciences. Other approaches are possible, however. They were developed most notably by neuroscience and psychoanalysis, two sharply contrasting disciplines born at nearly the same time. Despite their differences, both approaches are based on the study of nervous diseases. We shall describe their points of convergence and, at the same time, the reasons for their incompatibility. We conclude with the replication crisis that has confronted psychology more recently and with the means to resolve it.
In this article, we argue that emergent interests in social interaction, wider context and culture with regards to memory have united formerly disparate approaches within the discipline of psychology, namely, that from the discursive and experimental cognitive paradigms. Here, we develop the argument on the centrality of interaction and continuity and present an expanded approach that is best able to incorporate distressing events, which we call ‘Vital Memory’. We argue here that this perspective provides an analysis of continuity and interactional dynamics, while not losing sight of what is ethically at stake when individuals remember, especially where memories that are vital to a sense of self in the present are concerned. This perspective encourages a view that treats memory as emerging through the ongoing flow of experience, across time, space and narrative.
Psychological Science, 2010
This is the first empirical study of vivid autobiographical memories for events people no longer believe happened to them. Until now, this phenomenon has been the object of relatively rare albeit intriguing anecdotes, such as Jean Piaget"s description of his vivid memory of an attempted abduction that never happened. The results of our study show that non-believed memories are much more frequent than expected. Approximately 20% of our initial sample reported having at least one non-believed autobiographical memory. Participants" ratings indicate that non-believed memories share most recollective qualities of believed memories, but are characterized by more negative emotional events. The results have important implications for the way autobiographical memory is conceptualized and for the false memory debate. RUNNING HEAD: Non-Believed Memories 3 Imagine that you are trading stories about your shared childhood with a close sibling. You describe a memory about the time that you fell out of a tree and broke your arm. Your memory is vivid-you feel the bark on the tree, hear the leaves blowing in the breeze, experience the fear as you plummet to the ground. It is one of your most clear childhood memories. But your brother looks at you oddly, pauses, and then tells you that it was he and not you who fell and broke his arm. After arguing, you turn to your mother as arbiter. She decrees that this happened to your brother. For the sake of our narrative, we will even have her dig up a hospital bill featuring your sibling"s name and yellowed photos (or perhaps a digital slide-show) of him with arm in sling. In the face of overwhelming evidence, you are forced to conclude that your memory is erroneous. Despite your newfound knowledge, you remain able to "remember" the scene, which continues to feel very much like a true memory. This is a memory for an event you no longer believe has occurred to you.
Memory Studies, 2014
In this article, we argue that emergent interests in social interaction, wider context and culture with regards to memory have united formerly disparate approaches within the discipline of psychology, namely, that from the discursive and experimental cognitive paradigms. Here, we develop the argument on the centrality of interaction and continuity and present an expanded approach that is best able to incorporate distressing events, which we call ‘Vital Memory’. We argue here that this perspective provides an analysis of continuity and interactional dynamics, while not losing sight of what is ethically at stake when individuals remember, especially where memories that are vital to a sense of self in the present are concerned. This perspective encourages a view that treats memory as emerging through the ongoing flow of experience, across time, space and narrative.
Memory Studies, 2019
As a psychologist, when I think about memory, I think about questions such as the following: How do people-and other species-remember the past? What neurological or cognitive mechanisms are involved? What are its properties? Is there one form of memory or many different forms of memory? If more than one, how does one characterize them? To some extent, the philosophy of memory tackles at least some of the same issues, but it appears on the surface to involve much more. As a cursory examination of the Table of Contents of The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Memory indicates, there are concerns about the metaphysics and epistemology of memory and the morality of memory. When are you, for instance, morally obligated to remember? But then, when should you feel the obligation to forget? Questions such as these remain largely either unexplored or unrecognized by psychologists and neuroscientists, and one could reasonably argue, rightly so. One could equally argue, however, that psychologists have a great deal to learn about memory from philosophers. This volume is a good place to start. The editors-Sven Bernecker and Kourken Michaelian-have masterfully found articulate and authoritative contributors who address these topics and many more. I particularly welcomed the section on the history of the philosophy of memory. There are separate chapters on Plato (Chapter 30), Aristotle (Chapter 31), Augustine (Chapter 35), Indian Buddhist philosophy (Chapter 33), Hume (Chapter 39), Hegel (Chapter 40), Bergson (Chapter 42), Halbwachs (Chapter 44), and Ricoeur (Chapter 48), to name just of a handful of the 18 separate historical chapters. These will serve as a ready guide for anyone who wants to understand the contributions of different scholars to the study of memory. As I read through the altogether 48 chapters in this volume, I found myself thinking back to my graduate school days. After a year or two studying the psychology and neuroscience of memory, I decided that I needed to know something about the philosophy of memory. At the time, at Cornell, the formidable Wittgensteinian philosopher Norman Malcolm was teaching a course on memory. I distinctly remember being hopelessly confused from the start. At least in the beginning of the course, Malcolm appeared to treat a memory as a memory only if it captured "truthfully" the past. As Bernecker states in his entry on "Memory and Truth" (Chapter 4), "'To remember' is factive in the sense that an utterance of 'S remembers that p' (where 'S' stands for a subject and 'p' stands for a proposition) is true only if p is the case. If not-p, then S may think that she remembers that p, but she doesn't actually remember that p" (p. 52). A large number of chapters in this volume either embrace this notion, or feel that one must take it seriously enough to tackle it at length. To return to Bernecker again, many philosophers find the statement "I remember such-and-such, but suchand-such never happened," if not literally contradictory, paradoxical. For them, it is "not really a 883205M SS0010.1177/1750698019883205Memory Studies book-review2019 Book review symposium
New Directions in the Philosophy of Memory
This introductory chapter provides an overview of the chapters making up the book, which are grouped into six sections: challenges and alternatives to the causal theory of memory; activity and passivity in remembering; the affective dimension of memory; memory in groups; memory failures: concepts and ethical implications; and the content and phenomenology of episodic and semantic memory.
Cuadernos de Filosofía, 2023
Prosiding SENIATI, 2023
AZERBAIJAN 2TH. INTERNATIONAL CONGRESS OF SCIENTIFIC RESEARCH, 2024
Religions, 2024
International Studies in Educational Administration, 2017
Archivio Penale, 2023
Frontiers in Education, 2020
Géotechnique, 2009
Powder Metallurgy Progress, 2018
Philósophos-Revista de Filosofia, 2010
Graefe's Archive for Clinical and Experimental Ophthalmology, 2021
Molecular Ecology, 2006
PLOS ONE, 2020
SELAPARANG: Jurnal Pengabdian Masyarakat Berkemajuan
Palaeogeography, Palaeoclimatology, Palaeoecology
Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 80(3), 2024