Tolerance and the Use and Abuse of the Enlightenment
Olomouc, Czech Republic; IP Programme, Euroculture
24 June, 2015
The theme of this year s )P, as we know, is the Uses and Abuses of the Past. For me, as a
Germanist, my first association when considering this topic was with Friedrich Nietzsche s
1874 essay On the Use and Abuse of (istory which contrasts the ideas of living
historically and unhistorically. Nietzsche asks his readers to consider that the unhistorical
and the historical are equally necessary to the health of an individual, a community, and a
system of culture
. On the one hand, the power of forgetting and the ability to live
unhistorically in the present is crucial and important for our happiness, as an excess of
history can be burdensome and making life maimed and degenerate. However, he also
recognizes that we nevertheless need history and a knowledge of the past for the service
of the future and the present
. )n many ways, though, Nietzsche s essay is really about
historical education and the necessity to learn from the past: Modern man, he writes,
carries inside him an enormous heap of indigestible knowledge-stones that occasionally
rattle together in his body
. That internal rattling, though, reveals a most striking
aspect of modern men: the opposition of something inside them to which nothing external
corresponds, and the reverse (23). In essence, what Nietzsche is speaking of here is the
need for applicability—how to make history relevant to the present and how to relate the
present, external world to historical knowledge.
This is the topic that I would like to speak about today, particularly in regard
to recent debates in Europe about tolerance and the fundamental principles of the
Enlightenment as a foundation to European identity. In the wake of the Charlie Hebdo
shootings, the Copenhagen shootings and the violence in Texas in the aftermath of the
Copenhagen debate, Europe (and the secular West) has begun struggling with the legacy of
the Enlightenment, which somewhat paradoxically advocated both for freedom of religion
as well as for the freedom from religious doctrine and orthodoxy. With the rise of
immigration and the spread of globalization, a fundamental question about the limits of
tolerance in a post-secular Europe have shaken the foundations of Western society. The
increased secularization of Western society was once thought to be the norm in the new
millennium, as societies moved further away from identities based on religion in favor of
what J“rgen (abermas has called Occidental rationalism, rooted in Enlightenment
thinking. However Habermas himself has come to reconsider this idea and in 2008 he
published an essay arguing instead that we now live in a post-secular society: global
changes and the visible conflicts that flare up in connection with religious issues, he
writes, give us reason to doubt whether the relevance of religion has waned. As a result,
new tensions have arisen between secularist thinkers in the tradition of the Enlightenment,
who reject the imposition of religious ideology and who wish to maintain a strong
separation between church and state, and multiculturalists, who emphasize the importance
of individual freedom, tolerance of difference and the plurality of cultures. But how can
Europe reconcile this division, stay true to its Enlightened heritage and embrace a unity in
diversity, the motto that it has adopted for the EU?
Article
of the European Union s Lisbon Treaty from
declares that the EU was
founded on the values of respect for human dignity, freedom, democracy, equality, the rule
of law and respect for human rights, including the rights of persons belonging to
minorities. These values have a long tradition in Europe dating back to both Renaissance
and Enlightenment thought, when the notion of universal human rights and tolerance of
individual difference was first posited. Recent laws in Europe though banning religious
symbols in the public sphere have sparked a renewed debate over the importance of
individual freedom and the limits of tolerance in democratic societies. Ironically,
philosophers and intellectuals on both sides of the issue have utilized the values of the
Enlightenment to further their argument. One of the more interesting debates arose in
2006, when British historian Timothy Garton Ash published a review of two books dealing
with the seeming incompatibility of Islamic and European values. The two books in
question, Ayan (irsi Ali s The Caged Virgin and )an Buruma s Murder in Amsterdam, take
very different approaches to the issue of tolerance and multiculturalism, the former
warning of the dangers that Islam presents to the Enlightened European tradition and the
need to remain steadfast against it, while the latter considers both the need for as well as
the limits of tolerance in a liberal democracy. While Garton Ash reviewed Buruma s book
favorably, he was more critical of (irsi Ali s autobiographical work, going so far as to call
her an Enlightenment fundamentalist, echoing a phrase that Buruma himself used in
referring to the Somali-born member of Dutch parliament. Hirsi Ali, who grew up Muslim
and later fled Kenya to escape an arranged marriage, had gone from one ideological
extreme to another, Garton Ash argued, making her a heroine to many secular European
intellectuals. Such fundamentalists, he feels, wrongly …believe that a Europe based
entirely on secular humanism would be a better Europe . Garton Ash sets up an age-old
dichotomy of faith versus reason, writing: For secular Europeans to demand that Muslims
adopt their faith—secular humanism—would be almost as intolerant as the Islamist
jihadist demand that we should adopt theirs. But, the Enlightenment fundamentalist will
protest, our faith is based on reason. Well they reply, ours is based on truth. Such
arguments between the church and secular powers over faith and reason were common in
the 18th century, and they have re-surfaced again today in the multicultural discourses and
the tension between individual freedom and toleration, perhaps most notably in Pope
Benedict s controversial
university.
6 Regensburg speech on the subject of faith, reason and the
But what exactly is an Enlightened fundamentalist ? )n the European tradition
fundamentalists were those deemed lacking a critical intellectual or ideological view of
their own position. The Counter Enlightenment attacked thinkers who they felt embraced
reason and rationality in an uncritical manner. The term has been utilized in more recent
political debates and has gained currency, especially in Holland, in the wake of the attacks
on World Trade Center in 2001. It was then that the discussion shifted to multiculturalism,
cultural relativism and the defense of traditional European values, which has a long and
poisonous history in European politics. The Enlightenment in particular, Buruma notes,
…has a particular appeal to some conservatives because its values are not just universal,
but more importantly, ours, that is European, Western values. Already by the
s, the
political rhetoric in Europe had become exclusionary particularly of immigrants from the
developing world, who were viewed as a threat to the national identity and values of the
host countries because of their cultural and often religious differences. Such conflicts in and
of themselves are not new—they often arise in the context of immigration and the fear of
losing or diluting one s native culture—but Buruma s and Garton Ash s pejorative use of the
Enlightenment, and linking it to fundamentalist thought, was something new and
antithetical to Enlightened thinking.
After the appearance of Garton Ash s review, one of France s leading nouveaux
philosophes Pascal Bruckner published a scathing reply attacking both Buruma and
Garton Ash and accusing them of a new form of racism. Bruckner was particularly appalled
by what he saw as a rejection of the Enlightenment in favor of postmodern moral
relativism. In his defense of Hirsi Ali, Bruckner declared that Buruma and Garton Ash were
enemies of freedom who want to deny the benefits of democratic rights to those in
society belonging to another religion or ethnic group. Bruckner makes a philosophical
argument against the rise of Anglo-Saxon multiculturalism, which he views as a form of
legal apartheid, in that it does not afford the same freedoms to all. (e goes on to praise
the superiority of the French model
laïcité which does not engage in the questionable
worship of diversity. Bruckner offers a lengthy defense of the Enlightenment and
humanistic secularism and closes by citing Kant s seminal essay Was ist Aufklärung? and
its oft-quoted motto sapere aude. A culture of courage is perhaps what is most lacking
among today s directors of conscience, he writes, a courage that would defend (irsi Ali
and her fight against people chained to their cultural roots and against the encroachment of
religion into modern European secular society.
Bruckner s argument was supported in the ensuing debate by several other
intellectuals and philosophers, including noted Dutch philosopher and law professor Paul
Cliteur, who similarly argued for universal secular values and ethics. Multiculturalists, like
Garton Ash and Buruma he maintained, …reject the universality of the Enlightenment
ideas of democracy, human rights and the rule of law and replace it with the glorification
of otherness.
)n essence, Cliteur writes, if Western societies think they have no core
values important enough to fight for (by peaceful means), then there is no reason for
immigrant minorities to accept them. Only by recognizing and embracing the core values
of the Enlightenment—democracy, the rule of law, and human rights—can the West fight
off the assault directed at these values by a religion, Islam, that denies some people these
rights. What is interesting in this debate is the use (or abuse) of the Enlightenment as an
axis around which the arguments are constructed. )n Garton Ash s equally scathing
response—rather sarcastically entitled Better Pascal than Pascal Bruckner —he suggests
that Bruckner …speaks in the name of the Enlightenment, but […] betrays its essential
spirit namely critical thinking and the freedom of expression without taboos. Both Cliteur
and Buruma recognize that Islamic fundamentalism and Enlightenment fundamentalism
are both radical ideologies, but whereas Cliteur see the superiority of the latter over the
former, Buruma stresses that …one of [the Enlightenment s] greatest achievements is the
rejection of dogma, of any kind. But is the Enlightenment another kind of dogma or does it
represent an ethic of tolerance? Are we in the West simply seeking to embrace the worship
of a secular ideology over a religious one?
While most of the participants in this debate made reference to the Enlightenment
and principles of Enlightenment thought, few actually defined which 18th century thinkers
or which philosophies underlie their argumentation and thus which Enlightenment they
mean. Is it the Enlightenment of tolerance and acceptance that we find in Gotthold Ephraim
Lessing s Nathan the Wise? Or is it the Enlightenment that opposes religious dogma in favor
of critical debate and inquiry in the spirit of Spinoza and Diderot? The former advocates a
kind of multiculturalism that Bruckner rejects while the latter would favor a society with a
strict separation of church and state, which Garton Ash and Buruma find questionable. To
be sure, the Enlightenment has always been a contested, even a contradictory project. On
the one hand, Enlightenment thought defended individual freedom and liberty, yet it also
promoted universality of human rights and values. Similarly it argued for the autonomy of
the individual and free will but also defended religious tolerance. As recent scholarship has
shown, there were in fact at least two Enlightenments: the mainstream Enlightenment of
Kant, Locke and Rousseau and the radical Enlightenment of Condorcet, Diderot and
Spinoza. At the heart of the issue, as Kenan Malik has argued, is the question of whether
reason reigned supreme in human affairs, as the radicals insisted, or whether reason had
to be limited by faith and tradition – the view of the mainstream. Today we still see echoes
of this split in current debates over multiculturalism and the role of religion in Europe, with
the Anglo-American theorists falling more into the mainstream, while the French nouveaux
philosophes, follow the tradition of the French laïcité, arguing for the supremacy of human
reason. But is there a middle ground and the possibility of reconciling both sides of the
debate without sacrificing the central values of the West and the European Union?
One of the leading intellectuals to confront that challenge has been the FrancoBulgarian philosopher Tzvetan Todorov, whose recent work on cultural identity is deeply
rooted both in the Enlightenment (In Defence of the Enlightenment,
and in Europe s
humanistic tradition (The Fear of Barbarians, 2010). In Defence of the Enlightenment
presents an argument for the importance of these 18th century principles as a foundation
for a modern European society that is both enlightened and multicultural. Todorov writes
that there are three ideas found at the base of the Enlightenment project: autonomy; an
awareness of the humanistic purpose of our actions; and universality. Each of these is
important in their own way but they also play into the larger discourse of Enlightened
thought. For instance, a central tenet to our autonomy is that the individual must be free to
examine, question and challenge all institutions and dogmas. Enlightenment thinkers, he
reminds us, were especially critical of religious dogma and orthodoxy and they rejected the
submission of society and individuals to any authority whose legitimacy came from gods
or ancestors. At the same time, however, they did not reject religion per se, rather felt that
religion must withdraw from the realm of the state but not from the individual. Hence
freedom of religious belief and practice was still paramount. Todorov recognizes, however,
that the autonomy of the individual can be threatened not only by religion, but also by the
state and by the family. Whereas Enlightenment fundamentalists focus on the oppressive
threat of religion and of familial tradition, multiculturalists see a similar threat of
oppression from the state and laws that limit an individual s free expression of religious
belief. This dichotomy is at the heart of the debates over laws limiting veiling and wearing
religious symbols: are these laws designed to protect the freedom and autonomy of the
individual from religion and tradition or are they merely an intolerant form of religious
repression by the state?
Todorov acknowledges the threat that fundamentalist Islam poses to secularism and
sees terrorist acts and the oppression of women as the most pernicious (whereas the
former is a political act while the latter often represents the tyranny of family and cultural
tradition). But in The Fear Barbarians, he turns toward an exploration of the humanistic
tradition of Western thought and the need to respect the humanity of each individual. After
first exploring the Greek origins of the word barbarian as others or foreigners, he shows
us that the barbarian has come to mean one who denies the full humanity of others; in
other words, one who doesn t recognize the universality of human rights. And in our
globalized world today, Todorov warns us, our fear of the other, of the barbarian
threatens to make us barbarians ourselves, in that we risk denying the humanity of those
different from us. The influx of immigrants and the growth of religiosity in Western society
has increased that fear, and caused the West to amputate the real tradition of the
Enlightenment, namely combining the universality of values with the plurality of cultures.
As a result, the West increasingly fears losing its culture and national identity, which has
fueled the rise of far-right wing, anti-immigrant parties in the EU and increased the
animosity toward the faceless barbarian who embodies that threat. Much like the
philosophers of the counter-Enlightenment, we see a renewed rejection of the universality
of principles and emphasis instead the particularism of national identity. Not surprisingly
Greece s Golden Dawn, France s Front National and Germany s NPD attract disaffected
citizens who view non-nationals as a threat to their traditional values and cultural identity.
The danger of course is that these parties also threaten the unity in diversity that the EU
seeks to embrace and in doing so, they diminish civil discourse. Habermas recognizes this
dilemma as well: (ow should we see ourselves as members of a post-secular society, he
asks, and what must we reciprocally expect from one another in order to ensure that in
firmly entrenched nation states, social relations remain civil despite the growth of a
plurality of cultures and religious world views? This is certainly one of the greatest
challenges facing the EU in the 21st century. But it must meet that challenge without
sacrificing the Enlightenment values of universality upon which it was built. The American
philosopher Martha Nussbaum has argued in fact that this debate has set up a false
dichotomy between universality and multiculturalism. In her study The New Religious
Intolerance: Overcoming the Politics of Fear in an Anxious Age, she addresses France s
headscarf and burqa ban directly, refuting the various arguments made in favor of the ban,
and argues instead for consistency in applying the law. In this way, there would be no
discrepancy between the universality of values and the plurality of cultures.
Few have written as eloquently on this issue as the German-Iranian writer and Islam
scholar Navid Kermani. In his acceptance speech for the prize from the Helga und Edzard
Reuter-Stiftung, awarded for achievements in international understanding, Kermani makes
the case for a compromise between advocates of a Leitkultur
guiding cultural values
and multiculturalism. (is speech, entitled Why the West should spread its Leitkultur
evangelistically and why Germany should allow its teachers to wear a headscarf, subverts
traditional thinking about universality and particularism in that he argues that the
singularity of Western culture is its particularism. Unlike religion, he notes, which has its
own claim to universality, the European intellectual and cultural tradition allows for the
diversity of religions and religious beliefs. The greatest collective achievement of Europe
and the West, he feels, its true Leitkultur, is having developed a political system that not
only tolerates different religions and world views but radically treats them the same. As if
in answer to Paul Cliteur, who wondered if there were any fundamental principles in
Western culture that multiculturalists would find worth fighting for, Kermani argues that
this, in and of itself, is worth fighting and advocating for, as the political system in the West
demonstrates the superiority of the Western system in that it grants Muslims the freedoms
that Christians in Islamic countries are too often denied.
In conclusion this debate among European intellectuals invites us to consider the
fact that if Europe is to achieve a true unity in diversity, it must recognize the rights and
freedoms of all individuals. In doing so, it will not be relinquishing its fundamental values,
rather as Kermani has suggested it will be embracing them. After all, the relative health of a
democracy and the strength of its civil society can be measured by the openness towards
minorities and minority communities and the equality afforded them. The struggle for civil
and human rights in the West has been a long struggle, but one that has in the end
actualized the goals and universal values of the Enlightenment. Western democracies are
founded on laws rooted in these values, ones that guarantee individual freedom and
respect for humanity. However it is imperative that these laws be applied consistently and
fairly, for by doing so, the West will stay true to its political and cultural heritage, thereby
making our societies stronger—and better for all.