Chapter Title: R
Book Title: The Deleuze Dictionary Revised Edition
Book Editor(s): Adrian Parr
Published by: Edinburgh University Press
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.3366/j.ctt1g09vhf.21
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact
[email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Edinburgh University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to The Deleuze Dictionary Revised Edition
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
REAL
223
Schizophrenia organises desires outside of mainstream Oedipal models,
whose purpose is to block the flows of desire. When Deleuze and
Guattari deploy the term in the political context, schizophrenia refers
to both the system of liquidated flows on which capitalist deterritorialisation depends, as well as the tendency of these flows to leak from all
sides even when they are blocked or captured by the analyst or the state.
Schizophrenia provides a path toward liberation and it is the operative
mode of capitalism, which now dominates the planet because it has
understood, captured, and channeled desire more thoroughly than any
other regime ever has.
R
REACTIVE – refer to the entry on ‘active/reactive’.
REAL
James Williams
Deleuze subverts the concept ‘real’ through his distinction drawn between
the ‘actual’ and the ‘virtual’. For him, the actual is more like what we
would ordinarily understand as the real, that is, a realm of things that
exist independently of our ways of thinking about them and perceiving
them. Whereas the virtual is the realm of transcendental conditions for
the actual, that is, things that we have to presuppose for there to be actual
things at all.
More seriously, with respect to any discussion of his work in terms
of realism, Deleuze denies any priority accorded to human subjects, to
their minds, ideas, perceptual apparatuses or linguistic capacities. If we
traditionally frame the opposition between real and unreal through the
distinction drawn between a thing that is dependent on us (the chair I
dream of, or imagine) and an independent existent (the real chair), then we
shall have started with a conceptual framework that does not fit Deleuze’s
philosophy well at all.
Rather, Deleuze provides us with critical angles against traditional
realism and a new metaphysical framework for developing a concept of
the real. According to this concept the real is the virtual and the actual.
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 223
10/08/2010 16:17
224
REICH, WILHELM (1897–1957)
It is hence better to think of real things in terms more of complete things
rather than independent ones. Note that this commits Deleuze to degrees
of reality and unreality or illusion.We should not say real or unreal, but
more or less real, meaning a more or less complete expression of the thing.
It is questionable whether we can say that a thing is completely real, in
Deleuze’s work, other than the metaphysical statement that the real is all
of the actual and of the virtual. Whenever we give an expression of a thing
it will be under an individual form of expression that allows for further
completion. More importantly, that completion will involve a synthetic
alteration of the components of any earlier reality, to the point where no
component can be claimed to be finally real or complete.
For example, for Deleuze, a mountain exists as real with all the ways it
has been painted, sensed, written about and walked over. It also exists with
all the virtual conditions for them, such as ideas and different intensities of
sensations. The real mountain changes completely when it is painted and
sensed anew: when its name changes, when it is mined, or moved through
differently.
This means that traditional forms of realism are completely at odds with
Deleuze’s philosophy, since the notion that the real stands in opposition to
something unreal or imaginary already sets the real as something incomplete. So to speak of the real chair as if it could be identified independently
of our ideas about it is a mistake concerning the significance of things.
Reality goes hand in hand with ideal and emotional effects, rather than
being free of them.
Does this mean that Deleuze is an idealist, denying the existence of
an independent external reality and bringing all things into the mind?
Deleuze’s philosophy is beyond the idealist and realist distinction.
There are actual things and we should pay attention to them. Without
them it does not make sense to speak of virtual ideas or intensities. But,
reciprocally, it makes no sense to speak of real or actual things as if they
could be abstracted from the ideal and emotional fields that make them
live for us.
Connectives
Actuality
Virtual/Virtuality
REICH, WILHELM
‘schizoanalysis’.
(1897–1957)
–
refer
to
the
entry
on
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 224
10/08/2010 16:17
REPETITION
225
REPETITION
Adrian Parr
The concept of ‘repetition’, as it appears in the Deleuzian corpus, encompasses a variety of other concepts such as ‘difference’, ‘differentiation’,
‘deterritorialisation’, and ‘becoming’. To begin with, it should be noted
that for Deleuze, repetition is not a matter of the same thing occurring
over and over again. That is to say, repetition is connected to the power
of difference in terms of a productive process that produces variation in
and through every repetition. In this way, repetition is best understood in
terms of discovery and experimentation; it allows new experiences, affects
and expressions to emerge. To repeat is to begin again; to affirm the power
of the new and the unforeseeable. In so far as life itself is described as a
dynamic and active force of repetition producing difference, the force of
which Deleuze encourages us to think of in terms of ‘becoming’, forces
incorporate difference as they repeat giving rise to mutation.
The first question that arises is: How is repetition produced? For
Deleuze, repetition is produced via difference, not mimesis. It is a process
of ungrounding that resists turning into an inert system of replication. In
fact, the whole Platonist idea of repeating in order to produce copies is
completely undermined by Deleuze. For Deleuze maintains this approach
is deeply flawed because it subsumes the creative nature of difference
under an immobile system of resemblance. Deleuze refuses to seek an
originary point out of which repetition can cyclically reproduce itself.
He insists that the process does not depend upon a subject or object that
repeats, rather it is self-sustainable. Whilst repetition is potentially infinite, consisting of new beginnings, it is crucial we do not mistake this to be
a linear sequence: the end of one cycle marking the beginning of the next.
In his innovative discussions of Friedrich Nietzsche’s concept of the
eternal return, Deleuze turns his back on a teleological understanding
of repetition condemning such interpretations to be flawed. Instead, he
insists that the process Nietzsche outlines is considerably more complicated than that: the return is an active affirmation that intensifies as it
returns. Put differently, heterogeneity arises out of intensity. In addition,
the return points to a whole that emerges through difference and variation:
one and the multiple in combination. In his reading of Nietzsche, Deleuze
explains in his 1968 work Difference and Repetition that this is the ‘power
of beginning and beginning again’ (D 1994: 136).
This now leads us on to the second question: What is repeated? First, it
is important to note that repetition is not unidirectional, there is no object
of repetition, no final goal toward which everything that repeats can be
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 225
10/08/2010 16:17
226
REPETITION + CINEMA
said to direct itself. What repeats, then, is not models, styles or identities but the full force of difference in and of itself, those pre-individual
singularities that radically maximise difference on a plane of immanence.
In an early essay from 1956 on Henri Bergson, Deleuze insists repetition
is more a matter of coexistence than succession, which is to say, repetition
is virtual more than it is actual. It is this innovative understanding of the
process of difference and differentiation that mutates the context through
which repetition occurs.
Thus, in a very real sense, repetition is a creative activity of transformation. When Deleuze speaks of the ‘new’ that repetition invokes, he is
likewise pointing to creativity, whereby habit and convention are both
destabilised. The ‘new’, for Deleuze, is filled with innovation and actually
prevents the trap of routines and clichés; the latter characterise habitual
ways of living. As a power of the new, repetition calls forth a terra incognita filled with a sense of novelty and unfamiliarity. For instance, this is
a far cry from Sigmund Freud who posited that we compulsively repeat
the past, where all the material of our repressed unconscious pushes us to
reiterate the past in all its discomfort and pain. Actually, psychoanalysis
limits repetition to representation, and what therapy aims to do is stop the
process entirely along with the disorders it gives rise to. Deleuze, on the
other hand, encourages us to repeat because he sees in it the possibility
of reinvention, that is to say, repetition dissolves identities as it changes
them, giving rise to something unrecognisable and productive. It is for
this reason that he maintains repetition is a positive power (puissance) of
transformation.
Connectives
Active/Reactive
Becoming
Difference
Eternal return
Psychoanalysis
REPETITION + CINEMA
Constantine Verevis
Deleuze’s books on cinema – Cinema 1: The movement-image and Cinema
2: The time-image – are about the possibility of ‘repeating’ a film (or films)
within the institution of cinema studies. As in Roland Barthes’ account
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 226
10/08/2010 16:17
REPETITION + CINEMA
227
of re-reading, this repetition would not be the re-presentation of identity
(a re-discovery of the same), but the re-production – the creation and the
exhibition – of the difference that lies at the heart of repetition (B 1974).
For film studies, Deleuze’s Cinema books can be seen as an attempt to
negotiate the tension between (film) theory and history via a non-totalising
concept of difference, one which can attend to the heterogeneity – the
local and specific repetitions – of historical material.
In Difference and Repetition, Deleuze puts forward two alternative theories of repetition. The first, a ‘Platonic’ theory of repetition, posits a world
of difference based upon some pre-established similitude or identity; it
defines a world of copies (representations). The second, a ‘Nietzschean’
theory of repetition suggests that similitude and identity is the product of
some fundamental disparity or difference; it defines a world of simulacra
(phantasms). Taking these formulations as distinct interpretations of the
world, Deleuze describes simulacra as intensive systems constituted by
the placing together of disparate elements. Within these differential series,
a third virtual object (dark precursor, eternal return, abstract machine)
plays the role of differenciator, the in-itself of difference which relates different to different, and allows divergent series to return as diversity and its
re-production. As systems that include within themselves this differential
point of view, simulacra evade the limit of representation (the model of
recognition) to effect the intensity of an encounter with difference and its
repetition, a pure becoming-in-the-world.
The idea of the intensive system, and its frustration of any attempt to
establish an order of succession, a hierarchy of identity and resemblance
between original and copy, is nowhere more evident than in the serial
repetition of new Hollywood cinema, especially the film remake. The
majority of critical accounts of cinematic remaking understand it as a
one-way process: a movement from authenticity to imitation, from the
superior selfidentity of the original to the debased resemblance of the
remake. For instance, much of the discussion around the 1998 release
of Gus Van Sant’s close remake (‘replica’) of Alfred Hitchcock’s Psycho
(1960) was an expression of outrage and confusion at the defilement of a
revered classic. Reviewers and ‘Hitchcockians’ agreed that Van Sant made
two fundamental mistakes: the first, to have undertaken to remake a landmark of cinematic history; and the second, to have followed the Hitchcock
original (almost) shot by shot, line by line. Even for those who noted
that the remake differed in its detail from the Hitchcock film, the revisions added nothing to what remained an intact and undeniable classic, a
semantic fixity (identity) against which the new version was evaluated and
dismissed as a degraded copy.
Rather than follow these essentialist trajectories, Deleuze’s account of
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 227
10/08/2010 16:17
228
REPRESENTATION
repetition suggests that cinematic remaking in its most general application
might – more productively – be regarded as a specific aspect of a broader
and more open-ended intertextuality. A modern classic, Psycho has been
retrospectively coded as the forerunner to a cycle of slasher movies initiated by Halloween (1978) and celebrated in the sequels and series that
followed. More particularly, the 1970s interest in the slasher movie subgenre saw the character of Norman Bates revived for a number of Psycho
sequels (II–IV), and the Hitchcock original quoted in a host of homages,
notably the films of Brian De Palma. Each of these repetitions can be
understood as a limited form of remaking, suggesting that the precursor
text is never singular, and that Van Sant’s Psycho remake differs textually
from these other examples not in kind, but only in degree.
While the above approach establishes a large circuit between Psycho-60
and Psycho-98, there is another position: namely, that Van Sant’s Psycho
is not close enough to the Hitchcock version. This suggestion – that an
irreducible difference plays simultaneously between the most mechanical of repetitions – is best demonstrated by an earlier remake of Psycho,
Douglas Gordon’s 24 Hour Psycho (1993). So named because it takes
twenty-four hours to run its course, Gordon’s version is a video installation that re-runs Psycho-60 at approximately two frames per second, just
fast enough for each image to be pulled forward into the next. Gordon’s
strategy demonstrates that each and every film is remade – dispersed and
transformed – in its every new context or configuration. Gordon does not
set out to imitate Psycho but to repeat it – to change nothing, but at the
same time allow an absolute difference to emerge. Understood in this way,
Psycho-98 is not a perversion of an original identity, but the production
of a new event, one that adds to (rather than corrupts) the seriality of the
former version.
REPRESENTATION
John Marks
‘Representation’, for Deleuze, entails an essentially moral view of the
world, explicitly or implicitly drawing on what ‘everybody knows’, and he
conceives of philosophy as an antidote to this view. Representation cannot
help us to encounter the world as it appears in the flow of time and becoming. It constitutes a particularly restricted form of thinking and acting,
working according to fixed norms, and which is unable to acknowledge
difference ‘in itself ’. In Difference and Repetition Deleuze challenges the
representational conception of philosophy. Here, he contrasts the ‘poet’ to
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 228
10/08/2010 16:17
REPRESENTATION
229
the ‘politician’. The poet speaks in the name of a creative power, and seeks
to affirm difference as a state of permanent revolution: he is willing to be
destructive in the search for the ‘new’. The new, in this sense, remains
forever new, since it has the power of beginning anew every time. It
enables forces in thought which are not the forces of recognition, but the
powers of an unrecognisable terra incognita. The politician, on the other
hand, seeks to deny that which differs in order to establish or maintain a
particular historical order. In philosophical terms, Deleuze proposes to
‘overturn’ Platonism, which distinguishes between the original – the thing
that most resembles itself, characterised by exemplary self-identity – and
the copy, which is always deficient in relation to the original. Platonism
is incapable of thinking difference in itself, preferring to conceive of it
in relation to ‘the thing itself ’. In order to go beyond representation, it
is necessary, therefore, to undermine the primacy of the original over
the copy and to promote the simulacrum, the copy for which there is no
original.
A key influence on Deleuze as far as the anti-representational orientation of his thought is concerned, is Friedrich Nietzsche. Nietzsche’s
speculations on metaphor show that there is no ‘truth’ behind the mask
of appearances, but rather only more masks, more metaphors. Deleuze
elevates this insight into something like a general metaphysical principle.
For him, the world is composed of simulacra: it is a ‘swarm’ of appearances. Deleuze’s Bergsonism, which emphasises a radical analysis of time,
is an important element of his challenge to representation. In his books
on cinema in particular, Deleuze draws on Henri Bergson’s very particular materialism in order to claim that life is composed of images. Rather
than human consciousness illuminating the world like a searchlight, it is
the case that the world is ‘luminous’ in itself. Bergson’s critique of the
problematics of perception and action, and matter and thought, springs
from the claim that we tend to think in terms of space rather than time.
This tendency immobilises intuition, and to counter this Bergson conceives of materiality in terms of images that transmit movement. This has
important consequences for perception, which can no longer be conceived
of as knowledge that is rooted in consciousness. All life perceives and is
necessarily open to the ‘outside’ and distinctions between automatism
and voluntary acts are only differences of degree, rather than differences
in kind. This alternative, non-psychological metaphysics, according to
which the world is ‘luminous in itself ’, rather than being illuminated by
a beam of consciousness, is at the heart of Deleuze’s non-representational
project, and is explored at length in his books on cinema. Following
Bergson’s materialist ontology, according to which our body is merely an
image among images, Deleuze opens the self to the outside, the pure form
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 229
10/08/2010 16:17
230
REPRESSION
of time. The self comes into contact with a virtual, non-psychological
memory, a domain of diversity, difference, and with potentially anarchic
associations, that jeopardise the sense selfhood.
Such forms of anti-representational thought are threatening and
potentially disorientating. As Bergson argues, human beings choose on
the basis of what is the most useful. As such they tend to spatialise the
fluidity of duration, reducing it to a static and impersonal public form.
We separate duration into dissociated elements and reconfigure these elements in a homogeneous spatial form organised around the conventions of
‘public’ language that conveys widely recognised notions. We like ‘simple
thoughts’, Bergson remarks, and we prefer to rely on custom and habit,
replacing diversity with simplicity, foregoing the novelty of new situations. In short, we prefer the comforts and conventions of representation.
This helps to explain why art – literature, painting and cinema – plays
such an important part in Deleuze’s work. For Deleuze, art is not a way
of representing experiences and memories that we might ‘recognise’:
it does not show us what the world is, but rather imagines a possible
world. Similarly, art is concerned with ‘sensation’, with creating ‘sensible
aggregates’, rather than making the world intelligible and recognisable. In
order to challenge representational views of art, Deleuze talks of ‘affects’
and ‘percepts’. These are artistic forces that have been freed from the
organising representational framework of perceiving individuals. Instead,
they give us access to a pre-individual world of singularities. In this way,
Deleuze sees art as a way of challenging the interpretative tendency of
representation to trace becomings back to origins.
Connectives
Affect
Art
Becoming
Difference
Sensation
REPRESSION
Claire Colebrook
On the one hand, Deleuze might appear to be a philosopher set against the
dominant image of repression, that being repression in its everyday sense
and in its technical psychoanalytic sense. At its most general the concept
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 230
10/08/2010 16:17
REPRESSION
231
of ‘repression’ would seem to imply a natural self or subject who precedes
the operation of power of socialisation (so that all we would have to do is
lift the strictures of repression to arrive at who we really are). The concept
of repression seems, then, to be associated with the idea of a pre-social
self who must then undergo socialisation or structuration. Deleuze wants
to avoid this naïvety, and so to a certain extent he accepts the productive
nature of repression as it was put forward by Sigmund Freud and then
Jacques Lacan. It is only because of our existence within a symbolic order,
or perceived system, that we imagine that there must have been a real
‘me’ prior to the net of repression. For psychoanalysis, then, it is not the
self who is repressed, for the self – the fantasy of that which exists before
speech, relations and sociality – is an effect of the idea of repression.
Repression is primary and produces its own ‘ before’. Deleuze accepts this
Lacanian/Freudian picture up to a point. With Guattari he argues that
there are Oedipal structures of repression. Living in a modern age, we are
indeed submitted to a system of signification. We then imagine that there
must have been a moment of plenitude and jouissance prior to Oedipal
repression, and that we must therefore have desired the maternal incest
prohibited by the structures of the family. But Deleuze and Guattari
regard repression – or the internalisation of subjection – as a modern
phenomenon that nevertheless draws upon archaic structures and images.
Deleuze and Guattari’s main attack on what Michel Foucault (in The
History of Sexuality: Volume One) referred to as ‘the repressive hypothesis’ occurs in Anti-Oedipus. Whereas Freud’s Oedipus complex seeks to
explain why and how we are repressed – how it is that we submit to law and
renounce our enjoyment – Deleuze and Guattari argue that we suffer from
the idea of repression itself, the idea that there is some ultimate object that
we have abandoned. Psychoanalysis supposedly explains our repression
by arguing that we all desired our mothers but had to abandon incest for
the sake of social and cultural development. Deleuze and Guattari argue
that this repressive idea of renunciation and submission is a historical
and political development. Desire, they insist, is not the desire for some
forbidden object, a desire that we must necessarily repress. Rather, all
life is positive desire – expansion, connection, creation. It is not that we
must repress our desire for incest. Rather, the idea of incest – that we are
inevitably familial and desire only the impossible maternal object – is itself
repressive. What it represses is not a personal desire, but the impersonality
of desire or the intense germinal influx. To imagine ourselves as rational
individuals, engaged in negotiation and the management of our drives –
this idea of ourselves as bourgeois, selfgoverning, commonsensical agents
– represses the desire for non-familial, impersonal, chaotic and singular
configurations of life. We are repressed, then, not by a social order that
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 231
10/08/2010 16:17
232
RETERRITORIALISATION
prohibits the natural desire for incest, but by the image that our desires
‘naturally’ take the form of Oedipal and familial images.
The late modern understanding of the self or subject as necessarily
subjected to law is the outcome of a history of political development that
has covered over the originally expansive, excessive and constructive
movements of desire. A number of philosophical movements, including
psychoanalysis, have explained life from the point of view of the already
repressed subject, the bourgeois individual who has submitted his desires
to the system of the polity and the market. Against this, Deleuze and
Guattari aim to reveal the positive desire behind repression. In the case
of Oedipal repression, it is the desire of the father – the desire of white,
modern, bourgeois man – that lies at the heart of the idea of all selves as
necessarily subjected to repressive power.
Connectives
Desire
Foucault
Freud
Oedipalisation
Psychoanalysis
Woman
RETERRITORIALISATION – refer to the entry on ‘deterritorialisation/
reterritorialisation’.
RHIZOME
Felicity J. Colman
‘Rhizome’ describes the connections that occur between the most disparate and the most similar of objects, places and people; the strange chains
of events that link people: the feeling of ‘six degrees of separation’, the
sense of ‘having been here before’ and assemblages of bodies. Deleuze and
Guattari’s concept of the ‘rhizome’ draws from its etymological meaning,
where ‘rhizo’ means combining form and the biological term ‘rhizome’
describes a form of plant that can extend itself through its underground
horizontal tuber-like root system and develop new plants. In Deleuze and
Guattari’s use of the term, the rhizome is a concept that ‘maps’ a process
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 232
10/08/2010 16:17
RHIZOME
233
of networked, relational and transversal thought, and a way of being
without ‘tracing’ the construction of that map as a fixed entity (D&G
1987: 12). Ordered lineages of bodies and ideas that trace their originary
and individual bases are considered as forms of ‘aborescent thought’, and
this metaphor of a tree-like structure that orders epistemologies and forms
historical frames and homogeneous schemata, is invoked by Deleuze and
Guattari to describe everything that rhizomatic thought is not.
In addition, Deleuze and Guattari describe the rhizome as an action of
many abstract entities in the world, including music, mathematics, economics, politics, science, art, the ecology and the cosmos. The rhizome
conceives how every thing and every body – all aspects of concrete,
abstract and virtual entities and activities – can be seen as multiple in their
interrelational movements with other things and bodies. The nature of the
rhizome is that of a moving matrix, composed of organic and non-organic
parts forming symbiotic and aparallel connections, according to transitory
and as yet undetermined routes (D & G 1987: 10). Such a reconceptualisation constitutes a revolutionary philosophy for the reassessment of any
form of hierarchical thought, history or activity.
In a world that builds structures from economic circuits of difference
and desire, Deleuze responds by reconsidering how bodies are constructed. He and Guattari argue that such structures constrain creativity
and position things and people into regulatory orders. In A Thousand
Plateaus, Deleuze and Guattari staged the entire book as a series of
networked rhizomatic ‘plateaus’ that operate to counter historical and
philosophical positions pitched toward the system of representation that
fix the flow of thought. Instead, through a virtuoso demonstration of the
relational energies able to be configured through often disparate forms and
systems of knowledge, they offer the reader an open system of thought.
Rhizomatic formations can serve to overcome, overturn and transform
structures of rigid, fixed or binary thought and judgement – the rhizome is
‘anti-genealogy’ (D&G 1987: 11). A rhizome contributes to the formation
of a plateau through its lines of becoming, which form aggregate connections. There are no singular positions on the networked lines of a rhizome,
only connected points which form connections between things. A rhizomatic plateau of thought, Deleuze and Guattari suggest, may be reached
through the consideration of the potential of multiple and relational ideas
and bodies. The rhizome is any network of things brought into contact
with one another, functioning as an assemblage machine for new affects,
new concepts, new bodies, new thoughts; the rhizomatic network is a
mapping of the forces that move and/or immobilise bodies.
Deleuze and Guattari insist bodies and things ceaselessly take on new
dimensions through their contact with different and divergent entities
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 233
10/08/2010 16:17
234
RHIZOME
over time; in this way the concept of the ‘rhizome’ marks a divergent way
of conceptualising the world that is indicative of Deleuzian philosophy as
a whole. Rather than reality being thought of and written as an ordered
series of structural wholes, where semiotic connections or taxonomies can
be compiled from complete root to tree-like structure, the story of the
world and its components, Deleuze and Guattari propose, can be communicated through the rhizomatic operations of things – movements,
intensities and polymorphous formations. In opposition to descendent
evolutionary models of classification, rhizomes have no hierarchical order
to their compounding networks. Instead, Deleuzian rhizomatic thinking
functions as an open-ended productive configuration, where random associations and connections propel, sidetrack and abstract relations between
components. Any part within a rhizome may be connected to another part,
forming a milieu that is decentred, with no distinctive end or entry point.
Deleuze’s apparatus for describing affective change is the ‘rhizome’.
Deleuze viewed every operation in the world as the affective exchange of
rhizomatically-produced intensities that create bodies: systems, economies, machines and thoughts. Each and every body is propelled and
perpetuated by innumerable levels of the affective forces of desire and
its resonating materialisations. Variations to any given system can occur
because of interventions within cyclical, systematic repetition. As the
rhizome may be constituted with an existing body – including existing
thoughts one might bring to bear upon another body – the rhizome is
necessarily subject to the principles of diversity and difference through
repetition, which Deleuze discussed in his books Nietzsche and Philosophy
and Difference and Repetition.
Deleuze acknowledges Friedrich Nietzsche’s concept of the eternal
return as the constitution of things through repeated elements (existing
bodies, modes of thought) that form a ‘synthesis’ of difference through
the repetition of elements (D 1983: 46). ‘Synthesis’ is also described by
Deleuze and Guattari as an assemblage of variable relations produced
by the movement, surfaces, elusions and relations of rhizomes that form
bodies (desiring machines) through composite chains of previously unattached links (D&G 1983: 39, 327). As a non-homogeneous sequence, then,
the rhizome describes a series that may be composed of causal, chance,
and/or random links. Rhizomatic connections between bodies and forces
produce an affective energy or entropy. As Deleuze describes in his work
on David Hume, the interaction of a socially, politically, or culturally
determined force and any given body both produces and uses associations
of ideas (D 1991: ix, 103). The discontinuous chain is the medium for the
rhizome’s expanding network, just as it is also the contextual circumstance
for the chain’s production.
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 234
10/08/2010 16:17
RHIZOME + ARCHITECTURE
235
Rhizomatic writing, being, and/or becoming is not simply a process
that assimilates things, rather it is a milieu of perpetual transformation.
The relational milieu that the rhizome creates gives form to evolutionary
environments where relations alter the course of how flows and collective
desire develop. There is no stabilising function produced by the rhizomatic medium; there is no creation of a whole out of virtual and dispersed
parts. Rather, through the rhizome, points form assemblages, multiple
journey systems associate into possibly disconnected or broken topologies;
in turn, such assemblages and typologies change, divide, and multiply
through disparate and complex encounters and gestures. The rhizome is a
powerful way of thinking without recourse to analogy or binary constructions. To think in terms of the rhizome is to reveal the multiple ways that
you might approach any thought, activity, or a concept – what you always
bring with you are the many and various ways of entering any body, of
assembling thought and action through the world.
Connectives
Affect
Becoming
Desire
Hume
Intensity
Lines of Flight
RHIZOME + ARCHITECTURE
Graham Livesey
Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of the rhizome as a continuously reorganising network, or web, has application to both architecture and urbanism.
Deleuze and Guattari describe the principles of rhizomatic structures as
involving connection, heterogeneity, multiplicity, asignifying rupture,
cartography, and decalcomania. Applying Deleuze and Guattari is always
challenging, nevertheless rhizomatics provides a useful model for examining the internal relationships within buildings, the inter-connections
between buildings and their surroundings, and most specifically the
structure of cities. In fact Deleuze and Guattari describe Amsterdam as a
‘rhizome-city’ (D&G 1987: 15). Elsewhere, Deleuze describes the city as a
labyrinth in terms that strongly invoke the rhizome (D 1993a: 24).
The notion that a point or site (building, space, location, etc.) is
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 235
10/08/2010 16:17
236
RHIZOME + ARCHITECTURE
connected to an infinitude of other points or sites is a productive concept.
This results in structures and relationships that are ‘acentered, nonhierarchical, nonsignifying’ (D&G 1987: 21). The concentration on the line
inherent to the rhizome places emphasis on connectivity and movement.
This invokes both communication systems and the movement of people,
goods, and services; architecture and cities are widely engaged in these
functions.
Various examples can be cited for a rhizomatic architecture and
urbanism. Drawing from the plant and animal derivation of the term,
the concept of architecture behaving like a rhizomatic weed was invoked
by R.E. Somol when describing architect Peter Eisenman’s Wexner
Center for the Visual Arts in Ohio. Somol suggests that the building rises up in-between other structures, much like a weed, and that
it makes rhizomatic connections to various existing structures and
conditions (S 1989: 48-51). Another example of a rhizomatic architecture draws from the work of the post-war Team 10 movement, which
generally invoked arborescent structures in their design of buildings
and city. However, they also developed the ‘mat-building’ typology,
derived from open-ended urban structures. Mat-buildings such as
the Berlin Free University project, by the architects Candilis-JosicWoods, employed a web and matrix of spaces and movement systems.
Describing mat-buildings, the British architect, and Team 10 member,
Alison Smithson writes: ‘. . .the functions come to enrich the fabric,
and the individual gains new freedoms of action through a new and
shuffled order, based on interconnection, close-knit patterns of association, and possibilities of growth, diminution, and change’ (S 1974: 573).
The emphasis placed by Deleuze and Guattari on cartography, in their
definition of the rhizome, also resonates with architectural and urban
practices. However, the mapping they describe, and it is a powerful
formulation, ‘pertains to a map that must be produced, constructed, a
map that is always detachable, connectable, reversible, modifiable, and
has multiple entryways and exits and its own lines of flight’ (D&G 1987:
21). This implies that cartography is most productive when it captures
complexity and temporality; the mapping of non-conventional qualities and quantities has become an important aspect of architecture and
urbanism influenced by Deleuze and Guattari.
Architecture tends to focus on the material and formal aspects of buildings, however buildings are spatial, functional, and social environments.
Deleuze and Guattari’s concept of the rhizome is a vital concept for
shifting the emphasis of architecture to the complex networks of movement, social connections, and communications that buildings and urban
environments encompass.
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 236
10/08/2010 16:17
RHIZOME + TECHNOLOGY
237
RHIZOME + TECHNOLOGY
Verena Conley
The ‘rhizome’ replaces an arborescent structure that has been dominating the west and the world for centuries. The rhizome carries images
of the natural world, of pliable grasses, of weightlessness, and of
landscapes of the east. It is horizontal and flat, bearing what the mathematician in Deleuze calls ‘n-1 dimensions’. It is always a multiplicity;
it has no genealogy; it could be taken from different contexts (including
Freudian psychoanalysis); and is neither genesis nor childhood. The
rhizome does away with hierarchies. It augments its valences through
hybrid connections that consist by virtue of addition, of one thing ‘and’
another. The rhizome operates in a space without boundaries and defies
established categories such as binaries or points that would mark-off
and be used to fix positions in extensive space. It ceaselessly connects
and reconnects over fissures and gaps, deterritorialising and reterritorialising itself at once. It works toward abstract machines and produces
lines of flight.
The rhizome does not imitate or represent, rather it connects through
the middle and invents hybrids with viruses that become part of the
cells that scramble the dominant lines of genealogical trees. The rhizome
creates a web or a network; through capture of code, it increases its
valences and is always in a state of becoming. It creates and recreates
the world through connections. A rhizome has no structure or centre,
no graph or regulation. Models are both in construction and collapse. In
a rhizome, movement is more intensive than extensive. Unlike graphic
arts, the rhizome makes a map and not a tracing of lines (that would
belong to a representation of an object). It is a war machine: rhizomatic
or nomadic writing operates as a mobile war machine that moves at top
speed to form lines, making alliances that form a temporary plateau. The
rhizome is in a constant process of making active, but always temporary, selections. The selections can be good or bad. Good or bad ideas,
states Deleuze in consort with Gregory Bateson, can lead to good or bad
connections.
The proximity of the rhizome to digital technology and the computer
is evident. The connection with Donna Haraway’s cyborg has often been
made. Yet Deleuze and Guattari do not write much about computers.
They derive some of their ideas on rhizomes from Bateson’s Steps to an
Ecology of Mind. They connect with the anthropologist’s pronouncements
in which biology and information theory are conjoined. Bateson argues
that a person is not limited to her or his visible body. Of importance is
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 237
10/08/2010 16:17
238
SACHER-MASOCH, LEOPOLD VON (1835–95)
the person’s brain that transmits information as discrete differences. The
brain fires electrons that move along circuits. Through the transmission
of differences, the person connects and reconnects with other humans,
animals and the world.
Deleuze and Guattari see the potential in Bateson’s work for rhizomatic thinking. The nervous system is said to be a rhizome, web or
network. The terminology is the same as for computers though it does
not pertain to them exclusively. Clearly, computers do offer possibilities.
Not only the brain, but humans and the world consist of circuits in which
differences are transmitted along pathways. Through computerassisted
subjectivity, humans can increase their valences. Deleuze and Guattari
write about a ‘becoming-radio’ or ‘becoming-television’ that can yield
good or bad connections; productive or nefarious becomings. Computers
and the internet have great potential as rhizomatic war machines. The
way they are being captured by capitalism, that deploys order-words,
consumer codes, and their multifarious redundancies makes them too
often become ends in and for themselves, in a sphere of what Deleuze
calls a generalised ‘techno-narcissism’. The science of technology takes
over with its order-words. Yet, in Deleuze’s practical utopia, just as
every major language is worked through by minor languages, so the
capitalist war machine is always being threatened by mobile nomadic
war machines that use technologies to form new rhizomes and open up
to becoming.
S
SACHER- MASOCH, LEOPOLD VON (1835–95) – refer to the
entries on ‘art’, ‘Lacan’ and ‘psychoanalysis’.
SARTRE, JEAN PAUL (1905–80) – refer to the entries on ‘Guattari’
and ‘phenomenology’.
SAUSSURE, FERDINAND DE (1857–1913) – refer to the entries on
‘semiotics’ and ‘signifier, signified’.
This content downloaded from
203.220.159.251 on Wed, 06 Dec 2023 01:41:10 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
M2328 - PARR TEXT.indd 238
10/08/2010 16:17